Theory and Methods in Political Science
Theory and Methods in Political Science
Theory and Methods in Political Science
ʻWhat is the nature and purpose of political science? Posed in such a direct and stark
manner, this may well be a rather uncomfortable question to ask.ʼ (Hay, 2002, p.64)
But as Hay subsequently explains: the answer to this questions defines the core features
While this question may lead us to the core features of political science, (Stoker, 1995, p.1)
the answer to this question is still not widely agreed upon in academic circles.
Hay subsequently analyses that ʻthose with the most narrow, restrictive and formal
conceptions of politics are the most attached to the label ʻscienceʼʼ (2002, p.66) So by
trying to keep ourselves from being or becoming overly attached to the label ʻscienceʼ we
might be able to make our conceptions of politics wider, more unrestricted and less formal.
This essay will start by taking a closer look at the ʻpoliticalʼ aspect of the posed question
and its implications. Secondly, this essay will look at ʻscienceʼ and the requirements it
presents for the ʻpoliticalʼ. As third, this essay will define what an oxymoron is. Finally, this
essay will take a look at prominent or possible critiques and responses to the posed
conclusion. And last, this essay will conclude that ʻpolitical scienceʼ is indeed an oxymoron,
based on the notion that the prerequisite of impartiality, neutrality and autonomy can not
be met in the study of the ʻpoliticalʼ for it is too concerned with the study of values,
scientific and quantitative endeavor or does its very nature, as a complex human process,
require a more qualitative approach?ʼ (2004, p.17) This essay will follow Leftwichʼs subtle
suggestion in showing that the study of politics needs a more interpretative approach to
1
981418
suit its nature as a complex human process instead of a more scientific and quantitative
approach.
Hayʼs assessment of the ʻpoliticalʼ versus ʻscienceʼ matter offers a clear framework for this
In the philosophy of the social sciences, what we have thus far termed the political
question is referred to as an ontological issue; what we have thus far termed the
To define what the ʻpoliticalʼ is we have to step into an array of confusing and contradicting
Elshtain puts it: ʻall we know is that [the world of the political] would not be what we
currently have.ʼ (in Hauptmann, 2004, p.34) Admittedly, this does not have to be such a
negative issue, since ʻfor many, this is a deeply worrying and depressing state of affairs;
for just as many others, however, it is a sign of theoretical vibrancy and intellectual
Furthermore, as Adrian Leftwich analyses about the defining of ʻpoliticsʼ (2004, p.2):
because it is such a highly contested subject, debates about its proper definition
and the scope of its subject matter are themselves political, and that it is not likely
that there will ever be universal agreement on either what politics, as an activity, is
or what the appropriate composition of the discipline of Politics should be.
This essay sees a few basic features and characteristics that can be agreed upon to be at
the core of the ʻpoliticalʼ. Most academicsʼ concerns seems to be ʻwith the analysis of the
origins, forms, distribution and control over power.ʼ (Leftwich, 2004, p.2) rather than the
widely accepted angle to politics that it is the involvement of human beings in the ʻstudy of
influence and the influentialʼ (Lasswell in Leftwich, 2005, p.2). This essay argues that
whenever one talks about politics or anything political, one always talks about human
2
981418
relations and their perception of influence or power. It is this distinct emphasis on ʻhumanʼ
that makes it unfeasible to consider anything political to be a science for it rests too heavily
on human perception and philosophy as will be shown in the next section about science.
This second section will provide an analysis of what science entails and what aspects are
The public feeling seems to be that if political scientist were in the possession of
anything even faintly resembling a science, they could tell the world something
beyond what is in the daily news, could provide not just the known facts but general
explanations that would make the political world more understandable. This goal
has been elusive. Even when sophisticated statistics are brought to bear on politics,
the numbers frequently only repeat facts that were obvious enough to uninformed
observers without going to all that statistical trouble. (Lane, 1997, p.vii)
This essay acknowledges that there are many different angles to the problem that political
science may or may not be ʻscientificʼ. This essay will elaborate a theory that shows
politics and the ʻpoliticalʼ are missing a crucial pillar to be considered scientific in not
Hollis poses the following question about the philosophy of social science (1994, p.216):
Could it be that our difficulties in settling on the correct analysis of, for instance,
causation, explanation, understanding and knowledge stem from failure to realise
that an element of value-judgement is always involved?
This essay will argue that it is exactly this ʻfailure to realise that an element of value-
judgement is always involvedʼ that makes it impossible for the ʻpoliticalʼ or ʻsocialʼ to mix
ʻscience as value free represents a value of scientific practices and institutions.ʼ (Lacey,
2001, p.2) This essay acknowledges that there is a lively ongoing debate between
academics about the question ʻCan science itself comply to the requirements it sets out?ʼ
One of the most distinct requirements of science is that it needs to be value free. But this
leads us directly to the question ʻIs science itself value free?ʼ Lacey set out to answer this
3
981418
question and offers three components to dissect the discussion of ʻscience being value
freeʼ: impartiality, neutrality and autonomy. This essay will use these ideas to show how the
building blocks of the ʻpoliticalʼ make it impossible to build a foundation for science and
how by considering politics to be a science we are moving further away from ʻpure scienceʼ
First, impartiality leaves no space in science for ʻmoral, social and any other non-cognitive
valuesʼ (Lacey, 2001, p.1). However, politics and the ʻpoliticalʼ are entirely based on
humans and their social conventions and moral dimensions. Requiring politics to abandon
their social and moral roots would imply stepping away from e.g. ʻthe study of influence
and the influentialʼ (Lasswell in Leftwich, 2004, p.2), for the perception of influence is
Secondly, proper science needs to be neutral and not favor any views over others. Since
we are studying human relations and their struggle for influence it is unlikely that we - as
the researcher or observer - will remain neutral. The concepts of influence, power and
authority are entirely based on favoring one over another. Or as Robert Dahl puts it ʻA has
power over B to the extent that he can get B to do something that B would not otherwise
doʼ (1957, pp.202-203). The valuation, interpretation and perception of power, influence
and success depend greatly on personal views, opinions and definitions and are therefore
unlikely to be neutral. How can we assure that what B does in Dahlʼs definition is actually
caused by A having power over B? The observer will need to base his answer on his
personal qualitative explanation, rather than a general quantitative belief. Hence, the
necessity for a more qualitative approach, rather than a more quantitative approach as
The third requirement for science being value free is autonomy. Autonomy is explained by
cognitive interests.ʼ (p.1) Besides the clear claim that research should be ʻunencumbered
4
981418
humans and political science would thus imply having humans ʻstudyʼ human relations. So
with these parties being too similar, dependent and connected, the ʻpoliticalʼ can never be
autonomous.
The premise used by Lacey to address the need for science to be value free hands us
ʻThe meaning of concepts is not grounded in observation but somehow excogitated from
This third part of the essay will elaborate on what an oxymoron is and how it is used in this
This essay argues that the terms ʻpoliticalʼ and ʻscienceʼ are indeed an oxymoron on the
grounds that they contradict but still appear in conjunction. This essay shows the
When it comes to the exact explanation of the terms involved in this question, one could
argue that ʻscienceʼ simply refers to the ʻpossession of knowledge as distinguished from
implies that almost anything that involves investigation or any form of knowledge can be
seen as science, even e.g. washing the dishes: the ʻscience of washing the dishesʼ. This
5
981418
essay though approaches science as the systematized and value free attained knowledge
In conclusion, ʻpolitical scienceʼ is an oxymoron for the ʻpoliticalʼ is too concerned with
complex human processes to meet the requirement of science to be value free. The
ʻpoliticalʼ and politics is based on discourse, perception and interpretation and is thus in
focussing on the ʻscientificʼ side. By detaching the ʻpoliticalʼ from the ʻscienceʼ this essay
expects to see a stronger focus on qualitative research that will create a stronger
ontological premises for the discipline and that will thereby create stronger methodological
6
981418
Bibliography
Dahl, Robert, ʻThe Concept of Powerʼ, (1957), Behavioral Science, Vol. 2, No. 3, pp.
202-210
Hauptmann, Emily, ʻA Local History of "The Political"ʼ, (2004), Political Theory, Vol. 32, No.
1, pp. 34-60, Sage Publications
Kitcher, Philip, (1993), The advancement of science : science without legend, objectivity
without illusions, New York; Oxford: Oxford University Press
Lacey, Hugh, (2001), Impartiality, Neutrality and Autonomy: Three components of the idea
that science is value free, Swarthmore College
www.swarthmore.edu/Humanities/hlacey1/value-free.doc
Lane, Ruth, (1997), Political Science in Theory and Practice: The 'politics' Model, Danbury:
M.E. Sharpe
Marsh, D. & Stoker, G. (eds.), (1995), Theory and methods in political science (1st ed.),
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan
Marsh, D. & Stoker, G. (eds.), (2002), Theory and methods in political science (2nd ed.),
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan
Meehan, Eugene, (1982), ʻNorms and Valuesʼ, International Political Science Review /
Revue internationale de science politique, Vol. 3, No. 2, pp. 254-256, Sage Publications
7
981418
Rule, John, (1997), Theory and Progress in Social Science, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press