56 1palan PDF
56 1palan PDF
56 1palan PDF
International Organization, Volume 56, Number 1, Winter 2002, pp. 151-176 (Article) Published by The MIT Press
Over the past three decades there has been a spectacular rise in the number of microstates serving as tax havens and bogus locations for actual or phantom corporations. Most, but not all, of these havensthese paradis scaux as the French, with some irony, call themare small tourist resorts. Of the seventy or so tax havens identied in recent counts,1 most serve as mere booking centers for the larger nancial centers of London, Tokyo, and New York. Yet the combined effect of tax havens on the world economy is staggering: According to some estimates, as much as half of the worlds stock of money either resides in tax havens or passes through them.2 In contrast to other states, tax havens have distinguished themselves by enacting legislation that provides corporations and individuals with anonymity and shelter from their home governments. Lacking adequate mechanisms of internal prot
I thank Libby Assassi, Gary Burn, Angus Cameron, Sandra Halperin, Richard Phillips, two anonymous referees, and the editors of IO for their helpful suggestions and comments. 1. The exact number of tax havens is in dispute. The recently published task force name and shame report lists thirty-seven jurisdictions with signicant offshore activities. However, specialists claim the gure is much higher. An International Monetary Fund (IMF) study lists nearly seventy tax havens, while the latest authoritative study by Diamond and Diamond lists no fewer than sixty-two tax havens. See Financial Stability Forum 2000; Musalem and Luca 1999; and Diamond and Diamond 1998. Diamond and Diamond identify at least ten additional tax havens that have not made a great impact on the international nancial markets. Already in 1984, Richard Blum had arrived at a gure of over one hundred tax havens. Blum 1984, 27. Many nancial experts believe, however, that practically every country can serve as a tax haven. For a good discussion of the method by which different analysts arrive at the aggregate number of tax havens, see Doggart 1997; and Ginsburg 1991, 6. 2. See Cassard 1994; and Kochen 1991. This estimated gure is often mentioned but rarely explained. The original estimate may have been derived from Blum and Kaplan 1979, who estimated that in 1979 about two-fths of Swiss banking transactions were with, or via, tax havens. If London were added, they concluded, more than half of all Swiss transactions would be conducted in the offshore market. The gure of half of the stock of money may have been derived from their ndings. Switzerland is a special case, however, and its experience cannot be extrapolated to the world economy. The fact is, no one really knows how much money goes through offshore nancial centers. International Organization 56, 1, Winter 2002, pp. 151176 2002 by The IO Foundation and the Massachusetts Institute of Technology
generation,3 these so-called paper nancial centers have learned to take advantage of what The Economist scornfully describes as their main asset: the right to write the laws. But in so doing, tax havens are like the sovereign equivalent of parking lot proprietors: they could not care less about the business of their customers, only that they pay for parking their vehicles there. Likewise, tax havens are unconcerned with the true nature of the companies residing within their borders.4 Those using tax havens rarely relocate to them;5 instead they pay for the privilege of renting a residence there. That is, they take advantage of the juridical facilities offered to them for what is euphemistically called effective international tax strategy, which is another way of saying avoiding or evading taxes. But with increasing numbers of tax havens and those who use them, the principles of supply and demand appear to regulate the cost of license fees and the character of the legal protection that tax havens offer. In other words, tax havens are introducing choice and marginal utility into issues of residency and sovereignty. In this article I seek to explain the causes for the apparent commercialization of state sovereignty, and in particular the reasons why such commercialization is associated with tax havens. Thus far the subject has not attracted the attention it deserves. On the contrary, tax havens generally are viewed as a perfectly legal strategy for development particularly suited to microstates.6 The literature acknowledges, however, that the motive of these states is to draw rent surpluses from the income that otherwise would accrue to larger states.7 Some view the commercialization of sovereignty as it is practiced by these states to be an abuse of the rules and codes of sovereignty.8 Others maintain that it is a perfectly legitimate strategy, but that it can lead to abuses in that it encourages tax evasion and money laundering.9 The latter believe that such abuses can be corrected if stricter international standards are agreed to and acted upon. The consensus seems to be that tax havens ourish because of the rising regulation and taxation practiced by advanced industrial countries. I challenge the conventional view. I argue that the conditions that gave rise to the commercial use of sovereignty as perfected by tax havens cannot be dismissed either as legitimate responses to an unreasonable surge in taxation and regulation in the
3. Johns 1983. 4. Whenever the issue is raised it generates a chorus of indignant voices from the tax havens. Many scholars have demonstrated, however, that tax havens have very limited capacity or will to regulate corporations that supposedly are residing in their territories. For instance, Blum reports that in Antigua, government authorities have no adequate records of the number of registered companies that exist, although a regulation requires annual reporting by companies . . . we are told companies number in the hundreds or thousands. Blum 1984, 129. See also Naylor 1987; OECD 1987; Gilmore 1992; and Financial Stability Forum 2000. 5. See Doggart 1997, chap. 3; and Barber 1993. 6. Fabri and Baldacchino 1999, 141. 7. See Hampton 1996; and Johns 1983. 8. See, among others, Picciotto 1992; Gordon 1981; Hudson 1998; Marshall 1996; Palan 1998; and Palan and Abbott 1996. 9. See Hines and Rice 1994; and Johns and Le Marchant 1993.
postwar era or as mere abuse of sovereignty. On the contrary, they go to the heart of the continuing process of state formation in a period of intensied capital mobility. I trace the incipient commercial use of sovereignty not to deliberate or instrumental state behavior, but to the contradictions between two elements: (1) the continuing process of insulating the state in law, a process that began in the sixteenth century, culminated in the nineteenth century, and has only recently begun to reverse itself;10 and (2) the growing integration of the world market, a process that began in earnest with the emergence of multinational corporations at the end of the nineteenth century. Thus, paradoxically, improvements in communication and transportation technologies and accelerating capital mobility have been accompanied not by any loosening of the juridical unity of the state but by, if anything, the strengthening of it. The ensuing conict between the increasing insulation of the state in law and the internationalization of capital forced a series of pragmatic solutions, one of which proved conducive to the development of the tax haven and the commercialization of sovereignty. In making this argument I rely on two sets of observations, the rst having to do with timing; the second, with the nature of the tax havens strategy. We need to distinguish, as I will show, between the period that saw a tremendous proliferation in the number of tax havens in the world, namely, the nal quarter of the twentieth century, and the period that saw the emergence of the rst modern tax havens, the last years of the nineteenth century. Conventional theories may explain the reasons for the tremendous proliferation of tax havens in the later years of the twentieth century but not why they emerged in the nineteenth century, not least because taxation and state regulation in the nineteenth century remained relatively low. Nonetheless, while the argument about timing casts serious doubts on conventional theories, it does not preclude in principle a variant of conventional theories. I therefore place greater emphasis on a second argument, which addresses the nature of the tax havens strategy. In many ways, the tax havens strategy can be considered ctional or purely juridical;11 it is founded on the ability of companies and individuals to shift some of their legal residence without physically moving. The origins and causes of such facility have to be understood therefore in the context of establishing the legal facility for juridical relocation, a point that is entirely absent in conventional theories. Given that small and marginal social formations often exhibit eccentric development trajectories, how signicant are tax havens? Even more broadly, how significant is this burgeoning market in sovereignty to the world economy? There is a danger of misjudging the signicance of the tax haven phenomenon by treating it as a mere perversion or mutation of the principle of sovereign equality, or by marginalizing it because of the small size of tax havens. An examination of the conditions in the late nineteenth century that gave rise to the system of tax havens
demonstrates that far from being the exception, the relationship between tax havens and sovereignty is likely to prove the norm. My conclusion, therefore, is that the commercialization of sovereignty is endemic to a system characterized by increasing economic integration within the context of political fragmentation.
12. OECD 1987, 21. 13. Ginsburg 1991, 1. 14. See Starchild 1993; Johns 1983; and Banoff and Kanter 1994. 15. Johns 1983, 20. See also Palan and Abbott 1996, chap. 8. 16. Musalem and Luca 1999. Diamond and Diamond list sixty-two jurisdictions as tax havens, and Chavagneux and Palan list over seventy jurisdictions. See Diamond and Diamond 1998; and Chavagneux and Palan 1999. 17. Park 1982.
TABLE 1.
Asia and Pacic Australia Cook Islands Guam Hong Kong Japana Macau Malaysiab Marianas Marshall Islands Micronesia Nauru Niue Philippines Singaporec Thailandd Vanuatu Western Samoa
Europe Austria Andorra Campione Cyprus Gibraltar Guernsey Hungary Irelandd Sark and Isle of Man Jersey Liechtenstein Luxembourg Malta Madeira Monaco Netherlands Russia Switzerland United Kingdomf
Western Hemisphere Antigua Anguilla Aruba Bahamas Barbados Belize Bermuda British Virgin Islands Cayman Islands Costa Rica Dominica Grenada Montserrat Netherlands Antilles St. Kitts and Nevis St. Lucia Panama Puerto Rico St. Vincent Turks and Caicos United Statesg Uruguay
Source: Musalem and Errico 1999. a Japanese offshore market (JOM). b Labuan. c Asian currency units (ACUs). d Bangkok international banking facility (IBF). e Dublin. f London. g U.S. international banking facilities are located in New York, Miami, Chicago, and Los Angeles San Francisco.
the Isle of Man, Monaco, the Netherlands, the Netherlands Antilles, Austria, and Singapore). There are also tax havens with specic legislation for regional ofces of foreign companies (the Philippines, Jordan, Greece, and Tunisia). Notwithstanding the great variation among tax havens, they share the following attributes: minimal or no personal or corporate taxation; effective bank secrecy laws (quite often, bank or state ofcials are barred by law from disclosing the origins, character, and names of fund holders); few, preferably no, restrictions or regulations concerning nancial transactions; and protection of the secrecy of transactions. The more successful tax havens also have the following attributes:
1. They possess political and economic stability; hence some of the betterknown tax havens are dependencies of large, prosperous, and stable states. 2. They are supported by a large international nancial market or are equipped with sophisticated information-exchange facilities and are within easy reach of a major nancial center; Gibraltar, for instance, has invested heavily in communication infrastructure. 3. They are not tainted by scandals, money laundering, or drug money; hence the concern shown by Liechtenstein and the Caymans Islands regarding the recent report from the Financial Stability Forum. 4. They have agreements with major countries in order to avoid double taxation and regulation. Estimates of the economic impact of tax havens vary as well. Some analysts maintain that more than half of the worlds stock of money passes through these tax havens.18 In addition, it is estimated that about 20 percent of total private wealth and about 22 percent of banks external assets are invested offshore.19 Walter Diamond and Dorothy Diamond, however, estimate the current total assets located in tax havens at $5.1 trillion.20 James R. Hines and Eric M. Rice estimate that by 1994 the gross amount of U.S. investment in tax havens was $359 billion of $1.39 trillion, or over one-quarter of corporate activity conducted worldwide.21 By any standard, therefore, the tax haven phenomenon is of great and growing importance to todays economy. Conventional accounts explain the rise of tax havens by referring to the tremendous increase in state regulation and taxation during the postwar period. The heavier the regulations and taxation, so the argument goes, the keener some people are to avoid them. It is no coincidence, notes Paul Figleton, that banking, insurance, and ship registration are three of the main pillars of offshore business; they are among the most heavily regulated industries in developed countries.22 The Financial Stability Forums recently published report from the Working Group on Offshore Financial Centers reiterates the commonly held view: The main contributing factor identied for the historical growth of offshore banking and Offshore Financial Centers was the imposition of increased regulation . . . in the nancial sectors of industrialized countries during the 1960s and the 1970s.23 According to this account, faced by a growing demand for permissive regulations, a number of microstates began to offer zero or near-zero regulations in order to attract businesses to their territories. As Robert A. Johns observes, Given that some countries adopt a permissive regulatory environment and others a stringent one, gaps and differen18. 19. 20. 21. 22. 23. See n. 2 above. See Cassard 1994; and Diamond and Diamond 1998, 1. Diamond and Diamond 1998. Hines and Rice 1994, 151. Figleton 1989, 6. Financial Stability Forum 2000, 11.
tials arise in national systems of regulation. These differences can lead to perverse competition in regulatory laxity and a gravitation by some institutions to the least regulated nancial centers.24 Other analysts, however, have questioned such accounts, believing that tax havens evolve as deliberate state strategies aimed at attracting hot money. A study commissioned by the French Parliament demonstrates convincingly that both Liechtenstein and Monaco have persistently and knowingly sought to attract hot if not criminal money.25 Similarly, Tom Naylor shows that lawyers and nanciers associated with the infamous Maa boss Meir Lansky played a key role in drafting the nancial legislation of some of the best-known Caribbean tax havens.26 According to these theories, tax havens are quite simply abusing the system of sovereignty to advance parochial interests. In fact, tax havens have often been associated with arguments like those above that implicitly recognize the vast potential for the commercialization of state sovereignty. The vigorous campaign of the International Transport Workers Federation against ags of convenience, for instance, has generated a large number of publications deriding the inappropriate use of sovereignty. Indeed, Rodney Carlisle gave his excellent study of the Panamanian and Liberian ags of convenience the title Sovereignty for Sale.27 A recent Inland Revenue document refers to designer rate regimes that enable companies to pay just the right amount of tax needed in any given situation to sidestep Controlled Foreign Companies rules.28 Among international tax experts the expression treaty shopping has now come into wide usage.29 In 1933, in a dissenting opinion in Liggett Co. v. Lee, Justice Louis Brandeis recalled that companies were early formed to provide charters for corporations in states where the cost was lowest and the laws least restrictive. The states joined in advertising their wares. The race was one not of diligence but of laxity.30 Alfred Conard notes that there is nothing very unusual about a race between states, . . .[but] what is unusual about the race of laxity in corporation codes is that its effect will be felt among those almost entirely outside the state. He calls this the strictly-for-export aspect of corporation code.31 Similarly, in the 1970s Robert Aliber noted a curious arrangement between the Swiss government and Elizabeth Taylor: Miss Taylor and the Swiss have struck a
24. Johns 1983, 6. See also Charny 1991. 25. Montebourg 2000. 26. See Naylor 1987; and Robinson 1995, 133. 27. Carlisle 1981. 28. Inland Revenue 1999. 29. Treaty shopping means that taxpayer shops into the benets of a treaty which normally are not available to him. To this end he generally interposes a corporation in a country that has an advantageous tax treaty. Becker and Wurm 1988, 1. 30. Cited in Conard 1973, 631. 31. Ibid., 633. Conard insists on the difference between the tax haven game and the exportation of liberality within the United States [which] depends on a principle of conict of laws, according to which the law governing the internal affairs of a corporation is the law of the state of incorporation. Ibid., 634.
bargain. The Swiss sell Miss Taylor tax-avoidance services. The right to live in a low-tax jurisdiction. Miss Taylor buys this service because she likes the higher after-tax income; better to live where taxes are low than where they are high. The Swiss prot from the transaction, for Miss Taylors tax payments greatly exceed her demand on local public services.32 Both the Swiss government and Elizabeth Taylor pursue rational strategies in the sense that both are getting something out of the bargain. Aliber depicts tax havens as states that have learned to use their legislative capacities as baits to attract business into their jurisdictions. Such apparently rational arrangements between states and private operators are perfectly legal. Yet they are deeply disturbing, not least because the two parties to the exchange one of them a sovereign government handle highly charged normative issues, such as citizenship and nationality, in purely utilitarian terms. The willful misuse of ideas and practices that go to the heart of the legitimacy of the modern state as a national state is the most disturbing aspect of the tax haven phenomenon. Explanations for these sorts of arrangements are normally viewed in terms of variants of the so-called Tiebout-type efciency paradigm. Writing about the competitive incorporation of American cities, Charles Tiebout postulated that different jurisdictions provide individuals and rms with a bundle of public services and tax regulations.33 He argued that individuals and rms are likely to choose jurisdictions that offer desirable bundles of regulations by moving to them, and are likely to move away from jurisdictions that offer less desirable bundles of regulations. Since municipal jurisdictions want the business of these individuals and companies, the jurisdictions are compelled to compete with each other by offering the kind of regulations that the market wants. In contrast to the laxity races noted by Judge Brandeis, Tiebout maintained that such a market in bundles of regulations is likely to bring about optimal public service as taxpayers adapt to the economic system. Drawing on Tiebouts theory, Gary Hufbauer argues that competition between states does not necessarily lead to a race to the bottom but serves as the best safeguard against what Tiebout believed was states natural predisposition to abuse their monopoly positions.34 These ideas resonate well with the theory of the new political economy, which views states (or public authority) as being engaged in an exchange relationship with society, providing security in return for taxes.35 According to the theory, states are monopolistic service providers whose powers must be curbed. While only the most extreme positions in the rent-seeking literature would wish the state away, they are on the whole sympathetic to the Tiebout efciency argument, and they implicitly welcome the commercialization of sovereignty as a means of curbing the states excesses.
32. Aliber 1976, 182. 33. Tiebout 1956. For an excellent discussion of the context and failure of the Tiebout paradigm, see Miller 1981. 34. See Hufbauer 1992; and Hines and Rice 1994. 35. Auster and Silver 1979.
Tiebout-type efciency has been debated in many circles and has been found wanting on a number of fronts. However, the debate underscores two points that are relevant here. First, there is a shared perception that a sovereign right to write the lawwhether at the municipal, state, or national level combined with a competitive system can be used as a competitive asset. In other words, a link between a competitive system of jurisdictions and the potential for the commercialized use of the right to write the law is well recognized. Second, another Tiebout argument maintains that the raising or lowering of taxation or regulation is not in and of itself the cause for the commercialized use of sovereignty. On the contrary, Tiebout does not assume, as conventional theories of tax havens do, that corporations will necessarily migrate to the least regulated or least taxed realm. The causes for the commercialization of sovereignty lie elsewhere.
Doggart 1997. Diamond and Diamond 1998, 2. Smith 1912, 125. Ibid.
since revenue from the casino paid for all the public affairs of Monaco, low taxation and the Mediterranean climate attracted many wealthy visitors and residents, and Monaco became the epitome of the cheerful, fabulously rich tax haven. It took about half a century for Monaco to integrate these laws into a veritable tax haven strategy. In contrast, the practice of competitive reduction in corporate taxation can be traced back to the incorporation laws of New Jersey and Delaware. In fact, a behavioral characteristic of modern tax havens had already been witnessed in the late nineteenth century within the federal structure of the United States. Some of the smaller states in the Union, including New Jersey and Delawarein competition with West Virginia, Rhode Island, and Maine became known for enacting what Alfred Conard calls strictly for export laws.40 During the 1880s, New Jersey was in dire need of funds. A corporate lawyer from New York persuaded Governor Abbet to back his scheme of raising revenue by imposing a franchise tax on all corporations headquartered in New Jersey. The scheme provided that New Jersey should liberalize her laws regarding corporate regulation to an extent that would make it advantageous for all corporations to be organized under her protection.41 When the Delaware legislature debated the drafting of a new general incorporation act in 1898, it sought to emulate the success of New Jersey. Here, again, a group of lawyers from New York played a prominent role in drafting the proposed act.42 It was obvious at the time that Delaware was enacting liberal laws to attract corporate business.43 Although the smaller American states competed by offering liberal laws, the principle of purely ctional incorporation for tax purposes originated elsewhere. Sol Picciotto traces the origins of the practice to a series of rulings by the British law courts. In the last quarter of the nineteenth century, problems related to the tax liability of British companies whose activities took place abroad began to surface.44 The British government handled the issue with the aid of the courts. In 1876 the issue of extra-jurisdictional corporate taxation was brought before the Exchequer courts. In Cesena Sulphur Co., Ltd. v. Nicholson and Calcutta Jute Mills v. Nicholson, the courts held that although their activities took place abroad, these companies were under the control of persons belonging to a governing body located in England. They were therefore resident in Britain and liable to the national tax regime. Aware that many shareholders were foreign, the court contended that if they invested in a British company they were liable to pay British tax.45 The courts established the main principles of British taxation. British-registered companies could not escape potential liability for income tax on their trading prots unless the whole of their activities and all the management and control took place
Conard 1973. Lindholm 1944, 57. Larcom 1937, 9. Ibid., 17. The following draws on Picciotto 1992. Picciotto 1992. See also Schmitthoff 1954, 382 86.
abroad. The precedent for this was the 1929 case of the Egyptian Delta Land and Investment Co. Ltd. v. Todd. It was demonstrated that although the company was registered in London, The business of the company was entirely engaged and controlled from Cairo where the directors and secretary permanently resided; the seal, minutes, and books of accounts and transfer were kept; transfers were approved (before being registered in London; and dividend was declared and paid. . . . [Consequently, the] House of Lords held that the company was ordinarily resident in Egypt, and not in the United Kingdom.46 This case created, argues Picciotto, a loophole which, in a sense, made Britain a tax haven.47 Companies could now incorporate in Britain but avoid paying British tax. The ruling of the British courts proved signicant because it laid down the rule not only for the United Kingdom but also for the entire British Empire, a point later exploited by jurisdictions such as Bermuda and the Bahamas and perfected in the 1970s by the Cayman Islands. Modern bank secrecy laws, in contrast, evolved in Switzerland. Bank secrecy is an old and well-established principle. Swiss bankers began offering secrecy to aristocrats for a fee during the French Revolution.48 In fact, les comptes anonymes, numbered bank accounts, were invented at the end of the nineteenth century.49 The Swiss developed these laws further, so that as early as the 1920s Switzerland became the preferred location for asset protection.50 During that period, Switzerland was the only country in Europe not imposing restrictions on foreign exchange. In addition, the Swiss Supreme Court had ruled much earlier that, unless the customer specically authorized them to do otherwise, banks were under a binding obligation to preserve secrecy. Not surprisingly, many wealthy families moved their assets to Swiss banks. Around that time the Swiss began experimenting with the idea of the offshore corporation, drawing on the experience of the United States.51 A number of Swiss cantons, emulating Delaware and New Jersey, competed with one another by deliberately writing their company codes to allow incorporation of as many rms as possible under their statutes. Swiss lawyers created corporations, directed by dummy Swiss directors, whose shares were held by second personal holding companies, with the identity of their owners kept secret under the Swiss banking secrecy laws. In this way, the Swiss created companies that under international law were deemed to be completely Swiss and therefore protected by Swiss and international law, but whose assets were located in foreign countries. Threatened by the depression of 1929 and in particular by the series of bankruptcies in Austria and Germany in the early 1930s, the Swiss nancial industry managed to persuade Swiss authorities to adopt the stricter principles of bank secrecy. In an amendment to the Swiss Banking Law of 1934, for the rst time in
Schmitthoff 1954, 384. Picciotto 1992, 8. Robinson 1995, 133. Ibid., 133. Fehrenbach 1966, 49. See ibid., chap. 3; and Faith 1982.
history the principle of bank secrecy was put under the ofcial protection of the penal law.52 It became a criminal offense for bank ofcials to divulge any information regarding a customers identity, even to the Swiss, and the protection was extended to foreign nationals as well. Many countries viewed the Swiss interpretation of the law as a direct act of aggression. In fact, in some countriessuch as Spain owners of Swiss corporations could be jailed.53 The United States, in particular, sought to resist the Swiss. This meant that the United States had to contemplate either going to war or engaging in a trade war with the Swiss government over divergent interpretations of the principle of sovereignty. The problem was exacerbated by other countries following Switzerlands example. Such time-honored tax havens as the Bahamas, Liechtenstein, and Montevideo soon devised their own bank secrecy laws. (In most of these instances, a new center emerged, feeding off the collapse of a previous onefor example, Beiruts taking business from Haifa and the Bahamas from Cuba. A steady supply of bank deposits found its way to these havens from peopleincluding criminals, money launderers, and tax evaderswho for one reason or another sought to evade inspection in their own country. Swiss laws became the benchmark, and any newcomer had to up the ante. While the Swiss invented the numbered account, insisting that at least two bank ofcials should know the identity of an account holder, Luxembourg took the idea a step further by insisting that only one bank ofcial should know the identity of an account holder. Austria then took the principle to its logical conclusion: According to Austrian banking law, no one needed to know the identity of an account holder. Consequently, as other countries followed suit, the struggle to restrict it became far too difcult to pursue. Even if Switzerland had relented and changed its basic laws, there would still have been sixty-eight other tax havens to deal with. In the end, the United States abandoned the struggle and joined the ranks of offshore jurisdictions by creating its own international banking facilities. The inauspicious, eclectic beginning of the modern system of tax havens is not only a historical curiosity; it also alerts us to an important distinction between the origins of the modern tax havens strategy and the later diffusion and growth of the phenomenon. Although its development is naturally of great interest to nancial regulators, its origins are what international relations scholars nd interesting, not least because of the importance attached to a system of states, particularly a system of sovereign states that appears to have encouraged the experimentation and innovation in state laws that produced the tax havens strategy.
Here we come to the crux of the matter: International tax planning exploits loopholes that allow individuals and companies to shift residence without actually moving. Fictional or mere juridical relocation is the common denominator that turns diverse practicessuch as the incorporation laws of New Jersey and Delaware, the bank secrecy laws of Switzerland, and the tax haven laws of Britaininto a viable development strategy. In the rest of this article I uncover the roots of ctional relocation, the mystery tool that has facilitated the conversion of sovereign rights into a marketable product. I show that this phenomenon was emerging toward the end of the nineteenth century at the same time that embryonic forms of offshore locations were emerging, and that the two developments are connected.57
government was a nality of decision on all issues arising within his realm, but, he continues, insulation of the nation-state in the matter of law enforcement is a very different thing from insulation as respects law itself.60 The difference is subtle but important. Sovereigns certainly claimed a right to nality of decision on issues arising within their territorial realms, but formal adherence to the principles of natural law can be construed as limiting the purview of sovereignty. Only with the decline of natural law were the last vestiges of transnational ethical morality removed and the states fully insulated from each other in law. Historians agree, therefore, that the insulation of the state with respect to the law was accomplished only during the nineteenth century. Only then did sovereignty begin to express the exclusive, unique institutionalized and strictly public dominance over a territorial national ensemble and the effective exercise of central power without the extra-political restrictions of juridical or moral order which characterized the feudal state.61 In fact, writes Frederik M. Van Asbeck, since the nineteenth century we have been confronted with a new historical situation, viz., the existence side by side of isolated States, between which there is no moral or spiritual bond.62 Only during this period did the sovereign people come to be viewed as the ultimate source of rights and duties and hence of the law, as the state effectively nationalized the rule of contracts.63 Increasing insulation of the state in law found expression in legal theory through the rise of positive international law,64 a doctrine that maintained that the practice of government, rather than theories about it, is the source of international law. Originally the function of positive law was to attach penalties to violations of natural law, and by doing this, to remove arbitrariness from authority.65 But positive law in the nineteenth century gave the state ultimate authority. Institutions do not exist in isolation: They interact with other institutions. The rising fortunes of positive international law parallel the increasing acceptance of the doctrine of popular sovereignty rst promulgated by the Fronde movement in France in the eighteenth century.66 The theory of popular sovereignty changed the degree to which sovereignty was seen to imply exclusiveness, suggesting that once a nation-state is formed . . . a natural organic whole has come into existence, which seems to function as a closed actor.67 The analytical consistency between the idea
60. Cole 1948, 17 (emphasis added). The prince became the beholder of the moral fabric of his subjects, and as a result states laws broached areas such as blasphemy, homosexuality, witchcraft, and just price. Sovereignty therefore had ideologicallegal implications to the extent that it legitimized a certain order in terms that were explicable in ancient doctrines of justice and morality. 61. Poulantzas 1973, 162. 62. Van Asbeck 1976, 190. 63. Medwig 1992. 64. Positive international law can be traced back to Wolff and Vattel in the middle of the eighteenth century, but the principles became accepted only in the nineteenth century. For discussion, see Neff 1990. 65. Sabine and Shephard 1922, xxiii. 66. The idea of the nation was already found in the parliament of the Fronde, which Louis XVI rejected so vehemently in the parliament of Paris, 3 March 1766. 67. De Wilde 1991, 33.
of the nation (idea in the Kantian sense) and the institutions of positive international law and popular sovereignty is well established and needs no discussion here.68 It suggests, however, that the conict between the ideals of liberalism and positive international law cannot be reduced to a failure on the part of international lawyersas Neff believes but must be seen in historical or structural terms. Ideas about the functional necessity of insulating states from each other for the purpose of self-governance, still implicit in the late eighteenth century, became explicit in the early years of the nineteenth century as the concept of exclusivity vis-a ` -vis the Church, the nobility, and the Holy Roman Empire was replaced by the concept of exclusivity in the affairs of states in relation to each other. These principles, carved out in the midst of what was, in effect, a trans-societal space of economy and society,69 were then expressed materially in the formation of stricter forms of state bordersas replacements for the more amorphous types of frontiers that had constituted the boundaries between states. In other words, theories of national exclusiveness did not remain of purely abstract or academic interest but informed the practice of states. Consequently, parallel to states monopolizing the means of violence and representation, by the early nineteenth century some were beginning to adopt the principles of totality and exclusivity by physically demarcating their borders.70 On this historians agree. During the early nineteenth century European states began in earnest to dene and guard their territories and to control and regulate their populations.71 Over much of Europe, writes Sidney Pollard, frontiers gelled into economically meaningful barriers.72 Remnants of extra-territorial jurisdiction principles that had survived into the early nineteenth century were swept aside.73 Not only were boundaries established between one state and another, but also a clear distinction was created between national and international spaces in international law.74 Similarly, by the early nineteenth century nations were recognizing the principle that other nations could grant nationality and ags to ships.75 The origins of domicile laws can be traced to the late nineteenth century.76
68. Schnapper 1998. 69. Bienkowski 1981. 70. Robe 1997. 71. Murty comments that very few boundaries of state prior to the nineteenth century were either formalized or determined. He concedes that many European frontiers can trace their origins to the medieval period. Murty 1978, 33. 72. Pollard 1981, 253. 73. Liu describes ve different methods of the transfer of jurisdiction, or what Robe calls the nationalization of law. See Liu 1925; and Robe 1997. Similarly, Medwig notes, however, that starting in the sixteenth century, national governments began to regard the autonomous law merchant as an emptying target for nationalization. The law merchant was incorporated into the national court systems, [and] the processes continued during the eighteenth, nineteenth, and twentieth centuries. Medwig 1992, 593. 74. Kish 1973. 75. Carlisle 1981, 154. 76. Graveson 1977, 160.
The shift to clearly demarcated boundaries required an increasingly rigid interpretation of the relationship between sovereignty and territoriality as well as a new conception of the sovereign space.77 But as states demarcate their territories with greater rigor, they encountered a series of technical obstacles. For reasons partly to do with technology and later with the deterioration of the colonial empires, and in parallel with the extension of the law of the seas into space, the historical context by which boundaries were established had to evolve pragmatically as countries sought to demarcate their boundaries more strictly. The principles enshrined in the law of the seas served as the model for demarcating boundaries of sovereignty: The power of the land ends where the power of arms ends was the motto.78 However, technology in particular posed new challenges to the discrete concept of the national space. As states claimed new territories, the danger of conagrations due to the lack of clear boundaries was rising. From foreign invasion to satellite communications, the defense of national space raised a practical question: What is the precise boundary of the national space? As technology has increasingly become detached from physical constraints, the conception of the national space has been extended to dene intangible boundaries or shores.79 Stricter boundaries founded on the principles of positivist international law engendered tensions that began to manifest in earnest in the late nineteenth century in four key jurisdictional areas: (1) the treatment of aliensmore specically, guarantees that contracts signed in one country would be binding in another; (2) conicts between the principles of absolute sovereignty and taxation; (3) the difculty of identifying the scal location of intangible commodities (witnessed today in software and services); and (4) the possibility of one states rules and regulation eroding anothers sovereignty.80 These tensions exercised some of the best legal minds of the era, and jurists solutions were not straightforward. Considerable evidence indicates that in some areas of the law these tensions eroded the insulation of national territory in law. This is particularly true in the case of human rights and the limited acceptance of individuals as subjects of international law.81 Yet the process has also had the seemingly paradoxical effect of creating juridical boundaries that were ctional three-dimensional national cages of sovereignty. A states sovereign territory extended laterally into the seas to the length of the ight of a cannon ball, or three nautical miles, and was later extended to twelve miles. This twelve-mile zone became the norm in the early nineteenth century82 and generated internationally accepted horizontal lines separating one state from another. When hot air balloons and eventually aircraft began to ll the skies, national boundaries were extended
77. Liverani 1990. 78. Bynkershoek 1702 as quoted in Kish 1973, 6. 79. Palan 1998. 80. Neale and Stephens 1988, chap. 1. 81. See Van Asbeck 1976; and Cutler 1997. 82. Prescott 1975, 37. Not until 1930 did an international conference held at The Hague universalize this into the law of the seas.
vertically into the so-called von Ka rma n line of 50.55 miles. The principle also applied to the entire subsoil of national land territory, to the center of the earth.83 Faced with the problems of moving intangible goods, states relied on these same principles to extend their boundaries into imaginary spaces, that is, to extend the national cage into the purely juridical dimension. We see this rst with regard to patent laws, then with the introduction of passports and passport controls during World War I, and then with the delimitation of intangible forms of property rights.
83. Kish 1973. 84. This took place in the 1880s (although most companies waited until the end of World War I for expansion). Chandler 1990, 157 61. 85. See Picciotto 1992; and Neff 1990. 86. Jenks 1958, 29. 87. Nussbaum 1962, 203.
protection from discriminatory treatment in taxation and similar imposts, free access to courts, freedom of ownership, and exemption from military service.88 Many of these treaties were supported by stock clauses, such as the national treatment clause that promised the nationals of another country the same rights, in certain respects, as those enjoyed by the nationals of the promising country. Some treaties were signed for mutual assistance in the enforcement of the law among governments and among courts of civilized nations.89 The most important one, perhaps, was the treaty establishing uniform principles in the choice of lawthat is, that each contract must specify its location for jurisdictional purposes. In addition to the layers of municipal laws and bilateral treaties, states allowed companies to develop their own law. Jean-Phillipe Robe notes that as state lawyers have found great difculty in agreeing and formulating amongst themselves rules which apply to international commerce they preferred to leave the initiative to traders themselves.90 This allowed the growth of a hotly disputed branch of private international law: the lex mercatoria, or law merchanta branch of law that traces its origins to medieval times and already was being used as the basis for the treatment of consular representatives.91
In extending its protective laws to foreigners, the Swiss government, in effect, followed the British example and extended the notion of territoriality into a fourth juridical dimension. At the same time, the Swiss banking laws of 1934 denied any sovereign claims over foreign accounts by their real countries of residence. The Swiss government instead claimed a sovereign privilege to write its own laws. In so doing, the Swiss in effect legislated that individuals can be separated from their money: Account holders could reside in one location and, for all intents and purposes, be under the sovereignty of that location; but their money, when deposited in a Swiss bank in Switzerland, was deemed to be under Swiss sovereignty. It was, of course, entirely in accordance with the principles of territorial sovereignty for the Swiss government to devise laws that (1) extend the courtesy, as Paul Fehrenbach puts it, and provide foreigners with the same protection Swiss citizens were enjoying in Swiss courts, and (2) as a consequence, protect those foreigners from their own governments sovereign claims. Now, if we probe deeper into the Swiss law of 1934, we notice that the Swiss government proposed to resolve the tension between the insulation of the state in law and the internationalization of capital by questioning the legal unity of the subject in law. Individuals, as citizens or as corporate entities, could reside in one capacity in one jurisdiction and in another capacity in another jurisdiction. And since real, living individuals cannot spread themselves physically over different jurisdictions, they were offered ctional or juridical location in Switzerland. To resolve the taxation difculties posed by the activities of the multinational enterprises, the British state proceeded similarly: A series of court rulings from 1880 onward allowed for the division of the legal unity of enterprises. These enterprises could be incorporated in the United Kingdom but reside elsewhere. The U.K. courts insisted on evidence for real residence of companies as opposed to ctional residence. Other states, which were not as concerned with material evidence of corporate activity, used the same principle as mere bait by which they were able to sell companies off the shelf to any interested party. Because of the discrete nature of insulated national laws, the multinational enterprises do not exist in law. As Robe argues, de jure, the multinational enterprise, as differentiated from the corporation, does not exist in law!92 Yitzhak Hadari substantiates the argument, noting that the MNE [multinational enterprise] is a business and economic creature, and the usage of that term is presently found only in those elds. Properly viewed the MNE is not a single legal entity, but rather a group of corporations throughout the world sharing a single underlying economic unity.93 The patchwork of international as opposed to truly global law creates what Robert Johns calls the potential for government-induced frictions and factor immobility.94 But far from being a hindrance, the separation of the enterprise into distinct legal entities enables corporations to achieve greater efciency. It can
92. Robe 1997. 93. Hadari 1973, 754. For a similar view, see Robe 1997. 94. Johns 1983, 2.
provide a convenient vehicle through which a single group can manage much different business.95 Thus, the greatest challenge to state sovereignty comes from organizations which have no existence in law! . . . Although the economic or political reality of the existence of enterprises such as IBM, Toyota, Elf Aquitaine, and the like is not questioned by anyone, the enterprises themselves do not exist as such in positive law.96 Although Robe uses language too strong for most jurists, there is broad agreement that the legal status of the multinational enterprise is ambiguous. There are certainly ways and means by which different legal systems have sought to clarify their positions with regard to the nationality of corporations, not only for the purpose of taxation but also for diplomatic protection and inclusion in bilateral and multilateral treaties.97 More specically, in most countries income tax statutes contain specic provisions under which tax authorities may fully or partially disregard the separate existence of a corporation in a multicorporate structure, if this is necessary, in order to prevent tax avoidance or tax evasion. Courts also try to distinguish between real corporations and sham corporations.98 Nonetheless, the variations among different statutes and interpretations, including the marked difference between Anglo-Saxon and continental laws, muddy the waters considerably.99 Combined with the proliferation of tax havens and the practice of treaty shopping, the multinational enterprises have managed to obtain considerable freedom from national laws. The dissection of sovereignties would reach absurd proportion. In 1953, in Lauritzan v. Larsen, the U.S. Supreme Court determined an issue of the jurisdiction of foreign-registered ships by postulating the possibility of seven jurisdictions: the place of the wrongful act, the law of the ag, the allegiance or domicile of the injured party, the allegiance of the ship owners, the place of contract, the accessibility of the foreign forum, and the law of the forum.100 The denial of the legal unity of corporate personality makes perfect sense from the perspective of national sovereignty, sovereign equality, and national self-determination, but it has created huge problems for the regulatory capacity of the state. Under the circumstances of the growing insulation of the state in law and the internationalization of capital, it was logical to extend the same principle of demarcation into a new imaginary analytical space in which foreigners were presumed to reside in some capacity within the territorial boundaries of one state and in another capacity in another state. Furthermore, each state developed its own principles of demarcation.
95. Hadari 1973, 758. 96. Robe 1997, 52 (emphasis added). 97. In particular, there is international disagreement over the scope of U.S. state taxation of multinational enterprises, as a number of U.S. statesin particular, California use the worldwidecombined reporting standard for calculating local taxable income of multinational enterprises. Devgun 1995. 98. Hadari 1973. 99. Leben 1980. 100. Carlisle 1981, 160.
There was a price to pay for dividing the legal subject in law in order to accommodate a stricter notion of territorial demarcation and thus upholding and even strengthening the ction of the discrete juridical unity of the sovereign state. The scal subject was divided: In the ctional world of sovereign equality, its activities were placed under various jurisdictions, each representing a spatioanalytical (for want of a better term) territory. But while the scal subject was divided and was denied full legal unity, the real subjectwhether corporate or individualremained whole. With the complicity of a growing number of governments, these juridically dispersed subjects have learned to take advantage of the ction of their fragmentation by rearranging their legal existence in ways they see t. Since individuals and corporations were given the opportunity to spread themselves into different localities, they understandably went shopping for those localities that offered them what they considered to be the best arrangements. The ambiguity of the law, and the diverging and insecure interpretations of legal and scal jurisdictions ensured, however, that for the sake of prudence many corporations avoided the more scandalous tax havens. But the practice of jurisdiction shopping or commercialized sovereignty has spread. This is the true meaning of the term international tax planning; it is the planning of whichever aspect of their reality corporations or wealthy individuals are prepared to reveal at whichever location.
Conclusion
To resolve the two conicting aimsinsulation of the state in law in times of increasing internationalization of capitalstates were forced, somewhat reluctantly, to accept the principle that legal persons could reside concomitantly in a number of jurisdictions. Once these legal persons could reside in different locations, there was always the risk that they would go shopping for the best bundles of regulation they could nd. The commercialization of state sovereignty perfected by tax havens (though not exclusively) is founded therefore on an absurdity on the denial of the legal unity of the multinational enterprise. In employing sovereign rights as commercial assets, however, tax havens perform an important if controversial act: They demonstrate clearly the manner by which the modern state system not only accommodates globalization but also produces in subtle ways the infrastructure of globalization. In prostituting their sovereign rights, tax havens provide important legal platforms for globalizing nancial and, increasingly, other types of services. Thus, a virtual world of a state system can exist beside the real state system, feeding on its juridical and political infrastructure. The two are not adversarial; they merely present the complex face of the processes we call globalization. This nding underlies my contention that the tax havens strategy and the commercialization of state sovereignty are endemic to the modern state system. What would happen if, say, tomorrow the group of advanced industrialized countries, the G-7, announced that companies or individuals doing business in tax havens were no
longer allowed to operate in G-7 territories? The G-7 would have to pronounce on a whole sort of technical matters that is, the threshold of corporate and individual tax beneath which a state would be considered a tax haven, the kind of tax holidays or deferments that would be allowed and in which conditions, and so on. But for the sake of argument let us agree that the G-7 countries are willing and able to resolve these technical issues. The result of their action would be nothing less than the creation of a two-layered or even a multilayered system of sovereignties, because the G-7 countries would use their power to effect a change in the laws of tax havens or alternatively would legislate that residency of corporations in some countries is not equal to residency in others. De facto, such a system would signal the end of the principle of national self-determination and sovereign equality. This argument leads me to a controversial conclusion: Tax havens cannot simply be legislated away, because they are not perversions of the principle of sovereignty as much as they are a direct outcome of the conicting principles of national sovereignty in the age of mobile capital. Consequently, any serious attempt to combat the tax havens phenomenon would have to be conducted at a multilateral level, and would have great implications for the modern doctrine of sovereignty. The abolition of tax havens would require a degree of cooperation among the major industrialized countries and a limit on the sovereign rights of states, which effectively would spell the end of the so-called Westphalian system.
References
Aliber, Robert Z. 1976. The International Money Game. 2d ed. London: MacMillan. Auster, Richard D., and Morris Silver. 1979. The State as a Firm: Economic Forces in Political Development. Boston: Martin Nijhoff. Banoff, Sheldon I., and Burton W. Kanter. 1994. States Compete to Save Taxes Owed to Other States. Journal of Taxation 80 (3):382 84. Barber, Hoyt L. 1993. Tax Havens: How to Bank, Invest, and Do BusinessOffshore and Tax Free. New York: McGraw-Hill. Becker, Helmut, and Felix J. Wurm, eds. 1988. Treaty Shopping: An Emerging Tax Issue and Its Present Status in Various Countries. Dordrecht: Kluwer Law and Taxation. Bienkowski, Wladyslav. 1981. Theory and Reality: Development of Social Systems. London: Allison and Busby. Blum, Richard H. 1984. Offshore Haven Banks, Trusts, and Companies: The Business of Crime in the Euromarket. New York: Praeger. Blum, Richard, and John Kaplan. 1979. Offshore Banking Issue with Respect to Criminal Use. Paper prepared for the Ford Foundation, November. Born, Gary B. 1992. A Reappraisal of Extraterritorial Reach of U.S. Law. Law and Policy in International Business 24 (1):1100. Carlisle, Rodney. 1981. Sovereignty for Sale: The Origins and Evolution of the Panamanian and Liberian Flags of Convenience. Annapolis, Md.: Naval Institute Press. Cassard, Marcel. 1994. The Role of Offshore Centers in International Financial Intermediation. IMF Working Paper WP/94/107. Washington, D.C.: IMF. Chandler, Alfred D. 1990. Scale and Scope: The Dynamics of Industrial Capitalism. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press. Charny, David. 1991. Competition Among Jurisdictions in Formulating Corporate Law Rules: An American Perspective on the Race to the Bottom in the European Communities. Harvard International Law Journal 32 (2):42356.
Chavagneux, Christian, and Ronen Palan. 1999. Qui a Besoin des Paradis Fiscaux? Le conomy Politique 4 (4):14 44. Cole, Kenneth C. 1948. The Theory of the State as a Sovereign Juristic Person. American Political Science Review 42 (1):16 31. Conard, Alfred F. 1973. An Overview of the Laws of Corporations. Michigan Law Review 71 (4):62190. Cutler, Claire A. 1997. Artice, Ideology, and Paradox: The Public/Private Distinction in International Law. Review of International Political Economy 4 (2):261 85. De Wilde, Jaap. 1991. Saved from Oblivion: Interdependence Theory in the First Half of the 20th Century: A Study of the Causality Between War and Complex Interdependence. Aldershot: Dartmouth. Devgun, Derek. 1995. International Fiscal Wars for the Twenty-rst Century: An Assessment of Tax-Based Trade Retaliation. Law and Policy in International Business 27 (2):353 421. Diamond, Walter H., and Dorothy B. Diamond. 1998. Tax Havens of the World. New York: Matthew Bender Books. Doggart, Caroline. 1997. Tax Havens and Their Uses. London: EIU. Fabri, David, and Godfrey Baldacchino. 1999. The Malta Financial Services Centre: A Study in MicroState Dependency Management. In Offshore Finance Centers and Tax Havens, edited by Mark P. Hampton and Jason P. Abbott, 140 65. Basingstoke: Macmillan. Faith, Nicholas. 1982. Safety in Numbers: the Mysterious World of Swiss Banking. New York: Viking Press. Fehrenbach, T. R. 1966. The Gnomes of Zurich. London: Leslie Frewin. Figleton, Paul. 1989. Treasure Islands. Euromoney (May):14 25. Special supplement. Financial Stability Forum. 2000. Report of the Working Group on Offshore Centers. Available at www.fsforum.org/Reports/RepOFC.pdf. Accessed April 5. Gilmore, W. C., ed. 1992. International Efforts to Combat Money Laundering. Cambridge: Grotius Publications. Ginsburg, Anthony Saneld. 1991. Tax Havens. New York: New York Institute of Finance. Gordon, Richard A. 1981. Tax Havens and Their Use by United States Taxpayers: An Overview. Report to the Commissioner of Internal Revenue. Washington, D.C.: Books for Business. Graveson, R. H. 1977. Comparative Conict of Laws: Selected Essays, Vol. 1. Amsterdam: NorthHolland. Hadari, Yitzhak. 1973. The Structure of the Private Multinational Enterprise. Michigan Law Review 71 (4):729 806. Hampton, Mark. 1996. The Offshore Interface: Tax Havens in the Global Economy. Basingstoke: Macmillan. Hines, James R., Jr., and Eric M. Rice. 1994. Fiscal Paradise: Foreign Tax Havens and American Business. Quarterly Journal of Economics 109 (1):149 82. Hudson, Alan C. 1998. Reshaping the Regulatory Landscape: Border Skirmishes Around the Bahamas and Cayman Offshore Financial Centers. Review of International Political Economy 5 (3):534 64. Hufbauer, Gary Clyde. 1992. U.S. Taxation of International Income: Blueprint for Reform. Washington, D.C.: Institute for International Economics. Inland Revenue. 1999. Controlled Foreign Companies (CFCs)Designer Rate and Similar Regimes. Inland Revenue Press Release 165/99, 6 October. Jackson, Robert H., and Carl G. Rosberg. 1986. Sovereignty and Underdevelopment: Juridical Statehood in the African Crisis. Journal of Modern African Studies 24 (1):131. Jenks, C. Wilfred. 1958. The Common Law of Mankind. London: Stevens and Sons. Johns, Richard Anthony. 1983. Tax Havens and Offshore Finance: A Study of Transnational Economic Development. New York: St. Martins Press. Johns, Richard Anthony, and C. M. Le Marchant. 1993. Finance Centres: British Isle Offshore Development Since 1979. London: Pinter. Kish, John. 1973. The Law of International Spaces. Leiden: Sijthoff. Kochan, Nick. 1991. Cleaning Up by Cleaning Up. Euromoney (April):7377.
Larcom, Russell Carpenter. 1937. The Delaware Corporation. Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press. Leben, Charles. 1980. Une tentative de perception globale; le recourse a la nationalite des societes. In Lenterprise multinationale: face au droit, edited by Berthold Goldman and Phocion Francescakis, 12153. Paris: Librairies techniques. Lindholm, Richard W. 1944. The Corporate Franchise as a Basis of Taxation. Austin: University of Texas Press. Liu, Shih Shun. 1925. Extraterritoriality: Its Rise and Its Decline. New York: Columbia University Press. Liverani, Mario. 1990. Prestige and Interest: International Relations in the Near East circa 1600 1100 B.C. Padova: Sargon Sri. Marshall, Don D. 1996. Understanding Late-Twentieth-Century Capitalism: Reassessing the Globalization Theme. Government and Opposition 31 (2):193215. Medwig, Michael T. 1992. The New Law Merchant: Legal Rhetoric and Commercial Reality. Law and Policy in International Business 24 (2):589 616. Miller, Gary J. 1981. Cities by Contract: The Politics of Municipal Incorporation. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Montebourg, Arnaud. 2000. Rapport Dinformation De pose en Application de article 145 Du Re ` glement ` La Re Par La Mission Dinformation Commune Sur Les Obstacles Au Contro le et A pression De La De linquance Financie ` re et Du Blanchiment Des Capitaux en Europe (1) No. 2311, Assemble e ` La Pre Nationale, Onzie ` me Le gislature, Enregistre A sidence de Lassemble e Nationale le 30 Mars 2000, Tome 1 and 2. Murty, T. S. 1978. Frontiers: A Changing Concept. New Delhi: Palit and Palit. Musalem, Alberto, and Errico Luca. 1999. Offshore Banking: An Analysis of Micro- and MacroPrudential Issues. International Monetary Fund Working Paper WP/99/5. Washingon, D.C.: IMF. Naylor, R. T. 1987. Hot Money and the Politics of Debt. London: Unwin Hyman. Neale, A. D., and M. L. Stephens. 1988. International Business and National Jurisdiction. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Neff, Stephen C. 1990. Friends but No Allies: Economic Liberalism and the Law of Nations. New York: Columbia University Press. Nussbaum, Arthur. 1962. A Concise History of the Law of Nations. Rev. ed. New York: Macmillan. OECD. Committee on Fiscal Affairs. 1987. International Tax Avoidance and Evasion: Four Related Studies. Issues in International Taxation No. 1. Paris: OECD. Palan, Ronen. 1998. Trying to Have Your Cake and Eating It: How and Why the State System Has Created Offshore. International Studies Quarterly 42 (4):625 43. Palan, Ronen, and Jason Abbott, with Phil Deans. 1996. State Strategies in the Global Political Economy. London: Cassel. Park, Y. S. 1982. The Economics of Offshore Financial Centers. Columbia Journal of World Business 17 (4):3135. Picciotto, Sol. 1992. International Business Taxation. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson. Pollard, Sidney. 1981. Peaceful Conquest: The Industrialization of Europe 1760 1970. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Poulantzas, Nicos. 1973. Political Power and Social Classes. London: Sheed and Ward. Prescott, J. R. V. 1975. The Political Geography of the Oceans. New York: John Wiley. Ranke, Leopold. 1840. The Ecclesiastical and Political History of the Popes of Rome During the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries. 3 vols. London: John Murray. Robe , Jean-Phillipe. 1997. Multinational Enterprises: The Constitution of a Pluralistic Legal Order. In Global Law Without a State, edited by Gunther Teubner, 4577. Aldershot: Dartmouth. Roberts, Susan. 1994. Fictitious Capital, Fictitious Spaces: The Geography of Offshore Financial Flows. In Money Power and Space, edited by Stuart Corbridge, Nigel Thrift, and Ron Martin, 91115. Oxford: Blackwell. Robinson, Jeffrey. 1995. The Laundrymen: Inside Money Laundering, the Worlds Third Largest Business. London: Pocket Books.
Sabine, George H., and Walter J. Shephard. 1922. Translators Introduction. In The Modern Idea of the State by Hugo Krabbe, xilxxxi. London: Appleton and Co. Schmitthoff, Clive M. 1954. The English Conict of Laws. 3d ed. London: Stevens and Sons. Schnapper, Dominique. 1998. Community of Citizens: On the Modern Idea of Nationality. New Brunswick, N.J.: Transaction Publishers. Smith, Adolphe. 1912. Monaco and Monte Carlo. London: Grant Richards. Starchild, Adam. 1993. Tax Havens for International Business. Basingstoke: Macmillan. Tiebout, Charles M. 1956. A Pure Theory of Local Expenditures. Journal of Political Economy 64 (5):416 24 Van Asbeck, Frederik Mari. 1976. International Society in Search of a Transnational Legal Order. Leiden: Sijthoff.