V V V V V: Models of Second-Order Zermelo Set Theory
V V V V V: Models of Second-Order Zermelo Set Theory
GABRIEL UZQUIANO
289
290 GABRIEL UZQUIANO
§2. Axioms of infinity for Zermelo set theory. There are a variety of alter-
native formulations of the axiom of infinity, not all of them interderivable.
The purpose of this section is to review the relative strength of familiar ver-
sions of infinity, and establish the inability of some of these formulations,
modulo the rest of the Zermelo axioms (Z− ), to deliver the existence of Vù ,
the set of all hereditarily finite sets, as a consequence.
Zermelo’s original axiom of infinity asserts the existence of a set which
contains the null set and which contains the unit set of every set it contains:
This axiom yields the existence of the set Z0 = {∅, {∅}, {{∅}}, . . . }, Zer-
melo’s number sequence, as an immediate consequence, and still occurs
in some presentations of standard set theory. Z− + InfZ is the version of
Zermelo set theory whose axiom of infinity is InfZ .
A more standard formulation of the axiom of infinity is:
Inf ∃y (∅ ∈ y ∧ ∀x (x ∈ y → x ∪ {x} ∈ y)).
Inf delivers the existence of ù, the first transfinite (von Neumann) ordinal.
According to von Neumann’s construction of the ordinals, each ordinal α
coincides with the set of its predecessors, { â : â < α }, and < is just the
element-set relation on the ordinals. Thus, ù, the first transfinite ordinal,
is the set of all finite ordinals, and hence it contains 0 and the successor
α ∪ {α} of every finite ordinal α it contains.3 Inf is what is perhaps the
most common version of the axiom of infinity, and I will abbreviate Z− + Inf
as Z, in accordance with the fact that the name Zermelo set theory is most
commonly used to refer to Z− + Inf.
The following sentence is an ostensibly weaker axiom of infinity:
InfDed ∃y ∃f ∃x (Fnc f ∧ x ∈ y ∧ f : y →(1-1) y − {x}).
Not only does InfDed fail to imply either Inf or InfZ (modulo the axioms
of Z− , of course), as we will see in a moment, it can even be shown that no
infinite set is a member of all the models of second-order Z− + InfDed.
InfDed is equivalent, modulo the axioms of Z− , to the assertion that
there exists an ordinary infinite set, a set y which cannot be put in one-
one correspondence with any set of natural numbers less than some natural
number n. This result is due to Russell who proved that the power set
P(P(x)) of the power set P(x) of an infinite set x is Dedekind infinite.4 It
should be noted, however, that, absent choice, not only can it not be proved
that no infinite set is Dedekind finite, it cannot even be proved that there do
not exist infinite sets whose power set is Dedekind finite.5
The other, less common formulation of the axiom of infinity I want to
consider is:
InfNew ∃y (∅ ∈ y ∧ ∀x ∀z (x ∈ y ∧ z ∈ y → x ∪ {z} ∈ y)).
3
It should perhaps be mentioned that if one’s aim were to develop mathematics within
Zermelo set theory, then one would probably use a different construction of the ordinals.
For, after all, in a model of Zermelo set theory like Vù+ù , there are no von Neumann ordinals
equal to or greater than ù + ù, and thus no von Neumann ordinals that can be used, for
example, to count uncountable well-ordered sets in the domain, Vù+ù .
4
If x is infinite, it can be proved that for each natural number n, the set Sn of all subsets
of x of cardinality n is nonempty, and if m 6= n, Sm and Sn are distinct. But then, S0 and
the function that assigns S(n + 1) to Sn and T itself to each subset T of P(x) not of the
form Sn for some n bears witness to the fact that P(P(x)) is Dedekind infinite. This result
is sometimes erroneously attributed to Tarski, but see [3] for a detailed account.
5
Cf. [5, ch. 3].
292 GABRIEL UZQUIANO
of Z− + InfZ and that there are theorems of Z− + InfZ that are not theorems
of Z.
One moral to be extracted from these results is that neither of what are
perhaps the two most common second-order variants of Zermelo set theory
has the resources necessary to guarantee the existence of sets that appear at
level ù of the cumulative hierarchy, and are thus quite low down in terms
of their cumulative structure—some of these sets are in fact obtainable as
294 GABRIEL UZQUIANO
the model. But the fault for the failure of the axiom of regularity to prevent
the existence of infinite descending ∈-chains that are not definable in the
model is often supposed to lie merely in the fact that the first-order schemata
of separation and replacement are ill-suited to capture the full content of
these axioms.
Much less well-known is the fact that the axiom of regularity fails, even
in the presence of second-order separation, to prevent the existence of non-
well-founded models of several variants of Zermelo set theory:
Theorem 4. There are non-well-founded models of second-order Z− +InfNew.
Proof. To produce a non-well-founded model M of second-order Z− +
InfNew, take the domain of M to be Vù+ù , and let ð be a permutation of
the domain Vù+ù defined by:
ð(x) = {{x}}, if x ∈ {Z0 , {Z0 }, {{Z0 }}, . . . },
[[
ð(Z0 − x) = Z0 − x, if x ∈ Z0 − {∅, {∅}},
ð(Z0 − {∅}) = {Z0 }, and
ð(x) = x otherwise.
An informal, but more intuitive characterization of ð is that it shifts each
term forward two steps in the sequence:
. . . , Z0 − {{{∅}}}, Z0 − {{∅}}, Z0 − {∅}, Z0 , {Z0 }, {{Z0 }}, . . . .
The relation ∈new ⊆ (Vù+ù × Vù+ù ) by which the symbol ∈ is to be inter-
preted in M may then be defined by: x ∈new y if and only if x ∈ ð(y). It is
then immediate that ∈new is not well-founded in M, as Z0 , {Z0 }, {{Z0 }}, . . .
are the members of an an infinite descending ∈new -sequence in the model.
We must now see that M is a model of second-order Z− + InfNew. It
is routine to verify that the truth of the axioms of extensionality, null-set,
pairing, infinity, and second-order separation is unaffected by ð. The axioms
of union, power set, and regularity require more attention and are discussed
here:
Union: Let x be a member of Vù+ù , and note that it is a consequence of
our definition of ð that
∀x (x ∈ Vù+ù → rank(x) ≤ rank(ð(x)) ≤ rank(x) + 2).11
11
As usual, rank(x), the rank of x, is the least ordinal α such that x ⊆ Vα . I should
emphasize that this feature of ð plays an important role in the proof, for, in general, it is
not the case that a one-to-one map of Vù+ù onto Vù+ù induces a model of Z− + InfNew:
A permutation that assigns all the finite Zermelo ordinals to their obvious counterparts in
{Z0 , {Z0 }, {{Z0 }}, . . . } will generate a model in which union fails—consider the union of
Z0 in such a model. Compare with the Rieger-Bernays method for constructing non-well-
founded models of ZF minus regularity.
296 GABRIEL UZQUIANO
12
Replacement is not the only axiom whose absence may distort the content of regularity.
It is an old result of Jon Barwise that ZF − Inf cannot insure the existence of the transitive
closure of a set. Part of the interest of Barwise’s result is that it can readily be adapted to
show that all the axioms of second-order ZF − Inf can be verified in a model in which the
extension of the element-set relation is not well-founded.
13
In [4, pp. 110–111], Frank Drake exhibits a model of (second-order) Z in which not
every set has a transitive closure.
14
As defined in section 2.
298 GABRIEL UZQUIANO
§5. Characterizing the Vë ’s for limit ordinals ë > ù. The results of this
paper make plain, I would like to suggest, that what are perhaps the more
familiar versions of second-order Zermelo set theory fail to characterize the
initial segments of the cumulative hierarchy indexed by a limit ordinal ë > ù.
The question now remains of what else exactly is required to characterize
the Vë ’s for limit ordinals ë > ù. The purpose of this section is to answer
this question by producing a variation of second-order Zermelo set theory
whose axioms can only be satisfied in models of the form hVë , ∈ ∩ (Vë × Vë )i
for ë a limit ordinal greater than ù.
The first point to be noticed is that if we take the variables α, â, ã, . . .
to range over (von Neumann) ordinals, then the Vα ’s can be characterized
thus:
x = Vα ↔ ∃f (Fnc f ∧ Dom(f) = α + 1
∧ ∀â ≤ α ∀y (y ∈ f(â) ↔ ∃ë < â (y ⊆ f(ë))) ∧ f(α) = x).
And this immediately suggests a formulation of the axiom of regularity
which can be used to enforce the modern cumulative view of the set-theoretic
universe. This axiom reads:
∀x ∃α ∃y (y = Vα ∧ x ⊆ y).
15
Z, it should be noted, proves relativizations of all the instances of set-theoretic induction
and of the axiom asserting the existence of a transitive superset of a set. And perfectly
analogous results hold when we restrict our attention to first-order formulations of Zermelo
set theory.
300 GABRIEL UZQUIANO
Now consider the theory that results from second-order Z when the axiom
of regularity, Reg, is replaced by the axiom: ∀x ∃α ∃y (y = Vα ∧ x ⊆ y).
Then, the distinctions among the axioms of infinity discussed in section 2
collapse, and the axioms of second order Z + ∀x ∃α ∃y (y = Vα ∧ x ⊆ y)
do characterize the Vë ’s for limit ordinals ë > ù.16
Notice first that the second-order principle of set-theoretic induction,
∀X (∃x Xx → (∃x Xx ∧ ∀y (y ∈ x → ¬Xy))),
is a theorem of the system. (Suppose Xx. Then, ∃α ∃x (Xx ∧ x ⊆ Vα ),
and, by induction on the ordinals,
∃â (∃x (Xx ∧ x ⊆ Vâ ) ∧ ∀ë < â ¬∃x (Xx ∧ x ⊆ Vë )).
Pick such â and x. Then of course, ∀y ∈ x ¬Xy, since, otherwise, there
would be an ordinal ë < â such that Xy ∧ y ⊆ Vë .)
Theorem 6. M is a model of second-order Z + ∀x ∃α ∃y (y = Vα ∧ x ⊆ y)
if and only if M is of the form hVë , ∈ ∩ (Vë × Vë )i for ë a limit ordinal greater
than ù.
Sketch of proof. Suppose M is a model of second-order Z + ∀x ∃α ∃y
(y = Vα ∧ x ⊆ y). By the (second-order) principle of set-theoretic in-
duction and extensionality, the ∈-relation of the model is well-founded and
extensional, and, hence, by the Mostowski isomorphism theorem, M is
isomorphic to a transitive ∈-model. Without loss of generality, let us now
confine attention to transitive ∈-models of Z + ∀x ∃α ∃y (y = Vα ∧ x ⊆ y).
Suppose M is such a model, and let ë be the least von Neumann ordinal not
in the domain. ë is a limit ordinal greater than ù, since the model satisfies
the axiom of infinity and is closed under successor. Show that every member
of Vë is a member of the domain. For every â < ë, â is a member of the
16
Richard Montague devised in [8] a sentence whose models are only initial segments of
the cumulative hierarchy Vα indexed by an arbitrary ordinal α. Not much later, in [11],
Dana Scott exploited that insight to produce an axiomatization of set theory designed to
insure that the set-theoretic universe is arrayed in a cumulative hierarchy of stages or “partial
universes.” Intuitively, a partial universe is a set of sets of rank less than some one ordinal
α, and a partial universe W is earlier than a partial universe V if and only if W ∈ V . The
axioms of the theory are those of extensionality and separation, an axiom of accumulation
according to which the members of a partial universe are the members or subsets of earlier
partial universes, and an axiom of restriction according to which every set is a subset of a
partial universe. From these axioms, Scott is able to deduce that the partial universes are
well-ordered, that the sets are well-founded, and all the usual axioms of set theory other than
infinity, replacement, and choice.
Our new axiom here is, in effect, aimed to achieve the same effect achieved by Scott’s axiom
of restriction: to ensure that every set is a subset of some Vα for some ordinal α. It should
come as no surprise that the second-order theory one obtains from adjoining an axiom of
infinity to the rest of the axioms of the second-order version of Scott’s theory characterizes
the Vë for limit ë > ù. The proof of this fact is entirely analogous to the one to be offered
for the variation on second-order Zermelo set theory under consideration.
MODELS OF SECOND-ORDER ZERMELO SET THEORY 301
REFERENCES
[1] Paul Bernays, A system of axiomatic set theory VI, Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 13
(1948), pp. 65–79.
17
I would like to thank Michael Glanzberg for helpful comments. Thanks especially to
Vann McGee for providing extensive comments that much improved the paper.
302 GABRIEL UZQUIANO
[2] , A system of axiomatic set theory VII, Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 19 (1954),
pp. 81–96.
[3] George Boolos, The advantages of honest toil over theft, Mathematics and mind,
Oxford University Press, 1994.
[4] Frank Drake, Set theory: An introduction to large cardinals, North-Holland, 1974.
[5] Ulrich Felgner, Models of ZF-set theory, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, no. 223,
Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1971.
[6] Abraham Fraenkel, Yehoshua Bar-Hillel, and Azriel Levy, Foundations of set
theory, North-Holland, 1973.
[7] Azriel Levy, Basic set theory, Springer-Verlag, 1979.
[8] Richard Montague, Set theory and higher-order logic, Formal systems and recursive
functions (J. Crossley and M. Dummett, editors), North-Holland, 1967, pp. 131–148.
[9] Yiannis Moschovakis, Notes on set theory, Springer-Verlag, 1994.
[10] L. Rieger, A contribution to Gödel’s axiomatic set theory, Czechoslovak Mathematical
Journal, vol. 7 (1957), pp. 323–357.
[11] Dana Scott, Axiomatizing set theory, Axiomatic set theory (Thomas Jech, editor),
Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics, vol. II, American Mathematical Society,
1974, pp. 207–214.
[12] Ernst Zermelo, Über Grenzzahlen und Mengenbereiche: Neue Untersuchungen über
die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre, Fundamenta Mathematicae, vol. 16 (1930), pp. 29– 47.
DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY
UNIVERSITY OF ROCHESTER
P. O. BOX 270078
ROCHESTER, NEW YORK 14627-0078, USA
E-mail: [email protected]