History of Infinity

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 27

The History of Infinity What is it? Where did it come from? How do we use it?

Who are the inventors?


E\

G. Donald Allen Department of Mathematics Texas A&M University College Station, TX 77843-3368

 7KH %HJLQQLQJ
As there is no record of earlier civilizations regarding, conceptualizing, or discussing infinity, we will begin the story of infinity with the ancient Greeks. Originally the word apeiron meant unbounded, infinite, indefinite, or undefined. It was a negative, even pejorative word. For the Greeks, the original chaos out of which the world was formed was apeiron. Aristotle thought being infinite was a privation not perfection. It was the absence of limit. Pythagoreans had no traffic with infinity. Everything in their world was number. Indeed, the Pythagoreans associated good and evil with finite and infinite. Though it was not well understood at the time, the Pythagorean discovery of incommensurables, for example , would require a clear concept and understanding of infinity.

Yet, to the Greeks, the concept of infinity was forced upon them from the physical world by three traditional observations.

Time seems without end. Space and time can be unendingly subdivided. Space is without bound.

The History of Infinity

That time appears to have no end is not too curious. Perhaps, owing to the non-observability of world-ending events as in our temporal world of life and death, this seems to be the way the universe is. The second, the apparent conceivability of unending subdivisions of both space and time, introduces the ideas of the infinitesimal and the infinite process. In this spirit, the circle can be viewed as the result of a limit of inscribed regular polygons with increasing numbers of sides. These two have had a lasting impact, requiring the notion of infinity to be clarified. Zeno, of course, formulated his paradoxes by mixing finite reasoning with infinite and limiting processes. The third was possibly not an issue with the Greeks as they believed that the universe was bounded. Curiously, the prospect of time having no beginning did not perplex the Greeks, nor other cultures to this time. With theorems such that the number of primes is without bound and thus the need for numbers of indefinite magnitude, the Greeks were faced with the prospect of infinity. Aristotle avoided the actuality of infinity by defining a minimal infinity, just enough to allow these theorems, while not introducing a whole new number that is, as we will see, fraught with difficulties. This definition of potential, not actual, infinity worked and satisfied mathematicians and philosophers for two millenia. So, the integers are potentially infinite because we can always add one to get a larger number, but the infinite set (of numbers) as such does not exist. Aristotle argues that most magnitudes cannot be even potentially infinite because by adding successive magnitudes it is possible to exceed the bounds of the universe. But the universe is potentially infinite in that it can be repeatedly subdivided. Time is potentially infinite in both ways. Reflecting the Greek thinking, Aristotle says the infinite is imperfect, unfinished and unthinkable, and that is about the end of the Greek contributions. In geometry, Aristotle admits that points are on lines but points do not comprise the line and the continuous cannot be made of the discrete. Correspondingly, the definitions in Euclids The Elements reflect the less than clear image of these basic concepts. In Book I the definitions of point and line are given thusly:
 ,W ZDV WKLV REVHUYDWLRQ WKDW UVW LQVSLUHG PDWKHPDWLFLDQV WR EHOLHYH WKDW WKH FLUFOH FDQ EH VTXDUHG ZLWK D FRPSDVV DQG VWUDLJKW HGJH ,W LV D VLPSOH PDWWHU WR VTXDUH D SRO\JRQ &DQ WKH OLPLWLQJ FDVH EH PRUH GLFXOW LW ZDV WKRXJKW" ,W ZDV DQG ZRXOG QRW EH UHVROYHG XQWLO  E\ /LQGHPDQQ

The History of Infinity Definition 1. A point is that which has not part. Definition 4. A straight line is a line which lies evenly with the points on itself.

The attempts were consistent with other Greek definitions of primitive concepts, particularly when involving the infinitesimal and the infinite (e.g. the continuum). The Greek inability to assimilate infinity beyond the potential-counting infinity had a deep and limiting impact on their mathematics. Nonetheless, infinity, which is needed in some guise, can be avoided by inventive wording. In Euclids The Elements, the very definition of a point, A point is that which has no part, invokes ideas of the infinite divisibility of space. In another situation, Euclid avoids the infinite in defining a line by saying it can be extended as far as necessary. The parallel lines axiom requires lines to be extended indefinitely, as well. The proof of the relation between the area of a circle and its diameter is a limiting process in the clock of a finite argument via the method of exhaustion. Archimedes proved other results that today would be better proved using calculus. These theorems were proved using the method of exhaustion, which in turn is based on the notion of same ratio, as formulated by Eudoxus. We say

D E

F if for every positive integers P Q it follows that G PD  QE implies PF  QG and likewise for ! DQG 

This definition requires an infinity of tests to validate the equality of the two ratios, though it is never mentioned explicitly. With this definition it becomes possible to prove the Method of Exhaustion. It is By successively removing half or more from an object, its size can be made indefinitely small. The Greeks were reluctant to use the incommensurables to any great degree. One of the last of the great Greek mathematicians, Diophantus, developed a new field of mathematics being that of solving algebraic equations for integer or rational solutions. This attempt could be considered in some way a denial of the true and incommensurable nature of the solutions of such equations.

The History of Infinity

Following the Greeks, the Arabs became the custodians of the Greek heritage and advanced mathematical knowledge in general, particularly in algebra. They worked freely with irrationals as objects, they did not examine closely their nature. This would have to wait another thousand years.

 ,GHDV EHFRPH FOHDUHU


Following the Arabs, European mathematicians worked with irrationals as well, though there was some confusion with infinity itself. St. Augustine adopted the Platonic view that God was infinite and could have infinite thoughts. St Thomas Aquinas allowed the unlimitness of God but denied he made unlimited things. Nicolas of Cusa (1401 - 1464) was a circle-squarer that used infinity and infinite process as analogy to achieving truth and heavenly Grace. A type of paradox arose in medieval thinking. It was understood that a larger circle should have more points than a smaller circle, but that they are in one-to-one correspondence. (See below.)
 7KRXJK PDQ\ DQFLHQW *UHHNV EHOLHYHG WKDW WKH FLUFOH FRXOG QRW EH VTXDUHG E\ D FRPSDVV DQG VWUDLJKWHGJH &XVD WKRXJKW KH FRXOG GR VR 2QH NH\ ZDV KLV EHOLHI WKDW D FLUFOH LV D SRO\JRQ ZLWK WKH JUHDWHVW SRVVLEOH QXPEHU RI VLGHV

The History of Infinity

o n e-to - on e

In 1600 Galileo (1564 - 1642) suggested the inclusion of an infinite number of infinitely small gaps. But he understood the problem was using finite reasoning on infinite things. He said, It is wrong to speak of infinite quantities as being the one greater or less than or equal to the other. With the insight of genius, he claimed infinity is not an inconsistent notion, but rather it obeys different rules. In a more practical direction, Leonardo of Pisa, known as Fibonacci, demonstrated a cubic equation that could not be solved within the context of any of the numbers discussed in Euclid. (That is those numbers of the form D E, where D and E are rational.) Moreover, confusion was evident in understanding the nature of irrationals and its ultimate link with infinity. In his book Arithmetica Integra of 1544, Michael Stifel (1487-1567) makes the following observations about irrationals. There are irrationals because they work in proving geometrical figures. But how can they be because when you try to give a decimal representation they flee away. We cant get our hands on them. Thus, an irrational is not a true number, but lies hidden in a cloud of infinity. This typifies the confused, uncertain feeling of professional mathematicians, while clearly illustrating the connection to infinity.

TS S

The nature of infinity was not clarified until 1874, with a fundamental paper by Georg Cantor. In the interim, calculus and analysis was born and fully developed into a prominent area of mathematics. Steven Simon (1548-1620), an engineer by trade, was one of the earliest mathematicians to abandon the double reductio ad absurdum argument of antiquity and adopt a limit process without the official trappings of the Greeks, the double reductio ad absurdum argument.

The History of Infinity

This was the acceptance of limits as an infinite process not requiring metrization. In one result, Simon proves that the median of a triangle divides it into two triangles of equal area.

He accomplished this by a successive subdivision argument into rectangles and estimating the excess. was a practical mathematician/engineer who desired to establish results in an understandable way and to spread the new decimal methods. The limiting part of his argument, that  3 tends to zero as Q , he took as self-evident.



Fermat took limiting processes in another direction in proving quadrature formulas for power functions [S . His arguments appear in many ways modern, though again, his limiting process involves an essential step not unlike Simons. At this point the following arguments seem certain. There can be no theory of irrationals without a working facility and definition of infinity. Without a theory of irrationals, there can be no analysis, and without analysis, mathematics would be without a major branch. Even still, the understanding of polynomials can never be complete without a thorough understanding of irrationals, though not perhaps in the same way.

The History of Infinity

 7KH (PHUJHQFH RI &DOFXOXV


John Wallis (1616-1703), arguably the most important mathematician in 17WK century England except Newton, was Savilian professor of geometry at Oxford, having originally studied theology. In his work Arithmetica Infinitorum he extends the work of Torricelli (1608 - 1647)and Cavalieri (1598 - 1647) on indivisibles and establishes, by a great leap of induction that
  

This infinite expansion for , though not the first, clearly illustrates an infinite process without justification. In 1657 Wallis gives the symbol, , which indicates an unending curve. It caught on immediately. He also introduced fractional power notation.


           

Like Wallis, Newton, Leibnitz, the Bernoullis, Euler, and others that invented and then pursued the new calculus, there was little serious regard for proof and for any theory of limits and the infinite. An appearing in a computation would be attributed to be a paradox. The mathematical legitimacy of the calculation of derivatives by Newton, based on moments was faulted by George Berkeley, Anglican bishop of Cloyne, in his book The Analyst. Lets review the argument for computing the derivative of [ ala Issac Newton (1642-1727). We compute the difference

[  R 

[  [R  R  [ R  R


Divide by the moment

R to get [R

Now drop the term R to get the derivative [. This was exactly what Bishop Berkeley objected to. How, he argued, can this mathematics be legitimate when on the one hand one computes with the term R as if it is a true number and then simply eliminates it when needed.
 7KH WKHRU\ RI LQGLYLVLEOHV LV RQH RI WKH PRUH FXULRXV ?IDOVH VWDUWV RQ WKH URDG WR FDOFXOXV :LWK LW RQH DVVXPHV WKDW DQ DUHD FRQVLVWV RI D FRQWLQXXP RI YHUWLFDO OLQHV H[WHQGLQJ IURP WKH ERWWRP RI WKH UHJLRQ WR WKH WRS 5HTXLULQJ VXEWOH LQWHUSUHWDWLRQV RI DUHD LW ZDV GLFXOW WR DSSO\ ,QGHHG WKRXJK TXDGUDWXUHV IRU SRZHUV ZHUH REWDLQHG TXDGUDWXUHV RI RWKHU IXQFWLRQV ZHUH QRW REWDLQHG LQ WKLV ZD\

The History of Infinity

Berkeley did not object to the spectacular results this new analysis was achieving, but his objection struck at the heart of what had not yet been mathematically articulated as a legitimate process. And what are these fluxion? The velocities of evanescent increments? And what are these evanescent increments? They are neither finite quantities, nor quantities infinitely small, nor yet nothing. May we not call them the ghosts of departed quantities? Newton did give a definition of the derivative similar in appearance to the modern definition but sufficiently far off the mark not to satisfy objections. There resulted, on the basis of Berkeleys objection, a strong effort to place calculus on a theoretical foundation, but this was not to be achieved for another two centuries. In A Defense of Free-thinking in Mathematics of 1735, which was a response to a rejoinder to The Analyst Berkeley devastates the new analysis: Some fly to proportions between nothings. Some reject quantities because [they are] infinitesimal. Others allow only finite quantities and reject them because inconsiderable. Others place the method of fluxions on a foot with that of exhaustions, and admit nothing new therein. Others hold they can demonstrate about things incomprehensible. Some would prove the algorithm of fluxions by rreductio ad absurdum; others a priori. Some hold the evanescent increments to be real quantities, some to be nothings, some to be limits. As many men, so many minds... Lastly several ... frankly owned the objections to be unanswerable. The great Leonard Euler (1707-1783) did not improve the theoretical state of affairs at all. He pursued the new analysis with an abandon that would have cautioned even Newton and Leibnitz. Consider these two series studied by Euler.


[   


[  [

[


 

[  [ 

[ [


The History of Infinity Put

[ [

into (*) and there results

  

. There-

Put

into (**) and there results

The series for fore,

 

is term-for-term greater than the series for

!
   

These sort of computations were prevalent in the analysis of the day and were called paradoxes. By substituting [  into (**), Euler also noted






Euler freely allowed  to have a definite value, and thereby was influ ential in advancing the proportion between nothings. Such was the state of affairs, a field exploding with knowledge and profound results that still impact modern mathematics, with intrinsic inconsistencies neither understood nor for which there was anything resembling a theory. The Greek model of rigorous, axiomatic geometry had been forgotten.

 7KH 5RRWV RI ,QQLW\


What finally forced the issue were consequences owing to trigonometric series. Jean dAlembert (1717-1783) derived essentially the modern wave equation for the vibrating string, and showed that trigonometric series could be used to solve it. This was a considerable departure from power series, for which most mathematicians understood the limits of validity. On the other hand, trigonometric series were new and more difficult to analyze. dAlembert limited himself to initial conditions that were periodic functions, making the analysis easier. Euler, shortly afterward allowed the initial condition to be any function free of jumps as the string was one piece. He insured the periodicity by extending it
 7R WKH PDWKHPDWLFLDQV RI WKLV WLPH WKH FRQFHSW RI IXQFWLRQ ZDV PXUN\ $W WKLV WLPH (XOHU LQWHUSUHWHG D IXQFWLRQ WR EH DQ DQDO\WLFDO H[SUHVVLRQ RU D QLWH QXPEHU RI DQDO\WLFDO H[SUHVVLRQV SLHFHG WRJHWKHU

The History of Infinity



periodically outside the interval. Daniel Bernoulli (1700-1782) took the ideas further by claiming all the new curves, those defined piecewise by expressions, could be represented by trigonometic series. This was soundly rejected by dAlembert and Euler. Euler argued that functions cannot be continuous and discontinuous. The state of affairs remained unresolved for almost a century until Jean Baptiste Joseph de Fourier (1768-1830) applied trigonometric series to the heat problem. The trigonometric series are similar to those for the wave equation, but the requirement of continuity of initial conditions was not demanded, if only on physical grounds, as it was for the vibrating string. His fundamental paper of 1807 was rejected by no less than Legendre, Laplace and Lagrange, though later his continued work was encouraged. Fourier returned to the interpretation of the coefficients of the Fourier series as areas, as opposed to antiderivatives. Consider the sine series.

I [ EQ

 ;E Q Q  =


VLQ

Q[

I V VLQ QV GV

Fourier held that every function could be represented by a trigonometric series. The question of the day and for sometime to come was this: Classify the functions for which the Fourier series converge. This simple question had a profound impact on the development of analysis and literally forced rigor upon the subject, first for the ideas of continuity, then for the definition of the integral, and finally for the notion of set. This in turn put mathematicians square up against infinity itself. This is one of the more curious threads in the history of mathematics. A relatively straight forward problem led to the creation of set theory, functional analysis, and the rigorization of analysis. Below are listed a few steps along the way.

1817 Bolzano tried to prove what is now called the Intermediate


Value Theorem, but was stalled because no theory of the reals
 %HDU LQ PLQG WKDW )RXULHU YLHZHG D IXQFWLRQ LQ D IDU QDUURZHU VHQVH WKDW ZH GR WRGD\ %DVLFDOO\ IRU )RXULHU D IXQFWLRQ ZDV D SLHFHZLVH FRQWLQXRXV IXQFWLRQ H[SUHVV E\ D QLWH QXPEHU RI SLHFHV RI H[SUHVVLEOH DQDO\WLF IXQFWLRQV

The History of Infinity



1821 Cauchy gives a nearly modern definition of limit and con 1823 Cauchy gives the definition of integral in terms of the 1829 Dirichlet gives a condition on a function to have a con
limit of sums of rectangles. This makes Fouriers use of integrals more rigorous. vergent Fourier series. (The function must be monotonic with a finite number of jumps.) This condition, that the number of discontinuities the function can have is finite is due to the current state of the theory of integrability. As an example of a function that cannot be integrated, he produces the function tinuity, though he uses uniform continuity when he hypothesizes pointwise continuity. He defined convergence and divergence of series, and produced what is now known as the Cauchy convergence criterion.

existed. He needed the theorem that every bounded set has a least upper bound.

I [

 

if if

[ is rational [ is irrational

1831 Carl Frederich Gauss (1777 - 1855) objected to using 1850 Karl Weierstrass gives the modern  definition of continuity, discovers and applies uniform convergence and gave a theory of S irrational numbers (1860) as series of rationals. (For 3 example, Q .) Predecessors had defined ir  

sometimes called the salt and pepper function.

infinity in, I protest against the use of an infinite quantity as an actual entity; this is never allowed in mathematics. The infinite is only a manner of speaking, in which one properly speaks of limits to which certain ratios can come as near as desired, while others are permitted to increase without bound.

rationals, if they did at all, as limits of rationals. However, Cantor observed irrationals must already exist in order for them to be a limit of sequences. Using the method of condensation of singularities, Weierstrass produces a continuous function that is nowhere differentiable. This defeated decades of research to prove that all continuous functions must be differentiable, except at perhaps a set of exceptional points.

Q  Q

 

The History of Infinity



1854 Georg Friedrich Bernhard Riemann (1826-1866), Dirich-

1858 Dedekind gives a theory of irrational numbers based on cuts, now called Dedekind cuts. Cauchy and Weierstrass eliminate infinitesimals and infinite values

lets student, gives a more general definition of integral, the Riemann integral, thought by many to be the most general possible. He gave an example of a function with an infinite number of discontinuities that has an integral. Riemann posed many problems about Fourier series including those that led to set theory.

and replaced them by infinite processes and conditions very Eudoxian to say the least.

Infinity and Georg Cantor

Georg Cantor (1845 - 1918) was a student of Dedekind and inherited from him the problem of establishing the class of functions which has a converging Fourier series. Following his teacher, he began to study families of functions having convergence Fourier series as classified by their exceptional points. That is, following even the first ideas of convergence, Cantor expanded the number of exceptional points a function may have and still have a converging Fourier series except at those points. His first attempt in 1872 allowed for an infinite number of exceptional points answering a question of Riemann. Here are the details. Given an infinite set of points 6 . Define the derived of 6 ,6 , to be the set of limit points of 6 . Define 6 to be the derived set of 6 , also called the second derived set of 6 , and so on. Cantor was able to show that if the trigonometric series


Q 

 ;D

FRV

Q[  EQ

VLQ

Q[

converges to zero except at a set of points which has a finite N WK derived set, for some (finite) N , then DQ EQ  Q     . In this paper he also showed the existence of such sets for every Q.

The History of Infinity



Cantor most certainly was aware that the process of derivations could be carried out indefinitely. Use the notation 6 Q to be the QWK derived set of 6 . Then 6 Q 6 Q , the derived set of 6 Q . Defining in this way 6  to be those points in 6 Q for every finite Q, we can continue to apply the derive operation. Thus we get the following sets of points:

6   6       6   6   6       6 T       6 T      6       6     

The number

    and so on. The root of these infinite numbers was the attempt to solve a problem of analysis.

 appears naturally in this context. So also do numbers

However, Cantor now devoted his time to the set theoretic aspects of his new endeavor, abandoning somewhat the underlying Fourier series problems. He first devoted his time to distinguishing the sets of rationals and reals. In 1874, he established that the set of algebraic numbers can be put into one-to-one correspondence with the natural numbers. But the set of real numbers cannot be put into such a correspondence. We show the simpler Theorem. The set of rationals is one-to-one correspondence with the natural numbers.
P be a rational number represented in reduced Proof #1. Let UPQ Q form. Define the relation

UPQ

P Q

This gives the correspondence of the rationals to a subset of the natural numbers, and hence to the natural numbers. Proof #2. (Arrange all the rationals in a table as shown below. Now count the  )RU RXU FRQWH[W WKH algebraic QXPEHUV DUH DOO WKH UHDO ]HURV RI QLWH SRO\QRPLDOV

KDYLQJ LQWHJHU FRHFLHQWV  6XFK VHWV DUH QRZDGD\V FDOOHG denumerable RU countable  7KLV SURRI LV WKH PRUH FRPPRQ DQG VLPSOHU WR XQGHUVWDQG

The History of Infinity



1,

2,

3,

4,

5, ...

1/2 , 2/2 , 3/2 , 4/2 , 5/2 ,... 1/3 , 2/3 , 3/3 , 4/3 , 5/3 , ... 1/4 , 2/4 , 3/4 , 4/4 , 5/4 , ... 1 /5, 2 /5, 3 /5, 4/ 5, 5/5 , ...

numbers as shown by the arrows. This puts the rationals into correspondence with the natural numbers. As you may note, there is some duplication of the rationals. So to finish, simply remove the duplicates. Alternatively, build the table with the rationals already in lowest order. The proof for algebraic numbers is only slightly more complicated. The proof of the other result, that the real numbers cannot be put into such a correspondence invoked a new and clever argument. Called Cantors diagonal method, it has been successfully applied to many ends. Theorem. The set of reals cannot be put into one-to-one correspondence with the natural numbers.

I J

First Proof. We give here the 1891 proof. Restrict to the subset of reals in the interval   . Supposing they are denumerable as the set DQ   , we write their decimal expansions as follows: Q

D D D
. . .

 G G G      G G G      G G G   




where the Gs are digits 0 - 9. Now define the number by selecting G G  G G  G G     This gives a number not in the set DQ   , and the result is proved. Q

I J

 G G G   

Second Proof. This proof, which appeared in 1874, is not as well known. We show that for any sequence Y  Y    of reals there is a

The History of Infinity



number that is not in the sequence in any interval of real numbers D E . First, let D and E be the first members of the sequence in D E with D  E . Let D and E be the first members of the sequence in D  E with D  E , and so on. Thus D  D    is an increasing sequence, and E  E     is a decreasing sequence. There are three cases. If the sequences are finite, then any number inside the last chosen interval satisfies the requirement. Suppose now the sequences are infinite and they converge to limits, D and E , respectively. If they are equal, then this value satisfies the requirement. If not, any value in the open interval D  E does so. Seeking undenumerable sets, Cantor considered topological notions for D E . We his derived sets. We say a set 6 D E is dense if 6 . Finally, say 6 is closed if 6 6 6 . We say 6 is isolated if 6 we say 6 is perfect if 6 6 . Remarkably, Cantor showed that perfect sets must be uncountable. One of the most famous perfect sets is socalled the middle thirds set defined as the residual of the open interval      by first removing the middle third (i.e.  ). Next remove the   middle thirds of the two subintervals remaining and the middle thirds of the four remaining subintervals after that, and so on. This set is one of the first examples of an uncountable Lebesgue measurable set of measure zero that mathematics graduate students learn.

At this point he was in possession of two orders of infinity, countable and uncountable infinity. Being unable to determine an infinity in between, he gave a proof that every set of points on the line could be put in one-to-one correspondence with either the natural numbers or reals. His proof was incorrect, but his quest is known today and is called the continuum hypothesis. The problem is open today and is complicated. In 1938, Kurt Godel proved that the continuum hypothesis cannot be disproved on the basis of the set-theoretic principles we accept today. Moreover, in 1963, Paul Cohen established that it cannot be proved within these principles. This means that the continuum is undecidable. Cantor was not without detractors. Though his methods were enthusiastically received by some mathematicians, his former teacher Leopold Kronecker believed that all of mathematics should be based on the natural numbers. This may be called finitism. He also believed that mathematics should be constructed, and this is called constructivism. He soundly rejected Cantors new methods, privately and publicly. As a journal editor, Kronecker may have delayed the publication of Cantors

The History of Infinity work.



By 1879 Cantor was in possession of powers of infinity, defining two sets to be of the same power if they can be placed into one-toone correspondence. Using his diagonalization method, he was able to demonstrate orders or powers of infinity of every order. Here is how to exhibit a set of higher power than that of the reals. Let be the set of real-valued functions defined on the reals. Assume that this class of functions has the same power as the reals. Then they can be counted as I\ [ , where both [ and \ range over the reals. Define a new function I [ such that

I [

for each real [. This function cannot be in the original set . In turn, this method can be applied recursively to obtain higher and higher powers of infinity. There is another connection with subsets of sets. Indeed, in the argument above the subset of consisting of functions assuming only the values 0 and 1 could have been used. In such a way it is possible to see that we are looking at the set of all subsets of the reals. A subset corresponding to a particular function is the set of values for which it has the value 1. Conversely, any subset generates a function according to the same rule.

I[ [

In all this, infinity is now a number in its own right, though it is linked with counting ideas and relations to sets of sets. The term power gave us the expression power set, or set of subsets of a given set. For a finite set with Q elements, the set of all subsets has size Q . However, the power of a set is an attribute of a set akin to the cardinality of a set. Two sets have the same power if they can be put in one-to-one correspondence. In about 1882, Cantor introduced a new infinity, distinguishing cardinality from order, cardinal numbers from ordinal numbers. (i.e. one, two three from first, second, third). He would say that D  D     and E  E      E have the same cardinality or power, but their order is different. The first has order  while the second has order   . For finite sets, there is only one order that can be given, even though elements can be transposed. Therefore, ordinal and cardinal numbers can be identified. Using a method similar to the second proof above, Cantor showed how to produce a set with power greater than the natural numbers, namely,

The History of Infinity



the set of all ordinal numbers of the power of the natural numbers. From this, he went on to construct the power set of the set of ordinals, and so on generating higher and higher powers. Now, to make contact with the power of the real numbers, Cantor made the assumption that the reals were well-ordered, which is defined below. From this, he established that the power (cardinality) of the real numbers is less than, equal to or greater than each of the new powers, but not which of them it is. Notation: By 1895 Cantor defined cardinal exponentiation. Using the term  (aleph-null) to denote the cardinality of the natural numbers, he defined  for the cardinality of the reals. With  (and more generally  denoting the  WK cardinal) the next larger cardinal than   .  , the continuum hypothesis is written as 

Cantor and others produced similar examples of a special category of nowhere-dense sets as an application arose of these ideas. First, a nowhere dense set 6 is a set for which the complement of its closure is dense, i.e. a6 is dense. The set of binary fractions   and 3  the Cantor middle thirds set are nowhere dense, but the rationals are dense. The special new category consists of those that are fat in the following way: Every finite covering of the set by intervals should have total length greater than some given number, say 1. It becomes natural to say that such sets have content, and the content of the particular nowhere dense set under consideration is the infimum of the total length of all finite coverings. The idea of content was to play a major role in the development of the modern integral, notably the Jordan completion to the Riemann-Cauchy integral and ultimately the Lebesgue integral. So, we see here, sets and infinity now giving rise to new ideas for analysis. And note that the Fourier series problem that served as the root of these investigations would find its ultimate solution within the context of the modern integral.

I J

At this point we have come full circle. The problem created the solution. In 1873, the French mathematician Paul du Bois Reymond (1831 - 1889) discovered a continuous function for which its Fourier series diverged at a single point, solving a long standing open problem. That this was the tip of the iceberg on divergence of Fourier series is illustrated below by three theorems. These results are essentially the current best possible pointwise results for Fourier series. We first need the definition: A set ( 5 is said to have measure zero if for every

The History of Infinity



!  there exists a finite set of intervals ,  ,      ,N on for which

>NL ,L 3 2. N M,L M, where for any interval , , M, M is the length of , . L


1.

(Of course, on .)

N and the intervals , ,      ,N depend on the set ( and

Theorem. (L. Carleson, Acta Mathematica, 116, p.135-157, 1964.) If I [ is continuous on > @ (or even Riemann integrable) then 6P I [ I [ for all W ( , where ( is some set of measure zero.

Here

6P I [

Q 

P ;D

FRV

Q[  EQ

VLQ

Q[

In relation to Cantors theorem, it is easy to show that sets ( for which the N WK derived set is finite must have measure zero. Corresponding to Carlesons theorem, we have the Theorem.(Kahane and Katznelson.) If ( is a set of measure zero then there exists a continuous function I [ on > @ for which OLPP VXS 6P I [ for all [ ( .

These results compliment other counterintuitive results such as Theorem. (A. 2N. Kolmogorov) There exists a Lebesgue integrable function ) ; whose Fourier series diverges at every point. See Zygmund [1959] and Katznelson [1976] for further details.

 7KH 7KHRU\ RI 6HWV


According to Cantor, a set 0 is a collection into a whole, of definite, well distinguished objects (called elements) of 0 of our perception and thought. For example the numbers         constitute a set. So also does the set of primes between 1 and 1000. The order of

The History of Infinity



the elements of the set is unimportant. Thus, the sets     and       are the same. Therefore, two sets 0 and 1 are the same if they have the same number of elements.

This view was emphasized by Gottlob Frege (1848 - 1926), in his development of set theory, who took the approach that infinite collections cannot be counted. He sought a theory that is independent of counting. Thus, he took one-to-one correspondences to be basic, not well-orderings. Intrinsic to this is the notion of cardinality. Definition. A set 0 is said to be equivalent to a set 1 , in symbols: 1 , if it is possible to make the elements of 1 correspond to the elements of 0 in a one-to-one manner.

This is of course an equivalence relation: (1) 0 implies 1 0 ; (3) if 0 1 and 1 3 then 0

Definition. By a cardinal number of a power P we mean an arbitrary representative 0 of a class of mutually equivalent sets. The cardinal number of the power of a set 0 will also be denoted by 0 .

0 ; (2) 0 1 3. M M

At this point we have the following cardinals:




        

# ##




The latter three are called the transfinite cardinals. We also know how to construct more cardinals by taking the power set (the set of all subsets) of any representative of a cardinal. Note that cardinals are ordered by this

M M M M Of the transfinite cardinals, # is the smallest. The continuum hypothesis affirms that  # . We have shown that the cardinality of all the functions on any interval (or uncountable set) is # . Can you show that the cardinality of the continuous functions on any interval has cardinality # ? That there are infinitely many transfinite cardinals
 

Definition. A set 0 is said to have a smaller cardinal number than a set 1 , in symbols: 0  1 , if and only if 0 is equivalent to a subset of 1 , but 1 is equivalent to no subset of 0 .
 

follows from an argument similar to the diagonal argument above. We include this statement as Theorem. For every set 0 , the set 8 0 of all its subsets has a greater cardinal number than 0 .

The History of Infinity



By assuming there is a largest cardinal, we bump into one of the famous paradoxes of set theory, first formulated by Bertrand Russell (1872 - 1970) in about 1901. Often called Cantors paradox it goes like this: The class of classes can be no larger than the class of individuals, since it is contained in the class of individuals. But the class of classes is the class of all subclasses of the class of individuals, and so Cantors diagonal argument shows it to be larger than the class of individuals. Another paradox, formulated by both Russell and Ernst Zermelo (1871 - 1953), is this: Theorem. A set 0 which contains each of its subsets P P     as elements, is an inconsistent set. (That is, it leads to contradictions.)

Proof. Consider those subsets P which do not contain themselves as elements. Their totality is denoted by 0. Since 0 0 , we can inquire if it contains itself. If so it must be a subset of some P that does not contain itself. But P 0 and this implies P does contain itself, a contradiction. If not it must be a member of the original set of those subsets P which do not contain themselves as elements, and therefore is in 0 .

Russell published several versions of this paradox. The barber paradox is the simplest: A barber in a certain town has stated that he will cut the hair of all those persons and only those persons in the town who do not cut their own hair. Does the barber cut his own hair? Paradoxes of this type and the above paradox of size threatened early, intuitive set theory. Note that this one does not involve infinity at all; often, it is called a semantic paradox. The other axioms of set theory as given by Zermelo follow: 1. Axiom of Extensionality: if, for the sets 1 0 , then 0 1 .

0 and 1 , 0

1 and IJ

2. Axiom of Elementary Sets: There is a set with no elements, called the empty set, and for any objects in 0 , there exist sets D and D E . 3. Axiom of Separation: If a propositional function 3 [ is definite for a set 0 , then there is a set 1 containing precisely those elements [ of 0 for which 3 [ is true. 4. Power Set Axiom: If

I J

0 is a set, then the power set (the set of all

The History of Infinity subsets)



8 0 of a set 0 is a set. 0 is a set, then the union of 0 is a set.

5. Axiom of Union: If

6. Axiom of Choice: If 0 is a disjoint union of nonempty sets, then there is a subset 1 of the union of 0 which has exactly one element in common with each member of 0 . 7. Axiom of Infinity: There is a set 0 containing the empty set and such that for any object [, if [ 0 , then [ 0. Zermelo was never able to prove the consistency of the axioms and was criticized for it. In 1930, he introduced a new system, now called the Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, by including the axiom to ensure that the set

I J J

I= 8 =  8 8 =

 

exists, where = is the set of natural numbers. Without that set one cannot prove the existence of  , where, you recall,  is the first transfinite ordinal. Fraenkel introduced the replacement axiom.

8. Axiom of Replacement: The range of a function of a set is itself a set. This axiom solves the problem of ensuring the existence of

I= 8 =  8 8 =

 .

Returning to the paradoxes, there were two types that threatened early intuitive set theory. First there were the paradoxes of size: (1a) We can always construct a set with larger cardinality, and (1b) if there is a largest set (i.e. the set of all sets), we can construct a larger one by the diagonalization argument. The other type was of the Russellian type. These paradoxes occur when there is a hidden parameter whose value changes during the reasoning. For example, in a conversation between two people, one in New York and one in Texas, the first can state the time is 8:00PM and the other state the time is 7:00PM. Both are correct. So, is this a paradox? Certainly not, everyone knows of the two time zones. This is the hidden parameter. We correct this by requiring that time zones
IXUWKHU KH SURYHG WKDW ZLWKLQ DQ\ V\VWHP WKDW FRQWDLQV WKH D[LRPV IRU WKH QDWXUDO QXPEHUV PXVW KDYH SURSRVLWLRQV WKDW FDQQRW EH GHFLGHG +H DOVR ZDV FULWLFL]HG IRU WKH D[LRPV KH FKRVH DQG GLGQ
W FKRRVH
 ,QGHHG .XUW *GHO    SURYHG WKDW WKH FRQVLVWHQF\ FRXOG QRW EH SURYHG (YHQ R

The History of Infinity



should be specified. So, the New Yorker will say it is 8:00PM EST, and the Texan will say it is 7:00PM CST. There is now no possible confusion. Other Russellian type paradoxes are not as easy to resolve. Consider the barber problem. Can the sentence, there is a man who shaves all and only the men that do not shave themselves, be true? No, if the barber is in the range of the quantifier, all the men. Yes, if not. Restricting the quantifier is then the key to resolving such paradoxes. In general, these paradoxes all have a type characterized as

I[ M [  [J

The usual chain of reasoning shows that this set must both be and not be a member of itself; hence, a paradox. The fix to this state of affairs is to introduce a type of comprehension principle, proposed in 1930 by Zermelo, that gives the following parametric form of the Russell definition: for each set

I[  M [  [J

Once this assumption is made the chain of reasoning toward paradox is blocked. You see, we begin from the outset with a given set, wellfounded or not. What the faux paradox now shows is that \ cannot be a member of . Moreover, from this we can conclude that there is no universal set. If there were, then \ would have to be in it, but at the same time cannot be in it, by the conclusion drawn about the sets \ . In short, \ diagonalizes out of . In regards to the barber paradox, note now that the set of shavers must be defined before extracting those that dont shave themselves. The barber is diagonized out, and the paradox is avoided.

 7KH $[LRP RI &KRLFH


In 1904 Zermelo first formulated the axiom of choice as such in the distinguished journal Mathematicsche Annalen, though it had been in use for almost twenty years. Curiously, though it has been used many times previously, it had not been formally stated as such. It was just part of the proof of the various results that employed it. For example Cantor

The History of Infinity



used it in 1887 to show any infinite set has a subset of cardinality  . It was also used in topology, algebra, and analysis. In 1890 Giuseppe Peano (1858 - 1932) argued that one cannot apply a law that selects a member of a class from each of many classes an infinite number of times. After the appearance of Zermelos paper, the very next issue contained detractions by no less than Emile Borel (1871 - 1956) and Felix Bernstein (1878 - 1956) in Mathematicsche Annalen. Detractions were also submitted to the Bulletin del la Societe Mathematique de France though out 1905 by Henri Lebesgue (1875 - 1941) and Rene Baire (1874 - 1932). The kernel of their argument was this: Unless a definite law specified which element was chosen from each set, no real choice has been made and the new set was not really formed. Specifically, E. Borel referred to the Axiom of Choice as a lawless choice which when used is an act of faith, and that is beyond the pale of mathematics. Defenders did not see the need for a law of choice. The choices are determined, they argued, simply because one thinks of them as determined. Jacques Hadamard (1865 - 1963) was Zermelos staunchest supporter arguing the practicality of its application in making progress. This is the state of affairs today. The axiom of choice is widely used and with it, wide and varied results have been obtained. It will no doubt continue to be used until such time as contradictions are obtained. However, denying its validity leads to some rather unusual consequences. For example, if one accept only the countable axiom of choice, every (constructable) set of reals is measurable. Conversely, assuming that every set is measurable leads to the denial of the axiom of choice. Similarly, if one denies the continuum hypothesis by assuming that   , then every set of real numbers is measurable.

The Well Ordering Axiom, which was used for example by Cantor to bring the reals into the realm of his other ordinals, was also widely used during this time. A set if (linearly) ordered is there is a relation  for which given D and % in 0 , it follows that D  E, E  D, or D E is true. The set is well ordered if every subset of 0 , no matter how it is selected, has a least element. For example the natural numbers are well ordered under the natural order, but the reals are not. The well ordering axiom states that a linear order exists for the reals. Zermelo,
 )RU H[DPSOH LW ZDV XVHG WR VKRZ WKH IROORZLQJ WKHRUHP (YHU\ ERXQGHG LQQLWH VHW RI UHDO QXPEHUV KDV D FRQYHUJLQJ VXEVHTXHQFH

The History of Infinity



to answer some of the criticisms, of the axiom of choice gave a proof of the well-ordering of the reals that used the axiom of choice. Moreover, he proved the two axioms are equivalent. Question: Can you prove that every infinite set has a countable subset without the axiom of choice? Can you prove it with the axiom of choice (or an equivalent)? Answers: no and yes. Whether you can prove it or not, the point is you probably believe it can be done, or at the very least should be possible. The axiom of choice allows this natural fact. Call this its good side. That it has another side is indicated below. We would be remiss to leave out one of the colossal paradoxes that can be proved using the axiom of choice. The most remarkable of these, discovered in 1924, is the Banach-Tarski paradox. Called a paradox because of its remarkable conclusion, more properly it should be called the Banach-Tarski theorem. Theorem. (Banach-Tarski) Given two spheres, say, one of diameter one meter (6$ ) and the other the size of the earth (6% ), there are decompositions of both into a finite number of pieces, say, $L Q  L and %L Q  with $L 6$ and %L 6% , for which $L %L , L L      Q.

I J

>

>

I J

(Congruence here means that one set can be transformed to the other by a rigid rotation and a translation.) The rather technical proof is not difficult, but is a bit long for this article. Of the more intuition shattering consequences of this counterintuitive theorem is that a bowling ball can be decomposed into a finite number of pieces and reassembled as a sphere larger than and more massive than the earth. You may argue that the principle of conservation of mass is violated, and therefore something is definitely amiss. However, it can be shown that these decompositions are not measurable in the sense of Lebesgue, and therefore they have no measurable mass. Consequently, ones intuition is shattered further after acknowledging the existence of clumps of matter that cannot have mass. The axiom of choice is a marvelous tool, and in this context, could lead to an entirely new
 6WHIDQ %DQDFK    GHYHORSHG WKH WKHRU\ RI FORVHG OLQHDU QRUPHG VSDFHV QRZ FDOOHG %DQDFK VSDFHV 7KHVH VSDFHV IRUP WKH IRXQGDWLRQ RI PXFK RI PRGHUQ DQDO\VLV DQG QXPHULFDO DQDO\VLV $OIUHG 7DUVNL    ZDV DQ RXWVWDQGLQJ ORJLFLDQ WKDW DQDO\VHG WKH VHPDQWLF DVSHFWV RI ORJLF DQG ZDV LQVWUXPHQWDO LQ SURYLGLQJ D IUDPHZRUN LQ ZKLFK PDQ\ SDUDGR[HV FDQ EH UHPRYHG 7KH IRUHPRVW RI WKHVH SDUDGR[HV The Liar ZDV NQRZQ HYHQ WR $ULVWRWOH DQG LWV VWXG\ LV DQ DFWLYH SDUW RI FRQWHPSRUDU\ PRGHUQ VHW WKHRU\C

The History of Infinity cosmology. The only limit is ones imagination.



 +RZ %LJ LV ,QQLW\"


So far we have seen the cardinal numbers                 . Of course we can construct even larger cardinals by employing the power set construction. Is that the end of the line? Constructing power set after power set. In this very short section we consider whether there may be even larger cardinals, inaccessible from power set realization. It can be shown that for each set 0 of cardinals there is a smallest cardinal succeeding all members of 0 . Denote this cardinal by VXS 0 . For example  VXP       and  VXS  . A cardinal $ which is not 0 is said to be inaccessible if

# #

I# J

1. for every set

% of cardinals such that %  $

M M

2. if

&  $ for &

Certainly  is inaccessible in this definition. But are there others? In fact, it has been shown that the postulate that there are no other such inaccessible cardinals is consistent with the axioms of the standard Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory. Because of this Tarski introduced a very powerful axiom asserting the existence of inaccessible cardinals. Called the axiom for inaccessible sets it reads as For every set 1 there is a set 0 with the following properties: 1. 1 is equivalent to a subset of 0 ; 2. $  $ 0 $  0 is equivalent to 0 ; 3. there is no subset 3 0 with 3  0 such that the power set of 3 is equivalent to 0 .

$

VXS %  $


&

$

MM M M

Tarski has shown that the cardinal number of a set 0 is infinite and inaccessible if and only if 0 satisfies (2) and (3) above. This
 6HH 6XSSHV RU 5RWPDQ

The History of Infinity



axiom is so strong that its adoption implies that the axiom of the power set, the axiom of selection of subsets, the axiom of infinity, and the axiom of choice can all be omitted from the original system of axioms. Inaccessible cardinals are infinities beyond infinity in every sense of constructability of the alephs. It is remarkable that language allows its description. Such sets may well be beyond the comprehension of anyone as objects of true consideration.

 &RQFOXVLRQ
In some ways, the paradoxes and overall lack of agreement on basic principles in set theory can be seen as parallel to the paradoxes and overall lack of agreement on basic principles in the early days of calculus or noneuclidean geometry. Parallel to that, no doubt there were many paradoxes and overall lack of agreement of basic principles in the fledgling subject of geometry more than two thousand years earlier. It seems that by making various decisions about infinity via its agents, the axiom of choice and the well ordering axiom, different systems of mathematics result. Therefore, the original absolute axiomatic model of Euclidean geometry within which all propositions can be resolved and that all of science has tried to emulate, is gone forever. Infinity and these trappings of set theory so very much needed to advance the early and modern mathematical theories, has served up a second dish, the demise of certainty. Will the issues of infinity ever be resolved to the satisfaction of logicians and mathematicians? Like the limit, the understanding of which was finally assimilated after two millenia, a working definition of infinity satisfactory to all practitioners will probably percolate out. For most of us that point has already been achieved.

The History of Infinity References



1. Barwise, Jon, and John Etchemendy, The Liar, an Essay on Truth and Circularity, Oxford University Press, New York, 1987. 2. Dauben, Josheph Warren, Georg Cantor, His Mathematics and Philosophy of the Infinite, Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1979. 3. Kamke, E. Theory of Sets, First American Translation, Dover, New York, 1950. 4. Katznelson, Yitzhak, An Introduction to Harmonic Analysis, 2nd corrected edition, Dover, New York, 1976. 5. Kline, Morris, Mathematics, The Loss of Certainty, Oxford University Press, New York, 1980. 6. Lavine, Shaughan, Understanding the Infinite, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1994. 7. Rotman, B. and T. T. Kneebone, The Theory of Sets and Transfinite Numbers, Oldbourne, London, 1966. 8. Rucker, Rudy, Infinity and the Mind, Princeton University Press, Princeton, New Jersey, 1995. 9. Suppes, Patrick, Axiomatic Set Theory, van Nostrand, Princeton, 1960. 10. Zygmund, A. Trigonometric Series, 2nd ed., Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1959.

You might also like