Final Existentialism
Final Existentialism
Final Existentialism
The first philosopher to use the term was Soren Kierkegaard (1813 -
1855), who reacted against systematic rational philosophy, specially Hegel,
and grasped the notion of a truth inside of the evolving self.
Deriving from this stress on existence there are other main subjects
and images that have been developed by the existentialists.
Historical background
In 1670, Blaise Pascal’s unfinished notes were published under the title
of Pensées ("Thoughts"). He described many fundamental themes common
to what would be known as existentialism two and three centuries later.
Pascal argued that without a God, life would be meaningless and miserable.
People would only be able to create obstacles and overcome them in an
attempt to escape boredom. These token-victories would ultimately become
meaningless, since people would eventually die. This was good enough
reason not to choose to become an atheist, according to Pascal.
1
DISCUSSION
Types of Existentialism
Atheistic Existentialism
Theistic Existentialism
Theistic existentialism is, for the most part, Christian in its outlook, but
there have been existentialists of other theological persuasions (like
Judaism). The main thing that sets them apart from atheistic existentialists is
that they posit the existence of God, and that He is the source of our being. It
is generally held that God has designed the world in such a way that we
must define our own lives, and each individual is held accountable for his or
her own self-definition. God is incomprehensibly paradoxical (this is
exemplified in the incarnation of Christ); theism is not rationally justifiable,
and belief in God is the ultimate leap of faith.
Nihilism
What sets existential nihilists apart from pure nihilists is the fact that,
while nihilists don't believe in any meaning at all, existential nihilists only
believe this in relation to any sort of meaning to life (though this position is
implied in "regular" nihilism, and existential nihilists may also subscribe to
the full nihilistic view, existential nihilism is a separate view). While other
existentialists will allow for meaning in people's lives (that meaning they
themselves inject into it), existential nihilists will deny that this meaning is
anything but self-deception. Existential nihilists could thus seem to be more
2
pessimistic than the other existentialists, but even here, conclusions vary.
Some will claim that the best thing to do is to commit suicide while others
will claim that the lack of objective meaning to life means you should just do
as you wish - a hedonism of sorts. There also are those who hold that
nihilism is both a necessary burden of the authentic thinker and a source of
dread, pushing them to hold in suspension his or her tendency to accept the
reality of values while maintaining the unfulfilled desire for their discovery.
Major concepts
3
apparent contrast with our pre-reflexive lived lives which normally present
themselves to us as meaningful. A central theme is that since the world "in-
itself" is absurd, that is, "not fair," then a meaningful life can at any point
suddenly lose all its meaning. The reasons why this happens are many,
ranging from a tragedy that "tears a person's world apart," to the results of
an honest inquiry into one's own existence. Such an encounter can make a
person mentally unstable, and avoiding such instability by making people
aware of their condition and ready to handle it is one of the central themes
of existentialism. Albert Camus, for instance, famously claimed that "there is
only one truly serious philosophical problem, and that is suicide."
Dread
4
child's individuation. As such, the very condition of freedom can be said to be
a part of any individual's self.
Bad Faith
Bad Faith is seen as any denial of free will by lying to oneself about
one's self and freedom. This can take many forms, from convincing oneself
that some form of determinism is true, to a sort of "mimicry" where one acts
as "one should." How "one" should act is often determined by an image one
has of how one such as oneself (say, a bank manager) acts. This image
usually corresponds to some sort of social norm.
This doesn't mean that all acting in accordance with social norms is
bad faith: The main point is the attitude one takes to one's own freedom, and
the extent to which one acts in accordance with this freedom. A sign of bad
faith can be something like the denial of responsibility for something one has
done on the grounds that one just did "as one does" or that one's genes
determined one to do as one did. Exactly how one lies to oneself is hard to
get a hold of. Sartre denies the subconscious the power to do this, and he
claims that the person who is lying to him/herself has to be aware that
he/she is lying - that he/she isn't determined, or this "thing" he/she makes
him/herself out to be.
Freedom
5
What isn't implied in this account of existential freedom, however, is
that one's values are immutable; a consideration of one's values may cause
one to reconsider and change them (though this rarely happens). A
consequence of this fact is that one is not only responsible for one's actions,
but also for the values one holds. This entails that a reference to "common
values" doesn't "excuse" the individual's actions, because, even though
these are the values of the society he is part of, they are also his own in the
sense that he could choose them to be different at any time. Thus, the focus
on freedom in existentialism is related to the limits of the responsibility one
bears as a result of one's freedom: The relationship between freedom and
responsibility is one of interdependency, and a clarification of freedom also
clarifies what one is responsible for.
6
Another characteristic feature of the Look is that no Other really needs
to have been there: It is quite possible that the creaking floorboard was
nothing but the movement of an old house; the Look isn't some kind of
mystical telepathic experience of the actual way the other sees you (there
may also have been someone there, but he could have not noticed that you
were there, or he could be another Peeping Tom who just wants to join you).
In a similar vein, Camus believed that society and religion falsely teach
humans that "the other" has order and structure. For Camus, when an
individual's "consciousness", longing for order, collides with "the other's" lack
of order, a third element is born: "absurdity".
The Absurd
The notion of the Absurd contains the idea that there is no meaning to
be found in the world beyond what meaning we give to it. This
meaninglessness also encompasses the amorality or "unfairness" of the
world. This contrasts with "karmic" ways of thinking in which "bad things
don't happen to good people"; to the world, metaphorically speaking, there is
7
no such thing as a good person or a bad thing; what happens happens, and it
may just as well happen to a good person as to a bad person.
Religious Existentialists
Many Christians have never studied philosophy formally and are unfamiliar
with the mainstream of existentialist thought. However, they have heard of a
stream of existential thought that appears to be paradoxical. It is known as
religious or Christian existentialism. Many Christians have at least a vague
familiarity with some of the ideas of Karl Barth, Paul Tillich, and Rudolph
Bultmarm. We will not argue whether or not one can be religious and an
existentialist at the same time. There are competent observers on both sides
of the question.
Almost every knowledgeable observer, from either side, will agree that
religious existentialism is not the same as orthodox existentialism. Even the
term "orthodox existentialism" is a problem since the field is so diverse and
the prominent existential thinkers don’t agree about what existentialism is.
8
label; some adherents of the religious view prefer to be known as Neo-
Orthodox philosophers (Sahakian and Sahakian, Ideas, p. 167).
Kierkegaard's Philosophy
I. The Aesthetic
The man in the first stage, the aesthetic, is looking for fulfillment from his
outside activities and from within himself. He may seek romance, pleasure,
or intellectual pursuits as means to satisfy himself. However, these activities
are not enough. They are not ultimately satisfying. The man becomes bored
with himself and his activities. This boredom turns to despair. If not checked,
the despair ends in suicide.
What is the remedy for this aesthetic despair? Kierkegaard replied that
commitment gives meaning to life. Commitment to some arbitrary absolute,
and the ordering of one's life around that commitment, brings one out of the
aesthetic stage and into the second or ethical stage. The person achieves
selfhood through commitment. The individual becomes aware. His choices
are made with passion and emotional commitment. The person now chooses
and acts, thereby establishing his selfhood and integrity. He is a man of duty.
This is the type of person described by psychotherapist Viktor Frankl, who
revolutionized European psychoanalytic theory after World War II. He calls
the ethical urge the "will to meaning" and says:
Man's search for meaning is a primary force in his life and not a "secondary
rationalization” of instinctual drives. This meaning is unique and specific in
that it must and can be fulfilled by him alone; only then does it achieve a
significance that will satisfy his own will to meaning. There are some authors
9
who contend that meanings and values are "nothing but defense
mechanisms, reaction formations and sublimation." But as for myself, I would
not be willing to live merely for the sake of my "defense mechanisms," nor
would I be ready to die merely for the sake of my "reaction formations." Man,
however, is able to live and even to die for the sake of his ideals and values!
(Viktor E. Frankl, Man's Search for Meaning: an Introduction to Logotherapy,
NY Simon and Schuster, Inc., 1963, pp. 154, 155).
The third and greatest stage, the stage where man finally finds contentment,
is the religious stage. The person commits himself, as in the second stage,
and is looking for fulfillment, as in the first stage, but in this religious stage
his commitment is to One who is able to satisfy completely: God. In this
stage man is finally content because of his commitment to God. Selfhood
cannot be achieved ultimately and completely within the self. The self must
be committed to the One beyond, to God.
William Sahakian made some good contrasts between the concerns of Hegel
and the concerns of Kierkegaard:
10
system, Kierkegaard in paradox. The former sought the universe, the latter
the individual or particular. The former saw in logic a mediation of anitheses
or formulated an unbroken logic (Hegelian dialectic); the latter replaced it
with the leap or logical gap (qualitative dialectic). Either/Or was the
Kierkegaarthan answer to the Hegelian synthesis or mediation. Hegel found
truth in the Absolute and objectivity, while Kierkegaard found it in the
relative and subjective. Hegel emphasized necessity, Kierkegaard freedom.
The Christian philosophers Norman Geisler and Paul Feinberg point out a very
important feature of Kierkegaardian "truth." They note that Kierkegaard
never denies such a thing as objective truth: he merely denies its importance
over what he calls "subjective" truth.
While not denying that there is such a thing as objective scientific truth, the
existentialist does not consider that kind of truth important, at least not
nearly as important as subjective truth. Indeed, Kierkegaard declared "truth
is subjectivity." By that he did not mean that any subjective belief is true, but
that unless one believes something subjectively and passionately he does
not possess the truth. Truth is always personal and not merely propositional.
One never gains truth by mere observation, but by obedience: never by
being a spectator, but only by being a participator in life.
11
Truth is found in the concrete, not in the abstract: in the existential, not in
the rational. In fact, one places himself in the truth only by an act of his will,
by a "leap of faith” It is not deliberation of the mind but a decision of the will
by which one comes to know truth (Norman L. Geisler and Paul D. Feinberg,
Introduction to Philosophy, Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Book House, 1980, p.
46).
In Latin America and Europe, excluding, of course, the Soviet Union and her
European satellites, one of the dominant contemporary philosophers is
Heidegger. Heidegger's influence ranges widely over philosophers,
theologians (including Paul Tillich), and certain psychotherapists. In the
English-speaking world, too, there are philosophers who regard Heidegger
with as much respect as do his Continental and Latin-American admirers
(Alston and Nakhnikian, Readings, p. 679).
12
Heidegger's writings had a great effect on both the religious existentialist
Rudolph Bultmann, who attempted to build a theology from Heideggerian
existentialism, and jean-Paul Sartre, the French secular existentialist and
novelist.
13
Along with the difficulty in understanding Heidegger, and the added difficulty
of interpretation, we find that Heidegger did not view himself as an
existentialist!
Heidegger believes that the term "existentialist" does not apply to his
philosophy ... Heidegger grants that "existentialism” is an apt label for what
Sartre represents, but not for his own position. Heidegger is interested in
Being. He approaches the problem of Being through the study of Dasein,
Heidegger's word for human existence, "the being of what we ourselves are"
(Alston and Naklmikian, Readings, p. 680).
Dasein
Dasein (being-there), that is, the human Being or the human existent,
Heidegger identified as: (1) concern (Sorge), (2) being-toward-death (Sein
zum Tode), (3) existence (Existenz), and (4) moods (Stimmungen). The
human Being's essence is in his existence, for numerous possibilities are
open to him whereby he may choose different kinds of Being for himself. The
possibilities of what he may become are the pivotal points by which the
human being is oriented. Heidegger was greatly interested in interpreting
time in terms of temporality; consequently, in addition to the problem of
Being (Dasein), time is of utmost importance. Accordingly, his interest was in
the Being and temporality of Dasein (human existence) (Sahakian,
Philosophy, p. 349).
14
Angst
Angst is another term with heavy existential meaning for Heidegger. The
German word refers to anxiety, dread and hopeless fear of the future. This
concept is important to Heidegger because it forms the impetus for much of
human metaphysical development. It is the goad toward human existential
encounter.
Death
For Heidegger, man is the being that knows he is going to die. He dies not
only at the end of life, but every day of it. Death is certain, yet indefinite.
Because it is inevitable it marks the contingency of life. Life is cast up
between nothing and nothing. Death is its boundary and is its supreme
possibility.
To freely accept death, to live in its presence, and to acknowledge that for it
there is no substitute and into it one must go alone, is to escape from all
illusions and to achieve genuine dignity and authentic existence (Fuller,
Philosophy, p. 608).
The man who most popularized an atheistic brand of existentialism was the
French philosopher, Jean-Paul Sartre. Sartre's major work, Being and
Nothingness, was written in 1943 while he was a prisoner of the Germans
during World War 111. Some of his other writings, including Existentialism is
Humanism and the novel, No Exit, reflect an indebtedness to both
Kierkegaard and Heidegger. Sartre's great ability enabled him to have a clear
understanding of the history of philosophy. Marjorie Greene reports:
15
[Sartre] does indeed use the thinkers of the past (and present) for his own
ends, but at the same time he sees them with extraordinary clarity. In his
references, say, to Kant or Spinoza, he not only uses their thought as a
springboard for his own, but also exhibits a solid and scholarly penetration
into their principles and views. His relation to Marx is less straightforward, as
we shall see, but in general one finds in his philosophical works an
interweaving of themes in which the original strands stand out for
themselves with unusual distinctness, while at the same time they are being
worked into a characteristically Sartrean pattern (Marjorie Green, Sartre, NY.
Franklin Watts, Inc., 1973, p. 33).
Absurdity
One major tenet of Sartre's existentialism is that life is absurd. In his novel,
Nausea, Sartre brings out the absurdity of life through his main character,
Roquentin. Robert Davidson writes;
The story of Roquentin, the hero of Nausea, is not told as an end in itself.
Actually it expresses Sartre's own view concerning human existence. This
story provides a descriptive or phenomenological account of a man's growing
realization of the absurdity of human life in itself, and of his awakening to the
fact that if a man’s life is to have any meaning or purpose, the individual
himself must confer that meaning upon it. A sense of the absurd, the
absurdity of life and of man himself, permeates Sartre's early existentialism.
In Nausea he portrays this as an immediate insight in one’s own experience.
As he sat in a public park one day, staring at the long black roots of an old
chestnut tree, Roquentin became acutely aware of the absurdity of his own
existence:
"Absurdity was not an idea in my head nor the sound of a voice. It was this
long, lean, wooden snake curled up at my feet - snake or claw or talon or
root, it was all the same. Without formulating anything I knew that I had
found the clue to my existence, to my nausea to my life. And indeed
everything I have ever grasped since that moment comes back to this
fundamental absurdity" (Robert E Davidson, Philosophies Men Live By, NY:
Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc., 1974, p. 362).
Man is Autonomous
The existentialist, on the contrary, thinks it very distressing that God does
not exist, because all possibility of finding values in a heaven of ideas
disappears along with Him; there can no longer be an a priori Good, since
16
there is no infinite and perfect consciousness to think it. Nowhere is it written
that the Good exists, that we must be honest, that we must not lie: because
the fact is we are on a plane where there are only men.
Dostoevsky said, 'If God didn’t exist, everything would be possible! That is
the very starting point of existentialism. Indeed, everything is permissible if
God does not exist, and as a result man is forlorn, because neither within him
nor without does he find anything to cling to. He cant start making excuses
for himself. In other words, there is no determinism, man is free, man is
freedom. On the other hand, if God does not exist, we find no values or
commands to turn to which legitimize our conduct. So, in the bright realm of
values, we have no excuse behind us, nor justification before us. We are
alone, with no excuses (Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism and Human
Emotions, NY. The Citadel Press, n.d., pp. 22, 23).
Freedom
Man comes into the scene and defines himself. He lives in absolute freedom.
Sartre states:
That is the idea I shall try to convey when I say that man is condemned to be
free. Condemned, because he did not create himself, yet, in other respects is
free; because, once thrown into the world, he is responsible for everything he
does. The existentialist does not believe in the power of passion. He will
never agree that a sweeping passion is a ravaging torrent which fatally leads
a man to certain acts and is therefore an excuse. He thinks that man is
responsible for his passion (ibid., p. 23).
17
toward existence (ibid., pp. 15-16).
[It is that] choice that is called "will". But if existence really does precede
essence, man is responsible for what he is. Thus, existentialism's first move
is to make every man aware of what he is and to make the full responsibility
of his existence rest on him. And when we say that a man is responsible for
himself, we do not only mean that he is responsible for his own individuality,
but that he is responsible for all men (ibid., p. 16).
Fulfillment
Sartre believed that man could receive his own self-fulfillment, as Sahakian
reports:
Thus, man makes his own fulfillment. Those who try to accomplish this
through religion are guilty of bad faith, as Flew defines:
Forlornness
One of the major themes Sartre dealt with is also (not surprisingly) one for
which he is perhaps best known, the theme of forlornness. It arises out of
18
existential individuality and subjectivity. In some ways, it resembles
Kierkegaard's second and unsatisfying stage, where man realizes he is alone,
determines an ethic, but has nothing on which to depend. Sartre himself
presented a moving description of this forlornness in the previously cited
Existentialism and Human Emotion:
The boy was faced with the choice of leaving for England and joining the Free
French Forces - that is, leaving his mother behind - or remaining with his
mother and helping her to carry on. He was fully aware that the woman lived
only for him and that his going-off -and perhaps his death -would plunge her
into despair. He was also aware that every act that he did for his mother's
sake was a sure thing, in the sense that it was helping her to carry on,
whereas every effort he made toward going off and fighting was an uncertain
move which might run aground and prove completely useless; for example,
on his way to England he might, while passing through Spain, be detained
indefinitely in a Spanish camp; he might reach England or Algiers and be
stuck in an office at a desk job. As a result, he was faced with two very
different kinds of action: one, concrete, immediate, but vaster group, a
national collectivity, but for that very reason was dubious, and might be
interrupted en route. And, at the same time, he was wavering between two
kinds of ethics.
Who could help him choose? Christian doctrine? No. Christian doctrine says,
"Be charitable, love your neighbor, take the more rugged path, etc., etc” But
which is the more rugged path? Whom should he love as a brother? The
fighting man or his mother? Which does the greater good, the vague act of
fighting in a group, or the concrete one of helping a particular human being
to go on living? Who can decide a priori? Nobody No book of ethics can tell
him. The Kantian ethics says, "Never treat any person as a means, but as an
end." Very well, if I stay with my mother, I'll treat her as an end and not as a
means; but by virtue of this very fact, I'm running the risk of treating the
people around me who are fighting, as means; and, conversely, if I go to join
19
those who are fighting, I'll be treating them as an end, and, by doing that, I
run the risk of treating my mother as a means.
If values are vague, and if they are always too broad for the concrete and
specific case that we are considering, the only thing left for us is to trust our
instincts. That's what this young man tried to do; and when I saw him, he
said, "In the end, feeling is what counts. I ought to choose whichever pushes
me in one direction. If I feel that I love my mother enough to sacrifice
everything else for her -my desire for vengeance, for action, for adventure
then I'll stay with her. If, on the contrary, I feel that my love for my mother
isn't enough, I'll leave.
But how is the value of a feeling determined? What gives his feeling for his
mother value? Precisely the fact that he remained with her. I may say that I
like so-and-so well enough to sacrifice a certain amount of money for him,
but I may say so only if I've done it. I may say "I love my mother well enough
to remain with her" if I have remained with her. The only way to determine
the value of this affection is, precisely, to perform an act which confirms and
defines it. But, since I require this affection to justify my act, I find myself
caught in a vicious circle. (Sartre, Existentialism, pp. 24-27).
From this we can see the futility inherent in Sartre's existential thought.
Since "existence precedes essence," and the individual is enveloped within
"subjectivity" and must find his essence of "authenticity," he is truly alone.
Many people have embraced existentialism for a time, sincerely thinking that
its view of life is accurate. However, many leave existentialism because it
offers a solution, meaning, and commitment which is not truly satisfying.
Even Sartre, toward the end of his life, swung very close to theistic
commitment. The magazine National Review reported it this way:
However, during the philosopher's last months there were some surprising
developments. In 1980, nearing his death, by then blind, decrepit, but still in
full possession of his faculties, Sartre came very close to belief in God,
perhaps even more than very close.
The story can be told briefly, and perhaps reverently. An ex-Maoist, Pierre
Victor, shared much of Sartre's time toward the end. In the early spring of
1980 the two had a dialogue in the pages of the ultra-gauchiste Nouvel
Observateur. It is sufficient to quote a single sentence from what Sartre said
then to measure the degree of his acceptance of the grace of God and the
creatureliness of man: "I do not feel that I am the product of chance, a speck
20
of dust in the universe, but someone who was expected, prepared,
prefigured. In short, a being whom only a Creator could put here: and this
idea of a creating hand refers to God."
Students of existentialism, the atheistic branch, will note that in this one
sentence Sartre disavowed his entire system, his engagements, his whole
life. Voltaire converted on his deathbed; one never knows, the brilliant old
rascal is supposed to have said. Sartre did not convert, at least outwardly,
but came to understand. Everything ought to be forgiven hi
21