1 Median Voter & C.: 1.1 Arrow Theorem
1 Median Voter & C.: 1.1 Arrow Theorem
i
; = average,
m
median.
Max 1) subject to 2, 3):
4)l
i
= L(t) (
i
)
5) ng _ t
X
(L(t) (
i
)) == g _ tL(t) == W(t;
i
) = L(t) (1
t)(
i
)) + V (1 L(t) )
W(t;
i
) may not satisfy SP (depends on sign L
tt
(t)), but satises SC.
With multi-dimensional issues, SP or SC much harder to believe (classical
example, to be developed below, expenditure for public education with private
4
market supply too). Median voter generally fails, hence cyclying, hence more
strategic behaviour, hence agenda setting power. But some condition still en-
sures median voter eq. even with muldimensional setting.
Let voters preferences satisfy the intermediate property if their indirect
utility function can be written as:
W(q;
i
) = J(q) + K(
i
)H(q)
where K(
i
) monotonic in
i
; J(q); H(q), common among voters,q is now
a vector of policy choices.
Theorem If voters have intermediate preferences, a Condorcet winner exists
and it is given by q(
m
) .
Proof. See PT, p.26.
Very restrictive assumption however, very rarely used, in contrast with SP
or SC.
1.4 Side Issues
1) The above assumes sincere voting. Restrictive? No, with SP preferences.
Strategic voting: let v
i
(q
0
; q
00
) be the voting function of voter i between
q
0
; q
00
; v
i
(q
0
; q
00
) q
0
; q
00
:Let V : q
0
; q
00
n
q
0
; q
00
the voting function
that maps votes in policy outcomes (e.g. V
m
the majoritarian vote). Let
V (v
i
(q
0
; q
00
); v
i
(q
0
; q
00
)) be the policy outcome when i votes according to v
i
(q
0
; q
00
)
and all other voters according to v
i
(q
0
; q
00
): Voter i is strategic if
v
i
(q
0
; q
00
) = arg max W(V (e v
i
(q
0
; q
00
); v
i
(q
0
; q
00
);
i
); all e v
i
(q
0
; q
00
)
i.e. each voter chooses her voting strategy so as to max her utility given the
voting strategies of all other agents.
Theorem Suppose A.1 holds, voting rule is V
m
& preferences satisfy SP
over policy space.Then, sincere voting is a weakly dominant strategy for each
voter and there exists a unique weakly dominant equilibrium with q(
m
) as
Condorect winner.
weakly dominant strategy for i: a strategy that gives weakly higher payo
to i than any other is strategy, regardless the voting strategies of other voters.
Proof. Intuition. If voter is not pivotal, how she votes does not aect the
outcome; thus, voting for his preferred alternative is a best responce whatever
the others do. If voter is pivotal, then clearly voting for his preferred alternative
is the best responce. Hence voting sincerely is a weakly dominant strategy for
5
all voters; but if everybody votes sincerely, by SP and V
m
, the median voter is
the Condorcet winner.
2) Why the (simple) majoritarian rule?
Buchanan & Tullock (1962); the optimal decision rule must trade o internal
versus external cost of making decision.
But there is a kink at 50%; below 50% both a and not a could be approved
simultaneously leading to deadlock. Majoritarian rule is the smallest majority
that avoids deadlocks (but among decisive majoritarian rule is the one that max
external costs).
Mays theorem (1952). The Majoritarian rule is the only rule that satises
a number of normative requirements (i.e. anonimity, decisiveness, neutrality,
responsiveness). See Mueller (2007).
Of course, many more electoral rules are possible in theory and are applied
in practise (e.g. supermajority for costitutional amendments). See Cox, 1997.
We will come back to this.
1.5 Conclusive remarks
With multidimensional issues (would seem the normal case) generally electoral
cycles are pervasive. You would need a voter who is median in all dimensions,
that is very umplausible.
Mckelvey (1976) general theorem. With spatial prererences in multidimen-
sional issue, a sequence of pairwise votes connects any starting point with any
point in the Pareto set of agents.
Worse, you would expect lot of strategic behaviour.
Gibbard & Satterthwaite theorem "Assume at least three alternative, relax
informational assumption, keep U and allows agents to falsely state their prefer-
ences. Given U, an ecient social welfare function is implementable in thruthful
strategies i is dicatorial".
see Mas-Colell chapter 23 for an introduction to mechanism design and more
precise statement.
In voting theory, it means (loosely) that for unrestricted preferences there
is no hope to nd a "mechanism" (including majoritarian voting) that gives
individuals incentive to state thruthfully their preferences (voting sincerously).
Unless is a dictatorship, in which case a version of the theorem above applies.
In practice, this means lots of possible equilibria as a result of voting.
But if the above were a description of reality, we should expect to see a lot
of instability in voting results (cycling) and implemented policies. We instead
observe remarkable stability. Basic explanation in literature: most policy de-
cisions are taken in representative democracies and representative democracies
are very dierent from voting in committees. They have mechanisms to select
6
among equilibria (uncertainty in voting behaviour, structure induced equilib-
rium, legislative bargaining, agency model ect.). Furthermore, there may be
reasons to believe that in a representative democracy the single-dimensionality
of policy (i.e. left to right) is not so out to mark and that the assumption of
sincere voting is also not too unrealistic. More to follow.
7