MacLennan Elements of Consciousness and Neurodynamical Correlates
MacLennan Elements of Consciousness and Neurodynamical Correlates
MacLennan Elements of Consciousness and Neurodynamical Correlates
40924
THE ELEMENTS OF CONSCIOUSNESS AND THEIR NEURODYNAMICAL CORRELATES Bruce MacLennan,* Computer Science Department, University of Tennessee, Knoxville 37996, USA.
Abstract: The hard problem is hard because of the special epistemological status of consciousness, which does not, however, preclude its scientific investigation. Data from phenomenologically trained observers can be combined with neurological investigations to establish the relation between experience and neurodynamics. Although experience cannot be reduced to physical phenomena, parallel phenomenological and neurological analyses allow the structure of experience to be related to the structure of the brain. Such an analysis suggests a theoretical entity, an elementary unit of experience, the protophenomenon, which corresponds to an activity site (such as a synapse) in the brain. The structure of experience is determined by connections (e.g. dendrites) between these activity sites; the connections correspond to temporal patterns among the elementary units of experience, which can be expressed mathematically. This theoretical framework illuminates several issues, including degrees of consciousness, nonbiological consciousness, sensory inversions, unity of consciousness and the unconscious mind.
It should be apparent that I am using subjective and objective to distinguish private, first person phenomena from public, third person phenomena. As Searle (1992) observes, progress on the mindbody problem has been impeded by the connotations acquired by these terms, viz., the objective is unbiased and factual, whereas the subjective is biased or distorted. Indeed, I will argue for the possibility of unbiased, factual statements about subjective (private, first person) phenomena.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
410
B. MACLENNAN
its subjective and objective parts (felt vs. measured temperature), the objective part can be reduced to other objective phenomena (mean kinetic energy of molecules), but the subjective components of the original phenomenon remain unreduced. Although this approach has been very fruitful for the development of physical theory, it fails when the topic of the investigation is precisely that subjectivity that it ignores. In summary, the standard reduction pattern in science, which reduces the objective to the objective, cannot solve the hard problem, which deals with the relation between the subjective and the objective. If reduction is to play a role at all, it must take a different form. Finally, science traditionally seeks facts observations that are independent of the observer; this supposes that the observer can be separated from the observed (another aspect of the subjectobject distinction). However, in confronting the hard problem we cannot separate the observer and the observed, for consciousness is observation, the subject experiencing the object. That is, experience comprises both observer and observed, the termini of the vector of consciousness. Separating the two breaks the very connection that we aim to study.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
411
The camera analogy shows the importance of training, for the relevant phenomena, e.g. depth of field, might not be apparent to untutored observers. The difficulties with split-brain and blindsight patients as informants also illustrate the need for trained observers. I believe that the best example of the kind of training required comes from phenomenological philosophy and psychology (cf. Ihde, 1986). In summary, although consciousness cannot be reduced to physical phenomena by the standard reductive methods of the sciences, it can be investigated to yield publicly validatible facts about the structure of consciousness, which can be related, in turn, to the observations of neuroscience.
Phenomenology
Phenomenology studies the structure of phenomenal worlds, that is, the worlds actually experienced by individuals. Henceforth phenomenon will be used in a technical sense: a phenomenon is anything that appears in consciousness, anything we experience, no matter what its origin. For example, perceptions, recollections, dreams, pains (whether real or phantom), mental images, mental dialogues, moods, anticipations, desires and hallucinations are some of the kinds of phenomena. Further, your phenomenal world determines the structure of possible phenomena, and the state of your phenomenal world at a time is equivalent to the content of your consciousness at that time. That is, your phenomenal world is a structure of potential experiences; at any given time one of these is actualized as your conscious experience at that time. The phenomena are the starting point of all science, for they are what is given to us (cf. Latin data = given things).4 However, this is easily misunderstood for, at least since the appearance of logical positivism in the philosophy of science, there has been a tendency to suppose that the phenomena are simple things, such as sense data. Red-herenow, that is, the current experiencing of a patch of red at a particular location in the visual field, is a well-known example. The phenomenologists, especially Husserl and Heidegger, have demonstrated the incorrectness of this view, for rarely, if ever, do we actually experience red-here-now; they have revealed some of the complexity of real phenomena. Suppose, for example, you rotate an ordinary die in front of me and ask for a phenomenological account of what I see.5 I would be incorrect to describe a certain arrangement of black ellipses in white parallelograms, both of systematically changing shape. That does not accurately describe the phenomenon as I experience it, for I recognize the object and so it is seen as a die, and I see it rotating in space, not changing shape in some mysterious way. Even if I were unfamiliar with dice, I would see the rotation of a white cube marked with spots. Indeed, it would take very unusual conditions to make me see the die as parallelograms and ellipses changing shape. (Such a situation, a consequence of a brain tumor, is described by Oliver Sacks (1985) in the title essay of his The Man who Mistook his Wife for a Hat.) An additional complexity of phenomena is that they are not entirely in the here-andnow; for example, my current experience of the die includes some foreshadowing of future possible experiences.Thus we have expectations some vague and others precise in accord with our familiarity with dice about what we will see as the die is rotated. These expectations go beyond the visual; for example, we also have expectations about
4 This is true of the empirical sciences, but also of the so-called a priori sciences, such as mathematics, which start from the apparently invariable structure of the phenomenal world. 5 The die example derives from Husserls Cartesian Meditations, 1719, where it is developed at length.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
412
B. MACLENNAN
the hardness and weight of dice, and if we see two dice in an open palm, we have the expectation of some kind of dice game. All these and more are part of phenomenal field surrounding the visual perception of the die. Further, we see that much of the phenomenon is a construct, both of the culture and of individual experience. We must include expectation as part of our current conscious experience because, for example, we are in a different conscious state if we come to the pantry door expecting the shelves to be bare or come expecting them to be full.To the extent that the expectations contained in a phenomenon are met, we experience normality and familiarity; to the extent they are not, we experience dissonance and novelty. Phenomena appear gradually over the horizon of consciousness, and as they do so they actualize some, but not all, of the possibilities that may have been foreshadowed in the current state. This gradual actualization of foreshadowed phenomena creates the continuity of subjective time.6 In summary, phenomena are not simple; they are highly complex and strongly coupled to the rest of the phenomenal world in which they appear. Therefore some training is necessary to be able to observe phenomena accurately and to analyse the structure of the phenomenal world. Nevertheless I believe that phenomenological training of this kind provides a basis for making the characteristics (though not the experience) of consciousness public.7 Protophenomena
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
413
particular patch of skin, or a neuron in the visual cortex to light on a particular patch of the retina. In such a case we can identify the subjective experience corresponding to activity in this neuron, namely, the feeling of pressure in that patch of skin, or the sensation of light on that patch of retina. I call such an element of experience a phenomeniscon or protophenomenon.8 Further, we can see how, to a first approximation, the objective neurological processes corresponding to tactile or visual sensation can be reduced to a large number of receptive fields of this kind. This suggests phenomenological subjective-to-subjective reductions (phenomena to protophenomena) paralleling neurological objective-to-objective reductions (e.g. topographic maps to their neurons, and sensory surfaces of skin to receptive fields). This may seem to be a return to the red-here-now model of phenomena, but there are important differences. First, neurons have functional receptive fields that are more abstract than simple spatial patches. For example, primary visual cortex contains neurons whose receptive fields are four-dimensional combinations of retinal location, spatial orientation and spatial frequency (see MacLennan, 1991, for a survey). Indeed, Pribram (1991, pp. 7983) has stressed that they are not limited to these four dimensions, but respond to many additional dimensions of the stimulus. Next, as shown by the rotating-die example, there is much more to ordinary phenomena than the sense data, so we will have to take account of nonsensory protophenomena that represent the constituents of expectations, interpretations, intentions and many more abstract properties. Third, few neurons have simple fixed receptive fields, since even sensory neurons receive inputs from higher brain areas; therefore, virtually all protophenomena depend on other protophenomena. Finally, although I have used a simple sensation as an example, because its protophenomena are easy to visualize, sensation is only one aspect of most phenomena (many of which involve no sensation). The preceding model can be extended to nonsensory neurons as follows. The activity of a sensory neuron reflects the presence of a stimulus in its receptive field, which is a region of some (possibly abstract) physical space (pressure, light, sound, heat, space, frequency, orientation, etc.); it responds maximally to stimuli in that region. Similarly, the activity of a nonsensory neuron reflects the activities of other neurons, and so it has a functional receptive field, comprising certain patterns of activities of its input neurons, to which it responds. That is, as sensory neurons respond to combinations of physical energy, so nonsensory neurons respond to combinations of neural activity. Turning to the subjective side, we see that, as a sensory protophenomenon corresponds to the experience of the physical phenomena in a sensory neurons receptive field, so a nonsensory protophenomenon corresponds to the experience of combinations of other protophenomenal intensities, those intensities corresponding to activity in the nonsensory neurons functional receptive field.9
Definition of protophenomena
Chalmers (1995) has argued that a theory of consciousness requires the addition of something fundamental to our ontology and that where there is a fundamental property, there are fundamental laws. In this section I will propose protophenomena as a candidate
This is an approximate definition; protophenomena are described more precisely in the following sections. Phenomeniscon (accent on penult), a diminutive of phenomenon, is used in MacLennan (1995). I am grateful to David Chalmers for suggesting the alternative protophenomenon.
9 This description is simplified for the sake of exposition, since sensory neurons also respond to other neurons, and so their complete receptive field includes the activities of other neurons. Correspondingly, the subjective intensity of a sensory protophenomenon depends on the subjective intensities of other protophenomena as well as on the experience of objective physical processes. 8
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
414
B. MACLENNAN
for this something and describe fundamental laws governing them (analysed mathematically in MacLennan, 1996, Appendix). We have seen that activity in a neuron reflects the extent to which its functional receptive field is occupied at that point in time. Subjectively, this activity corresponds to the intensity in consciousness of a protophenomenon corresponding to the site of that activity. Therefore I hypothesize a one-to-one relationship between protophenomena and certain activity sites in the brain, and further hypothesize that the intensity of a protophenomenon varies directly with the neurological activity at that site. What are these activity sites? Following Sherrington, who said, Reflex action and mind seem almost mutually exclusive the more reflex the reflex, the less does mind accompany it, Pribram has argued that consciousness is associated with graded dendritic processes rather than all-or-nothing axonal spiking (Miller et al., 1960, pp. 234; Pribram, 1971, pp. 1045; Pribram, 1991, pp. 78). For concreteness I will accept this hypothesis and take synapses to be the activity sites (though the identification is not crucial to most of the following).10 Candidates for the activity of the synapse include presynaptic membrane potential, postsynaptic membrane potential and neurotransmitter flux across the synaptic cleft. Since for the most part each is proportional to the others, it doesnt matter much which we pick; for concreteness, Ill hypothesize postsynaptic membrane potential. The easiest way to understand protophenomena is to think of them as the atoms (indivisible constituents) of consciousness. As atoms make up macroscopic objects (trees, tables, etc.), so protophenomena make up phenomena. In both cases, the effect of each individual element on the whole is usually minute. Indeed, our phenomenal world comprises perhaps 1014 to 1015 protophenomena (i.e. the number of synapses in a human brain). Normally a change in the intensity of a single protophenomenon will not be perceived since it will not usually lead to a macroscopic change in conscious state, such as a judgement. Normally the intensity of a large number of prototphenomena must change in a coherent way for a phenomenon to appear in consciousness, that is, for there to be a macroscopic change in conscious state. On this view, the state of the phenomenal world, that is, the content of consciousness, is identical with the intensities of all the protophenomena. The appearance of coherent or stable phenomena can be identified with cohesive or coherent patterns of intensity among the protophenomena (just as macroscopic objects and events can be identified with cohesive and coherent patterns of activity among atoms).11
In particular, my proposal does not exclude the possibility that microtubules, as proposed by Hameroff (1994), are among the activity sites.
11 10
An interesting question is just how the intensities of protophenomena combine to form a conscious state. A recent analysis by Sanger (submitted) of activity in populations of neurons suggests an answer. The functional receptive field of a neuron is proportional to a conditional probability density field (CPDF), defined over possible stimuli, which determines the probability a given stimulus will cause the neuron to fire. (More precisely, it determines the rate of a Poisson firing process). Collectively, a population responding to a common set of inputs has a CPDF that is proportional to the (pointwise) product of the fields of the neurons firing at a given time. This analysis can be transferred to the phenomenal realm as follows. Each protophenomenon has an associated CPDF defined over the protophenomena upon which it depends (its inputs). (In fact, the conditional probability density of an input signal is proportional to the temporal convolution of that signal with the protophenomenons characteristic pattern, defined below, p. 9.) A population of protophenomena dependent on the same input protophenomena has a CPDF that is the product of the CPDFs of all the high-intensity input protophenomena, that is, of all the input protophenomena present in the current conscious state.The CPDFs of individual protophenomena can be quite broad, but in the joint response to the same input of a large number, the product can be very narrow, so that they define a phenomenal state quite precisely.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
415
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
416
B. MACLENNAN
in neural (or physiological) state. Denying this would permit conscious states unsupported by physical states, which would, it seems to me, undermine the whole project of reconciling conscious experience with the scientific world view, the raison dtre of the hard problem. Second, I hypothesize that differences in activity at activity sites imply differences in conscious experience. Here the reason is Occams Law, for we would otherwise have to suppose that some activity sites (e.g. synapses) have associated protophenomena while others dont. Although this may be the case, I see no evidence supporting it.13 In any case, this hypothesis is not necessary for the overall theory of protophenomena.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
417
Protophenomenal dependencies
Lets consider protophenomenal relations in more detail. Neurologically, the activity at a synapse is a complex spatiotemporal integration of the activities of the synapses which connect to it. To a first approximation this process is linear, and can be described by the methods of linear system analysis (MacLennan, 1993b), which shows there is a certain spatiotemporal pattern to which the synapse shows the maximum response. Indeed, this pattern can be used to characterize the temporal response of the synapse to any spatiotemporal signal, in so far as the synapse behaves linearly. For this reason I will call this maximum-response spatiotemporal pattern the characteristic pattern of the synapse.14 (Technically, the response of a synapse is a temporal convolution of its characteristic pattern with the input signal.) This account may be transferred directly to the phenomenal realm. Each protophenomenon has a characteristic pattern, which is the spatiotemporal pattern of intensities of its input protophenomena that will maximize its intensity. Further, its characteristic pattern determines (by convolution) the protophenomenons time-varying intensity in response to any spatiotemporal pattern in the intensities of the protophenomena on which it depends. As a consequence we can give a mathematical theory of the dynamical relations among protophenomena (see MacLennan, 1996, Appendix). The characteristic patterns may be simple, as when a protophenomenon corresponds to a conjunction or disjunction of protophenomena, or more complex, as when they respond to appearance or disappearance of protophenomena, rhythmic or other temporal patterns in protophenomena, priming or inhibition of future occurrences of protophenomena, etc. Each protophenomenon contributes its characteristic pattern to conscious experience, with its intensity at a given moment determining the degree of the patterns presence in that moments experience. That is, conscious experience is given by a dynamic superposition of the characteristic patterns of the protophenomena. Overall, the dynamical relations among protophenomena are nondeterministic. First consider a synapse formed by a sensory neuron, the activity of which depends on physical stimuli as well as on the activities of other synapses. Corresponding to this activity site in the phenomenal realm we have a protophenomenon whose intensity depends on physical processes as well as on other protophenomena. But physical processes are not part of the phenomenal world, so such a protophenomenon is phenomenologically undetermined (i.e. not fully determined by other protophenomena); the physical inputs act as independent variables in the phenomenal world. In terms of the ontology of the phenomenal world, they are causal primaries, which does not imply, however, that there are not corresponding phenomenal expectations (as the rotating-die example shows). Thus sensory protophenomena are inherently nondeterministic (i.e. undetermined in the phenomenal world). Since nonsensory protophenomena depend only on other protophenomena, to a first approximation they can be considered deterministic; indeed their responses are defined by their characteristic patterns. This is only an approximation because even nonsensory neurons depend on non-neural processes, such as the physiology of the brain, and the physical environment of the body. Although these effects can sometimes be treated as extra, hidden inputs to the synapses, they are often nonlinear and comparatively non-
In physics and engineering it is commonly called the impulse response of the system; it corresponds (via the Laplace transform) to the transfer function, which describes the system dynamics in terms of its transparency to different frequencies of activity.
14
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
418
B. MACLENNAN
specific in their effects, so it is usually better to treat them as phenomenologically undetermined alterations of the characteristic patterns of the affected protophenomena.15 I have described the protophenomenal dependencies from a mechanistic perspective; now it is worthwhile to say a few words from a functional perspective. Topographic maps show us how receptive fields are ordered in space, frequency, speed, colour and many other dimensions, and hence how their protophenomena are ordered in corresponding subjective domains. Thus dependencies among protophenomena correspond to order in a variety of dimensions. This order means that objects extended in space or other dimensions will lead to high intensities among closely dependent protophenomena (which will therefore cohere as full-fledged phenomena). Furthermore, since change is generally continuous, or if discontinuous in some dimensions, then continuous in others, it follows that changing objects tend to move from the receptive fields they occupy to others that overlap along one or more dimensions. Think of a visual image of a moving object: it moves between overlapping spatial receptive fields; further, its edges change orientation continuously, and the light it reflects changes continuously, and so it also moves gradually from receptive field to receptive field in these dimensions. Phenomenologically, we can say that change tends to be between protophenomena that are strongly connected. Conversely, the presence (high intensity) of a protophenomenon is correlated with the future presence of the other protophenomena that depend on it. In approximate terms, the dependencies among protophenomena correspond to the likelihood (or unlikelihood) of change between protophenomena. More accurately, the characteristic pattern of a protophenomenon represents likely (excitatory) or unlikely (inhibitory) antecedent spatiotemporal patterns of protophenomena.
Phenomenological plasticity
I have treated the phenomenal world, the structure of possible conscious states, as fixed, but it is now time to say a few words about plasticity.16 One type of plasticity is short- or long-term change in synaptic efficacy as a result of learning or habituation, which changes the strength of the dependencies between protophenomena, or, more accurately, changes the characteristic patterns that define their time-varying intensity. These changes affect the topology (the abstract relations of near and far) and the protophenomenal dependencies of the phenomenal world. These changes, in turn, affect coherence and cohesion among protophenomena, and thus the emergence of coherent, high-level phenomena. Second, although the adult brain does not generate new neurons, it does generate new synapses for a number of reasons, including injury and learning (Shepherd, 1994, pp. 2223). Since I have hypothesized that protophenomena correspond one-to-one with synapses, the generation of new synapses implies the generation of new protophenomena, that is, new degrees of freedom in the phenomenal world literally, expanded consciousness. Thus we see that the phenomenal world has a flexible ontology at both the macroscopic (phenomenal) and microscopic (protophenomenal) levels.
15 Thus there may be phenomenologically causeless change to the phenomenal world; an extreme example is a stroke. The view advocated here might be seen as either epiphenomenalism or parallelism, but it is not; rather, it is dual-aspect monism. That is, causal relations in the phenomenal world parallel causal relations in the physical world, but, just as the phenomenal and physical worlds are alternative perspectives on one reality, so also phenomenal causation and physical causation are two alternative and equally valid descriptions of the constraints on the evolution of events in this reality. We can switch between the two kinds of causation as convenient for the problem at hand. There can be no contradiction between the phenomenological and physical accounts because they are both bound to conform to the same reality. 16
My concern here is not so much plasticity in the developing animal as plasticity in the adult.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
419
I will consider briefly the implications of this theory for several issues pertaining to consciousness.
Degrees of consciousness
By hypothesis the degrees of freedom of a phenomenal world correspond to the protophenomena it comprises, which are equal in number to the activity sites in the nervous system; further, the structural relations of the phenomenal world correspond to the connections between activity sites. Therefore, with decreasing nervous system complexity we expect a proportional decrease in both the dimension and structure of the corresponding phenomenal world. The conclusion to be drawn is that consciousness is a matter of degree; in general terms we can say that the consciousness of simpler animals is less than ours in both dimension and structure.17
Nonbiological consciousness
Ill consider briefly whether the theory of protophenomena sheds any light on the perennial question of computer consciousness. From the perspective of the theory, the central question is: what sorts of physical processes have associated protophenomena, and how could we tell? For example, liquidity follows from certain physical properties of H2O molecules, but other substances besides water may be liquid because they share these properties. Analogously, consciousness follows from certain physical properties of synapses, but other things besides brains may be conscious if their parts share these properties. Thus we need to determine sufficient conditions for the existence of protophenomena, that is, the properties of synapses (or whatever the activity sites may be) that cause them to have protophenomena. It is possible, at least in principle, to attack this problem empirically. We would have to identify some observable protophenomenon, the presence or absence (high or low intensity) of which can be reported reliably by a trained observer, and for which the corresponding synapse (or other activity site) can be identified and made accessible (e.g. through brain surgery). With care we may control some of the variables (e.g. postsynaptic potential) independently of the others (e.g. presynaptic potential), and thus determine which affect protophenomenal intensity. Indeed, one could replace the synapse by devices that are functionally equivalent in one way or another (e.g. electrically or chemically), to determine which are necessary or sufficient for the existence of the protophenomenon. It will be objected that the investigation depends on subject report, which is a form of behaviour, and therefore need not reflect subjective experience. That is correct. Since subjectivity is private, the only way such doubts can be eliminated is for the doubter to be the subject of the experiment.18 Practically, though, the observations would become public through a consensus of trained observers of differing commitments.
17 Chalmers (1995) tentatively reaches the same conclusion on the basis of his double-aspect principle. Also, from the probabilistic perspective, for a given sensory bandwidth, the conditional probability density fields associated with the protophenomena of a simpler nervous system less sharply delimit the input phenomena; thus, for simpler nervous systems, perceptual experience is less definite. 18 If this seems far-fetched, it is worth noting that William McDougall requested, if he should become incurably ill, that Sherrington would perform a cerebral commissurotomy (split-brain operation) on him, so that he might directly experience its effect on his consciousness (Gregory, 1987, p. 741).
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
420
B. MACLENNAN
From such a demonstration of protophenomena associated with nonsynaptic or even nonbiological objects we could reasonably conclude that a phenomenal world, and therefore consciousness, would emerge from sufficiently complex interconnections of those objects. Indeed, my guess is that we will find that the representational and information processing properties of synapses are all that matters, and that other physical systems with the same capabilities (such as appropriately structured massively parallel analogue computers) will have protophenomena and be conscious.19
Unity of consciousness
A phenomenal world derives its structure from the dependencies between protophenomena, which correspond to connections between activity sites; thus the unity of a
19 It will be apparent from this that I do not accept Searles reply to the Virtual Minds version of the System Reply to the Chinese Room Argument (MacLennan, 1993a, 1994). See also the thought experiment in Chalmers (1995). 20 Thus I disagree with Chalmers (1995) when he asserts, There are properties of experience, such as the intrinsic nature of the sensation of red, that cannot be fully captured in a structural description. I will argue that the experience is exhausted by its structure.
The analysis here addresses pitch inversions rather than colour inversions, since colour vision is considerably more complex than hearing. Nevertheless, I am confident that a similar analysis will show the impossibility of a colour inversion.
21
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
421
phenomenal world is a consequence of this connectivity. We see this in split-brain operations (cerebral commissurotomy), wherein severing the corpus collosum causes a split in consciousness: each hemisphere is unconscious of what the other is experiencing (Gregory, 1987, pp. 7407). However, it is significant that these operations do not completely separate the hemispheres; at very least the brainstem is left intact. Therefore the protophenomena corresponding to the two hemispheres are not completely independent, and so the phenomenal world has separated into two loosely-coupled subworlds. An analogy may clarify this. A picture is an emergent effect of its individual pixels and their relative positions. If we cut a picture in half, it becomes two pictures, because there is no longer a fixed relations between pixels in one half and those in the other. However, instead of cutting the picture, we may gradually separate it into two parts, pixel by pixel, by stretching and eventually breaking the connections between them. The gradual uncoupling of the pixels in the two halves causes the picture to change gradually from one to two. So also, consciousness is emergent from the individual protophenomena and the dependencies between them. As the neural connections are weakened or broken, the protophenomena in the two subworlds decouple from each other, and the one mind becomes two. This thought experiment demonstrates that the unity of consciousness is a matter of degree. Indeed, in principle we can measure the unity of consciousness by the tightness of the coupling between its protophenomena, for it is this coupling that gives the phenomenal world its coherence. (The tightness of coupling can, in principle, be calculated from the characteristic patterns; it can be quantified in terms of mutual information.) One may wonder what sort of coupling is sufficient to unify consciousness. For example, in split-brain patients it has been observed that one hemisphere may communicate with the other through transactions with the external world, for example, twitching the skin on one side of the face so that it can be felt on the other. (The patient is unconscious of doing this.) Can external transactions such as these effect the coupling of protophenomena? If so, then our individual phenomenal worlds may not be so independent as we commonly suppose, for any sort of communication couples protophenomena in one mind to those in another. I think the answer is, again, a matter of degree. There is an enormous difference between the bandwidth of the corpus collosum (approximately 800 million nerve fibres) and the narrow bandwidth of most external media. Nevertheless, the interconnection of phenomenal worlds by non-neural physical processes is a thought-provoking possibility.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
422
B. MACLENNAN
An analogy may clarify this. Project a slide on a screen, and defocus the lens. All of the same information is being projected on the screen as before, but now it is incoherent and the pattern is not salient; this is analogous to unconscious patterns in the protophenomena: they are there but not manifest. Focusing the lens makes the image manifest, which is analogous to the emergence of the unconscious content into conscious experience. (2) The split-brain operations suggest another solution: in many cases the right hemisphere is unable to respond verbally to problems, and so it cannot easily manifest its consciousness to observers. Further, since the consciousness of the right hemisphere is largely disjoint from that of the left, the right forms a kind of unconscious mind for the left. Of course, the right hemisphere is as conscious as the left, and can manifest its consciousness in other ways, but its experience is not part of the left hemispheres experience (or vice versa). The analogy becomes more striking when we recall that in these patients the hemispheres are not completely disconnected, so the right hemisphere can inject ideas into the left via the brainstem or via external transactions. Indeed, split-brain patients experience these communications as inexplicable hunches just like those from the unconscious (Gregory, 1987, p. 743). In summary, what the perceivingacting-speaking ego experiences as the unconscious mind may be an equally conscious but loosely coupled part of the phenomenal world, which manifests itself only through hunches, dreams, urges, etc. More precisely, my phenomenal world may comprise two (or more) loosely coupled populations of tightly coupled protophenomena. One of these subworlds, which includes the motor protophenomena, is identified with the conscious ego because it can manifest its consciousness in behaviour. However, other populations may be just as conscious, but unable to declare or demonstrate their consciousness to observers. (3) Finally, according to the hypothesis of Sherrington and Pribram discussed earlier, consciousness is associated with graded dendritic microprocesses but not with all-ornone impulses in the axon. Therefore the unconscious mind may reside in the axons, which would make it comprise the more reflexive or instinctive aspects of the psyche. In fact, such a model fits well with Jungs description of the unconscious, for he stressed that the archetypes of the collective unconscious are contentless behavioural patterns grounded in our shared biological or even physical nature.23 Thus they correspond to the axonal pathways, which are for the most part genetically determined. On the other hand, when an archetype emerges into consciousness, it does so with some individual content, which determines its particular appearance. The conscious manifestation of the archetypes corresponds to the dendritic microprocesses triggered by the axonal processes. In fact, it is reasonable to suppose that all three of these explanations apply to the unconscious mind (which is primarily, it must be noted, a negative concept). Comparison to Other Work The philosophical view advocated here is consistent with that proposed independently by Chalmers (1995; 1996). First, it acknowledges his distinction between consciousness, the
Again and again I encounter the mistaken notion that an archetype is determined in regard to its content, in other words, that it is a kind of unconscious idea (if such an expression be admissible). It is necessary to point out once more that archetypes are not determined as regards their content, but only as regards their form and then only to a very limited degree. A primordial image is determined as to its content only when it has become conscious and is therefore filled out with the material of conscious experience . . . The archetype in itself is empty and purely formal, nothing but a facultas praeformandi, a possibility of representation which is given a priori. The representations themselves are not inherited, only the forms, and in that respect they correspond in every way to the instincts, which are also determined in form only. (Jung, CW 9 i, 155; Storr (1983), p. 4156.)
23
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
423
phenomenal world as experienced, and what he calls awareness, the neurological correlates of consciousness as an emergent physical phenomenon. Next, it is consistent with his principle of coherence, which postulates a direct correspondence between the structure of consciousness and the structure of awareness, since the phenomenological dependencies between protophenomena directly parallel the neurological dependencies between synapses, even to the extent of obeying the same mathematical laws, so the emergence of higher level structures is also parallel. Third, my theory is consistent with his principle of organizational invariance, which postulates that identity of microscopic functional organization implies qualitative identity of experience, since it is the dynamical interdependencies among protophenomena that create the phenomenal world. Finally, my view is compatible with his double-aspect principle, which hypothesizes that information has two aspects, one phenomenal and one physical. In the present theory, the basic units of information have a phenomenal aspect as protophenomena in consciousness and a physical aspect as activity sites in the brain. Beyond that, the theory of protophenomena is a step toward the sort of fundamental theory for which Chalmers has called, for it postulates a simple theoretical entity governed by mathematical laws, which provides a foundation for understanding the structure and dynamics of consciousness. There are some superficial similarities between protophenomena and the psychons proposed by Sir John Eccles (1990; 1993); they are both elementary units of consciousness associated with synaptic activity in dendrites. The first difference is one of scale: Eccles associates psychons with dendrons, bundles of the apical dendrites of approximately one hundred pyramidal cells. Therefore, a dendron contains approximately 100,000 synapses, and so we could say that a psychon corresponds to approximately 100,000 protophenomena. The second difference is ontological, for Eccles theory is explicitly dualistic. He takes a psychon to be a causal primary, which can influence synaptic processes by momentarily altering the quantum mechanical probability of an exocytosis of neurotransmitter into the synaptic cleft. In contrast, my theory is essentially monistic, for it views the phenomenal and the physical as two aspects of the same reality. The theory presented in this paper has both philosophical and scientific aspects. As Searle (1992, pp. 545) and others have noted, distinctions such as monism/dualism and mentalism/physicalism have outlived their usefulness, and their use to classify views such as ours are more likely to be misleading than helpful. Nevertheless, it is worthwhile to explain the philosophical aspects in these terms. The present theory is dualistic in the sense that certain objects in certain situations (namely, activity sites in a functioning brain) have fundamental properties (protophenomena and their intensities), which are not reducible to physical properties. It is also dualistic in that the inherently private fact of experience is not reducible to the phenomena experienced, which are all potentially public (through a consensus of trained observers). Nevertheless, it is a kind of monism in postulating one stuff, which happens to have two fundamental, mutually irreducible aspects (phenomenal and physical). Irreducibility enters in another way, for emergent causation operates in both the phenomenological (mental) and neurological (physical) realms: macroscopic consciousness governs microscopic protophenomenal dynamics (without violating the microscopic protophenomenal laws), as macroscopic awareness governs microscopic neurodynamics (without violating microscopic neurophysiology). Once the philosophical arguments for irreducibility are granted, scientific investigation can proceed by parallel analyses in the phenomenological and neurological realms, each supplying the other with hypotheses, theories and empirical data. However, phenomenologically trained observers will be needed to obtain repeatable observations of the characteristics of consciousness.
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction
424
B. MACLENNAN Summary
As a first step I have proposed a theoretical entity, the protophenomenon, as an elementary unit of consciousness associated with microscopic activity sites in the brain, tentatively identified with the synapses. Like other theoretical entities in science, protophenomena are validated by their explanatory value and their fruitfulness for further progress. According to this theory the phenomenal world is structured by dynamical dependencies among the protophenomena, which parallel the neurodynamical dependencies among the corresponding activity sites; indeed they are described by the same mathematical laws. References
Chalmers, D.J. (1995), Facing up to the problem of consciousness, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2 (3), pp. 20019. Chalmers, D.J. (1996), The Conscious Mind (New York: Oxford University Press). Dennett, D.C. (1991), Consciousness Explained (Boston, MA: Little, Brown and Company). Eccles, J.C. (1990), A unitary hypothesis of mind-brain-interaction in the cerebral cortex, Proceedings Royal Society London B, 240, pp. 43351. Eccles, J.C. (1993), Evolution of complexity of the brain with the emergence of consciousness, in Rethinking Neural Networks: Quantum Fields and Biological Data, ed. K.H. Pribram (Hillsdale: L. Erlbaum). Fleck, L. (1979), Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact, trans. F. Bradley & T.J. Trenn (Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press). Gregory, R.L. (ed. 1987), The Oxford Companion to the Mind (Oxford and New York: Oxford Univ. Press). Hameroff, S.R. (1994), Quantum coherence in microtubules: a neural basis for emergent consciousness?, Journal of Consciousness Studies, 1 (1), pp. 91118. Hempel, C.G. (1965), Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science (New York: The Free Press). Ihde, D. (1986), Experimental Phenomenology: An Introduction (Albany: State Univ. of New York Press). MacLennan, B.J. (1991), Gabor representations of spatiotemporal visual images, Technical Report CS-91-144 (Knoxville: University of Tennessee Computer Science Department); accessible via URL http://www.cs.utk.edu/~mclennan. MacLennan, B J. (1993a), Grounding analog computers, Think, 2, pp. 4851. MacLennan, B.J. (1993b), Information processing in the dendritic net, in Rethinking Neural Networks: Quantum Fields and Biological Data, ed. K.H. Pribram (Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum). MacLennan, B.J. (1994), Words lie in our way , Minds and Machines, 2 (4), pp. 42137. MacLennan, B.J. (1995), The investigation of consciousness through phenomenology and neuroscience, in Scale and Conscious Experience: Is the Brain Too Important to be Left to Specialists to Study?, ed. J. King & K.H. Pribram (Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum). MacLennan, B.J. (1996), Protophenomena and their neurodynamical correlates, Techical Report CS-96331 (Knoxville: University of Tennessee Computer Science Department); accessible via URL http://www.cs.utk.edu/~mclennan. Maxwell, G. (1980), The ontological status of theoretical entities, in Introductory Readings in the Philosophy of Science, ed. E.D. Klemke, Robert Hollinger & A. David Kline (Buffalo: Prometheus Books). Miller, G.A., Galanter, E. & Pribram, K.H. (1960), Plans and the Structure of Behavior (New York: Adams-Bannister-Cox). Pribram, K.H. (1971), Languages of the Brain: Experimental Paradoxes and Principles in Neuropsychology (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall). Pribram, K.H. (1991), Brain and Perception: Holonomy and Structure in Figural Processing (Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum). Sacks, O. (1985), The Man who Mistook his Wife for a Hat (London: Duckworth). Sanger, T.D. (submitted),Probability density estimates for the interpretation of neural population codes, submitted to Journal of Neurophysiology. Searle, J. (1992), Rediscovery of the Mind (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press). Shepherd, G.M. (1994), Neurobiology, 3rd ed. (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press). Storr, A. (1983), The Essential Jung (Princeton: Princeton University Press).
Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2005 For personal use only -- not for reproduction