Final Existentialism

Download as doc
Download as doc
You are on page 1of 21
At a glance
Powered by AI
The key takeaways are that existentialism emphasizes individual existence, freedom and choice. It also discusses the notion that existence precedes essence.

The main types of existentialism discussed are atheistic existentialism, theistic existentialism, and nihilism.

Atheistic existentialism rejects the notion of God while theistic existentialism posits the existence of God as the source of being. Theistic existentialism also believes that individuals must define their own lives.

INTRODUCTION

Existentialism is a philosophical movement which emphasizes on


individual existence, freedom, and choice.

There are several philosophical positions all related to existential


philosophy but the main identifiable common proposition, is that existence
precedes essence. By this, existentialism states that man exists and in that
existence man defines himself and the world in his own subjectivity, and
wanders between choice, freedom, and existential angst.

The first philosopher to use the term was Soren Kierkegaard (1813 -
1855), who reacted against systematic rational philosophy, specially Hegel,
and grasped the notion of a truth inside of the evolving self.

Deriving from this stress on existence there are other main subjects
and images that have been developed by the existentialists.

Historical background

Existential themes have been hinted at throughout history. Examples


include the Buddha's teachings, the Bible in the Book of Ecclesiastes and
Book of Job, Saint Augustine in his Confessions, Averroes' school of
philosophy, Saint Thomas Aquinas' writings, and Mulla Sadra's transcendent
theosophy. Individualist political theories, such as those advanced by John
Locke, advocated individual autonomy and self-determination rather than
state rule over the individual. This kind of political philosophy, although not
existential per se, provided a welcoming climate for existentialism.

In 1670, Blaise Pascal’s unfinished notes were published under the title
of Pensées ("Thoughts"). He described many fundamental themes common
to what would be known as existentialism two and three centuries later.
Pascal argued that without a God, life would be meaningless and miserable.
People would only be able to create obstacles and overcome them in an
attempt to escape boredom. These token-victories would ultimately become
meaningless, since people would eventually die. This was good enough
reason not to choose to become an atheist, according to Pascal.

Existentialism, in its currently recognizable 20th century form, was


inspired by Søren Kierkegaard, Dostoyevsky and the German philosophers
Friedrich Nietzsche, Edmund Husserl, and Martin Heidegger. It became
popular in the mid-20th century through the works of the French writer-
philosophers Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir, whose versions of it
were set out in a popular form in Sartre's 1946 Existentialism is a Humanism
and Beauvoir's The Ethics of Ambiguity.

1
DISCUSSION

Types of Existentialism

Atheistic Existentialism

Atheistic Existentialism is the form of existentialism most commonly


encountered in today's society. What sets it apart from theistic existentialism
is that it rejects the notion of a god and his transcendent will that should in
some way dictate how we should live. It rejects the notion that there is any
"created" meaning to life and the world, and that a leap of faith is required of
man in order for him to live an authentic life.

In this kind of existentialism, belief in god is often considered a form of


Bad Faith.

Theistic Existentialism

Theistic existentialism is, for the most part, Christian in its outlook, but
there have been existentialists of other theological persuasions (like
Judaism). The main thing that sets them apart from atheistic existentialists is
that they posit the existence of God, and that He is the source of our being. It
is generally held that God has designed the world in such a way that we
must define our own lives, and each individual is held accountable for his or
her own self-definition. God is incomprehensibly paradoxical (this is
exemplified in the incarnation of Christ); theism is not rationally justifiable,
and belief in God is the ultimate leap of faith.

Nihilism

Though nihilism isn't existentialism, and existentialism isn't nihilism, these


two philosophies are often confused. While a sort of nihilistic existentialism
does indeed exist, it isn't as radical as pure nihilism. Another reason why
these philosophies are often confused is that Friedrich Nietzsche is a central
philosopher in both.

What sets existential nihilists apart from pure nihilists is the fact that,
while nihilists don't believe in any meaning at all, existential nihilists only
believe this in relation to any sort of meaning to life (though this position is
implied in "regular" nihilism, and existential nihilists may also subscribe to
the full nihilistic view, existential nihilism is a separate view). While other
existentialists will allow for meaning in people's lives (that meaning they
themselves inject into it), existential nihilists will deny that this meaning is
anything but self-deception. Existential nihilists could thus seem to be more

2
pessimistic than the other existentialists, but even here, conclusions vary.
Some will claim that the best thing to do is to commit suicide while others
will claim that the lack of objective meaning to life means you should just do
as you wish - a hedonism of sorts. There also are those who hold that
nihilism is both a necessary burden of the authentic thinker and a source of
dread, pushing them to hold in suspension his or her tendency to accept the
reality of values while maintaining the unfulfilled desire for their discovery.

Major concepts

Existence Precedes Essence

A central proposition of existentialism is that existence precedes


essence. This amounts to the assertion that the outer manifestation
(existence) of an entity is more determinative than its inner being (essence).
Asserting that "existence precedes essence" is a rebellion against the
Platonic Ideas, the Forms, which in Plato's philosophy are the true reality
behind appearances of things in the world.

When it is said that man defines himself, it is often perceived as stating


that man can "wish" to be something - anything, a bird, for instance - and
then be it. According to Sartre's own account, however, this would rather be
a kind of bad faith. What is meant by the statement is that man is (1) defined
only insofar as he acts and (2) that he is responsible for his actions. To
clarify, it can be said that a man who acts cruelly towards other people is, by
that act, defined as a cruel man and in that same instance, he (as opposed
to his genes, for instance) is defined as being responsible for being this cruel
man. Of course, the more positive therapeutic aspect of this is also implied:
You can choose to act in a different way, and to be a good person instead of
a cruel person. Here it is also clear that since man can choose to be either
cruel or good, he is, in fact, neither of these things essentially.

To claim, then, that existence precedes essence is to assert that there


is no such predetermined essence to be found in man, and that an
individual's essence is defined by him or her through how he or she creates
and lives his or her life. As Sartre puts it in his Existentialism is a Humanism:
"man first of all exists, encounters himself, surges up in the world – and
defines himself afterwards."

Existentialism tends to focus on the question of human existence and


the conditions of this existence. What is meant by existence is the concrete
life of each individual, and his concrete ways of being in the world. Even
though this concrete individual existence must be the primary source of
information in the study of man, certain conditions are commonly held to be
"endemic" to human existence. These conditions are usually in some way
related to the inherent meaninglessness or absurdity of the earth and its

3
apparent contrast with our pre-reflexive lived lives which normally present
themselves to us as meaningful. A central theme is that since the world "in-
itself" is absurd, that is, "not fair," then a meaningful life can at any point
suddenly lose all its meaning. The reasons why this happens are many,
ranging from a tragedy that "tears a person's world apart," to the results of
an honest inquiry into one's own existence. Such an encounter can make a
person mentally unstable, and avoiding such instability by making people
aware of their condition and ready to handle it is one of the central themes
of existentialism. Albert Camus, for instance, famously claimed that "there is
only one truly serious philosophical problem, and that is suicide."

Aside from these "psychological" issues, it is also claimed that these


encounters with the absurd are where we are most in touch with our
condition as humans. Such an encounter cannot be without philosophical
significance, and existentialist philosophers derive many metaphysical
theories from these encounters. These are often related to the self,
consciousness and freedom as well as the nature of meaning.

Dread

Dread, sometimes called angst, anxiety or even anguish is a term that


is common to many existentialist thinkers. Although its concrete properties
may vary slightly, it is generally held to be the experience of our freedom
and responsibility. The archetypal example is the example of the experience
one has when standing on a cliff where one not only fears falling off it, but
also dreads the possibility of throwing oneself off. In this experience that
"nothing is holding me back," one senses the lack of anything that
predetermines you to either throw yourself off or to stand still, and one
experiences one's own freedom.

It is also claimed, most famously by Sartre, that dread is the fear of


nothing (no thing). This relates both to the inherent insecurity about the
consequences of one's actions (related to the absurdity of the world), and to
the fact that, in experiencing one's freedom, one also realises that one will
be fully responsible for these consequences; there is no thing in you (your
genes, for instance) that acts and that you can "blame" if something goes
wrong. Of course, most of us only have short and shallow encounters with
this kind of dread, as not every choice is perceived as having dreadful
possible consequences (and, it can be claimed, our lives would be
unbearable if every choice facilitated dread), but that doesn't change the
fact that freedom remains a condition of every action.

It is also worth noting that Søren Kierkegaard, in his The Concept of


Dread, maintains that dread, when experienced by the young child in facing
the possibility of responsibility for his actions, is one of the main forces in the

4
child's individuation. As such, the very condition of freedom can be said to be
a part of any individual's self.

Bad Faith

Bad Faith is seen as any denial of free will by lying to oneself about
one's self and freedom. This can take many forms, from convincing oneself
that some form of determinism is true, to a sort of "mimicry" where one acts
as "one should." How "one" should act is often determined by an image one
has of how one such as oneself (say, a bank manager) acts. This image
usually corresponds to some sort of social norm.

This doesn't mean that all acting in accordance with social norms is
bad faith: The main point is the attitude one takes to one's own freedom, and
the extent to which one acts in accordance with this freedom. A sign of bad
faith can be something like the denial of responsibility for something one has
done on the grounds that one just did "as one does" or that one's genes
determined one to do as one did. Exactly how one lies to oneself is hard to
get a hold of. Sartre denies the subconscious the power to do this, and he
claims that the person who is lying to him/herself has to be aware that
he/she is lying - that he/she isn't determined, or this "thing" he/she makes
him/herself out to be.

Freedom

The existentialist concept of freedom is often misunderstood as a sort


of liberum arbitrium where almost anything is possible and where values are
inconsequential to choice and action. This interpretation of the concept is
often related to the insistence on the absurdity of the world and that there
are no absolutely "good" or "bad" values.

However, that there are no values to be found in the world in-itself


doesn't mean that there are no values: Each of us usually already has his
values before a consideration of their validity is carried through, and it is,
after all, upon these values we act. In Kierkegaard's Judge Vilhelm's account
in Either/Or, making "choices" without allowing one's values to confer
differing values to the alternatives, is, in fact, choosing not to make a choice
- to "flip a coin," as it were, and to leave everything to chance. This is
considered to be a refusal to live in the consequence of one's freedom,
meaning it quickly becomes a sort of bad faith. As such, existentialist
freedom isn't situated in some kind of abstract space where everything is
possible: Since man is free, and since he already exists in this world, it is
implied that his freedom is only in this world, and that it, too, is restricted by
it.

5
What isn't implied in this account of existential freedom, however, is
that one's values are immutable; a consideration of one's values may cause
one to reconsider and change them (though this rarely happens). A
consequence of this fact is that one is not only responsible for one's actions,
but also for the values one holds. This entails that a reference to "common
values" doesn't "excuse" the individual's actions, because, even though
these are the values of the society he is part of, they are also his own in the
sense that he could choose them to be different at any time. Thus, the focus
on freedom in existentialism is related to the limits of the responsibility one
bears as a result of one's freedom: The relationship between freedom and
responsibility is one of interdependency, and a clarification of freedom also
clarifies what one is responsible for.

The Other and The Look

The Other (when written with a capitalised o) is a concept more


properly belonging to phenomenology and its account of intersubjectivity.
However, the concept has seen widespread use in existentialist writings, and
the conclusions drawn from it differ slightly from the phenomenological
accounts.

The experience of the Other is the experience of another free subject


who inhabits the same world as you do. In its most basic form, it is this
experience of the Other that constitutes intersubjectivity and objectivity. To
clarify, when one experiences someone else, and that this Other person
experiences the world (the same world that you experience), only from "over
there," the world itself is constituted as objective in that it is something that
is "there" as identical for both of the subjects; you experience the other
person as experiencing the same as you. This experience of the Other's look
is what is termed the Look (sometimes The Gaze).

While this experience, in its basic phenomenological sense, constitutes


the world as objective, and yourself as objectively existing subjectivity (you
experience yourself as seen in the Other's Look in precisely the same way
that you experience the Other as seen by you, as subjectivity), in
existentialism, it also acts as a kind of limitation of your freedom. This is
because the Look tends to objectify what it sees. As such, when one
experiences oneself in the Look, one doesn't experience oneself as nothing
(no thing), but as something. Sartre's own example of a man peeping at
someone through a keyhole can help clarify this: At first, this man is entirely
caught up in the situation he is in; he is in a pre-reflexive state where his
entire consciousness is directed at what goes on in the room. Suddenly, he
hears a creaking floorboard behind him, and he becomes aware of himself as
seen by the Other. He is thus filled with shame for he perceives himself as he
would perceive someone else doing what he was doing, as a Peeping Tom.

6
Another characteristic feature of the Look is that no Other really needs
to have been there: It is quite possible that the creaking floorboard was
nothing but the movement of an old house; the Look isn't some kind of
mystical telepathic experience of the actual way the other sees you (there
may also have been someone there, but he could have not noticed that you
were there, or he could be another Peeping Tom who just wants to join you).

Reason as a problematic defense against anxiety

Emphasizing action, freedom, and decision as fundamental,


existentialists oppose themselves to rationalism and positivism. That is, they
argue against definitions of human beings as primarily rational. Rather,
existentialists look at where people find meaning. Existentialism asserts that
people actually make decisions based on what has meaning to them rather
than what is rational.

The rejection of reason as the source of meaning is a common theme


of existentialist thought, as is the focus on the feelings of anxiety and dread
that we feel in the face of our own radical freedom and our awareness of
death. Kierkegaard saw rationality as a mechanism humans use to counter
their existential anxiety, their fear of being in the world: "If I can believe that
I am rational and everyone else is rational then I have nothing to fear and no
reason to feel anxious about being free."

Like Kierkegaard, Sartre saw problems with rationality, calling it a form


of "bad faith", an attempt by the self to impose structure on a world of
phenomena — "the other" — that is fundamentally irrational and random.
According to Sartre, rationality and other forms of bad faith hinder us from
finding meaning in freedom. To try to suppress our feelings of anxiety and
dread, we confine ourselves within everyday experience, Sartre asserts,
thereby relinquishing our freedom and acquiescing to being possessed in one
form or another by "the look" of "the other" (i.e. possessed by another
person - or at least our idea of that other person).

In a similar vein, Camus believed that society and religion falsely teach
humans that "the other" has order and structure. For Camus, when an
individual's "consciousness", longing for order, collides with "the other's" lack
of order, a third element is born: "absurdity".

The Absurd

The notion of the Absurd contains the idea that there is no meaning to
be found in the world beyond what meaning we give to it. This
meaninglessness also encompasses the amorality or "unfairness" of the
world. This contrasts with "karmic" ways of thinking in which "bad things
don't happen to good people"; to the world, metaphorically speaking, there is

7
no such thing as a good person or a bad thing; what happens happens, and it
may just as well happen to a good person as to a bad person.

This contrasts our daily experience where most things appear to us as


meaningful, and where good people do indeed, on occasion, receive some
sort of "reward" for their goodness. Most existentialist thinkers, however, will
maintain that this is not a necessary feature of the world, and that it
definitely isn't a property of the world in-itself. Because of the world's
absurdity, at any point in time, anything can happen to anyone, and a tragic
event could plummet someone into direct confrontation with the Absurd.

The notion of the absurd has been prominent in literature throughout


history. Franz Kafka, Fyodor Dostoevsky and many of the literary works of
Jean-Paul Sartre and Albert Camus contain descriptions of people who
encounter the absurdity of the world.

Arguably, the most extensive existentialist study of "the absurd" was


done by Albert Camus in his classic essay The Myth of Sisyphus.

Religious Existentialists

Many Christians have never studied philosophy formally and are unfamiliar
with the mainstream of existentialist thought. However, they have heard of a
stream of existential thought that appears to be paradoxical. It is known as
religious or Christian existentialism. Many Christians have at least a vague
familiarity with some of the ideas of Karl Barth, Paul Tillich, and Rudolph
Bultmarm. We will not argue whether or not one can be religious and an
existentialist at the same time. There are competent observers on both sides
of the question.

Almost every knowledgeable observer, from either side, will agree that
religious existentialism is not the same as orthodox existentialism. Even the
term "orthodox existentialism" is a problem since the field is so diverse and
the prominent existential thinkers don’t agree about what existentialism is.

Nevertheless, religious existentialists are concerned with some of the same


themes as are non-religious existentialists. They just address them from
different (religious) perspectives.
The Sahakians separate these two types of existentialists in much the same
way as we will. They write:

Two main schools of Existentialist philosophy may be distinguished; the first


is religious as delineated by the father of Existentialism, Soren Aabye
Kierkegaard (1813-1855); the second is atheistic, as expounded by its most
articulate contemporary spokesman, jean-Paul Sartre. A number of
outstanding Existentialists in each of these schools disclaim the Existentialist

8
label; some adherents of the religious view prefer to be known as Neo-
Orthodox philosophers (Sahakian and Sahakian, Ideas, p. 167).

Kierkegaard's Philosophy

William S. Sahakian has concisely summarized Kierkegaard's main tenets:

The essence of Kierkegaard's philosophy can be seen in his doctrine that


there are three stages of life experience: (1) aesthetic, (2) ethical, and (3)
religious. These represent three attitudes toward life, three philosophies of
life. Some of us progress from one stage to the next, while others never go
beyond the first stage. Kierkegaard sometimes fused the second and third
stages, referring to them as the religio-ethical. The third stage is superior to
the other two stages. All of them reflect man’s attempt to win salvation, to
gain satisfaction for life's greatest good, while it is still within reach.
Kierkegaard discussed the three stages in a number of his writings, but he
devoted a most famous work, Either/Or, to a detailed analysis of the first two
stages (William S. Sahakian, History of Philosophy, NY. Barnes and Noble
Company, Inc., 1968, p. 343).

I. The Aesthetic

The man in the first stage, the aesthetic, is looking for fulfillment from his
outside activities and from within himself. He may seek romance, pleasure,
or intellectual pursuits as means to satisfy himself. However, these activities
are not enough. They are not ultimately satisfying. The man becomes bored
with himself and his activities. This boredom turns to despair. If not checked,
the despair ends in suicide.

II. The Ethical

What is the remedy for this aesthetic despair? Kierkegaard replied that
commitment gives meaning to life. Commitment to some arbitrary absolute,
and the ordering of one's life around that commitment, brings one out of the
aesthetic stage and into the second or ethical stage. The person achieves
selfhood through commitment. The individual becomes aware. His choices
are made with passion and emotional commitment. The person now chooses
and acts, thereby establishing his selfhood and integrity. He is a man of duty.
This is the type of person described by psychotherapist Viktor Frankl, who
revolutionized European psychoanalytic theory after World War II. He calls
the ethical urge the "will to meaning" and says:

Man's search for meaning is a primary force in his life and not a "secondary
rationalization” of instinctual drives. This meaning is unique and specific in
that it must and can be fulfilled by him alone; only then does it achieve a
significance that will satisfy his own will to meaning. There are some authors

9
who contend that meanings and values are "nothing but defense
mechanisms, reaction formations and sublimation." But as for myself, I would
not be willing to live merely for the sake of my "defense mechanisms," nor
would I be ready to die merely for the sake of my "reaction formations." Man,
however, is able to live and even to die for the sake of his ideals and values!
(Viktor E. Frankl, Man's Search for Meaning: an Introduction to Logotherapy,
NY Simon and Schuster, Inc., 1963, pp. 154, 155).

III. The Religious

The third and greatest stage, the stage where man finally finds contentment,
is the religious stage. The person commits himself, as in the second stage,
and is looking for fulfillment, as in the first stage, but in this religious stage
his commitment is to One who is able to satisfy completely: God. In this
stage man is finally content because of his commitment to God. Selfhood
cannot be achieved ultimately and completely within the self. The self must
be committed to the One beyond, to God.

Kierkegaard and Hegel

Kierkegaard's philosophy was in opposition to that of the German philosopher


Hegel, although they both used a system of dialectics. Samuel Stumpf points
out:

At the University of Copenhagen Kierkegaard was trained in Hegel's


philosophy and was not favorably impressed by it. When he heard
Schellings's lectures at Berlin, which were critical of Hegel, Kierkegaard
agreed with this attack upon Germany's greatest speculative thinker. "If
Hegel had written the whole of his Logic and then said ... that it was merely
an experiment in thought," wrote Kierkegaard, "then he could certainly have
been the greatest thinker who ever lived. As it is, he is merely comic." What
made Hegel comic for Kierkegaard was that this great philosopher had tried
to capture all of reality in his system of thought, yet in the process lost the
most important element, namely, existence. For Kierkegaard, the term
existence was reserved for the individual human being. To exist, he said,
implies being a certain kind of individual, an individual who strives, who
considers alternatives, who chooses, who decides, and who, above all,
commits himself. Virtually none of these acts were implied in Hegel's
philosophy (Stumpf, Socrates, p. 455).

William Sahakian made some good contrasts between the concerns of Hegel
and the concerns of Kierkegaard:

Kierkegaardian philosophy is fundamentally in direct antithesis to


Hegelianism. Whereas Hegel placed the emphasis on speculative thought,
Kierkegaard placed it on existence. Hegel discerned truth in the rational

10
system, Kierkegaard in paradox. The former sought the universe, the latter
the individual or particular. The former saw in logic a mediation of anitheses
or formulated an unbroken logic (Hegelian dialectic); the latter replaced it
with the leap or logical gap (qualitative dialectic). Either/Or was the
Kierkegaarthan answer to the Hegelian synthesis or mediation. Hegel found
truth in the Absolute and objectivity, while Kierkegaard found it in the
relative and subjective. Hegel emphasized necessity, Kierkegaard freedom.

Other Kierkegaarthan concepts, which replaced Hegelian ones were:


repetition for recollection, concealment for openness, possibility for actuality,
indirect communication (Socratic maimetic) for direct communication,
transcendence of God for the immanence of God, and mediacy (or reflection)
or immediacy (Sahakian Philosophy, p. 347).

Kierkegaard and Truth

Kierkegaard defined truth as "subjectivity." For him it was paradoxically the


only thing one could be sure about and yet the one thing one was anxious
about. Sahakian explains:

Truth is subjectivity; the highest expression of subjectivity is passion. To think


Existentially is to think with inward passion. Objectivity accents what is said,
but subjectivity accents how it is said. The inward how is passion; decision is
found only in subjectivity. Subjectivity is the truth; truth is defined as "an
objective uncertainty held fast in an appropriation-process of the most
passionate inwardness". Uncertainty creates anxiety which is quieted by an
exercise of faith. The preceding definition of truth also serves as a definition
of faith. There is no faith without risk, choice, passion, and inwardness; nor is
there truth without them. Uncertainty always accompanies subjectivity,
calling for the leap of faith (ibid., p. 348).

The Christian philosophers Norman Geisler and Paul Feinberg point out a very
important feature of Kierkegaardian "truth." They note that Kierkegaard
never denies such a thing as objective truth: he merely denies its importance
over what he calls "subjective" truth.

While not denying that there is such a thing as objective scientific truth, the
existentialist does not consider that kind of truth important, at least not
nearly as important as subjective truth. Indeed, Kierkegaard declared "truth
is subjectivity." By that he did not mean that any subjective belief is true, but
that unless one believes something subjectively and passionately he does
not possess the truth. Truth is always personal and not merely propositional.
One never gains truth by mere observation, but by obedience: never by
being a spectator, but only by being a participator in life.

11
Truth is found in the concrete, not in the abstract: in the existential, not in
the rational. In fact, one places himself in the truth only by an act of his will,
by a "leap of faith” It is not deliberation of the mind but a decision of the will
by which one comes to know truth (Norman L. Geisler and Paul D. Feinberg,
Introduction to Philosophy, Grand Rapids, MI: Baker Book House, 1980, p.
46).

In summary, Kierkegaardian philosophy is much more complicated than at


first meets the eye. One especially must be aware that common and
philosophical vocabularies take on new definitions for Kierkegaard. The
evangelical Christian who declares that Jesus Christ is the truth means
something quite different from what Kierkegaard means. Kerkegaard's three-
fold path to personal fulfillment sounds good until it is examined from within
the context of the claims of the Bible or until attempts are made to
authenticate it by history and objective reason.

The Secular Existentialists

By far the largest group of thinkers categorized as extentialists are those


with no religious orientation at all, the secular existentialists. Some of them
ignore religion completely, others are forcefully atheistic. The secular
existentialists are concerned with the same themes as the religious
existentialists, but their pre-suppositions and belief systems preclude any
supernatural or any idea of God.

In our overview, we will examine three secular existentialists: Martin


Heidegger, Karl Jaspers and jean-Paul Sartre.

Martin Heidegger (1889-1976)

Martin Heidegger was one of the most influential promoters of contemporary


existentialism. He wrote in German but his works have been translated into
English. His most famous, Being and Time, has become one of the most
popular expressions of English/American existentialism in the philosophical
world. Alston and Nakhnikian note the scope of Heidegger's spreading
influence:

In Latin America and Europe, excluding, of course, the Soviet Union and her
European satellites, one of the dominant contemporary philosophers is
Heidegger. Heidegger's influence ranges widely over philosophers,
theologians (including Paul Tillich), and certain psychotherapists. In the
English-speaking world, too, there are philosophers who regard Heidegger
with as much respect as do his Continental and Latin-American admirers
(Alston and Nakhnikian, Readings, p. 679).

12
Heidegger's writings had a great effect on both the religious existentialist
Rudolph Bultmann, who attempted to build a theology from Heideggerian
existentialism, and jean-Paul Sartre, the French secular existentialist and
novelist.

Heidegger studied under the philosopher Edmund Husserl before he became


rector of Freiburg University in 1933. His main treatise, Sein und Zeit(Being
and Time), was published in 1927. Although Being and Time reflected the
influence Husserl and Kierkegaard made on Heidegger, it also showed he
differed from those men in some important ways.
Heidegger's existentialism is unique and complex. It is difficult for even
professional philosophers to understand:

Heidegger is an extremely original thinker. The problem of his historical


affiliations is not of primary concern here and we need only mention that he
borrows his method from Husserl, that he is in many ways influenced by
Dilckey, and that his general thesis is largely inspired by Kierkegaard.
Heidegger is equipped with an unusual knowledge of the great philosophers
of the past, among whom he frequently quotes Aristotle, although he
interprets him in very arbitrary fashion. A stir was caused by the volume
which he devoted to Kant, Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik (1929).
Few philosophers are so hard to understand as Heidegger (Bochenski,
European Philosophy, p. 161).

Because Heidegger's philosophy is so difficult to understand, interpretations


of his thought vary and even contradict one another. Philosopher/historian A.
Robert Caponigri remarks:

Heidegger's thought has given rise to extensive interpretations, varying


much among themselves and frequently at variance with the line of exegesis
which Heidegger himself has suggested. From the point of view of doctrine
and interests, his thought falls into two phases. The line of demarcation is
drawn (but not too sharply),. . by the Holderlin lecture in 1936. The first
phase centers about the great work of 1927: Sein und Zeit. This work is still
considered as presenting the essential Heidegger. It most clearly exhibits his
originality as a thinker in his "existential analysis" of human behavior with
respect to the "unveiling of truth" and his "ontological" mode of treating
phenomenology. It is the basis for the wide influence he has enjoyed. The
second phase possesses no strict unity but shows Heidegger's concern with a
number of themes, both historical and analytical, stemming from his main
concern: being and truth (A. Robert Caponigri, A History of Western
Philosophy.
Philosophy from the Age of Positivism to the Age of Analysis, Notre Dame, in:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1971, p. 264).

13
Along with the difficulty in understanding Heidegger, and the added difficulty
of interpretation, we find that Heidegger did not view himself as an
existentialist!

Heidegger believes that the term "existentialist" does not apply to his
philosophy ... Heidegger grants that "existentialism” is an apt label for what
Sartre represents, but not for his own position. Heidegger is interested in
Being. He approaches the problem of Being through the study of Dasein,
Heidegger's word for human existence, "the being of what we ourselves are"
(Alston and Naklmikian, Readings, p. 680).

Because of these problems, we will not deal extensively with Heidegger


although he bears mentioning because of his influence on other
existentialists. Recognizing our limits of space and purpose, we will confine
our discussion to three concerns of Heidegger: Dasein, angst, and death. The
reader is referred to the bibliography for books that deal more extensively
with Heidegger.

Dasein

The most important concept unique to Heidegger's system is Dasein (a word


Heidegger used to refer to the human being, or the existing-ness of the
human, which causes or becomes his essence). William Sahakian describes
Dasein:

Dasein. The idea of Being is an old one to a philosopher grounded in


Scholasticism, as Heidegger was. But Heidegger was interested in the
meaning of Being, its sense, or its purpose-i.e., what renders it intelligible.
Furthermore, he was interested primarily in the human Being, for the nature
of the human Being leads to other levels of Being or reality. Only Dasein (his
term for the human Being) can be said to have or not to have meaning;
hence Being is meaningful solely in terms of human existence.

Dasein (being-there), that is, the human Being or the human existent,
Heidegger identified as: (1) concern (Sorge), (2) being-toward-death (Sein
zum Tode), (3) existence (Existenz), and (4) moods (Stimmungen). The
human Being's essence is in his existence, for numerous possibilities are
open to him whereby he may choose different kinds of Being for himself. The
possibilities of what he may become are the pivotal points by which the
human being is oriented. Heidegger was greatly interested in interpreting
time in terms of temporality; consequently, in addition to the problem of
Being (Dasein), time is of utmost importance. Accordingly, his interest was in
the Being and temporality of Dasein (human existence) (Sahakian,
Philosophy, p. 349).

14
Angst

Angst is another term with heavy existential meaning for Heidegger. The
German word refers to anxiety, dread and hopeless fear of the future. This
concept is important to Heidegger because it forms the impetus for much of
human metaphysical development. It is the goad toward human existential
encounter.

In existentialist philosophy, (angst is) the dread occasioned by man's


realization that his existence is open towards an undetermined future, the
emptiness of which must be filled by his freely chosen actions. Anxiety
characterizes the human state, which entails constant confrontation with
possibility and the need for decision, with the concomitant burden of
responsibility (Flew, Philosophy, p. 13).

Death

As it is with most existential thought, death is important in Heidegger's


system. His secular (non-supernatural) presuppositions, and his commitment
to existence preceding essence give Heidegger no view of reality for an
individual before birth or after death. According to his scheme, the man who
recognizes this fact, freely accepts its inevitability, and seeks nothing
beyond, is then free to choose his own existence. He is no longer bound by
fear of death or imaginary retributive punishment after death. He is able to
choose his actions, thereby choosing his existence and ultimately his
essence. This is man with dignity.

For Heidegger, man is the being that knows he is going to die. He dies not
only at the end of life, but every day of it. Death is certain, yet indefinite.
Because it is inevitable it marks the contingency of life. Life is cast up
between nothing and nothing. Death is its boundary and is its supreme
possibility.
To freely accept death, to live in its presence, and to acknowledge that for it
there is no substitute and into it one must go alone, is to escape from all
illusions and to achieve genuine dignity and authentic existence (Fuller,
Philosophy, p. 608).

lean-Paul Sartre (1905-1980)

The man who most popularized an atheistic brand of existentialism was the
French philosopher, Jean-Paul Sartre. Sartre's major work, Being and
Nothingness, was written in 1943 while he was a prisoner of the Germans
during World War 111. Some of his other writings, including Existentialism is
Humanism and the novel, No Exit, reflect an indebtedness to both
Kierkegaard and Heidegger. Sartre's great ability enabled him to have a clear
understanding of the history of philosophy. Marjorie Greene reports:

15
[Sartre] does indeed use the thinkers of the past (and present) for his own
ends, but at the same time he sees them with extraordinary clarity. In his
references, say, to Kant or Spinoza, he not only uses their thought as a
springboard for his own, but also exhibits a solid and scholarly penetration
into their principles and views. His relation to Marx is less straightforward, as
we shall see, but in general one finds in his philosophical works an
interweaving of themes in which the original strands stand out for
themselves with unusual distinctness, while at the same time they are being
worked into a characteristically Sartrean pattern (Marjorie Green, Sartre, NY.
Franklin Watts, Inc., 1973, p. 33).

Absurdity

One major tenet of Sartre's existentialism is that life is absurd. In his novel,
Nausea, Sartre brings out the absurdity of life through his main character,
Roquentin. Robert Davidson writes;

The story of Roquentin, the hero of Nausea, is not told as an end in itself.
Actually it expresses Sartre's own view concerning human existence. This
story provides a descriptive or phenomenological account of a man's growing
realization of the absurdity of human life in itself, and of his awakening to the
fact that if a man’s life is to have any meaning or purpose, the individual
himself must confer that meaning upon it. A sense of the absurd, the
absurdity of life and of man himself, permeates Sartre's early existentialism.
In Nausea he portrays this as an immediate insight in one’s own experience.

As he sat in a public park one day, staring at the long black roots of an old
chestnut tree, Roquentin became acutely aware of the absurdity of his own
existence:
"Absurdity was not an idea in my head nor the sound of a voice. It was this
long, lean, wooden snake curled up at my feet - snake or claw or talon or
root, it was all the same. Without formulating anything I knew that I had
found the clue to my existence, to my nausea to my life. And indeed
everything I have ever grasped since that moment comes back to this
fundamental absurdity" (Robert E Davidson, Philosophies Men Live By, NY:
Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc., 1974, p. 362).

Man is Autonomous

The absurdity of the universe leads Sartre to another major tenet of


existentialism; namely, that man is autonomous. Sartre wrote:

The existentialist, on the contrary, thinks it very distressing that God does
not exist, because all possibility of finding values in a heaven of ideas
disappears along with Him; there can no longer be an a priori Good, since

16
there is no infinite and perfect consciousness to think it. Nowhere is it written
that the Good exists, that we must be honest, that we must not lie: because
the fact is we are on a plane where there are only men.

Dostoevsky said, 'If God didn’t exist, everything would be possible! That is
the very starting point of existentialism. Indeed, everything is permissible if
God does not exist, and as a result man is forlorn, because neither within him
nor without does he find anything to cling to. He cant start making excuses
for himself. In other words, there is no determinism, man is free, man is
freedom. On the other hand, if God does not exist, we find no values or
commands to turn to which legitimize our conduct. So, in the bright realm of
values, we have no excuse behind us, nor justification before us. We are
alone, with no excuses (Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism and Human
Emotions, NY. The Citadel Press, n.d., pp. 22, 23).

Freedom

Man comes into the scene and defines himself. He lives in absolute freedom.
Sartre states:

That is the idea I shall try to convey when I say that man is condemned to be
free. Condemned, because he did not create himself, yet, in other respects is
free; because, once thrown into the world, he is responsible for everything he
does. The existentialist does not believe in the power of passion. He will
never agree that a sweeping passion is a ravaging torrent which fatally leads
a man to certain acts and is therefore an excuse. He thinks that man is
responsible for his passion (ibid., p. 23).

Existence Before Essence

Another major tenet of Sartre's existentialism is that existence precedes


essence. This means that man, by his own choices, defines his character, his
essence and the person he is becoming. His choices determine his make-up.
Sartre argues:

Atheistic existentialism, which I represent, is more coherent. It states that if


God does not exist, there is at least one being in whom existence precedes
essence, a being who exists before he can be defined by any concept, and
that this being is man, or as Heidegger says, human reality What is meant
here by saying that existence precedes essence? It means that, first of all,
man exists, turns up, appears on the scene, and, only afterwards, defines
himself. If man, as the existentialist conceives him, in indefinable, it is
because at first he is nothing. Only afterward will he be something, and he
himself will have made what he will be. Thus, there is no human nature,
since there is no God to conceive it. Not only is man what he conceives
himself to be, but he is also only what he wills himself to be after this thrust

17
toward existence (ibid., pp. 15-16).

In Being and Nothingness, Sartre states:

Human freedom precedes essence in man and makes it possible. The


essence of the human being is suspended in freedom (jean-Paul Sartre,
Being and Nothingness, NY Philosophical Library, Inc., 1956, p. 25).

He continues with the ramifications of this assertion:

[It is that] choice that is called "will". But if existence really does precede
essence, man is responsible for what he is. Thus, existentialism's first move
is to make every man aware of what he is and to make the full responsibility
of his existence rest on him. And when we say that a man is responsible for
himself, we do not only mean that he is responsible for his own individuality,
but that he is responsible for all men (ibid., p. 16).

Fulfillment

Sartre believed that man could receive his own self-fulfillment, as Sahakian
reports:

Notwithstanding the pessimistic views in most of Sartre's writings his


existentialism ends on a note of optimism, for his Existentialism is Humanism
concludes with the declaration that existentialism does not plunge man into
despair but is an optimistic doctrine of action, that man is his own lawmaker,
a creator of values, living in a human universe of human subjectivity, and
capable of self-fulfillment (Sahakian, Philosophy, p. 357).

Thus, man makes his own fulfillment. Those who try to accomplish this
through religion are guilty of bad faith, as Flew defines:

Bad faith. In the existentialism of Sartre, a form of deception of self and


others; the attempt to rationalize human existence through religion, science,
or any belief in operative forces that impose meaning and coherence. Man
shapes his own destiny through a succession of free choices for which he is
totally responsible. In "bad faith" he denies the necessity of relying on his
own moral insight and fallible will, trying to escape the burden of
responsibility by regarding himself as the passive subject of outside
influences, and his actions as being predetermined by these rather than
freely chosen by himself (Flew, Philosophy, p. 35).

Forlornness

One of the major themes Sartre dealt with is also (not surprisingly) one for
which he is perhaps best known, the theme of forlornness. It arises out of

18
existential individuality and subjectivity. In some ways, it resembles
Kierkegaard's second and unsatisfying stage, where man realizes he is alone,
determines an ethic, but has nothing on which to depend. Sartre himself
presented a moving description of this forlornness in the previously cited
Existentialism and Human Emotion:

To give you an example which will enable you to understand forlornness


better, I shall cite the case of one of my students who came to see me under
the following circumstances: his father was on bad terms with his mother,
and moreover, was inclined to be a collaborationist; his older brother had
been killed in the German offensive of 1940, and the young man, with
somewhat immature but generous feelings, wanted to avenge him. His
mother lived alone with him, very much upset by the half-treason of her
husband and the death of her older son; the boy was her only consolation.

The boy was faced with the choice of leaving for England and joining the Free
French Forces - that is, leaving his mother behind - or remaining with his
mother and helping her to carry on. He was fully aware that the woman lived
only for him and that his going-off -and perhaps his death -would plunge her
into despair. He was also aware that every act that he did for his mother's
sake was a sure thing, in the sense that it was helping her to carry on,
whereas every effort he made toward going off and fighting was an uncertain
move which might run aground and prove completely useless; for example,
on his way to England he might, while passing through Spain, be detained
indefinitely in a Spanish camp; he might reach England or Algiers and be
stuck in an office at a desk job. As a result, he was faced with two very
different kinds of action: one, concrete, immediate, but vaster group, a
national collectivity, but for that very reason was dubious, and might be
interrupted en route. And, at the same time, he was wavering between two
kinds of ethics.

On the one hand, an ethics of sympathy, of personal devotion; on the other,


a broader ethics, but one whose efficacy was more dubious. He had to
choose concerning only one individual; the other concerned an incomparably
between the two.

Who could help him choose? Christian doctrine? No. Christian doctrine says,
"Be charitable, love your neighbor, take the more rugged path, etc., etc” But
which is the more rugged path? Whom should he love as a brother? The
fighting man or his mother? Which does the greater good, the vague act of
fighting in a group, or the concrete one of helping a particular human being
to go on living? Who can decide a priori? Nobody No book of ethics can tell
him. The Kantian ethics says, "Never treat any person as a means, but as an
end." Very well, if I stay with my mother, I'll treat her as an end and not as a
means; but by virtue of this very fact, I'm running the risk of treating the
people around me who are fighting, as means; and, conversely, if I go to join

19
those who are fighting, I'll be treating them as an end, and, by doing that, I
run the risk of treating my mother as a means.

If values are vague, and if they are always too broad for the concrete and
specific case that we are considering, the only thing left for us is to trust our
instincts. That's what this young man tried to do; and when I saw him, he
said, "In the end, feeling is what counts. I ought to choose whichever pushes
me in one direction. If I feel that I love my mother enough to sacrifice
everything else for her -my desire for vengeance, for action, for adventure
then I'll stay with her. If, on the contrary, I feel that my love for my mother
isn't enough, I'll leave.

But how is the value of a feeling determined? What gives his feeling for his
mother value? Precisely the fact that he remained with her. I may say that I
like so-and-so well enough to sacrifice a certain amount of money for him,
but I may say so only if I've done it. I may say "I love my mother well enough
to remain with her" if I have remained with her. The only way to determine
the value of this affection is, precisely, to perform an act which confirms and
defines it. But, since I require this affection to justify my act, I find myself
caught in a vicious circle. (Sartre, Existentialism, pp. 24-27).

From this we can see the futility inherent in Sartre's existential thought.
Since "existence precedes essence," and the individual is enveloped within
"subjectivity" and must find his essence of "authenticity," he is truly alone.
Many people have embraced existentialism for a time, sincerely thinking that
its view of life is accurate. However, many leave existentialism because it
offers a solution, meaning, and commitment which is not truly satisfying.
Even Sartre, toward the end of his life, swung very close to theistic
commitment. The magazine National Review reported it this way:

Throughout his mature career, the philosopher jean-Paul Sartre was a


militant atheist. Politically, although he quarreled with Marxist materialism,
his rhetoric was often indistinguishable from the most heavy-handed Stalinist
boiler-plate.

However, during the philosopher's last months there were some surprising
developments. In 1980, nearing his death, by then blind, decrepit, but still in
full possession of his faculties, Sartre came very close to belief in God,
perhaps even more than very close.

The story can be told briefly, and perhaps reverently. An ex-Maoist, Pierre
Victor, shared much of Sartre's time toward the end. In the early spring of
1980 the two had a dialogue in the pages of the ultra-gauchiste Nouvel
Observateur. It is sufficient to quote a single sentence from what Sartre said
then to measure the degree of his acceptance of the grace of God and the
creatureliness of man: "I do not feel that I am the product of chance, a speck

20
of dust in the universe, but someone who was expected, prepared,
prefigured. In short, a being whom only a Creator could put here: and this
idea of a creating hand refers to God."

Students of existentialism, the atheistic branch, will note that in this one
sentence Sartre disavowed his entire system, his engagements, his whole
life. Voltaire converted on his deathbed; one never knows, the brilliant old
rascal is supposed to have said. Sartre did not convert, at least outwardly,
but came to understand. Everything ought to be forgiven hi

The epilogue is much less edifying. His mistress, Simone de Beauvoir,


behaved like a bereaved widow during the funeral. Then she published La
cérémonie des adieux in which she turned vicious, attacking Sartre.

He resisted Victor's seduction, she recounts, then he yielded. "How should


one explain this senile act of a turncoat?" she asks stupidly. And she adds:
"All my friends, all the Sartrians, and the editorial team of Les Temps
Modernes supported me in my consternation."
Mme. de Beauvoir's consternation v. Sartre's conversion. The balance is
infinitely heavier on the side of the blind, yet seeing, old man. (National
Review, June 11, 1982, p. 677).

21

You might also like