Tânia Stolze Lima - Juruna Shamanism
Tânia Stolze Lima - Juruna Shamanism
Tânia Stolze Lima - Juruna Shamanism
In his celebrated comparison between studies of hysteria and totemism, Lvi-Strauss refers to a situation where the thoughts of the scientist account for more than those of the people studied the latter for this reason becoming more different than they are (Lvi-Strauss, 1974, p. 5). This image comes to mind when I find myself faced with certain characterizations of indigenous Amazon cosmologies employing notions such as anthropocentrism or animism: these remind me directly of the totemic illusion that is, the idea that it should be possible to deduce the identity between animality and humanity, nature and culture, from ethnographic materials. Starting from the obvious fact that the extensive and intensive definitions of the terms nature and culture are historical and/or cultural products, I shall argue that the differences in the ways this distinction functions in various semiotic systems or regimes (see Deleuze and Guattari 1984 and 1988) is a more significant ethnographic fact than the diversity of
* Published originally in Revista Brasileira de Cincias Sociais, volume 14, n. 40, June 1999, pp. 43-52. Translated by Frances Tornabene de Sousa and revised by David Rodgers and the author.
contents it may assume in particular epochs and cultures. First I shall make some brief observations concerning this distinction in anthropology, before moving on to the Juruna ethnography.1
44
It is also true that the distinction may be represented by a segmentary schema, since it may be transposed to the field of culture, thereby generating a dichotomy between society and culture. In this instance, it is generally society that receives the values attributed to nature, while culture may become newly dichotomized as an opposition between material culture and symbolism. But this segmentarity should not conceal the fact that at each of its levels the terms still obey a concentric regime. For Durkheim or RadcliffeBrown, for example, culture is clearly enveloped and determined by society, while for Sahlins, the inverse is true. Expressing, therefore, a hierarchical reading of the distinction, anthropology shares with common sense the strange idea that nature is more real than culture, that nature is objective while culture is not. Moreover, it is on this basis that Lvi-Strauss formulates the curious paradox of the opposition of nature and culture. He begins by observing that its simplicity would fall apart if it were the work (as the anthropologists claim) of humanity as such, as then, he continues, it would be neither a primitive fact, nor an objective aspect of the worlds order (LviStrauss, 1967, p. xvii.). That is, if anthropology were correct in saying that humans distance themselves from nature, then the opposition would be strictly imaginary. The way out of this paradox is wellknown: Lvi-Strauss proposes the existence of a real continuity and a logical discontinuity between nature and culture, an outcome that then allows the opposition to be employed as an instrument of analysis. If an anthropologist like Lvi-Strauss can choose to disbelieve in the opposition of nature and culture in the name of a superior naturalism (Sahlins, 1976), it may also be rejected in the name of a new culturalism, based on the principle of natural relativism (Latour, 1994). In an attitude which at first seems to clash with current anthropological rhetoric, Bruno Latour (1994; Latour and Woolgar, 1997) maintains that if there is one rule to be respected in any ethnographic research into the science and cosmology of selfstyled modern societies, this rule is none other
45
Here, culture denotes a universal function which is simultaneously defined as thought and sociality (and is, therefore, neither a domain isolated from an exterior reality, nor a distinctive function of humanity in opposition to animality).3 This fact is suggestive of a profoundly anthropocentric vision of the world and seems to correspond to what is conventionally called animism. From Tylor to Descola, the question of the applicability of the nature/culture distinction to so-called pre-modern systems has been put forward. The question is whether it is suitable for us to apply such labels to Amazon cosmologies: despite Descolas argument (1992), I think it is not. Firstly, the question of culture is not only situated on the level of generality that I just outlined. There is another level, for which we may conveniently employ the term civilization, a level defined by the diversity of food regimes, numerous musical instruments and artifacts, categories of spirits and regions of the cosmos, and even the environment itself wherein the lives of humans and animals unfold. And here a differential between wild and civilized is introduced: certain human societies have practices that are reminiscent of those of the jaguar. It is true that on the first level the humans implied are the Juruna: peccaries and howler monkeys think and act as if they were Juruna. However, as far as the human genus is concerned, each social group possesses its own modes of action, and their subjective experience is not a simple replica of the action and subjectivity of the Juruna. Secondly, what I learnt about the soul and civilization amounted to a very elementary lesson: (a) animals and the souls of the dead have different points of view to ours in respect to reality, and (b) the Juruna are not necessarily in agreement with what these other beings think of themselves and the Juruna. I believe, then, that to fashion a general characterization of Juruna cosmology through the use of notions like anthropocentrism and animism is to lose sight of the essential: for the Juruna, the relation of identity between humanity and animality is primarily given as a condition for imagining their difference (Lima, 1996).
46
In order to define the relations of similarity and difference (or identity and alterity) the Juruna employ a conceptual device formed by the terms nana and imama. Between two cats, similarity exists; between a cat and a dog, difference. Between two parallel cousins, similarity exists; between two cross cousins, difference. Nana serves to distinguish the classificatory kin relation from the full relation, while imama serves to distinguish (within the kinship domain as a whole) consanguinity and the full affinity of the relation between cross cousins, marking the latter as a relation of alterity. In addition, when applied to the sociological domain, the two notions follow gradients: more similarity exists between two parallel first cousins than between second cousins; more alterity exists between non-kin than between cross cousins. To summarize then: (a) nana expresses the similarity between individuals of the same species and imama the alterity between individuals of different species; (b) a parallel exists between the diversity of animals and the diversity of social relations. That one and the same device allows the two types of diversity to be thought simultaneously is not surprising following the critique of totemism developed by Lvi-Strauss. In fact, the best evidence that Juruna ethnography provides in respect to the totemic method are two animal societies in which differences between kinship relations, combined with differences in social status, link people who belong to distinct species. This homology between the differences of animals and of social relations implies not only that humans can (and should according to the message of certain myths) apprehend the political alterity between social groups through the model of animal diversity; animals can also apprehend their relation with others those that are relatively close to their species as a social relation of alterity. This is the case in vulture society: formed by king-vultures, red-headed vultures and yellowheaded vultures, the three species are similar in forming one and the same social group; but also different, since they are united through cross kin relations and by distinct social statuses chiefshaman, warriors and paternal aunts respectively.
47
(3) a triad of oppositions can be applied to each entity or type of being, in such a way that each entity consists of a cluster of oppositions; for example, a collared peccary may not be a peccary or an animal, but a spirit; (4) this means that, from an ethnographic point of view, the differential between animal species should not be eliminated due to its common belonging to the class of animals; (5) the same requirement is imposed on humanity; exemplifying this, humanity divides into the Juruna, peoples of the forest and whites: the Juruna are simply humans, the second present values linked to animals (drinking only water, and eating almost raw meat), while the last, through their technological power and spatial journeys, present values linked to the divine shaman who created humanity; (6) as in the case of the human genus, there are genuses formed by animal species that are taken to be proximate; for example: the monkeys, which comprise (among others) four important species: (a) the capuchin monkey and the spider monkey are animals in a double sense: they are named as such and are considered prey; (b) the night monkey, which is not an animal but a phantom; and (c) the howler monkey, which is an animal in the proper sense of the term, but only the ancient Juruna they say treated it as prey (currently, people consider that they appear like phantoms and feel no desire to eat them; they narrate a myth about the conjugal life of the howler monkeys in which the husband provokes the wifes jealously by threatening to go to a Juruna beer festival); (7) it is notable, however, that the three oppositions are applied in order to draw a differential relation between the terms of a same genus; (8) on the other hand, the relations between the terms (the Juruna and the peccaries, the vultures, and the dead, etc.) present a considerable potential asymmetry: if a human point of view has a greater chance of prevailing over an animal point of view (in hunting, for example), this chance diminishes significantly when confronted with the spirits point of view (in the festival of the dead, for example);
48
(9) asymmetry should be understood here as the capacity of a subject (human, animal or spirit) to impose its point of view on another; (10) since it follows that the Juruna believe an animal point of view can, in theory, prevail over their own (for example, a hunter becoming first an enemy and then a captive of the prey), then a spirit point of view can also show itself to be insufficiently potent to dominate a human; (11) or put otherwise, asymmetry is a reversible relation, and this means that it cannot be considered to be determined a priori; at least in principle, the domination of one over another is only determined a posteriori; (12) in addition, the triple opposition allows the distinguishing of common phenomena from singular phenomena; this corresponds to a differential between ordinary human life dominated by the human point of view, and the unusual that is, a situation in which the animal or spirit point of view transforms human reality for humans themselves; (13) this makes evident the fundamental presence of a fourth opposition, namely, the distinction I/another, or put better, Other/non-Other; (14) finally, the difference between points of view has nothing to do with the theory of cultural relativism, as it is not based on any of the characteristic notions of Anthropology, namely: partiality, arbitrariness, equivalence, incommensurability and antinomy between object and subject, that is, nature and culture (Lima, 1995); (15) what the Juruna theory emphasizes is the struggle between points of view and that reality is what the point of view affirms. I believe, therefore, that the point of view of the animals represents not so much the inapplicability of a differential between nature and culture, but rather the inexistence of the overlapping, which, according to ourselves, may be conceived between the dichotomies of nature/culture and animal/human. I emphasize again that these terms do not designate impermeable domains of reality, but a differential relation which is better translated by the qualifiers wild and civilized.5 In order to describe this cosmological regime, I shall base my argument on Deleuze and Guattari
49
argument is precisely that we are dealing not so much a global system of segmentarity (in such a way that at some moment the distinction between Cariocas and Paulistas would dissolve to make way for the distinction Brazilians versus other national identities), but with a scheme for which the point of view of the definition of categories of alterity pertains to the terms themselves, and not to a term situated within a superior point of view. For it is evident that, in our sociocosmological system, the distinction Cariocas and Paulistas is permitted by a point of view which is dislocated in relation to the terms and which is superior to them: the point of view of the whole. The label perspectivism is useful and, I believe, necessary in order to translate the absence of the point of view of the whole,8 and therefore hierarchy defined a priori. Another objection would be the following. If we consider that the most adequate anthropological approach would be that which is capable of allowing the lived world (Gow, 1998) produced by the groups that we study to have the last word about the play of symmetries in ethnographic texts, it could be objected that perspectivism conceals a non-perspectival residue, meaning by this the fact that, for the Juruna, the tucunar (peacock bass) is simply the tucunar! For the Piro, a peccary is just a peccary! The objection is valid but is not insurmountable, since this problem is not alien to the Juruna, who confer on it precisely a perspectivist treatment, as I will now show.9 Taken in the strict sense, the human being, alive and alert, presents an irreducibility that I cannot avoid stressing: its inimitable wisdom. The antonym of wisdom translates the most varied concepts: incest, bestiality, adultery, sexual and verbal incontinence, intrepidity, mental stupidity and the exchange of words with animals, all related to incredulity, and which directly or metaphorically evoke a tapir quality or affect, if not the actual transformation of the person into a tapir. Human wisdom consists of that which we ourselves call recursivity: the living know that the dead consider the tucunar to be a corpse, but the dead do not know that this is what they know, nor that the living consider the tucunar as tucunar. Their relative insensateness, or that is, this inability
50
to put themselves in perspective also characterizes our own dream existence and the condition of animals. The peccary knows itself to be human, knows that a Juruna is a similar, but does not know that it is a peccary for the Juruna. This is the type of moral relation which the Juruna entertain with animals. A bit like Rimbaud put it: Too bad for the wood if it finds out its violin!
Conclusions
To conclude, it is necessary to highlight some points: (1) In the study of indigenous cosmologies, it is impossible to situate the question of the nature/culture and human/animal distinction on a level of generality such that the internal diversity of each of these terms loses its relevance. I have tried to show that we can understand this phenomenon as a manifestation of a positive property of Juruna cosmology, namely, perspectivism, which, formulated in negative terms, consists in the absence of a point of view of the whole, that kind of panoptic point of view which generates the illusions of objectivity and absoluteness. The classificatory operations that we can observe do not suppose a distancing of the subject in relation to the constituted world, but, on the contrary, its interaction with what is being classified, an interaction that is always changing and (as Lvi-Strauss showed) always attentive to sensible qualities, and also (as Lvy-Bruhl showed) to the unusual. (2) The hierarchical relation between nature and culture characteristic of our way of thinking is not opposed to the absence of hierarchy in Juruna cosmology. What is observable in the latter is hierarchy operating in a regime that impedes the a priori codification of relations, imposing itself only a posteriori, the cosmological dynamic depending much more on a principle of variation of entities and of their reciprocal relations, rather than on a non-temporal system where all the entities would occupy a predefined position. (3) Mauss showed that giving produces an asymmetry (an obligation or subordination) and that, in the gift regime, the only way to liberate
51
humans, represented as predators, and animals, represented as prey, is directly expressed by means of two relational categories. In this sense, it could be said that the humans are the animals of the animals! An equation of the same type is true, in part, for the Juruna dead, but not though for Juruna animals. 7 8 For a critique of contemporary attempts to essentialize modernity, see the twin texts of Foucault (1994). For an examination of this question in a different ethnographic context, see Strathern (1992). My distinction between contextualism (parts integrated into a larger whole, that in its turn is part of a larger whole and so on in succession) and perspectivism does not mean, obviously, that the Juruna are incapable of thinking in terms of context. It also does not mean that perspectivism has been ignored in fields other than the plastic arts: the work of Henry James (1994) is full of this. Consider also the example of Nietzsche. My thanks to Peter Gow for criticisms which allowed me to develop this point.
NOTES
1 The Juruna are a small Tupi people who live in the upper Xingu. Canoeists, farmers and hunters, they inhabited the islands of the middle Xingu until the end of the XIX century. My fieldwork with this group took place between 1984 and 1990 and was supported by funding from the Ford Foundation and Financiadora de Estudos e Projetos (Finep). When I say there is no inside/outside distinction, I mean that we should not believe in the existence of inside and outside. We should sit exactly at the place where the inside and the outside of the network are defined. So the point is exactly the same: we have to see inside-and-outside as an active category, created by the actors themselves, and it has to be studied as such. (Latour and Crawford, 1993). Thought and language mutually imply one another: the first is silent language, without a voice. This is recorded in the space of cosmogonic myths, where the mythic inscription of the difference between humans and animals stands out, (a) the humans transformed into animals already bore prefigurations of their specific animality, and (b) what the myth extracts from the animals is not exactly the language but the possibility of their communication with humans in the waking world. This double meaning of the term imama is expressed in the Portuguese of the Juruna through the use of two terms: brabo and Outro (wild and Other). I think in fact, that the distinction between wild and civilized is not strange to the Juruna, nor is it lacking in importance. But it has nothing to do with the evolutionist anthropological distinction: the wild is not primitive and civilization consists above all in the knowledge and preservation of cultural practices given since the origin of present day humanity. While it is true that in Juruna cosmology the expression of this perspectivism reveals itself to be fairly abstract, other Amazonian systems express it in a relatively more concrete form: according to the Makuna or the Wari (rhem, 1996; Vilaa, 1996), the differential between 9
10 Majority implies a constant, of expression or content, serving as a standard measure by which to evaluate it. Let us suppose that the constant or standard is the average adult-white-heterosexual-European-male speaking a standard language (Joyces or Ezra Pounds Ulysses). [...] For the majority, insofar as it is included in the abstract standard, is never anybody, it is always Nobody Ulysses whereas the minority is the becoming of everybody, ones potential becoming to the extent that one deviates from the model. There is a majoritarian fact, but it is the analytic fact of Nobody, as opposed to the becoming-minoritarian of everybody. (Deleuze and Guattari, 1988, p. 105).
REFERENCES
RHEM, Kaj. (1996), The Cosmic Food Web: HumanNature Relatedness in the Northwest Amazon, in P. Descola and G. Plsson (eds.), Nature and Society: Anthropological Perspectives, London, Routledge. BOURDIEU, Pierre. (1996), Marginlia. Algumas Notas Adicionais sobre o Dom. Mana, 2(2): 7-20. DELEUZE, Gilles and GUATTARI, Flix. (1984), AntiOedipus. Capitalism and Schizophrenia. London, The Athlone Press. __________. (1988), A Thousand Plateaus. Capitalism and Schizophrenia. London, The Athlone Press. DESCOLA, Philippe. (1992), Societies of Nature and the Nature of Society, in A. Kuper (ed.), Conceptualizing Society, London/New York, Routledge, pp. 107-126.
52
DUMONT, Louis. (1975), Introduccin a Dos Teoras de la Antropologa Social. Barcelona, Anagrama. FOUCAULT, Michel. (1994a), Quest-ce que les Lumires? (1984), in M. Foucault, Dits et crits, vol. 4, Paris, Gallimard, pp. 562-578. __________. (1994b), Quest-ce que les Lumires? (1983), in M. Foucault, Dits et crits, vol. 4, Paris, Gallimard, pp. 679-688. GOW, Peter. (1998), A Man who Was Tired of Living. How an Amazonian world changes in time. London, London School of Economics, mimeo. JAMES, Henry. (1994), Pelos Olhos de Maisie. So Paulo, Campanhia das Letras. LATOUR, Bruno. (1994), Jamais Fomos Modernos: Ensaio de Antropologia Simtrica. Rio de Janeiro, Editora 34. LATOUR, Bruno and CRAWFORD, T. Hugh. (1993), An Interview with Bruno Latour. Virginia Military Institute. Internet. LATOUR, Bruno and WOOLGAR, S. (1997), A Vida de Laboratrio: a Produo dos Fatos Cientficos. Rio de Janeiro, Relume Dumar. LVI-STRAUSS, Claude. (1967), Les Structures lmentaires de la Parent. Paris, Mouton. __________. (1974), Le Totmisme Aujourdhui. Paris, PUF. __________. (1976), O Pensamento Selvagem. So Paulo, Companhia Editora Naiconal. LIMA, Tnia Stolze. (1995), A Parte do Cauim. Etnografia Juruna. Rio de Janeiro, doctoral thesis, PPGAS/Museu Nacional/UFRJ. __________ . (1996), O Dois e seu Mltiplo: Reflexes sobre o Perspectivismo em uma Cosmologia Tupi. Mana, 2(2): 21-47. SAHLINS, Marshall. (1976), Cultura e Razo Prtica. Rio de Janeiro, Zahar. STRATHERN, Marilyn. (1992), Parts and Wholes: Refiguring Relationships in a Post-Plural World, in A. Kuper (ed.), Conceptualizing Society, London/New York, Routledge, pp. 74104. VILAA, Aparecida. (1996), Quem Somos Ns: Questes da Transformao no Encontro dos Wari com os Brancos. Rio de Janeiro, doctoral thesis, PPGAS/Museu Nacional/UFRJ.