Block, Two NCCS, TICS05
Block, Two NCCS, TICS05
Block, Two NCCS, TICS05
Neuroscientists continue to search for the neural correlate of consciousness (NCC). In this article, I argue that a framework in which there are at least two distinct NCCs is increasingly making more sense of empirical results than one in which there is a single NCC. I outline the distinction between phenomenal NCC and access NCC, and show how they can be distinguished by experimental approaches, in particular signal-detection theory approaches. Recent ndings in cognitive neuroscience provide an empirical case for two different NCCs.
Introduction I have previously proposed a conceptual distinction between phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness [13]. Phenomenally conscious content is what differs between experiences as of red and green, whereas accessconscious content is content information about which is broadcast in the global workspace. Some have accepted the distinction but held that phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness coincide in the real world ([4,5] but see [6]). Others have accepted something in the vicinity of the conceptual distinction but argued that only access consciousness can be studied experimentally [7]. Others have denied the conceptual distinction itself [8]. This article argues that the framework of phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness helps to make sense of recent results in cognitive neuroscience; we see a glimmer of an empirical case for thinking that they correspond to different NCCs.
Phenomenal NCC Christof Koch denes the NCC as the minimal set of neuronal events and mechanisms jointly sufcient for a specic conscious percept ([9] p. 16). However, since there is more than one concept of consciousness, this denition allows that a given percept may have more than one NCC. In my proposed framework, the Phenomenal NCC is the minimal neural basis of the content of an experience, that which differs between the experience as of red and the experience as of green. I will start with an example: the neural basis of visual experiences as of motion is likely to be activation of a certain sort in area MT/V5. (Philosophers often use the terminology as of motion instead of simply of motion, since the experience can and does occur without motion.) The evidence includes:
Corresponding author: Block, N. ([email protected]).
Activation of MT/V5 occurs during motion perception [10]. Microstimulation to monkey MT while the monkey viewed moving dots inuenced the monkeys motion judgements, depending on the directionality of the cortical column stimulated [11]. Bilateral damage to a region that is likely to include MT/V5 in humans causes akinetopsia, the inability to perceive and to have visual experiences as of motion [12,13]. The motion after-effect a moving afterimage occurs when subjects adapt to a moving pattern and then look at a stationary pattern. These moving afterimages also activate MT/V5 [14]. Transcranial magnetic stimulation (TMS) applied to MT/V5 disrupts these moving afterimages [15]. MT/V5 is activated even when subjects view implied motion in still photographs, for example, of a discus thrower in mid-throw [16]. TMS applied to visual cortex in the right circumstances causes phosphenes brief ashes of light and color [17]. When TMS is applied to MT/V5, it causes subjects to experience moving phosphenes [18]. Mere activation over a certain threshold in MT/V5 might not be enough for the experience as of motion; the activation probably has to be part of a feedback loop what Lamme [19,20] calls recurrent processing. PascualLeone and Walsh [21] applied TMS to both MT/V5 and V1 (the rst cortical destination for signals from the eyes) in human subjects, with the pulses placed so that the stationary phosphenes produced by the pulses to V1 and the moving phosphenes from pulses to MT/V5 overlapped in visual space. When the pulse to V1 was applied 545 ms later than that to MT/V5, all subjects said that their phosphenes were mostly stationary instead of moving (see [21] for references to single-cell recording in monkeys which comports with these results.) The delays are consonant with the time for feedback between MT/V5 and V1, which suggests that experiencing moving phosphenes depends not only on activation of MT/V5 but also on a recurrent feedback loop to V1 and back to MT/V5, [21]. So recurrent activity in and around MT/V5, in the context of other brain areas functioning normally exactly which brain areas are required is unknown at present is a good bet for being the physical basis of visual experience as of motion (but see [22,23] for some data that complicate this conclusion). Corresponding conclusions can be drawn for other types of contents of experience. For example, recurrent activation of the fusiform face area on the ventral surface of the temporal lobe (again in context) may determine experience as of a face [24]. The overall
www.sciencedirect.com 1364-6613/$ - see front matter Q 2004 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2004.12.006
Opinion
47
conclusion is that there are different Phenomenal NCCs for different phenomenal contents (cf. Zeki on microconsciousness [25,26]). Of course, no one would take recurrent activation of MT/V5C V1 all by itself in a bottle as sufcient for experience of motion (Box 1). A useful distinction here is that between a core and a total NCC [27,28]. The total NCC of a conscious state is all by itself sufcient for the state. The core NCC is the part of the total NCC that distinguishes one conscious state from another the rest of the total NCC being considered as the enabling conditions for that conscious experience [9]. In these terms, then, the core Phenomenal NCC for the neural basis of the experience as of motion as opposed to the experience as of red or as of a face is likely to be recurrent activation of MT/V5 (see Figure 1). Access NCC We can distinguish between phenomenal contents of experience and access-conscious contents contents information about which is made available to the brains consumer systems: systems of memory, perceptual categorization, reasoning, planning, evaluation of alternatives, decision-making, voluntary direction of attention, and more generally, rational control of action. Wide availability motivates the idea that there is a global workspace [29], and that information concerning conscious representations is broadcast in this global workspace. The neural basis of information being sent to this global workspace can be called the Access NCC. Rees et al. [13] note that in studies of the neural correlates of bistable perception, in which there are spontaneous uctuations in conscious contents, reports of conscious contents correlate with activation in frontal and parietal areas. Dehaene and Changeux [7] suggest that a signicant piece of the neural machinery of what they call access to consciousness (roughly equivalent to my access-consciousness) is to be found in workspace neurons, which have long-range excitatory axons that allow, for example, visual areas in the back of the brain to communicate with frontal and parietal areas. Thus it is a
www.sciencedirect.com
V5A
V4
Figure 1. The core Phenomenal NCC for the visual experiential content as of motion: MT/V5 activation with recurrent loops (indicated by arrows) to and from lower areas. Adapted from [51], p 97, as modied in [52], arrows indicating recurrent loops added.
good guess that the visual Access NCC, the neural basis of access, is activation of these frontal and parietal areas by occipital and inferior temporal areas (see Figure 2). As Dehaene and his colleagues [7] have emphasized, there is a winner-take-all competition among representations to be broadcast in the global workspace. This point is crucial to the nature of the Access NCC and the difference between it and the Phenomenal NCC. One item of evidence for winner-take-all processes derives from the attentional blink paradigm, in which the subject is given a string of very brief visual stimuli, most of which are distractors. If there are two targets separated by an appropriate delay, the subject does not report seeing the second one, even though the second one would have been likely to be reported if the subject had not been given the rst target. Dehaene et al. [30] used a modied attentional blink paradigm, in which subjects were asked to indicate on a continuous scale the visibility of the second target. The second target was at its peak of invisibility when the targets were separated by 260 ms. The result of interest here is that the subjects almost never used the intermediate cursor positions (at the 260 ms delay); that is, they rated the blinked stimulus as either totally unseen or as totally seen almost all the time. Thus, Phenomenal NCC activations compete for dominating the Access NCC. Importantly, it is not the case that the Phenomenal NCC representation that is highest in initial activation will dominate, because domination can be the result of biasing factors such as expectations or preferences [20,31]. Although the winning Phenomenal NCC will in general be amplied by the recurrent loop, a losing Phenomenal
48
Opinion
Lumer et al. (1997) Lumer and Rees (1998) Kleinschmidt et al. (1998)
Figure 2. Suggestion for the core Access NCC for visual experiences, from [13]. Different colors indicate different studies (references in [13]). Activations cluster in superior parietal and dorsolateral prefrontal cortex as indicated by the large light circles. Activity in these frontal and parietal areas uctuates spontaneously in binocular rivalry and other bistable perception in a way that is time-locked to uctuation in reported experience. The core Access NCC may be activation of these areas by neural ring in the occipital cortex. Do we count the Phenomenal NCC as part of the Access NCC in which case this gure pictures the Access NCC minus the Phenomenal NCC? Or do we regard the Access NCC as not including the Phenomenal NCC, in which case this gure pictures the Access NCC? This is a terminological issue: assuming that phenomenal consciousness is the gateway to full-blooded access consciousness, there can be no access consciousness without phenomenal consciousness.
experiential content of seeing something as a face. That content itself is a kind of phenomenology, a kind of consciousness. But this answer is too quick, since the doubt that motivates the question is a doubt that the Phenomenal NCC really does determine the contents of experience, and since the Phenomenal NCC was dened in terms of the contents of experience, the doubt challenges the evidence presented earlier for a Phenomenal NCC. The doubter may say that without access, there can be no true phenomenal contents but only proto-contents that become contents when globally broadcast. But how does the doubter claim to know that? Some are motivated by a terminological point that we shouldnt call something phenomenal or conscious if it isnt broadcast for access [24]. The substantive empirical question is: if our evidence always concerns phenomenal contents that are accessed, how can the Phenomenal and Access NCC ever be empirically distinguished? The answer is that it is not true that our evidence always concerns experiential contents that are accessed. There are a variety of paradigms in which we can use convergent evidence involving varying degrees of access to try to separate the Phenomenal from Access NCC. One such paradigm is signal detection theory. Signal detection theory (SDT) approaches Suppose a subject is shown a series of stimuli at around threshold level and asked to press one button if a target is seen and another if not. SDT models the subjects behavior in terms of two factors: the extent to which the subject has an experience of seeing it and the criterion the subject implicitly sets for reporting seeing it. The criterion is famously inuenceable by features of the experimental setup that affect the subjects expectations or motivation such as the proportion of catch trials (where no stimulus is presented) and by rewards for hits and penalties for false alarms. We know from standard SDT analyses that the subjects reports of whether there was a target or whether he saw it do not only reect the extent to which the subject did see it, but also the subjects threshold for reporting. Two experimental setups in which there are the same experiential contents may result in different reports. A dramatic example is a series of experiments concerning the exclusion paradigm [33], in which subjects are instructed to complete a word stem with something other than the end of a masked word just presented to them. If the word reason is presented unconsciously (for 50 ms), the subject is more likely than chance to disobey the exclusion instructions, completing rea_ with -son, whereas if reason is presented consciously (for 250 ms), the subject is more likely than chance to choose some other ending (e.g. reader). This paradigm has impressed many because it appears to yield opposite results for unconscious and conscious stimuli. However, Visser and Merikle [34] showed that changing the motivation of subjects by using a reward structure can change the degree of exclusion. They started subjects with a $15 credit and docked them $1 for each error. Visser and Merikle interpret their result in terms of the effect of reward vs. punishment on increased attention, accepting the idea
NCC might itself involve recurrent loops to lower areas that will be sufcient for an experiential or phenomenal content. For example, an activation of area MT/V5 might have recurrent interactions with V1, making it the neural basis of an experiential content, but nonetheless lose in the winner-take-all competition and so not be accessed [20]. The general point is that the simplest and most explanatory theory may be one in which recurrent MT/V1 loops are sufcient for an experiential content despite not being accessible when they lose the winner-take-all competition. Thus, the winner-take-all process that is part of the nature of global broadcasting also strongly suggests that the Phenomenal NCC can be instantiated without the Access NCC, so global broadcasting does not encompass all of consciousness. This idea is further bolstered by evidence that there is brief parallel processing of many objects in the ventral visual stream (up to infero-temporal cortex) before zooming in on one or two of them [32]. But is the phenomenal NCC really the neural basis of a kind of consciousness? You may ask, If the Phenomenal NCC can perhaps occur without the Access NCC, how do we know that the Phenomenal NCC is really the neural basis of anything conscious? A quick answer is that, since the Phenomenal NCC determines the contents of experience, what it determines is ipso facto a kind of consciousness. The Phenomenal NCC for visual motion determines the experiential content of visual motion as distinct from, say, the
www.sciencedirect.com
Opinion
49
that the 50 ms/250 ms difference engenders an unconscious/conscious difference. But there is an alternative an SDT interpretation suggested by Snodgrass [35] in which the results in part reect a criterion shift rather than a difference in consciousness. The idea is that punishment for errors of failing to exclude pushes the criterion for inhibiting the natural response so low that weak conscious perception of reason blocks use of -son even though the subjects are so uncondent that they think they dont see the word. That is, their criterion for belief is higher than their criterion for inhibiting a response. The subjects state of mind when successfully excluding one of the 50 ms stimuli could be articulated over-articulated, no doubt as I probably didnt see a word but if I did, it was reason, so Id better complete the stem with reader. [36]. And the SDT interpretation is conrmed by the effect on inclusion instructions. With inclusion instructions, the subject sees reason and then is given rea_ but is told to complete the stem with the word he saw if possible. In this paradigm, SDT predicts no shift with change in reward or punishment, because there is no issue of a criterion: the subject just uses the rst word that comes to mind regardless of level of condence that it is the word he saw. And the result [34] is just that: the difference in reward/punishment structure makes no difference in the result under inclusion instructions. There is therefore evidence in the exclusion case of experiential contents (e.g. as of seeing reason) without the kind of access required for report, planning, decisionmaking, evaluation of alternatives, memory and voluntary direction of attention. Some of the 50 ms stimuli are weakly conscious although not broadcast in the global workspace. Thus, SDT gives us reason to think that experiential content based on the Phenomenal NCC can be instantiated without the kind of access that is based in the Access NCC. Neural SDT In a landmark series of experiments, Super et al. [37] recorded from V1 during a task in which monkeys were rewarded for saccading to a target if there was one or continuing to look at the xation point if not. Super et al. manipulated whether the locations in V1 corresponded to gure or ground. When the monkey detected the target, there was an increased V1 response for gure as compared with ground (see Figure 3, in which this increased gure response is referred to as modulation). Super et al. were able to manipulate the modulation by varying the saliency of the stimulus (i.e. the number of pixels in line segments in the target; Figure 3b) and the proportion of catch trials in which there was no target. For high saliency stimuli and small numbers of catch trials, there was a near perfect correlation between modulation and saccades to the target, and in that sense modulation and access to the target corresponded well. But moving the saliency down or the percentage of catch trials up boosted the modulation when the animal did not saccade to the target to the 50% range. That is, with low saliency or a high number of catch trials, the decision criterion was close enough to the visual signal that the
www.sciencedirect.com
modulation averaged the same whether the animal saccaded to the target or not. For example, this happened when the pixel count was reduced from 16 to 4, maintaining catch trials at 20%, and also when the pixel count was 16 and the catch trials were raised to 50%. If the pixel count was reduced to 4 but the catch trial percentage was also reduced to zero, then the correlation between modulation and access was restored. These results show that the modulation does not reect access to the target (since in the low saliency condition it was the same whether the target was or was not accessed). Nor does the modulation reect the saccade, so it is on the sensory rather than motor side of the decision process. Nor does it reect attention, since the detected targets can be assumed to draw more attention. The modulation therefore seems to reect something intermediate between the stimulus and access. In a classic signal detection analysis, Super et al. showed that the modulation is indeed an intermediate level representation that can be disconnected from access either by raising the perceptual decision criterion or by decreasing saliency of the stimulus, lowering the visual signal to the range of the decision criterion. The modulation seen by Super et al. disappears under anesthesia [38] and is probably produced by recurrent processes [39], unlike other V1 representations like direction and orientation tuning. So there is some plausibility to taking it as an indication of, if not directly part of, a Phenomenal NCC for the experiential content of seeing the target (see also [40]). Can the phenomenal NCC be studied empirically? Doubts about whether phenomenal consciousness (and hence its neural basis, the Phenomenal NCC) can be studied empirically are common (see also Box 2), and often based on the idea that ultimately, introspective reports, that is, reports about ones conscious experience, are the fundamental epistemological basis of theories of consciousness, the gold standard. [7,41,42]. Reports are not supposed to be infallible, but any discounting of reports as reporting too much or too little, will supposedly have to be based solely on other reports. Reports inevitably reect the Access NCC, not just the Phenomenal NCC: when people tell you about their conscious states, you only hear about the ones that have won the winner-take-all competition. Hence we can only study access to consciousness [7], that is, access to experiential content, not experiential content itself. I do not agree with this methodological view for several reasons. First, observed electrons can provide evidence about electrons that cannot in principle be observed, for example electrons that are too distant in space and time (e.g. outside our light cone) to be observed. Why should we suppose matters are any different for consciousness? Second, there is no gold standard of evidence, here or in any area of science. We should go for the simplest theory compatible with all the evidence. No evidence is privileged. In particular, it is not true that our theory of consciousness should be completely determined by the introspective reports of subjects. As an analogy, it is trivial to program two computers to yield the same inputoutput
50
Opinion
(a)
Figure trial
(b)
Fixate
Fig texture on
Hom texture on
Saccade
Maintain fixation
(c)
Figure on RF 0.8
0.8
Response strength
0.4
Response strength
Figure
Figure 0.4
Background on RF Fp RF
0.0 Ground
0.0 Ground
Figure 3. (a) Super et al. [37] trained monkeys to saccade from a xation point to a target (bottom left of (a). Initially, a xation point was presented (top). Then a target texture was presented (Fig texture on, left) or there was a homogenous pattern with no target (Hom texture on, right). If there was no target, the monkey was rewarded for maintaining xation for 500 ms (right panels). The target could be in one of three locations. (b) The targets were areas of an overall pattern in which the lines were orthogonal to the rest of the pattern. (c) Super et al. recorded from sites in V1 whose receptive elds (RF) included those three locations in which targets could occur. When the monkey saccaded from the xation point (Fp) to the target, the neural response from the target counted as gure and the other two sites were counted as ground. Figure responses were greater than ground responses after w90 ms, as indicated in the orange shaded area (central panel). The shaded area indicates the degree of modulation. When the targets were highly salient and the number of catch trials were few, modulation disappeared when the monkey did not detect the target (right panel). Modulation also disappeared under anesthesia. Super et al. manipulated the saliency of the target by decreasing the size of the line segments used. The target shown in (b) is 16 pixels on a side, but they also used 8 and 4 pixel targets. For 16 pixel targets, modulation is present as shown in (c) when the target is detected and absent when the target is absent. But as the number of pixels is decreased, the difference between the case when the target is detected and not detected decreases, so long as the number of catch trials is held constant. When the pixel count is 4, there is no signicant difference in modulation between detection and non-detection. Figures (courtesy of Victor Lamme) redrawn with permission from [37].
function via different algorithms. No theory of what goes on in computers based wholly on the computers reports, that is inputoutput relations, stands a chance of success. Why should we suppose consciousness is any different? Third, any neuroscientic approach that bases everything on reports about a subjects own experience will end up nding only the neural basis of higher order thought thought to the effect that I myself have an experience rather than the neural basis of conscious content or even access to conscious content. To give an introspective report, the subject has to have a higher order thought so to insist on introspective reportability as the gold standard is to encourage leaving out cases in which subjects have experiences without higher order thoughts.
www.sciencedirect.com
Finally, even those who assimilate experiential content to its accessibility should not accept introspective reports as a gold standard. Animals have plenty of access to their experiences, but probably little in the way of higher order thought about them of the sort that could be the basis of an introspective report. Cowey and Stoerig [43] showed that monkeys that had been made blindsighted on one side and trained to make a visual discrimination in their sighted eld, could make the discrimination in their blind eld. However, when given the option, they preferred a third nothing response. This is evidence about the monkeys perceptual state that does not depend on any introspective reports. But is the monkeys button-pushing just a non-verbal introspective report? Non-human primates that have
Opinion
51
learned symbolic systems for communication may not even make spontaneous reports about the world [44,45], so there is little ground for supposing that they are prone to give reports about their own experience. If a human were to push the nothing button, we might guess whether there is a thought underlying the response. We might consider two hypotheses: rst, the introspective report, I am having no visual experience and second, the environmental report, There is nothing on the screen. If the subject were a child of 34 yrs, the introspective report would be unlikely since children have a great deal of difculty with states of mind about their own mental states [46,47]. Given that the environmental report would be preferable for a child, we can hardly suppose the introspective report would be preferable in the case of a macaque! The take-home message is that you dont need reports about the subjects experiences to get good evidence about what the subject is experiencing: indications of what the subject takes to be in front of him will do just ne. Conclusion Where are we? I have proposed a distinction between a Phenomenal NCC and an Access NCC. The single NCC framework does not do as well in making sense of the empirical data, in particular, signal detection theory data, as an account in which there are two NCCs. Of course both these NCCs are to be rmly distinguished from perceptual representations that are not conscious in any sense (as in the rightmost panel of Figure 3c). More generally, rather than asking What is the direct evidence about the Phenomenal NCC independently of the Access NCC? we should instead ask What framework makes the most sense of the data?
References
1 Block, N. (1990) Consciousness and accessibility. Behav. Brain Sci. 13, 596598 2 Block, N. (1992) Begging the question against phenomenal consciousness. Behav. Brain Sci. 15, 205206 3 Block, N. (1995) On a confusion about a function of consciousness. Behav. Brain Sci. 18, 227247 4 Chalmers, D. (1996) The Conscious Mind, Oxford University Press
www.sciencedirect.com
5 Chalmers, D. (1997) Availability: The cognitive basis of experience. Behav. Brain Sci. 20, 148149 6 Block, N. (1997) Biology versus computation in the study of consciousness. Behav. Brain Sci. 20, 159165 7 Dehaene, S. and Changeux, J-P. (2004) Neural mechanisms for access to consciousness. In The Cognitive Neurosciences III, (Gazzaniga, M., ed.), MIT Press 8 Dennett, D. (1995) The path not taken. Behav. Brain Sci. 18, 252253 9 Koch, C. (2004) The Quest for Consciousness: A Neuroscientic Approach, Roberts & Co. 10 Heeger, D. et al. (1999) Motion opponency in visual cortex. J. Neurosci. 19, 71627174 11 Britten, K. et al. (1992) The analysis of visual motion: A comparison of neuronal and psychophysical performance. J. Neurosci. 12, 47454765 12 Zihl, J. et al. (1983) Selective disturbance of movement vision after bilateral brain damage. Brain 106, 313340 13 Rees, G. et al. (2002) Neural correlates of consciousness in humans. Nat. Rev. Neurosci. 3, 261270 14 Huk, A. et al. (2001) Neuronal basis of hte motion aftereffect reconsidered. Neuron 32, 161172 15 Theoret, H. et al. (2002) Repetitive transcranial magnetic stimulation of human area MT/V5 disrupts perception and storage of the motion aftereffect. Neuropsychologia 40, 22802287 16 Kourtzi, Z. and Kanwisher, N. (2000) Activation in human MT/MST by static images with implied motion. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 12, 4855 17 Kammer, T. (1999) Phosphenes and transient scotomas induced by magnetic stimulation of the occipital lobe: their topographic relationship. Neuropsychologia 37, 191198 18 Cowey, A. and Walsh, V. (2000) Magnetically induced phosphenes in sighted, blind and blindsighted subjects. Neuroreport 11, 32693273 19 Lamme, V. and Roelfsema, P. (2000) The distinct modes of vision offered by feedforward and recurrent processing. Trends Neurosci. 23, 571579 20 Lamme, V. (2004) Separate neural denitions of visual consciousness and visual attention: A case for phenomenal awareness. Neural Netw. 17, 861872 21 Pascual-Leone, A. and Walsh, V. (2001) Fast backprojections from the motion to the primary visual area necessary for visual awareness. Science 292, 510512 22 Zeki, S. and Ffytche, D.H. (1998) The Riddoch syndrome: insights into the neurobiology of conscious vision. Brain 121, 2545 23 Sincich, L. et al. (2004) Bypassing V1: a direct geniculate input to area MT. Nat. Neurosci. 7, 11231128 24 Kanwisher, N. (2001) Neural events and perceptual awareness. Cognition 79, 89113 25 Zeki, S. (2001) Localization and globalization in conscious vision. Annu. Rev. Neurosci. 24, 5786 26 Pins, D. and Ffytche, D. (2003) The neural correlates of conscious vision. Cereb. Cortex 13, 461474 27 Shoemaker, S. (1981) Some varieties of functionalism. Philos. Topics 12, 93119 28 Chalmers, D. (2002) What is a neural correlate of consciousness? In Neural Correlates of Consciousness: Empirical and Conceptual Questions (Metzinger, T., ed.), MIT Press 29 Baars, B.J. (1997) In the Theater of Consciousness: The Workspace of the Mind, Oxford University Press 30 Dehaene, S. et al. (2003) A neuronal network model linking subjective reports and objective physiological data during conscious perception. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 100, 85208525 31 Lamme, V. (2003) Why visual attention and awareness are different. Trends Cogn. Sci. 7, 1218 32 Rousselet, G. et al. (2004) How parallel is visual processing in the ventral pathway? Trends Cogn. Sci. 8, 363370 33 Debner, J.A. and Jacoby, L.L. (1994) Unconscious perception: Attention, awareness and control. J. Exp. Psychol. Learn. Mem. Cogn. 20, 304317 34 Visser, T. and Merikle, P. (1999) Conscious and unconscious processes: The effects of motivation. Conscious. Cogn. 8, 94113 35 Snodgrass, M. (2002) Disambiguating conscious and unconscious inuences: Do exclusion paradigms demonstrate unconscious perception? Am. J. Psychol. 115, 545580
52
Opinion
36 Block, N. (2001) Paradox and cross purposes in recent ndings about consciousness. Cognition 12, 197219 37 Super, H. et al. (2001) Two distinct modes of sensory processing observed in monkey primary visual cortex (V1). Nat. Neurosci. 4, 304310 38 Lamme, V.A.F. et al. (1998) Figureground activity in primary visual cortex is suppressed by anaesthesia. Proc. Natl. Acad. Sci. U. S. A. 95, 32633268 39 Lamme, V.A.F. et al. (1998) Feedforward, horizontal, and feedback processing in the visual cortex. Curr. Opin. Neurobiol. 8, 529535 40 Ress, D. and Heeger, D. (2003) Neuronal Correlates of perception in early visual cortex. Nat. Neurosci. 6, 414420 41 Weiskrantz, L. (1997) Consciousness Lost and Found, Oxford University Press, Oxford 42 Papineau, D. (2002) Thinking about Consciousness, Oxford University Press, Oxford 43 Cowey, A. and Stoerig, P. (1997) Visual detection in monkeys with blindsight. Neuropsychologia 35, 929939
44 Terrace, H. (2004) Metacognition and The Evolution of Language. In The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Knowing Consciousness (Terrace, H. and Metcalfe, J., eds), Oxford University Press 45 Wallman, J. (1992) Aping Language, Cambridge University Press 46 Esbensen, B.M. et al. (1997) Childrens behavioral understanding of knowledge acquisition. Cogn. Dev. 12, 5384 47 Gopnik, A. and Graf, P. (1988) Knowing how you know: Childrens understanding of the sources of their knowledge. Child Dev. 59, 13661371 48 Nakamura, R. and Mishkin, M. (1980) Blindness in monkeys following non-visual cortical lesions. Brain Res. 188, 572577 49 Nakamura, R. and Mishkin, M. (1986) Chronic blindness following lesions of nonvisual cortex in the monkey. Exp. Brain Res. 3, 173184 50 Rees, G. et al. (2002) Neural correlates of conscious and unconscious vision in parietal extinction. Neurocase 8, 387393 51 Zeki, S. (1993) A Vision of the Brain, Blackwell 52 Gazzaniga, M. et al. (2002) Cognitive Neuroscience (2nd edn) Norton
http://www.current-opinion.com/claim_online_access.htm
www.sciencedirect.com