An Enactive Approach To Acting - Zarrilli
An Enactive Approach To Acting - Zarrilli
Zarrilli, Phillip B., 1947Theatre Journal, Volume 59, Number 4, December 2007, pp. 635-647 (Article)
Phillip B. Zarrilli is professor of performance practice in the drama department of Exeter University (UK), where he directs the MA/MFA program in theatre practice. He has developed an approach to training actors through psychophysical methods based on Asian martial arts and yoga, which is the subject of his forthcoming book, The Psychophysical Actor at Work: A Post-Stanislavskian, Intercultural Approach.
1 Phillip B. Zarrilli, ed., Acting (Re)Considered: A Theoretical and Practical Guide (London: Routledge, 2002), 3. 2 Joseph Roach, The Players Passion: Studies in the Science of Acting (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1993); see also Jonathan Pitches, Science and the Stanislavsky Tradition of Acting (London: Routledge, 2006). 3 See, in particular, Mark Nearman, Kakyo: Zeamis Fundamental Principles of Acting, Monumenta Nipponica 37, no. 3 (1982): 33374; Kakyo: Zeamis Fundamental Principles of Acting Part Two, Monumenta Nipponica 37, no. 4 (1982): 45996; Kakyo: Zeamis Fundamental Principles of Acting Part Three, Monumenta Nipponica 38, no. 1 (1983): 4970. On Zeami, see also Yasuo Yuasa, The Body: Toward an Eastern Mind-Body Theory (Albany: SUNY Press, 1987); and Shelley Fenno Quinn, Developing Zeami: The Noh Actors Attunement in Practice (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 2005).
Theatre Journal 59 (2007) 635647 2008 by The Johns Hopkins University Press
Using this taxonomy of categories, Gordon discusses many of the major theorist/ practitioners of twentieth-century Western theatreStanislavsky, Michael Chekhov, Strasberg, Craig, Meyerhold, Copeau, Saint-Denis, Spolin, Brecht, Boal, Artaud, Grotowski, Brook, Barba, among othersin order to enable the reader to grasp the dialectical relationship between major traditions of performance.6 An additional seventh category might be added to Gordons taxonomy: performance as psychophysiological process, the embodiment and shaping of energy. Here, psycho does not mark the recent Western invention of psychologies of the self/individual as in the compound psychological,7 but rather refers to another meaning of the Greek psyche: the vital principlenamely, the lan vital or the enlivening quality of the (actors) breath/energy.8 However important psychology has been to shaping the dramaturgy
4 See especially Phillip B. Zarrilli, Kathakali Dance-Drama: Where Gods and Demons Come to Play (London: Routledge, 2000), and When the Body Becomes All Eyes: Paradigms, Practices, and Discourses of Power in Kalarippayattu (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1998). 5 Robert Gordon, The Purpose of Playing: Modern Acting Theories in Perspective (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2006), 6. 6 Ibid., 5. Gordon argues that the beginning place for all theories of acting is the fact that the actors body must always be cultivated as an instrument capable of varied and subtle expressive forms. Each practitioner/theorist proposes a different solution (ibid., 2) to the underlying phenomenon of cultivation toward expressive form. 7 On the historical invention of psychology, see Joel Pfister and Nancy Schnog, eds., The Invention of the Psychological (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1997). 8 This alternative meaning of psyche is akin to the Greek psychein, meaning to breathe, blow, and therefore comes very close to the inner experience marked by the Sanskrit term prana (or prana-vayu) and the Chinese qi (the Korean and Japanese ki)breath, life force, or vital energy. Gordons sixth category incorporates the intercultural work of Eugenio Barba, which draws extensively on non-Western principles and dynamics. Much of Gordons discussion includes the psychophysical as defined here, but without specific reference to non-Western genres/practices/theories of acting per se.
/ 637
of realist and naturalist plays from the late nineteenth through the twentieth centuries, it is inappropriate or inadequate to the realization of the dramaturgy and acting tasks that constitute an actors performance score in many postdramatic texts/performances or in non-Western performance.9 A psychophysiological approach through embodiment and the shaping of energy is an extension of Stanislavskys early, innovative use of the compound term psychophysical (psikhofizicheskii). Paralleling the use of this term in the new sciences of the period, Stanislavskys use of it was an innovative, if historically limited and not always successful, attempt to problem-solve the relationship between the psycho (inner) and the physical elements of acting. He drew not only on the psychology of Theodule Armand Ribot (18381916), but also on the limited versions of Indian yoga available to Stanislavsky in turn-of-the-century Russia, filtered through then-popular occultism and spiritualism.10 Later manifestations of a psychophysiological approach to embodiment and energy in action are seen in the varied approaches of Michael Chekhov, Grotowski, Barba, Artaud, and my own use of Asian martial arts and yoga in training actors.
/ 639
Figure 1. Phillip Zarrilli (Reader) and Andy Crook (Listener) in Ohio Impromptu. Photo: Brent Nicastro.
seen, and they cannot see each other. These two (identical?) figures are illuminated against a black void. As Reader reads the story in the book open before him, the two figures sit motionless throughout most of the performance as though turned to stone.16 Ohio Impromptu is almost noh-like in its sparseness and stillness. The actors performance scores are quite simple. Reader reads the text, but does so, according to Beckett, without colorthat is, without the intonation or typical vocal contours that identifies the voice as belonging to a particular individual. Listener listens to the story. The physical actions constituting the actors scores are minimal. Listener knocks on the resonant wooden table when he wishes Reader to stop and repeat a phrase, or when he wishes the reading of the narrative to continue. When the reading of the story is complete and the book has been closed, after a final knock Reader and Listener gradually raise their heads to look into each others eyes for the first time. This action takes place at a glacially slow pace. This is clearly a postdramatic text.
September 15, 2006. The Gilbert Hemsley Theatre (Madison, Wisconsin). Tonight is the first of eight performances of The Beckett Project on tour. We have just received our five-minute call for Ohio Impromptu. Andy Crook (Listener) and I (Reader) leave our dressing room, mirror images
16
Ibid., 287.
/ 641
What I have just described, as best I can, is how as a stage actor I simultaneously inhabit, act within, and respond as a sentient, perceptual being to the very specific (theatrical) environment that constitutes the mise-en-scene of Becketts Ohio Impromptu during its opening moments. As Reader, the actions I initiatereading the text, turning a page, closing the bookand my responses to stimulimy reading of the first line or Andys knockare specific to the plays dramaturgy as actualized in this theatre on this day. Precisely when does his knock with the knuckles of his left hand stop my reading of the text? Ideally, I never know. By being perceptually responsive to Andys actual presence in this environment, my reading is stopped by his knock as/when it happens in each performance. The word or part of a word that is interrupted differs every night; precisely what my imagination will conjure in response to that first line, Little is left to tell, I do not know. Andy Crook and I are not abstract constructs, but rather specific persons acting, sensing, perceiving, and imagining as living human organisms in the moment to each other and to the environment. In this view, acting may be (meta-theoretically) defined as enactive: a psychophysiological process by means of which a (theatrical) world is made available at the moment of its appearance/experience for both the actors and audience. However pedestrian it may be, the above description of acting in Ohio Impromptu is intended to provide some idea of just how complex the embodied phenomenon and experience of acting is at the moment it happens. Although any such account can never completely describe or represent acting in all its complexities, by following philosopher Alva Ne I have tried to provide a description that catch[es] experience in the act of making the world available.17
Implicit in Merleau-Pontys theory of the body as an I can is a theory of perception.23 Western philosophy has long viewed perception and action as distinct. As Maximilian de Gaynesford explains:
On this old view, the mind receives sensory information from its environment, information which is then given structure by various cognitive processes and fed into the motor cortex to produce action. This view seems erroneous for numerous neurophysiological, behavioural and philosophical reasons. We should, instead, treat perception and action as constitutively interdependent.24
One of the first to challenge the old view of perception and to argue for perception and action as interdependent was psychologist James Gibson. In his seminal 1979 book The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, Gibson challenged the commonplace view among psychologists at the time, which assumed that we constructed representations of the world around us in our brains/heads. Anthropological ecologist Tim Ingold explains how psychologists in the 1960s and 1970s assumed that
the mind got to work on the raw material of experience, consisting of sensations of light, sound, pressure on the skin, and so on, organizing it into an internal model which, in turn, could serve as a guide to subsequent action. The mind, then, was conceived as a kind of
ings in Little Rooms: On the Phenomenology of Theatre (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1971); Bruce Wilshire, Role Playing and Identity (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982); Alice Rayner, To Do, To Act, To Perform: Drama and the Phenomenology of Action (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1994); and Stanton Garner, Bodies Spaces: Phenomenology and Performance in Contemporary Drama (Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 1994). What differentiates both my 2004 essay and this current account from earlier studies is my focus on the livedness of the actors modes of embodiment, perception, and experience from the actors perspective inside training and performance. The constitutive nature of embodied experience in shaping not only our experience, but also as a basis for how we linguistically conceptualize our relationship to the world has been argued at length in the co-authored studies of George Lakoff and Mark Johnson: Metaphors We Live By (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1980), and Philosophy in the Flesh (New York: Basic Books, 1999). 21 Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Primacy of Perception (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1964), 87. 22 Francisco Varela, J. Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch, The Embodied Mind: Cognitive Science and Human Experience (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991), 19. 23 For a general discussion of the philosophical problem of perception, see Barry Maund, Perception (Chesham, UK: Acumen Publishing, 2002). 24 Maximilian de Gaynesford, Corporeal Objects and the Interdependence of Perception and Action, in The Philosophy of the Body, ed. Mike Proudfoot (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 2003), 2139.
/ 643
data-processing device, akin to a digital computer, and the problem for the psychologist was to figure out how it worked.25
Gibson took a radically different approach. He rejected the notion first developed by Descartes that the mind is a separate organ that operates on the data the bodily senses provide. Gibson argued that
[p]erception . . . is not the achievement of a mind in a body, but of the organism as a whole in its environment, and is tantamount to the organisms own exploratory movement through the world. If mind is anywhere, then, it is not inside the head rather than out there in the world. To the contrary, it is immanent in the network of sensory pathways that are set up by virtue of the perceivers immersion in his or her environment.26
Ne is among the most prominent proponents of this new view of the interdependence of perception and action. He draws on the earlier work of Gibson, phenomenology, and cognitive science to further develop an enactive approach to perception and perceptual experience. Nes thesis is that perceiving is a way of acting. Perception is not something that happens to us, or in us. It is something we do . . . the world makes itself available to the perceiver through physical movement and interaction.27 If perception is not something that unfolds in the brain, neither is it like the sense of sight that makes it seem as if we are passive to the world. Ne argues that perception is like the sense of touch: [T]he content of perception is not like the content of a picture. In particular, the detailed world is not given to consciousness all at once in the way detail is contained in a picture. In vision, as in touch, we gain perceptual content by active inquiry and exploration.28 Perception is active and relational. Paralleling Nes perspective, Ingold takes an ecological approach to perception in which the sentient, perceiving person is considered an organism like other organisms.29 He invites us to consider what happens when we think of ourselves as a living thing existing in relation to one or more environments. A relational view of the organism conceives of the human being not as a composite entity made up of separable but complementary parts, such as body, mind, and culture, but rather as a singular locus of creative growth within a continually unfolding field of relationships.30 For Ingold, the whole-organism-in-its-environment is not a bounded entity, but rather is constituted by an ongoing process in real time: a process, that is, of growth or development.31 This process of growth or development consists of the acquisition of perceptual skills. For Ingold, the notion of skills incorporates, but should not be reduced to bodily based skills; rather, perceptual skills are the capabilities of action and perception of the whole organic being (indissolubly mind and body) situated in a richly structured environment.32 Indeed, the content of our perceptual experience is acquired through bodily skills that we come to possess. What we perceive is determined by what we do (or what we
Tim Ingold, The Perception of the Environment (New York: Routledge Press, 2000), 3. Ibid., 3. 27 Ne, Action in Perception, 1. 28 Ibid., 33. 29 Ingold, The Perception of the Environment, 3. 30 Ibid., 45. 31 Ibid., 1920 (emphasis in original). 32 Ibid., 5.
25 26
/ 645
embodied knowledge of the organization and structure of sensation-in-action. As Ne explains, the shape is made available thanks to the way in which your sensations covary or would co-vary with actual or possible movements.42 As one learns a specific form of movement, both the pattern and optimal quality of ones relationship to the repetition of each form constitutes a form of sensorimotor knowledge.
/ 647
of enacting the score. In the moment of enactment, we are utilizing our perceptual and sensory experience and cumulative embodied knowledge as skilled exploration in the moment of the specific theatrical world or environment created during the rehearsal process.
Conclusion
To summarize my argument, human perception is enactive, relational, and specific to an environment. I have considered a meta-theory of acting not in terms of how the actor constructs a character or how the actor makes a performance believable, but rather from the perspective of the actor-as-(human) doer/enactor inside the performance of an acting score. Stage acting may therefore productively be considered as one among many extra-daily skilled modes of embodied practice requiring the performer to develop a heightened attunement of sensory and perceptual awareness in order to be fully responsive to theatrical environments and dramaturgies. According to this alternative paradigm or meta-theory, it may be more useful to consider acting in terms of its dynamic energetics than in terms of representation. Acting according to an enactive paradigm is not in the first instance about meaning or representation; rather, it implies an energetic theatrea theatre not of meaning but of forces, intensities, present affects.51 Meaning and representation may present themselves to the viewer or critic of a performance, but they are the result of the actors immediate energetic engagement in the act of performance and the spectators experience of that performance. In this view, the actor practically negotiates interior and exterior via perception-in-action in response to an environment. Although psychology may inform the construction of particular actions the actor inhabits according to the needs of a particular dramaturgy-in-action, acting per se is not primarily about psychology or behavior. In this view, the actor-as-perceiver ideally undergoes training that allows one to become like an animal, ready to leap and act.52
51 Jean-Franois Lyotard, quoted in Lehmann, Post-Dramatic Theatre, 37; see also Patrice Pavis, Analyzing Performance (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2003), 95ff. 52 Eugenio Barba and Nicola Savarese, A Dictionary of Theatre Anthropology (London: Routledge, 1991), 197. How the actor is trained to become animal-like is specifically explored in Zarrilli, The Psychophysical Actor at Work; see also Phillip B. Zarrilli, Embodying the Lions Fury: Ambivalent Animals, Activation and Representation, Performance Research 5, no. 2 (2000): 4154.