Karl Jaspers - Plato and Augustine, 1957, English Translation, 1962
Karl Jaspers - Plato and Augustine, 1957, English Translation, 1962
Karl Jaspers - Plato and Augustine, 1957, English Translation, 1962
THE
ID|^gjP^JNIVERSITY
TRUTH AND SYMBOL
REASON ANDEXISTENZ
PLATO
AND
AUGUSTINE
EDITED BYHANNAH ARENDT
TRANSLATED BY RALPH MANHEIM
A Harvest Book
Bibliography 121
Syracuse. The tyrant had resolved to build a new state in collaboration with
the philosopher, who saw a wonderful opportunity to put his political ideas
into practice. His dealings with Dionysius (366-365) were unsuccessful. But
once again let himself be tempted (361-360), and again
five years later, Plato
the enterprise ended badly. These two ventures occurred when Plato was
sixty-two and sixty-seven. Some years later Dion raised an army, drove the
tyrant from Syracuse, and determined once again to establish Plato's re-
public.Dion was murdered in 354 when Plato was seventy-four. His deepest
friendships had been with Socrates, forty years older than himself, and with
Dion, who was twenty years younger. After the loss of Dion he lived an-
other seven years.
Plato was born one year after the death of Pericles; as a child and young
man he experienced the downfall of Athens, the alternation of parties and
forms of government, the disastrous political turmoil. His life was situated
in the period before the turn from the polis to the empire, from the Greek
to the Hellenistic world. He saw the ruin but did not see or foresee the
other, new world. In this situation the young man, spurred on by his family
tradition, was passionately drawn to political life. But he recognized the
hopelessness of the situation. After the death of Socrates he made the
radical decision to withdraw from public life and live for philosophy, though
1
Seventh Letter, 326 a-b, TAr Republic, tr. F. M. Cornford, p. acxv.
PLATO
a part, with "the best that under
merely for the sake of playing
is possible
the circumstances." ..He wanted everything or nothing. He demanded a
kind of politics
that would mold true men and so lay the foundations of a
human ethos/All his life Plato reflected on politics. The greatest work of
his mature age is concerned with the state; his most extensive work, com-
2. Works
The philological efforts of a century have classified and arranged the writings
of Plato as handed down from antiquity in the corpus platonicum,
and es-
scholars
tablished reliable texts. After extraordinary fluctuations of opinion,
are pretty well as to which texts are authentic and the order in
agreed
2
which they were written.
The following chronological sequence is generally accepted, though there
doubt about the order within the i. The trial of Socrates:
is some groups:
Ion, Laches, Lysis, Charmides,
Apology, Crito. Early dialogues: Protagoras,
Greater 2. After the first journey in 388 and the found-
Euthyphro, Hippias.
Meno, Euthydemus, Cratylus; cer-
ing of the Academy, probably: Gorgias,
Theaetetus. 3. After the second journey
tainly: Symposium, Phaedo, Republic,
After the
of 366: Parmenides, Sophist, Statesman, Philebus, Phaedrus. 4.
third journey in : Timaeus, Criuas, Laws, Seventh Letter.
361
Each group has its distinct character.
with the trial of Socrates, are in a class by
Apology and Crito, dealing
themselves. The early
"Socratic" are
dialogues distinguishedby the un-
this quality
common vividness of the scene in which they are set (though
some of the later dialogues, particularly Phaedrus, where it attains
occurs in
its utmost perfection). In content, they arc
characterized by aporias: the
main questions are left open. In the ensuing dialogues, particularly Gorgias
and Meno, Plato's characteristic manner of thinking is already at work. The
Phaedo, reflect Plato's philosophy with
classical works, Symposium, Republic,
of
its well-balanced themes, its wealth of reference, its profound conception
the On<(Ttelcctic becomes dominant in Theaetetus,
Parmenides, Sophist,
is unique, combining youthful freshness
and
Statesman^, PhUebus\Phaedrus
work that has most often
a maturity. This is the
perfect philosophical
as early, today it is
changed chronological position; formerly regarded
its
Phaedo, the book that taught men how to die; Apology and Crito with
their portrait of Socrates, the steadfast, independent man, who by his death
bears witness to the truth; Symposium and Phaedrust which show Socrates
as he lived in the world, a man intoxicated with the Eros; Gorgias, which
dialogues. We
consider each one as a whole, as an exposition of ideas and
as a work of art We
take thematically similar passages from other dialogues
and compare the structure, scenery, characters. It may seem barbarous to
dismember such works of But each dialogue points beyond itself ;
art. its
Plato's system was formulated in his academic lectures, which unlike those
of Aristotle have not been preserved. Aristotle's notes may permit us to
reconstruct the content of the lectures, at least those of Plato's later years.
On the basis of this assumed system, we now approach the dialogues as
quarries from which we draw the blocks for a systematic edifice: Plato's
system in the form of a comprehensive doctrine (Zeller). In this process we
encounter one difficulty after another. We
rebel against the absurdity of
destroying existing structures for the sake of a rational system that can
never be anything but imaginary. The building does not advance, because
once we resolve to fit each idea into its proper place in a rational totality,
we run into contradiction.
Everyone will agree that the fifty years of Plato's thinking and writing
must be viewed as a continuous whole. But the question remains: In what
sense is it a whole? The very earliest dialogues are masterpieces, unexcelled
in their kind. Proceeding from work to work, we find development, an
increasing breadth and richness, but no abrupt leaps. The one revolution in
Plato's thinking was brought about by Socrates and occurred before any
of the extant works were written. The dialogues show no sudden advance
that might have left a fissure in the groundwork of his philosophizing. But
though there is no explicit system and no indication of the stages of Plato's
development, wholeness must be seen in something which pervades the
entire work and defies exact formulation, namely philosophizing itself, the
another. The first step must be to interpret the problems discussed in the
texts. Each dialogue has its questions and themes. They deal with logic,
cosmology, in short, almost every aspect of the world
and
politics,. physics,
of human existence. We reflect on what Plato puts into the mouth of his
ining the themes themselves in order to see what they show independently
of Plato.
The contradictions, in particular, help to call our attention to Plato's
may
central meaning. Of course the problems he treats are important in them-
selves,and of course they were of the deepest interest to Plato. The philo-
itself through the themes
sophical mind, in any case, ran only communicate
of philosophy; they cannot be set aside as irrelevant. But we must go on
to ask the essential question: How do they relate to the whole, what is
their function, what do they mean, directly or indirectly? Since it has not
been possible to construe them as fragments that can be assembled into an
encompassing rational system, let us approach them as elements of an
infinitely mobile philosophizing that utilizes the thematic problems only
as a language in which to express something else.
We begin by looking for this something else in the characters who philos-
ophize in Plato's dialogues, first in the unique Socrates who towers above
them all, then in the others. They are not mere mouthpieces for the discus-
sion of philosophical problems, but are characterized as living philosophical
or unphilosophical realities by the way in which they speak, their conduct in
the situations of the dialogues, their reactions and responses. They are
portraits not so much of a psychology as of an intellectual mood. In the
most meet in personal
significant passages, they are spiritual forces that
form. The
philosophical problems acquire truth only by being taken into
the encompassing truth, and it is from die vantage point of this encompassing
truth that they first arouse our interest.
If the full truth is attained neither by a discussion of the contents nor by
an investigation of the personal figures in their agreements and conflicts,
we must take a further step. Plato guides our attention to something that
cannot be understood or demonstrated by reason, something that is not
analyzed but merely narrated, namely the myths. Despite the rationalist
criticswho regard these myths as superfluous, Plato clearly attaches great
importance to them. We
are led for a moment to hope that they will
reveal the ultimate secret of Platonic truth. But in vain, for Plato expressly
thoughts
what was
in
which came *J*
to him m &e ^
he imputed to him dwugh the
as a matter of course
presence of Socrates would seem to
of die sort (this
older philosopher had never said anything
be the case with the theory of Ideas as set forth m
the Phatdo where
R ex-
Socrates tells how he arrived at it).
We
may say that what Plato
first
many aspects, is one man. The reader always sees the one Socrates even
when he is portrayed from different points of view. In most of the dialogues,
Socrates is the main character; in some of the late dialogues, he becomes a
secondary figure, and in Laws he disappears, because the subject matter no
longer fits in with the individuality of Socrates.
Can poetry disclose reality? But what is objective truth in our picture of
a man? Only externals can be demonstrated to the satisfaction of all. What
a man really is, is inseparably reality and idea, realization and potentiality,
success and failure in finding himself, the process whereby he becomes what
he is.
Only modern psychologists suppose that they really know the man
they submit a report on. What a man
a light in the eyes of one who
is, is
loves him; for true love is clearsighted and not blind. What Plato saw in
Socrates was really Socrates compounded of the idea, the visible embodi-
ment, and the man who looked as Xenophon describes him.
It is not possible to draw an objective line between the ideas of Socrates
and those of Plato. Where there is a personal bond between two men, that
is never possible. In such cases there are no rights of ownership. Plato
develops what is implicit in an idea, what can spring from a philosophical
reality. Socrates-Plato is the only case in the history of philosophy of a
thinker who is
great only in bond with another, of two thinkers who exist
through each other.
Plato's profound relation to Socrates has three main consequences for
Plato's philosophy:
1. Plato built his thinking on the philosopher and not merely on an ab-
stract, universal, free-floating truth. His presentation of the philosophy in
one with the philosopher maintains a unity of thinking and existence. That
is what gave Platonic
thinking its enduring historical concreteness (though
Plato, who had no sense of history, found the source and meaning of his
philosophy in its apprehension of the universal). And it enabled Plato to
do what is impossible for any thinker who merely follows out a doctrine:
to think in perfect freedom while maintaining a historical bond; to venture
every idea, because his ideas, sustained by a man and his living reality,
would not lead him into the void. This accounts for the measure and limit
in Plato, his avoidance of all philosophizing that would have led to mere
universals. But, what is most astonishing in all this, the person of Socrates
is not dogmatized. Love was no check on freedom. Plato's thinking was
subservient neither to a fixated doctrine nor to an idolized
man, but only
to a spirit of endlessly burgeoning discovery rooted in human companionship.
2. This method of
thinking exempted Plato, in certain situations, from
the need to set his name to statements that he might not have ventured
on his own
authority. He
lets the transfigured Socrates say these things, just
as Socrates, beyond certain limits, lets others speak, Diotima or the narrator
of the myths. With this device Plato seems to be saying: The claims of
philosophy are so great that I should not dare to call myself a philosopher.
PLATO jj
emerging personalities of the thinkers, the natural forces and human situa-
had entered into men's awareness, the innumerable problems that
tions that
had made their appearance Plato made all this his own and transformed it
Plato once said of the traditional ideas: everything these thinkers said is
fairy tales (mythoi) told to children. The one says this, the other something
else, without foundation: being is threefold; there is conflict and, again,
there is two elements, moist and dry, hot and cold, and so
love; there are
on; everything is one; being is many and one. But with all this they talk
over our heads. Heedless of whether or not we can follow and keep up
with their disquisitions, each one carries out his own argument In every
case it is questionable whether we understand the meaning of the words. In
all this it is hard to decide whether one of them is
right or not- v
assertion, language as such. Up until then this had been the situation in
gives rise we can admire it but not enter into it. For in their radicality
these philosophies are like a set of new prejudices. Despite the Romantic
longing with which one may look back at this lost world of primordial
revelation, one may well utter a sigh of relief on coming to Plato from the
prc-Socratics.
task.
TheSophists claimed to teach arete, particularly of the political sort
They aspired to teach men how to achieve success and power. Socrates, on
the contrary, contends that for each activity, for
farming, navigation, shoe-
making, carpentry, and so on, it is best to choose an expert. If you want
someone to learn a particular thing, send him to such an expert But who
is
expert in education, in arete as a whole, or in political matters? In other
words, who is expert in what is most important of all? Clearly many
aretai can be taught But the most important cannot, as is evident from
the fact that the great and successful, those men who are rich in the arete
that applies to matters of state, cannot teach their own sons; that
discerning
citizens cannot communicate their arete to others.
can be taught, it must be a knowledge. But certain aretai, such
If arete
as courage, are innate and have
nothing to do with knowledge. Others, those
of craftsmen for example, can be
acquired by practice. If there is a knowl-
edge of arete, it should further be distinguished whether this knowledge
a means by which to attain arete, or whether there is a
is
knowledge which
so that in this case, arete
is itself arete, is
knowledge and knowledge itself is
the being of him who Such knowledge cannot be taught in the
acts well.
same way as the knowledge that is a means to an end. Where the latter
suffices, the Sophists arc not wrong. But the other knowledge is on an
important, and so difficult to carry through that it crops up time and time
again in Pkto, and is never brought to a complete and final solution.
In the early dialogues it is stated in different variants, as for example in
Lysis, in the question: In that which is dear (fhilon) to us, what ultimately
is the dear as such? If we continue to ask for the sake of what, we shall
run out of breath unless we can arrive at a beginning which no longer re-
fers to other dear things, but in which our questioning comes to rest in that
basically dear, for the sake of which we have declared all
which is other
things to be dear. Our endeavor is not directed toward the means that help
us to attain the end, but toward the end itself, for the sake of which all
these means are provided.
Or let us suppose, with Charmides, that there is a miraculous man who
knows the whole past, present, and future, in short, a man from whom
nothing is hidden. Which of all the branches of knowledge makes him
happy, or do all do so equally: the art of playing drafts, arithmetic,
med-
icine? It turns out that none of them, that no specialized science nor all
together, enables men to live happily.CA happy life is made possible only
lacking, there can be no true benefit from any specialized knowledge. And
this one knowledge is not prudence, nor is it the knowledge of knowledge
and ignorance, but solely the knowledge of good and eviL
In Euthydemus knowledge and skill are distinguished from their pur-
the music. The hunter pro-
pose. He who makes the lyre does not make
to the
vides food for the kitchen. general hands his conquest over
The
statesman. We
require a knowledge and a skill (uchne)
that know how
to utilize what they have gained possession of. Or to put it in another way:
We require a knowledge and a skill, in which
the activity that produces
coincides with an of how to use what has been produced.
understanding
Even a skill that succeeded in making us immortal would be useless to us
"unless we knew how to make proper use of immortality^If
we acquire
use them, we are in the foolish position of children trying to catch larks:
with each new science we think we have knowledge in our grasp, but each
time it eludes us.
we where
always sense a striving toward the goal,
all
In this thinking
i6
begins with the Socratic thinking about arete and keeps its tie with it to
the end (Discourse on the Good). This mode of knowledge is amplified
in the course of Plato'swork and extended to the whole realm of knowl-
edge: man, the state, the world. What is already present in the early dia-
logues runs through the whole of Plato's philosophizing, whose power of
growth seems to know no limits.
thing becomes arbitrary. He looks for concepts that have a fixed, definable
meaning, that are universal over against the many particular cases, and
valid for all
But this does not suffice. Plato's achievement has been seen in his founding
of a cogent and demonstrable scientific knowledge. Perhaps he was the
founder of scientific knowledge, but for him such knowledge is only a
part of the prevailing concept of knowledge. The essential is elsewhere.
The knowledge turned out to be a knowledge without aim or
prevailing
purpose, because it has no ultimate goal It is a limited knowledge, because
ll fr
authority, nor of the good, is this One a universal concept under which
all phenomena are subsumed as cases. It is not the
goal for which we strive.
It is not a standard by which we distinguish correct and incorrect. No, it
is what truly illumines all definite concepts, what grounds all aims in an
absolute aim beyond which we can question no further, what first makes
the merely correct true. It is the guiding principle; to think and live toward
it lends
meaning to existence.
We cannot know this One exactly as we know definite concepts. But
we find no satisfaction in what we know without it, even with the utmost
our thinking, in our exact thinking which indefatigably
precision. In all
and rightly^p strives for a mayiniTim of precision, we are oriented toward
what we do no? know exactly, what we cannot know with the definite
knowledge of the understanding, namely the ineffable One, which guides
us while remaining open, which, though touched upon in die clearest dis-
course, can be experienced only in the illumination that transcends the
understanding and all palpable intelligibles.
2. It is one with self-awareness:
Anyone who reflects knows that he
does and self-knowledge are one. Reflection alone is a knowl-
so. Reflection
them, except in so far as they can identify what is good with what is their
but a soaring of one's own being: with this knowledge man is transformed
A transcending of one's own nature through thinking, guided by whatever ii
revealed in thought, is the basic trait of philosophical reflection from Plato
down to Kant's formulation of enlightenment as "man's exodus from a
state of tutelage for which he himself has been to blame."
Therefore no knowledge is indifferent. Even in its seemingly most ir-
relevant forms, it
may well become a factor of transcendence. No knowl-
edge is without its effect on the soul. Knowledge is not like a foodstuff. You
can take a foodstuff home in a bag and, if you wish, ask an expert whether
it is fit to eat But you cannot put knowledge into a container; you can
take it home only by incorporating it in your mind, and you have no way
of knowing whether you have done yourself good or harm in the process.
From philosophical thinking arises the conscience that makes me responsible
for what I allow to enter into myself, for what I concern myself with.
What I read, hear, see, what work I knowledge and
do, the possibilities of
feeling that I encourage, how I choose and how
keep my distance none
I
The Laws, where he once again repeats a sentence that occurs frequently be-
ginning with the early dialogues: "No one can do wrong voluntarily." This
proposition can have meaning only if we have in mind not finite but
fundamental knowledge.
Finite knowledge is either indifferent, without consequences, or it has
itself be dragged about by all other states of mind." Only fundamental knowl-
edge gives this finite knowledge guidance and so dispels its neutrality. In
the fundamental knowledge of justice I myself become just. It is no longer
a knowledge that can exist in itself, without consequences. But the con-
sequences are knowledge itself. Knowledge and the application of knowl-
edge are no longer distinguishable. If a man knows what is right and does
the opposite, it means that he did not truly know.
This brings us to the relation between will and knowledge: The true will
is the
knowing will The desire that overpowers is not will but ignorance.
Only he wills and is not merely driven who wills the good. Only he who
does what is right acts freely. In fundamental knowledge, the good and
the right are one with the wilL Here one can no longer speak of passions
controlled by wilL Where there is true knowledge, which is at the same
time true will, what is incompatible with it ceases to be. Because it no
longer is, it does not have to be combated.
The proposition that no one can voluntarily do wrong, that one cannot
knowingly, contrary to one's knowledge, commit an evil act, applies only
to genuine knowledge. With finite
knowledge, which as such remains
ignorance, I can act intentionally with a view to satisfying my lust, anger,
violence, or I can act unintentionally from mere passion. In finite knowledge
of something, I can also do something harmful against my better knowl-
edge; I can either take evil consequences into account or put them out of
mind. For this knowledge, which is a
knowledge of something, is not the
reality of the thinlHfig map T As such
knowledge that is identical with die
it
partakes of the ignorance that is the greatest of evik.
It might seem as
though all finite reality vanished in this Platonic dunk-
ing with its
aspiration to what is highest. Two questions become urgent:
(i) Can such thinking be communicated, and if so, how? Plato considers
this question explicitly. The answer
provided in the dialogue form, his
is
ose of irony and playfulness, his dialectic method*
(2) What is die sub-
PLATO 21
stance of this thinking, or its motive force, or the fulfillment that is already
present in the search? The answer is the Platonic Eros.
for us to ask: What did Plato actually attempt to do in his written work?
How was he able to achieve a maximum of true communication?
A. The dialogue: It cannot be an accident that nearly all Pkto's works are
in dialogue form. Form and substance are concomitant. It is impossible to
suppose that the philosophy was there first and that then Plato chose the
dialogue as the best possible way of communicating it. If this philosophiz-
ing was to be communicated in writing, the dialogue form was its neces-
they suggest translations of lectures into dialogue form, they preserve their
atmosphere of ease one is never conscious of any effort and at the same
time die free spirit that cannot be captured in concepts and formulas and
dogmas but moves freely and masterfully among them.
Such portrayal comparable to literary creation. The great novelists of
is
the modern era (above all Dostoevski and Balzac) also depict a world in
which philosophical discussions arc frequent. Like them, Plato seems to
portray the whole gamut of possibility, to give each character his due, to
remain impartial, to show what is, and without judging as to good and
evil, to leave each man his existence in the light of good and evil at once.
But the great difference is that the substance of Plato's work is not the
portrayal of a world, but the philosophical truth that lies in thinking.
Since this thinking cannot be adequately communicated in formal lectures,
it invites all means of exploration
even the writing of dialogues but never
rlaim to
surrenders itself or pre-eminence. Plato dissociates himself
its
from the poet Poets, he says, are not quite right in their mind. In repre-
senting persons of conflicting opinion, they arc often at odds with them-
selves, not knowing whether the one opinion or the other is true. In Plato's
intention, his poetic dialogue is always guided by a single reference point,
the one and eternal truth, which can call attention to itself only indirectly
PLATO 23
potentiality. This permits him to hold his own position in suspense. How-
ever, we cannot understand his philosophical dialogue with an attitude of
demands of the reader an experience of serious self-
aesthetic neutrality; it
and only such an experience can enable us to understand it.
realization,
For the dialogue is an indirect communication of truth through the forms
of philosophical thought.
The one goal remains this thinking of the truth, The first step is always
liberation from the rigidity of rationally determined but sharply developed
hence a skepticism in the usual sense of the word, whose
finite positions,
talking toitself, asking questions and answering them, and saying, Yes or
No. So I should describe thinking as a discourse, and judgment as a state-
ment pronounced, not aloud to someone else, but silently to oneself."
Dialogue is the way to the truth. An enemy of the truth who accepts
dialogue is lost. An attitude of fundamental hostility to the truth and hence
tocommunication makes dialogue an absurdity. For this reason dogmatists
and nihilists reject any true dialogue. They rob dialogue of its nature. All
governments that desire untruth reject discussion with the adversary or, if
ject; wanting to be right at all costs; breaking off the discussion with a "What
* 5
the dialogue form, through the relation of the content to men and situations,
makes it possible to actualize the existential
meaning of ideas along with their
logical meaning.
Eristic speeches, the tricks which seem to crush the
adversary by logic,
are possible only because of the contradictions in thought itself. Plato's
indirect meaning of irony requires not only practice in rational thinking but
also training in philosophical sensibility. This irony is varied and complex.
The intermingling of truth and falsehood, the ambiguity that can become
truth only for those who hold the key to it, must lead to constant misunder-
standing. Plato seems to say: Let those who cannot understand misunder-
stand. Sometimes there seems to be anger beneath the frothy surface. In this
communication where rationality ceases, understanding cannot be forced
by rational arguments. In profound irony there is concern for the genuine
truth. It deters usfrom supposing that we possess the truth in object
knowledge, in the work, in the figure, which, magnificent as they may be,
become untrue the moment we take them as absolutes.
An ambiguous irony can quickly lose its profound meaning. Without
meaning of its own, it becomes an instrument of destruction, the language
of nihilism. Laughter kills. This irony follows the principle of Gorgias:
answer the ridiculous with seriousness, the serious with ridicule. This irony
discloses nothing but nothingness. It is not the self-effacing language of
the Eros, but a weapon serving the power of nothingness. Directed against
all seriousness as such, it is the groundless warfare of a tumultuous non-
being.
Philosophical irony, on the other hand, expresses the certainty of a funda-
mental meaning. Perplexed by the discrepancy between the simplicity of
rational discourse and the ambivalence of appearances, it strives to attain the
Socrates leads nis opponent up a false track, or graciously spares his feel-
ings, or delivers a cutting attack. On the next level we find the attitude
of fundamental irony by which Socrates seeks to provoke the knowledge
of nonknowlcdge At the highest level, Plato creates a general atmosphere of
deter-
bctweenness; this irony resides in the absolute ambiguity of all finite,
minate things. It is only in this ambiguity, this total irony where everything
loses its fixity, that the heart of being discloses itscE Ideas and myths are
like arrows shot off toward the realm where even the name of being must
vanish. Discursive philosophy merely explores possibilities along the way.
It is earnest not with the dark earnestness of the dogmatic possessor of
the truth or the earnestness of nihilistic mockery, but with the
angry
earnestness of freedom (eleutheriotcs), which can perfectly well be playful
Two examples may give an idea of this total irony in which Plato includes
himself:
28
spect Thus in the irony of his disillusionment with men, men are puppets
only in comparison with the gods. And this irony has its limits: an area is
left open for man.
A. The highest authority, the agathon: From the very outset Plato searched
for the supreme authority, knowledge of which first lends meaning to all
thought and action. He calls it the highest science (megiston mathema).
To attain it, no effort is too great It is the only important thing. Its object
is the good (agathon). A
Platonic parable gives an idea of what the good
is: The good in the realm of thought is like the sun in the realm of the
visible. We
do not see the sun, but we see everything in its light What in
the realm of the visible the sun is to the eye (the most sunlike of all the
organs of sense perception) and to what is seen, the good, in the realm of
lated to the good, but is not the good itself. Just as the sun not only lends
things the faculty of being seen, but gives them change, growth, and nour-
ishment, though itself free from change, so the good gives to the knowable
not only the power to be known, but also being and essence, though itself
not a being. For in dignity and power, it towers even above being (cpcfaina
tes ousias).
B. The world of Ideas. Two worlds: What is it then that has its eternal being
from the good, from that which is above being? What is it that we think
in the light of the good? It is a realm of Ideas of prototypes that stand un-
changing above all change. It is the eternal realm of the essences: likeness
and diversity as such, justice as such, beauty as such, bed and table as such,
and so on for all the forms that we see before our eyes in their definite
shapes.
^ To put it undialectically, there is a world of being (the realm of un-
changing Ideas, without beginning and indestructible, neither receiving any-
thing else into itself nor entering into anything else, itself hidden to the eye,
an object of pure contemplation) and the world of becoming (changing,
never resting, created, in continuous movement, arising in one place and
there vanishing, apprehensible only by belief in bond with sense percep-
tard inference, logismos nothos). Space and the world of change within
it are the realm to which we refer when we look about us as in a dream
and say: Everything that exists must after all be in a definite place; what is
neither on earth nor anywhere in the cosmos has no being. And because of
the dream state we are in, we transpose these delusions to the realm of au-
thentic, never slumbering being.~?
The realm is called the supracelestial place (hyperouranios topos)
of Ideas
or the place of intelligibles (topos noetos). It is adumbrated in metaphors
and concepts: "There abides the very being . . . ; the colorless, formless,
the pilot of the soul. ^
intangible essence, visible only to the mind,
.
.
[There]
she beholds and temperance, and knowledge absolute, not in the
justice,
form of generation, or of relation, which men call existence, but knowledge
of absolute existence" (Phaedrus). The man whose soaring thought attains
to its goal beholds "a beauty whdsc nature is marvelous indeed, the final
of neither
previous efforts- This beauty is first all eternal; it
goal of all his
comes into being nor passes away, neither waxes nor wanes; next, it is not
beautiful in part and ugly in part, not beautiful at one time and ugly at an-
other, nor beautiful in this relation and ugly in that, nor beautiful here and
ugly there, as varying according to beholders; nor again will this beauty
its
appear to him like the beauty of a face or hands or anything else corporeal,
or like the beauty of a thought or a science, or like beauty which has its
30
seat insomething other than itself, be it a living thing or the earth or the
sky or anything else whatever; he will see it as absolute, existing alone
with itself, unique, eternal."
One might be tempted to call such words empty,
consisting only of nega-
tive statements and tautologies. But it is just this absence of all finite
clarity
that gives us an intimation of
something that cannot be communicated
in any other way. This is what
gives Diotima's words their validity. 'This
above all others, she goes on to say, is the region where a man's life is worth
living. ... Do you think that it will be a poor life that a man leads who
has his gaze fixed in that direction . . . and is in constant union with it?
Do you not see that in that region alone . . will he be able to bring forth
.
not mere reflected images of virtue [arete] but true virtue. . . . And
having
brought forth and nurtured true virtue, he will be beloved of God, and
become, if ever a man can, immortal himself,"
Thus Pkto knows two worlds: the world of Ideas and that of the senses,
the world of being and that of
becoming, the noetic (intelligible) world and
the world of appearance.
(homoiotes), the Ideas of the just, the beautiful, of man and of other living
PLATO 3i
creatures, of manufactured articles, table, bed,of the elements, fire, water, and
even of mud, dirt, and other base things. In one passage, he speaks of five
higher Ideas: being, likeness, otherness, rest, motion (Sophist).
The good, which is beyond being, is also called an Idea. But the name
that
is misleading. For the good is distinguished from all other Ideas. They are
the static, inactive prototypes or models of the things that are, while it is the
creative power that confers being itself.
its discovery and all subsequent thinking of its content arc temporal.
makes use of visible forms; the object of his thinking, however, is not these
forms but those of which they are the copies: the square as such, the diagonal
as such. The figures serve as illustrations which merely help us learn what
can be known only through the understanding {dianoia).
our sensory perception of the continuously changing world we add a
To
knowledge that is timeless and enduring. We had this knowledge before
our perception (later it came to be termed a priori knowledge in contra-
distinction to a posteriori experience). In the Meno, Plato shows (by the
(Timaeus) they reappear in their simplest form, namely as the models that
the Demiurge contemplates while fashioning the world. A line seems to
run from the perplexities (particularly in the early dialogues) to the theory
of Ideas and thence to the ineffable. The frame seems to grow steadily
wider, the place of action more open and at the same time more richly in-
habited; as to the solution, never complete.
it is
G. The parable of the cave: The theory of Ideas is brought home to us most
forcefully in the celebrated parable of the cave (Republic, Book VII), illus-
trating our human situation and the knowledge and action that are possible
in it
Men live in an underground cave, their legs and necks chained so they
cannot move. They can only see straight ahead, for the chains prevent them
from turning their heads. Above and behind them a fire is blazing at a
distance, and between the fire and the prisoners there is a raised path, beside
which runs a low wall. Along the wall men pass carrying all manner of
statuesand figures. Some of them are talking, others are silent. Of all these
things and of each other the prisoners see only the shadows cast by the fire
on the wall opposite from them. They take the shadows of the objects for
the truth and imagine that the words they hear are spoken by the passing
shadows.
And now a wonderful thing happens. The prisoners are unchained When
one of them is compelled to stand up and turn his neck, he suffers sharp
pains. His eyes are blinded by the glare of the fire. He is unable to recognize
the things whose shadows he saw before. He believes that the shadows were
more real and true than what is shown him now. If he were compelled to look
at the fire, his eyes would hurt. He would turn away and take refuge in the
water, then real objects themselves, then at night the heavenly bodies, the
light of the moon and stars, and finally by day the sunlight and the sun
itself. Now sees not mere reflections but all things in their full reality.
he
He proceeds to reason that it is the sun which gives us the seasons, that it
rules over all and is even in a certain sense the source of all the things
he has seen in the cave. And now he considers himself fortunate, when he
remembers his former abode. There honors and distinctions were conferred
on those who most clearly perceived the shadows of the passing objects, who
best remembered them, and were thereby best enabled to predict what would
happen in the future. But now he would rather do anything than be en-
slaved to such false notions and live in such a way.
Now he returns to the cave to set the others free. At first his eyes,
full of darkness, see nothing. He would make himself ridiculous if he tried
to compete with the prisoners in interpreting the shadows. They would
say that his ascent was to blame, that it had ruined his eyesight, and that any
such attempt to rise was folly. And if he attempted to unchain them and lead
them upward, they would kill him.
That is Plato's parable. It is extraordinarily rich in implications. It can
be taken as a metaphor for the two worlds and the modes of knowledge
prevailing in them; for the ways of human life and the two kinds of blind-
ness springing from opposite causes; for the modes of truth; and for tran-
scendence as the essence of human being and human knowledge. Here there
is no need to set forth these interpretations, either those presented by Plato
himself or those that have been added. The parable with its interpretations is
unforgettable. It is a miracle of philosophical invention, providing an ap-
proach to thoughts that do not lend themselves to direct statement.
Certain themes of the parable have lived on in history: the image of man
as a cave dweller, the metaphysics of light which played so important a role
in medieval philosophy, the sun as the author of all life. Moreover, the
parable states three themes that play a determining role in all Platonic philos-
ophizing: the turning around, the stages of knowledge, the twofold direc-
tion of human life.
stage, "the man versed in confutation has an easy time of it and if he wishes
can convince most listeners that anyone who expresses his ideas in speech,
writing, or response, is a bungler. . ." For at the lower stages of knowledge
.
the truth must move in contradictions. "But the listeners often fail to suspect
that what is
being confuted is not really what the mind thinks but the
intrinsic inadequacy of the lower stages of knowledge."
abandon the world; his transcending docs not lead to solitary ecstasy, deifica-
tion. Plato and Plotinus both cast off the heaviness of the world. But
Plotinus contents himself with release from the world, while Plato's
PLATO 35
B. DIALECTIC
We have spoken o the Ideas and have cited parables. stop here would be To
to pass over the core of Plato's philosophic endeavor. Mere statement is not
enough, for at crucial points the inquiring mind runs into difficulties. Thus
the cleavage (chorismos, tmema) between being and becoming leads us
either to conclude that they arc unrelated or to ask how the gap is bridged.
The answers in turn lead to impossible conclusions. If everything that is
has its its character of goodness, for then it must include
Idea, the Idea loses
also the ugly, the evil,and the false. But according to the theory, what has no
Idea can have no being. Each Idea is said to be independent, yet the Ideas
are interrelated. They limit one another or depend on one another. This
raises the question of what Ideas have in common.
In order to solve these difficulties we must thin\ philosophically. Such
thinking is what Plato calls dialectic. But it is not as though we first ran
into difficulties and then had recourse to dialectic; no, it is in the methodic
A. What is Platonic dialectic? There are many brief and simple statements
of what dialectic though they approach
is, it from different angles:
the touchstone by which to determine who, forgoing the use of his
It is
in bond with
eyes and all other sensory perception, is capable of advancing,
the truth, to being itself (Republic). Dialectic is directed toward being,
toward the always identical (Philebtts). All other knowledge and ability
serves only to bring in the spoils, which should be given to the dialectician
to make use of (Euthydcmus). Dialectic is the keystone to the edifice of
ment and thinking in being itself; thus, it is cither a dynamic that drives
us forward or the eternal circular movement of speculation
(particularly
the second part of Parmenides).
ample the paradoxes of motion). The contradictions clash like flint and
steel and the spark they strike is the sought-for knowledge (Republic).
"Serious things cannot be understood without laughable things, nor op-
posites at all without opposites" (Laws). To know the noble we must know
the base. In action, to be sure, we must not follow the base, but we must
know it if we are not to make ourselves ridiculous by sheer ignorance.
Opposites are combined in all sensuous things, wherever there is space and
time. But they are mutually exclusive. For no opposite can "ever be or be-
come its own opposite, but either it passes away or perishes in the change."
But then Plato (in Parmenides) achieves the amazing insight that not
only sensuous things, but the Ideas themselves contain contradictions.
In either case, in the world of things and the world of Ideas, what at
firstends in perplexity becomes dialectically a means of speculation by
which, with the contradictions themselves, one penetrates to deeper knowl-
edge. Contradiction is the dynamic factor. It leads the eristic thinker
through the decomposition of thought straight to nihilism. It "draws the
dialectician toward Being" (Republic).
2. Differentiation and synopsis: Mere listing (the endless citing of ex-
amples) brings no insight into any question. The essence can be grasped
only through an over-all vision (synopsis). In many individual cases the
physician sees the recurrent form (eidos) of the sickness. To know a thing
we must, by means of the logical understanding (logismos), gather its
form (eidos), which is always one, from the many perceptions (Phaedrus).
Pkto is not yet thinking of the abstracting of a universal from many in-
dividual cases; what he has in mind is an apperception of unity of essence.
"The chief test of a natural gift for dialectic .
[is] the ability
. . to see the
connections of things" (Republic). But the truth of the over-all vision is
always dependent on clarity of distinctions (diaircsis). It is the differentiation
that first gives thinking in oppositions its sharpness. Hence Plato's delight
structure of the world of Ideas is made clear and the thinker comes to feel
standing (dianoia), at
an exact determination of invisible relations, he
as the nature of a straight line, the
always starts from presuppositions (such
different kind of figures, the three kinds of angles, etc.).
He cannot go
beyond these presuppositions.
He regards them as self-evident.
out
But dialectic proceeds differently by the hypothetic method. It tries
can be
a hypothesis to see what follows from it, for example: If virtue
it must be knowledge (Meno). But then
without images, working
taught,
with concepts, dialectic thinks its way back to the beginning that pre-
solely
Or rather, thinking (logos) attains to
the be-
cedes all presuppositions.
dialectic; instead of taking the presuppositions as ab-
ginning through
it considers them as mere hypotheses, steps
solutely first and highest,
the true beginning (arete)
mounting to that which has no presupposition,
of the whole. Once it has apprehended the beginning, it descends again,
is related to the beginning, but disregarding every-
retaining everything that
senses and working only with the con-
thing that can be perceived by the
cepts (eide) and
their inner
relationships.
It is an indirect method. If man attempted
to see being itself, he must fear
when sun. Thus
to be blinded, as the eyes are blinded they look into the
it is necessary to operate by way of concepts (logot)
and to investigate the
best way." In this
essence of things with their help. This is "the second
that I as irrefutable. Then
method, I start with a proposition (logos) regard
what seems with it is true, and that what seems
I assume that compatible
is untrue. For example, I start with
the assumption:
incompatible with it
the as such, and so on.
There is such a thing as the beautiful as such, large
as such is beautiful, this
It Mows that if something other than the beautiful
the beautiful" . . .
at
are not ultimate opposites but are both present
Being and nonbeing
38
every step, though in different ways: The highest good is beyond being,
before being and nonbeing. The world of Ideas has being in every Idea, but
in its divergence from another Idea, from otherness, every Idea is also non-
being, which
is expressed in the negative judgment "is not" The world
of
becoming on the one hand being through participation in the Ideas, on
is
the other hand nonbeing, insofar as it merely participates but does not
fully
"be." Matter or space is radically nonbeing, but with its potential
becoming or
coming-into-being, it is also an eternal potentiality toward being.
Plato describes (in Sophist) the "battle of giants" over being, between
those on the one hand who regard all things as bodies in motion, who regard
corporeity in space and time as identical with being and, on the other hand,
those who regard only incorporeal, intelligible Ideas as truly real. The former
are always left with something to which they cannot attribute
corporeity:
their insight, for example. The latter are driven into an untenable
position.
For: "Can we ever be made to believe that motion and life . . . have no
place in perfect being? that it has neither life, nor thought, but stands im-
mutable in solemn aloofness, devoid of intelligence?"
So it is One and the Other (heteron), or with the one and the
with the
many (hen and polla), also with the immutable and that which is "big
and little," and also with the One and "the indefinite Two" (aoristos dyas),
the limited and unlimited (peras and apeiron), or with the good and the
many good things in every case, we must search for the connection, the
Encompassing wherein they unite, the intermediate links, the "between."
Let us try to sum up the substance of the dialectic:
Contradiction becomes a spur to motion, the medium in which opposites
occur is
being developed, and in both a "driving power toward being" is
experienced. The objects of thought are ordered by differentiation and combi-
nation (dicarcsis and
synopsis) in such a way that every meaning derives its
definition from
place in the pyramid or family tree of concepts (in con-
its
conceptual relations is held to cleanse the mind, preparing it for the journey
to the suprasensory. For the thinking- man the purpose of this activity is a
PLATO 39
being itself, the One and immutable, which he can touch upon in thinking
but not grasp.
was an answer to the dialectic that undermined all thought.
Plato's dialectic
Hence on the indispensable requirement for all dialectic: the
his insistence
definite concepts which enable us, when we use a word, to mean always
the same thing. For we must form an identical view of things if we are to
develop their consequences in a compelling way and achieve mastery over
the limitless manifold. To arrive, by means of definite concepts, not at the
eristic dialectic of disintegration (in which the concepts, instead of being
set in a dialectic movement governed by method, are treated haphazardly),
but at the dialectic of the speculative stage that is Plato's method of think-
ing toward the truth.
these assumptions, from which it extracts what is in them and thus ends
in tautologies.
All logic down to modern logistics treats the question by fonnalizations.
For example, the ambivalence of the copula "is" and the corresponding re-
lations between subject and predicate are elucidated by means of a sign
relations in a particular
language which fixates each of the many different
of verbal
sign, so putting an end to the ambiguity language.
40
But began with Plato. He was perfectly well aware of the ambiguity
all this
of the copula "is." "The become is become and the becoming is becoming
and the future is future and the nonbcing is not being all these are in-
accurate statements." Plato elaborates logical forms of cogent relations be-
tween deductions; he singles out premises, arranges a multiplicity of concepts
by progressive dichotomic division from the most universal class to the
indivisible individual He raises the question of compelling correctness in
general The whole of logic down to modern logistics has drawn inspiration
from him. The aim is an edifice of cogent formal relations between things.
But in Plato this logical endeavor stands in the service of something else;
it is itself this something The question is: Has a thinking that is not a
else.
knowing any meaning? Can such thinking, as distinct from logistic formu-
lations, disclose something else, which vanishes in logistic operations?
If we reflect on the nature of language and meaning, on the bond that
attaches our fulfilled thinking to language, and on the futility or rather the
limited possibility of translating word meanings into sign language, we
shall be bound to conclude that the logical formulations which Plato was
first to set forth in a systematic way are designed as the medium of an in-
tention which suffuses them and which is likely to be lost when the medium
is
developed as such in endless logistic determinations.
Can
the perennial magic of all conceptual philosophy and its futility be
understood at one and the same time? Can it be that in its "void" some-
thing is awakened which falls silent if too much thought is devoted to the
void itself? Can it be that something irreplaceable is actualized in tautologies
through their place in the context of thought, through the moment for
which they speak but in such a way that a statement may equally well be
taken as an eccentric
way of saying nothing or as a deeply moving claim?
Consider for example the words spoken by Max Weber shortly before his
death: The true is the truth."
Tautology is a foundering on the shoals of logical emptiness. Thinking can
come to grief in contradictions and vicious circles. Plato's philosophizing
awakens our ear to something which finds its expression in logical emptiness
Plato takes up the question of the relation between thinking and being,
between knowing and the known. Knowledge, he says, springs from the
faculty within us that is related to true
being. He touches on die question
only in passing and with creative simplicity thrusts it aside by the act of
thinking, by setting out to see what happens in this act and what it means
in practice. But in the ensuing development, which became decisive only in
the modern era, the question took on central importance. It was asked: How
isknowledge possible? How is the subject related to the object? What is it
that comprehends them both? How can both be the same, or if not, how
can the subject know of the object? What does it mean to be an object?
Can the dichotomy be overcome and how? These so-called epistemological
questions as to the meaning, modes, limits of our knowledge have found
many answers. There can be no question of a solution. Plato remains il-
luminating to all epistemologists, to those who combat him as well as those
who follow him.
In opposition to this anti-Platonic objection one can ask: Even though
knowledge of things in the world is dependent on experience and observa-
tion, might there not be meaning and content in a thinking that has no
objective bearing on our knowledge of things in the world? Docs the artless
identification of thinking and being not conceal a lofty truth which recurs,
if only implicitly, in every theory of knowledge?
On the third objection: The objection that Plato obscures all knowledge
by intercalating a world of concepts between ourselves and being is based
on the assumption that we can obtain a better insight without a medium,
that we have a language that can dispense with objects. When, for example,
the medium,in the form of mathematics, encounters reality through the ex-
faculty; nor does he ever deny the sublime possibility of transcending. His
thinking bears less analogy to scientific inquiry than to exercises in medita-
tion. It cleanses the mind by rationality and in its operations yields a glimpse
of being itself. It remains in motion. Every answer turns back to become
a question. The meaning of these operations is to be sought in the discovery
of something that I show my confidence in by looking for it, something
wherein I already am if I am on the way to it
Plato's philosophy never becomes a doctrine, but it is always concerned
with the same thing. This same thing cannot be stated once and for all, but
it discloses itself in different ways in the paths of thought that Plato in-
ventively pursued.
The three objections we have discussed attack something of which Plato
had beginning of awareness, and with methods that Plato himself
at least a
endlessly varied pscudo insights into the relation between subject and object,
both of which come to be treated as objects; and speculation on being ceases
to be anything more than an
ontology, dull or fascinating as the case may be,
PLATO 43
opposition to Plato, they demand the separation of the three, or they attack
one of them through the others. All three succumb to the attacks to which
their statements have laid them open, and only logistic remains, the triumph
of a knowledge that is demonstrably correct but utterly indifferent and empty.
All the objections are based on assumptions about the meaning and pos-
sibilities of cognition. They restrict it to rational
thinking, but in so doing
involve themselves in new confusion, because they do not carry out their
own operations strictly. If Plato had started from these assumptions, he would
not have made the "mistakes" that are imputed to him. But then he
would have had no need to be Plato; any man's mind could have thought
the same thing. And there would be no such thing as philosophy.
dialectic gives all this its structure by making it flare up and vanish at
one stroke.
The distance between these modes of thought and what can be appre-
hended by the senses or by reason and is equally valid for every mind, is
obvious. In the first case (that of mystical union) Plato seems to speak of
an objectless and therefore incommunicable experience; in the second, he
seems to carry out empty movements of abstract logic; in the third, he seems
to display images that remain images. Yet all this, which bursts into a
moments of comprehension and through comprehension
fullness of light in
(for cannot be held fast as a possession that is ready for use whenever one
it
inspires recollection of the eternal and the ascent begins with sensuous
beauty; but it is seduction when sexuality becomes self-sufficient, when by
isolating itself it is sullied and debased. Without sensual origin there is
unruly, and tending downward. With its two horses, reason must reach the
place where all knowledge has its goal and whence it derives its guidance,
(Symposium)^ Eros is the son of wealth and poverty, "on one and the same
day he will live and flourish when he is in plenty, and also meet his death,
and come to life again through the vigor he inherits from his father; but
"
what he wins he always loses. . . The Eros of philosophy belongs to our
temporal existence and outside it has no dwelling place. Gods do not phi-
losophize and they do not love, for they know.
In Platonic thinking the Eros is represented now as a reality with multiple
appearances, now as a symbol for the ascent to the eternal,
now as the real
medium of this ascending movement, now as the light that shows the way,
now in the differentiation of true love from the degenerate forms of love.
To speak of love reminds and awakens. Beneath the clarity of rational dis-
There are many mirrors of the modes of love along the way. A mistake is
A. Theology: Plato speaks of God. The good, which in the Republic is com-
pared to the sun, the life-giving Idea that transcends being, what in Parmen-
ides is touched upon in the dialectic of the One, what in Timaeus is
represented as the Demiurge, who, looking upon the Ideas, brings forth the
world from the nothingness of space or matter all these, one may say, refer
to the same thing. But if we combine these statements into a Platonic
theology, the thought is lost. For in each case his thinking approaches the
limit in a different way, in mctaphoric intuition, in a rising dialectic of
B.Psychology: Before Plato, the soul was a name for a being inside the
cosmos, or for a vital force. It was immortal, taking the form of a shadow,
migrating into new births, or eternally tortured in hell. Thinking toward
something that transcends and precedes these myths, Pkto conceives the
PLATO &
soul as what man himself is, his rational essence. He thinks of it in three-part
structures (the rational, the courageous, the acquisitive soul, corresponding
to the three elements in political life: the philosophers who rule, the war-
riors, and the working masses who nourish the community), or in the two-
a Political theory: A
sketch of the best possible state and another outlining
the laws for the second-best state provide the content of the two longest
dialogues, the first written in Plato's maturity, the second in his
old age.
They show how Plato's philosophical thinking moves in one with his
philosophy that is accessible to all men, that is, the constraints to which they
submit through belief, while dialectic philosophy is restricted
to the rulers,
selves to the earnestness of the task in their own actual community, who live
jy the norms that illumine the truth and untruth of the world around them.
operating causes, but was produced by a cause endowed with reason and
knowledge. To be sure, the course of events in nature is also subject to a
blind causality called necessity (anan\e) (sprung from the nonbeing of
space or of matter), but this is only a concomitant cause. Far from being
the sole cause, it is subordinated to the purposive planning of a divine
reason embodied in the Demiurge (in other words, causality is subordinated
to teleology). An
atomic theory after the manner of Dcmocritus (but, unlike
that of Democritus, conceived in mathematical figures) combines with the
only briefly), when we consider the concreteness and subtlety, the simplicity
and richness of the ideas he developed in these realms. It is assuredly unique
in history that one man should have had such an abundance of creative and
historically pregnant ideas, that he should have developed them with so
much force and simplicity and gathered them all into a superordinate,
never completed meaning which left him free, that he should never have
become a captive to any of his creations or to any of his objective discoveries
hi special fields.
A.The unchanging: In the course of the fifty years in which Plato wrote,
many discoveries were made; there was an enormous increase of factual
knowledge. This was the time of the great movement of mathematical and
astronomical investigation. The political upheavals brought new interests.
Plato listened aad took note and intervened with bis ideas. In the course of
PLATO 49
his work we observe changes in the dialogue form. But contrary to the belief
that great transformations occurred in the depths of Plato's thinking is the
B. In Plato themes that were later separated are held together (man and
statefphilosophy and science, philosophy and poetry):
Man and state: Everything depends on man. Concern for the soul comes
before all else. For every individual a turning around is necessary. It is
achieved in philosophical thinking. Pkto provides the groundwork for the
philosophizing of the man who, thinking independently, relies on himself
in the world. He can withdraw from political life, but he does so from
so that all men gain a share in the truth appropriate to the place they occupy
in the whole, though the overwhelming majority of course will never, by
their own knowledge, come into direct contact with the agathon.
In Plato passion for the true state is one with an extrapolitical and supra-
political philosophizing, for which polis and world sink into nothingness.
Thus, in the state he outlines, the philosophers will govern only out of duty;
they will take turns, so that after the practical activity that interrupts his
contemplative idleness, each one will return to the most glorious thing of
all,to pure knowledge. There is no more contradiction between negation of
the world and the will to establish a state than between contempt of men and
the desire to educate them.
Philosophy and science. Plato concerns himself with scientific inquiry,
above all with mathematics and astronomy, but in such a way as to gather
science into philosophizing. Plato's openness toward science is one with the
is
something that cannot be repeated.
If we try to enjoy Pkto's works as literature, to take a noncommittal,
purely aesthetic attitude toward them, the truth of Pkto is lost. What mat-
ters to him is the truth and its fulfillment. And it is in this light that we must
PLATO 51
cannot be split into the poet and the philosopher. His truth would vanish.
Nothing would be left but, first, a sum of propositions which taken by them-
selves would be incomprehensible and mutually contradictory; secondly, a
thinking itself, at the limits of thinking, from out of the thinker's freedom-
It can be encouraged, obstructed, or wasted. In the groundlessness of think-
ing itself, we
gain an intimation of the ground.
>n
fathom. Crucial for all success in the world is divine decree (theia moira).
The freedom of his autonomous thinking is grounded in a historic bond.
That why
is he was able to attain the autonomy of thought, which in the
Egypt, never denied the superiority of the free intellectual life of Athens.
there is in Plato an atmosphere of veneration, of piety, of
Consequently
love for his origins.
2. Plato s Limitations
philosophy.
physically wretched; for one who lives so must necessarily lead a wretched
life." In all these notions Plato negates what even in
antiquity was known
as philanthropia and humanitas.
Both in its
physical manifestation and in its
philosophical interpretation,
there is to us
something dissatisfying about Plato's conception of love. The
homosexual love that the Greeks took for granted is the historic setting
which, though it does not impair the truth of Plato's thinking, compels
us to fight off a feeling of strangeness. The philosophical interpretation con-
centrates so exclusively on the Idea, disregarding the historic possibility of
love for a single, definite individual, that if we had only Plato to
go by we
should not even recognize the metaphysical love between the sexes mat
Biblical religion has made possible in the West Plato's tendency to represent
sexuality in general as evil bars the way to the fulfillment of carnal love
as a pledge of eternity. There is no sublimation of the unique reality, and
drafted laws for an immutable state. The leap from the eternity he discerned
in his philosophizing to the gyi-tf^nrtal reality of a unique, irrevocable history
did not take place. Plato elucidated profound impulses, perceived lofty
norms, but he failed to see the necessity of a bond with the reality given
here and now, in space and time. This limitation, as Plato himself under-
stood, made his ideas inapplicable. Yet these same ideas made possible the
growth of an area where political impulses could spring from the political
ethos grounded in God
It has to 60 with this limitation of his political thinking that Plato, think-
ing tinhistorically, could so easily neglect the present tasks of concrete political
reality, preferring a philosophical
retirement from the evil world. Since
historical continuity did not enter his field of vision, he felt that the ideal
could at some moment or other in the infinite course of time be realized
by "divine decree" (theia moira). There was always plenty of time, and some-
day perfection would set in- This was all that mattered He gave no
thought to political action within the realm of the possible, to the education
of men in the art of living together through the ethos of a democracy. To be
sure, he saw the problems which for every democracy remain problems. But
in conceiving the ideal prototype, he saw only the authoritarian and totali-
tarian solution, which in his hands developed grotesquely inhuman features.
progress which merely creates steps for successors to stand on, which leaves
men dissatisfied unless they can content themselves with the work itself,
with the business of advancing into
uncertainty, there remains the un-
answered question: To what end?
In the Academy, Plato not
only took an interest in the contemporary
scyttfific movements of mathematics,
astronomy, medicine (in which be-
PLATO 57
questioning.
He used them as the material of his philosophizing. He em-
in the scientific myth of the building of the world in
ployed their findings
Timaeus; their methods were for him guides for the practice of purely
conceptual thought as a preparation for the transcending movement
of
the dialectic. He despised mere empirical knowledge.
What he regarded as essential in astronomy was not the knowledge itself
but that it disclosed a reflection of die Ideas. He dismissed as useless play
ophizing. Its central concern was to educate and form future statesmen. The
men of the Academy were prepared, if the occasion offered, to seize the
3. Plato's Significance Us
for
Plato for the first time saw man in the situation of total disaster that arises
isthinldng if it is false and fails to understand itself.
the task of a Accordingly
turning of the mind. Since, with the great
radial
thinking had started on the way of enlightenment, Lee
"eredbySophi
and the conditioas of men's life
together seemed to lid to
of all this * was
necessary to seek the
TKJW
meU, wttk the instruments of the
such disaster. In Plato we see
way through
very same tLught that
the firsT^eat movement of
right
^
PLATO 59
itsadversary philosophy comes for the first time to itself. Plato became the
source of philosophy in the crisis that never ceases even though it may be
denied or talked away.
It is a fearful irony that Socrates should have been convicted as a Sophist
by an Athenian court, a distortion that characterizes the situation -of philos-
ophy in the world. For the undiscerning, Socrates and Sophism were
the same. Invisible to the general public, the new, the great countermove-
ment and rebirth, was embodied in this one man. To the public he was the
very essence of the Sophism they hated. The public mincl, defending itself
against enlightenment and the demands of philosophy, condemned him as
evil incarnate. In their the Sophists are at once irritating and
frivolity,
acceptable to the crowd. For the Sophists are pliable, affable, serviceable,
and sometimes pleasingly seductive. But when it is a question of thinking
in earnest, when an absolute is manifested, an eternal truth that makes a
rl^im on independent thinking, then there is something in man that rebels
against the rigors of responsible self-clarification. He does not want to wake
up but to go on sleeping.
But did Plato show the way? Does he still show us the way? The essence
of his communication is to make men aware of the necessity of finding the
way, and to give them the strength to search for it. The way itself is not
manifested in definite instructions. For it cannot be indicated by pointing
to a finite goal in the world. That is Plato's indispensable contribution to
the self-responsibility ofhuman thinking (though Plato restricts responsible
thinking to philosopher-kings).
The philosophizing reader of Plato is spurred to transcend anything that
may look like a doctrine. And in this transcending there is a peculiar
philosophical satisfaction. The essential always seems near at hand, hence
Plato's great force of attraction. It is never definitively present, hence the
great demand to devote new powers to it. Plato seems to promise the ex-
traordinary. But to attain it the Platonist must draw it from himself. Plato
brings us philosophizing, which by its very nature is never completed or
concluded.
we seem to sec the incarnation of philosophizing as
In Plato such. By
his reality, we ascertain what philosophy is. Through him we test the value
of our own thinking.
IV. INFLUENCE
ing. For Plato follows the paths of definite knowledge and, through the
attains for the first time
process and content and limits of such knowledge,
a fulfilled nonknowkdge. It is through the inexhaustible richness of the
world that this philosophizing leads to being.
Plato gave to philosophy its widest scope. He opened up new possibilities
and stamped it with the idea of unity. Tbis unity is not the synthesis of all
knowledge in a whole, but the essence of Plato's thinking, oriented toward
the transcendent One. He assimilated the whole past, and knew himself to
be a link in the chain of philosophers, but at the same time the founder
of what first gave the chain hs binding character and made it, properly
speaking, a chain. Through him who looked back at his predecessors in the
light of the spiritual present, philosophy became a lasting process. Since
Pkto all philosophers have been born into what he initiated.
Nearly all the themes of philosophizing converge in Plato and spring
from though philosophy began and ended with him. Everything
Plato, as
that preceded Platonic thinking seems to serve it, and everything that came
after seems to interpret it. Nevertheless, earlier philosophy is not a prepara-
But Platonism also included a scientific impulse that pressed in the op-
posite direction. What Plato attempted dialectically in deductive
construc-
tions, his challenge which led the mathematicians to the path that found its
A. Academy: Plato made his influence felt through his school, the Academy.
In his lifetime this was a meeting place of independent personalities from
all over the Greek world, particularly mathematicians. For twenty years
Aristotle belonged to the Academy. It has been regarded as a school of
doctrine and systematic investigation which provided the background of
the dialogues. According to this theory, the dialogues are exoteric writings
based on the esoteric doctrines of the school. It seems more likely that the
that took place at
dialogues are idealized versions of the finest conversations
the Academy. The Academy was the scene of the real conversations from
which Plato derived his extraordinary experience of scrupulous dialogue,
of the possible perversions of discussion, of personal friendship based on
common intellectual interest, of the different kinds of opposition and
62
spirit.
It lies in the very nature of a school that an utterly un-Platonic spirit
death. Speusippus and Xenocrates in-
triumphed immediately after Plato's
troduced a dogmatization in which all independent philosophizing was lost
Aristotle left and founded his own school based on free research, but aban-
the so-called Academic
doning the Platonic spirit. In later generations,
Skeptics even transformed
the freedom of Platonic thinking into a lifeless
dogma* Yet the school preserved an extraordinary mobility and the power
kinds. It flourished
to produce outstanding philosophers of many different
for almost a thousand years, until A J>. 529, when it was forcibly closed.
B.Aristotle: The question of the relation between Plato and Aristotle has
been alive for more than two thousand years. The answer has determined
the nature of each epoch's philosophizing. The conflict between Platonism
and Aristotelianism has been realand radical But there has also been, as
the third possibility, the belief, and an attempt to prove, that the two were
fundamentally one.
This unifying attitude turns in favor of Pkto when Aristotle is invoked
'
part of it, but this was a matter of mood far more than of thinking. His
critique, for example, of the proposition that virtue is knowledge and that no
one can knowingly commit injustice, or of the Ideas that exist independently,
outside of dungs, is always plausible and even conclusive. But it utterly
misses the essence of Pkto,
Aristotle was the first to classify Pkto*s fKinking according to its pkce in
the history of philosophy: "Next came the doctrine of Pkto, which derived
in the main from the doctrine of die Italic school
[Pythagoreans], but also
had something of its own," namely what came from
Cratylus and Socrates.
In answer to this classification, we may ask whether it is
possible to under-
stand Pktaffic thinking by it to norm. "Theo-
1*
subordinating any objective
rems from Plato's work can be treated in this way, but not the
philosophy
itselL The higher vantage point from which Aristotle classifies it is his own
philosophy, a mere philosophy of the rational that sets itself up as an ab-
PLATO 63
the form which Plato's thinking, losing its original character, assumed for
late antiquity and the Middle Ages, For more than a thousand years
Platonism was Neoplatonism rather than Plato. The active aspect of Plato
was submerged in contemplation. Plato's sober hardness, his either-or was
blunted; the cleavage (tmema) was bridged over in the doctrine of degrees;
the cool Eros was lost in mysticism and finally in magic. Now philosophy
claimed to be a religion* It preserved its independent existence, but the
philosopher became the "hierophant of the whole world" (Proclus, 410-485).
It never occurred to Plato that he had founded a religion. But he had.
Proclus filled in the frame of Neoplatonism with all the gods of late antiquity
and created a Greek theology; Origen peopled the Platonic area with Biblical
and Christian figures and, aided by Plato, founded Christian theology. In
this, Proclus and Origen are akin, and it was from the Greek theology of
Proclus that the Christian Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite (c. 500) largely
derived his ideas.
Augustine was a Neoplatonist. He transformed Plato's Demiurge, who
made the world from the matter of space, into a Biblical Creator who called
it forth from the void, transformed the Ideas into the thoughts of God from
whom the Logos emanates, replaced self-liberation through thinking by
redemption from original sin through grace,
D. Platonism in the Middle Ages, the Renaissance, and the Enlightenment:
The Platonism of the Middle Ages, from Scotus Erigena and the Chartres
school to Meister Eckhart and Nicholas of Cusa, is in large part Neoplaton-
ism, derived from the pagan Proclus by way of the Christian Dionysius
and translated into Latin by Erigena. Beginning with the twelfth century,
the Timaeus, a part of the Parmenides, and later the Phaedo and the Meno
became known. It was only hi the fifteenth century that the Republic
and the other dialogues came to light.
In the Renaissance, the Florentine Academy centered around Marsilio
Ficino honored Plato as the man who had combined the two ways of
beatitude (lamblichus), that of the philosopher and that of the priest. For
Ficino he was the acute dialectician, the pious priest, and the great orator.
The medieval tradition was enriched by the new knowledge of all the
dialogues, but no radical break occurred and a knowledge of the true Plato
was not achieved. Later, in the seventeenth century, the English Platonists,
Cudworth and More, took part in this movement. Love and the Beautiful
took their place the old religious contents.
among
On
Kepler and Galileo, Plato exerted an entirely different influence-
based on Meno, Tkeaetetus, and Sophist. It was from him that they drew
their toward a new, modern, mathematical science of nature,
impulsion
64
i.
Biography
2. The Writings
The eleven folios of Augustine's works arc like a mine. The jewels and
veins of gold arc embedded in great masses of barren rock. It is in the midst
65
66
Augustine's meeting
with Ambrose, his conversion and abandonment of
the teaching of rhetoric. The earliest of them grew out of his philosophizing
with his friends in Cassiciacum. The first group consists of philosophical
Christ is rarely mentioned and there are few Biblical
writings, all dialogues;
But his Christian conviction was real and final. Even after
quotations.
his baptism he wrote largely in the philosophical style until his ordination
(387-391). Then began the great body of work that was to continue for
the rest of his life: tie sermons and letters, the cxegetic works (particularly
on the Psalms and St. John), the didactic writings (On the Instruction of
Novices, On Christian Doctrine, the Enchiridion) and side by side with
these, the great works, three of which are of particular importance: i) The
Confessions, c. 400; here Augustine gives praise and thanks to God by way
of an autobiography in which philosophical and theological thoughts appear
as the substance of a life that knows itself to be under God's guidance, 2)
On the Trinity (De Trinitate), a profound, purely speculative work (c.
i. The Conversion
long hesitation. The Christian sceo!s of his childhood had opened, but it
consuming desire that had no counterpart in the reality of the world, that
found no pkclge of truth in the authority of an encompassing community.
Augustine first found peace in the Biblical God who spoke to h?rr> in the
Scriptures, who brought unity to a life that had hitherto been
dispersed,
quelled the world and its passions, and received Hrr> into a real, world-
embracing community, the Church,
Now the old philosophical ideas, which in themselves were powerless,
became instruments in a perpetual thinking of God, who however is brought
to lie in the mind by faith and not
by thinking. Thinking is a way, but
only one way, by which to confirm and elucidate what faith has already
made a certainty. Augustine's ideas of God, detached from their ground
in faith, can be worked outas independent philosophical ideas. But that is
not how they are intended in Augustine, for they arc guided by a faith that
has become one with reason.
Augustine explores all the ways of coming
into contact with God
through thinking. But his thoughts are held together
by authority, not by a jAilosophical principle.
The movement of Augustine's intuition of God required that philosophy
adopt die Biblical idea of God and thus become a different kind of philos-
ophy. Nor, in this philosophical metamorphosis, did the Biblical God re-
main what He had been in the Scriptures. Augustine
transposes the Bible
to a single plane,
thinking away the diversities and contradictions of Bibli-
AUGUSTINE 69
edge. Plotinus' triad the One that is above being, the spirit that is being,
and the world-soul that is reality -becomes in Augustine the Trinity, the
One God in three persons, Plotinus' One emanates spirit, world-soul, matter
in an eternal cycle. In Augustine not eternal emanation, but a unique Crea-
tion is the ground of the world, which has a beginning and an end.
Plotinus' is at rest, man turns toward it. Augustine's Biblical God is an
One
active will, which turns toward man. Plotinus did not pray. Prayer is the
center of Augustine's life. Plotinus finds exaltation in speculation aimed at
and defined in controversy against pagan philosophy and the heresies. Clarity
leads faith to full awareness of itself. The na-
brings depth. Lucid discourse
ture of God and of evil is clarified in the polemics against the Manichaeans;
freedom and grace, original sin and redemption, are clarified in the contro-
versy against Pelagius and the Pelagians; the catholicity of the Church as the
matics, specifically the Donatists. And the nature of the Church is clarified in
way to the demand for their compulsory inclusion in the Catholic Church
(cage inirare). His doctrine of free will is almost entirely lost in his doctrine
of grace.Looking back, he becomes aware of past errors. At the end of his
life he wrote the Retractationes, in which he considers his writings in
Augustine presses forward to every limit in order, thrown back upon him-
to hear the voice of Another within him. "Go not outward, turn in-
self,
ward into thyself; in the inner man dwells the truth; and if thou hast
found thy nature to be changeable, transcend thyself** (Noli faras ire, in te
rather, to elucidateour inner action, the presence of God in our soul as the
starting point of our knowledge.
The soul's bond with God is not cut for the benefit of a mere theology.
Augustine's talent for speculation has been much praised, but the meta-
physical, transcending movements of his thinking are not so much insights
into something other as fulfillments of his own upward striving. has been He
seen as a great dogmatist and accorded a leading position in the history of
dogma, but his dogmas are not yet articles of faith as in later theology; they
own emotion, expressed in rational terms. Windelband
are revelations of his
called thismanner of thinking a "metaphysics of inner experience," rightly
because Augustine was concerned in clarifying the suprasensory motivation
in man, wrongly because the term suggests a new objective metaphysics of
the souL
Never before had a man faced his own soul in this way. Not Heraclitus
("You could not find the boundaries of the soul, so deep is logos"), not
its
Socrates and Plato, for whom everything depended on the good of the
souL "Man," cried Augustine, an immense abyss [grande profundum est
"is
ipse homo], whose very hairs Thou numberest, O Lord And yet arc the
hairs of his head more readily numbered than are his affections and the
movements of his heart.**
And he sums up the whole of his awe in one short sentence: "I became
a question to myself" (questio mihi foetus sum). Augustine often busies
himself with everyday phenomena. He finds wonderfully simple sentences to
describe in a few words things of which no one before him had been so
clearly aware. He thinks in the form of progressive questioning, of ques-
tions that are not simply answered but open up a field. A
few examples:
First example: memory. One of the so<alled psychological phenomena de-
scribed by Augustine is the way in which our own inwardness puts a world
at our disposal. Endlessly we visualize things we have seen in the past, that
our imagination produces. A vast inner temple stands open to me. It apper-
tains to my But such words, Augustine says, are easily spoken. They
nature.
do not bring a grasp of what he is trying to communicate, which is always
more than what I think of myself. And so he continues: "I say, it is a
power of mine and appertains unto my nature," and yet, "I myself do not
grasp all that I am. Therefore is the mind too narrow to contain itself?
And where should that be which it does not contain of itself? ... A great
admiration rises upon me; astonishment seizes me." When Augustine speaks
of the waves of the sea, the rivers, and the stars, he marvels "that when I
spoke of all these things, I was not looking on them with my eyes, and yet
I could not speak of them unless those mountains, and waves, and rivers,
and stars which I saw, and that ocean which I [never saw and
only]
believe in, I saw inwardly in my memory in the same vast dimensions as
I saw them outside myself."
Second example: self-certainty. Augustine was first to express the thought,
which he couches in a number of forms, that all doubt in the truth is dis-
pelled by the certainty of the "I am." "For even if he doubts ... he under-
stands that he is doubting. ... A man may doubt everything else, but he
should not doubt any of these facts; for if they were not so, he could doubt
of nothing" (De Trinitate). Thus doubt in itself demonstrates the truth: I
am if I doubt. For doubt itself is possible only if I am.
Now the question arises: What is the content of this certainty? In Augus-
tine it is not an empty observation made once and for all, but the outcome
of a reflection that is never concluded. The certainty that arises in extreme
doubt has more to offer than a feeling of existence. Self-certainty shows me
not only that I am, but what I am. The following dialogue is a
beginning
of progressive questioning:
We exist,we know of our being, and we love this being and this knowledge.
And in these three elements no possibility of error need trouble us. For we ap-
prehend them, not as we apprehend the things outside us, with any bodily sense,
but beyond any possibility that my fancy is deluding me, I am absolutely certain
that I am, th?t I know it, and that I love this knowledge.
No more rfon there is anyone who does not wish to be happy is there anyone
who does not wish to be. ... It is only because there is something so naturally
and powerfully pleasant about being that unhappy men do not want to die. . . .
If they were granted an immortality in which their misery did not cease,
and
offered the choice of either living in such misery forever or of not existing at all,
to live forever in diis state than not
they would surely cry out for joy and prefer
to exist at alL
not know the will to delusion, nor conscious self-deception, nor the
possi-
bility that all "truth" may be questionable.
Thus Augustinian shelteredness in God is something other than
philosophi-
cal self-certainty. He toward the place where "our being will know no
lives
death, our knowledge no error, and our love no stumbling block." But here
in time, if we are so certain of our being, our knowledge, and our
love, it
is not
primarily "on the strength of someone else's testimony. In our very
own person we feel it to be really present and perceive it with the inner
eye that cannot be deceived" (philosophically, that is to say). But at the same
time "we have other witnesses whose credibility cannot be doubted." Thus
for Augustine self-certainty and the "other witnesses" (the authority of the
Church, revelation) stand abruptly side by side. The content and fullness
of the self spring from God's image in man and are confirmed
by the other
witnesses.
Third cxamfle: time. Augustine concerns himself with time. It is
present
at every moment. And the more deeply he delves into it with his
question-
ing, the more unfathomable its mystery becomes for him.
We
speak of past, present, future. "If nothing passed away, there would
not be past time; and if
nothing were coming, there would not be future
time; and if nothing were, there would not be present time." But
1
strange:
past and future are not, the past is no longer, die future is not yet, and if
the present were always
present, if it did not lose itself in the past, it would
no longer be a time. In order to be a time, the
present must exist in the
feet that it passes into
immediately nonbcing.
Are
there three times, or
only one, the present? For indeed, future and
past arc only in the present. When I relate things past, I
regard their
images in the present. When I think of the future, possible actions and
images arc present in mind. There is
my the
only and in the
present present
three times. The memory present in regard to the past, intuition is present
is
For Augustine the Bible was the language of revelation that is the source
of all truth; the philosophical idea of transcendence was fulfilled by the
Biblical idea of God, which transformed speculation into
living presence. The
finest philosophical sentences paled before a line of the Psalms.
Reason and faith are not two separate sources that meet at some point
Reason is in faith, faith in reason. Augustine knows of no conflict that can
be resolved only by the surrender of reason. A
sacnfidum intcllcctus, Tertul-
lian's credo quia absurdum is alien to him. Hence
Augustine's believing
verification of the truth docs not start with
unequivocal Bible quotations
from which dogmas are deduced Rather, faith, as living and active presence,
isin fact (though not consciously) free in its approach to the Bible as an
unfathomable depth that remains to be understood. The unphilological
and unhistorical methods of interpretation, developed before Augustine,
made it
possible to find almost any tenet of faith in the Bible. For this
reason, Augustine's writings (except for the earliest) are shot through
with quotations from the Bible. On the other hand, the main contents of
Augustine's thinking, even if we do not share in his revealed faith, are
intelligible to us because of the freedom of his operations. And then, in
the area of reason, we can re-enact the secure truth of this Augustinian
thought process as the elucidation of the soul's inwardness down to the
limits where it transcends itself; the examination of time, memory, in-
finity; the disquisitions on freedom and grace, Creation and the world
The truth is only one. It is the "common possession of all its friends." The
claim to have a truth of one's own is a "presumptuous assertion," it is "vain-
glory." "Because Thy truth, O
Lord, does not belong to me, to this man or
that man, but to us all, Thou hast called us to it with a terrible warning
not to claim exclusively for ourselves, for if we do we shall lose it
it
Accordingly, Augustine sets out to seek the common truth, even in the
company of his adversaries. Such a quest is possible only if both parties
his adversary, it is not to command, but to convince him. What arouses ideas
o or insincerity in us is on the one hand an abrupt turnabout that
sincerity
Augustine effects over and over again: from a searching for the truth to a
having-found the one truth and, on the other hand, an attitude which per-
petually transforms having-found to a thinking search. This contradiction
makes both the sternest intolerance and a readiness to meet the
possible
other halfway. The turnabout annuls communication by restricting it to
The question is: How shall I find, in the other and hi myself, the hall-
mark of the particular, of that which is not common to us, hence of the lie?
Though Augustine sees the truth in the common freedom of reason, hi the
attempt of two men to convince one another, nevertheless it is present only
in revelation, Church and Bible. Hence in practice, Augustine, contrary
to his earlier demands, concludes that force should be used against those
of different faith. This same turnabout from open communication to the
pass him by." Authority is only in God. Everything else is along the way
and becomes idolatry if taken in God's stead. But now comes the turnabout.
To the question: Where does God speak? the answer is always: In revela-
tion. With revelation we do not remain on the way but, through the love
with which God seizes hold of us, we attain to God in the faith of the
Church, to which we bow in obedience.
Or the turnabout may take this form: on the way, an independent life of
reason is reflected in rational endeavors. Such endeavors require justification.
In DC musica, Augustine declares that he would never have undertaken such
a venture had the need to refute the heretics not compelled him "to sacri-
fice somuch strength to such childish occupations as discourse and dis-
Thus thinking is an aid to those of weak faith. To do what holy
cussion."
men accomplished by a swift flight of the spirit required long and tedious
ways on which they would not have deigned to set foot. For they worship,
in faith, hope, and charity, "the consubstantial and immutable
triunity of the
one supreme God. They are purified not by the flickering lights of human
reason but by the mighty, burning power of love." Over and over again,
this deprecation of
thinking and single-minded devotion to faith and love,
which surpass all thought and can do without it, this sharp view of the
fundamental difference between thinking and faith, results in a turnabout
from thinking to faith. But though the highest, fullest truth speaks to the
believer akme, though reason in its endless
searching can never attain to it,
AUGUSTINE 79
still there can be no faith without reason. Therefore Augustine says: "Know
in order to believe, believe in order to know" (intellige ut credos, crede ut
intelligas). Belief, too, is thinking. To believe is nothing other than to think
with assent (cum assensione cogitare). A
being that cannot think can also
not believe. Therefore: Love reason (intettectum vdde ama). Without faith
there can be no insight. Yet insight does not eliminate, but reinforces, faith.
Thus the astonishing Augustinian turnabout culminates in the coercion
of those of different belief. But before that, it had led to the ideas that God
Himself is heard in His revelation and that thinking and believing are one.
This turnabout is a universal manifestation of the Christian world which
had its greatest thinker in Augustine. Is it merely an error that we can
quickly dispel with the enlightened ideas of an all-embracing reason? Were
men of high stature, men able to think sharply and profoundly and to pro-
duce magnificent art and poetry, misled by a mere error? Or did philosophy
itself operate under the cloak of revealed faith? Here we shall content our-
something that I do not see outside myself in space and time. do I, a How
finite creature of the senses, living in space and time, come to truth of
it, I see it with a light that comes from God. Without this light there
Augustine's reflection on the riddle of valid truth leads him to find God's
action in valid truth. What was later unfolded in rich developments, com-
and knowledge, has its historic ground in the sharp formula-
plex distinctions
tionswhich Augustine derived from various sources.
But there is one Platonic idea from which Augustine never departs:
Though we see the truth in a divine light, we do not sec God Himself; and:
Our knowledge is no feeble reflection of divine knowledge, but different
from it in essence.
B. Revelation and Church: The truth has reason and revelation as com-
ponents. They are one and separate. God not only illumines the knowledge
of the mind, but bestows the truth itself through the revelation of the
present Church and the Biblical Church. Faith is ecclesiastical faith or it is
no faith at all For Augustine it is God can be found only in
certain that
this way. His fundamental experience of selfhood as
faith is not only the
wider, more open than at a later day, but even in Augustine they took on
the very concrete forms in which the
self-understanding of Church power
was to develop.
processes,
the struggle between two cosmic powers, by considerations ac-
cessible to the understanding. His indictment was: "They made believe me
blindly." Hesaw through the unreason of their pseudo knowledge.
In this rejection of pseudo knowledge as superstition lies the power of his
belief in God, his hostility to occult knowledge, magic, and charlatanism.
This belief in God made for honesty and openness. But then Augustine came
to feel that none of this worldly knowledge, whether true or false, is the
saving knowledge that helps the soul. His use of reasoned arguments against
it,however, bears witness for a moment to his inclination for scientific, that
is to say, logical, methodic, empirical investigation, and for the distinction
between the knowable and the unknowable. But this feeling is present only
in fleeting ideas that are not held fast by method. It is quite unreliable.
For in many questions concerning realities in the world, to which a science
can provide universally valid answers, Augustine on the basis of Christian
faith makes assertions which, on scientific grounds, draw from us the same
verdict as he delivered against the pseudo knowledge of the Manichaeans,
His belief in God did not prevent him from putting forward a pseudo
knowledge similar to theirs, though in different contexts.
I shall cite an example which at the same time shows the profundity of
the salvation of the souL Some of his arguments are perfectly sound and
valid today. But then he goes on to observe that since many men have
still
They gain power over those men who lust for evil things and deliver them
over to mockery and deception. In themselves, these delusions have no force
or reality, but "because men concerned themselves with these things and
for each man something
gave them names, they first acquired power. Hence,
different comes from one and the same thing, according to his ideas and
assumptions."
are not
Augustine takes the existence of the demons for granted. They
superstition,because the Bible speaks of them. In the statements of the
lofty standard is the source of the many contradictions in his work, which
indicate that in practice neither Augustine nor the believers of his time
observed the distinction between God and creature.(And indeed this has
been true throughout the greater part of Christian history, applying also to
Luther and many other Protestants, who combated the superstition, 'the
belief in devils, witches, miracles, that they themselves carried on.)
In dealing with concrete problems, subject to scientific investigation,
death at the hands of this world. Jesus, the man, is a model for us. Jesus,
things . . . *Ye have told me concerning my God, that ye are not He; tell
me something about Him.' And with a loud voice they exclaimed, *He
"
made us.'
breaks through
B. Jfsus Christ: In philosophical transcending, Augustine
all the thinkable. We
feel the reality of God by saying nothing. His reality
is such that every finite thing and every thought, even the greatest, seems
to turn to nothing before Him, and how can God be represented in nothing?
If thus, when we to conceive of God, everything is withdrawn from our
try
finite thinking, so that nothing remains of it,
two ways arc possible: Either
we may accept this utterance of transcending philosophy as an appropriate
of mortals overpowered by the one
expression for the existential situation
or, disillusioned, we may reject it as an indication
that for us God
reality,
is unthinkable and has no being.
Here is die decisive point. Man desires a bodily presence. God is present
in Christ. 'The word became flesh."
by death, He killed death." For Augustine the two the example and the
grace of the divine act, right human conduct and the vision of divine
action are reflections of one another. And thence result magnificent, absurd
propositions
which in turn clash to produce new perplexities.
For the suffering and death of Jesus, his crucifixion and resurrection,
ascension and entrance into the kingdom of God are at the same time the
life of the believer. The perplexities elucidated by Augustine as abysses of
the human condition are radical. "The Christ who humbled Himself was
exalted on the Cross; His abasement could not possibly be anything but
grandeur." And correspondingly in man: "Humility is our perfection." The
lowest becomes the highest, humility becomes man's glory.
But the forced humility that strives for lowliness and takes delight in it
becomes automatically a new pride. Once it is self-satisfied, humility ceases
to be humble. In driving myself to humility by asceticism, I show pride;
through the power it gains over the self, becomes a triumph
active asceticism,
of proud selfhood. We find many paradoxes of this kind in Augustine's
revaluation, which turns the lower into the higher, becomes a cloak for the
revenge of the inferior. A falsification of values gives impotence power,
and baseness rank (Nietzsche). These psychological intricacies offer a vast
and fertile field for an understanding, discerning psychology.
But all this cannot be turned against die truth at the source of these ideas
and realities. For ia every reality, in every success, in every triumph, in
is no
superiority as such, lies something that is subject to question. There
unless the adversary becomes a friend. Respect for the ad-
joy in victory
versary, struggle without hatred, the spirit of conciliation
can indeed spring
from a sublime will to which, as it advances into higher levels of
power,
being, always wants more; but truly and authentically they can spring
still
only from man's awareness of his utter helplessness, of his impotence in the
presence of real power, from the humility in which man is never adequate
to himself, but seeks the other, seeks all men, for without them he cannot
be himself. These considerations arc the source of chivalry, of nobility in
battle, of solidarity. An unexplored world of the ethos opens up
with die
86
mythical idea of Christ, in which the source and model of human action
are disclosed in simple signs.
gusdne writes: "I have striven to behold with reason what I believed
\dcsidcratn, intcllectu videre, quod credidi] There were not many words,
because there were only the necessary ones. Save me, O God, from prolixity
[a mululoquio\ ... I am not silent in my thoughts
even if I am silent with
my tongue ... but numerous are my thoughts, that are vain as human
thoughts. . . . Grant that I may not consent to them, that even if
they
should delight me I may reject them." Here we have an outstanding
expression of the tension which cannot be overcome in the temporal world
and which Augustine experiences in his thinking of God: the striving for
knowledge, the passion for thinking, and awareness of the futility of such
striving. The authoritative sureness of his assertions is tempered by the way
in which from all thought he turns back to God Himself. It is as though
A. FREEDOM
A. Self-refection:
Constantly scrutinizing his conscience, Augustine discerns
impulses, feelings, tendencies that are in conflict with his conscious will. He
finds self-deceptions, as, for
example, when he prays to God for a sign to
justify his postponement of something that should be done at once; when
up as thirst for knowledge. He recognizes carnal pleasure
curiosity sets itself
when, listening to the singing of the Psalter, he finds himself paying more
attention to the sound than to the content. He finds it
necessary to combat
eating. He is able to dispense with cohabita-
the desire he experiences while
tion but not with sexual dreams. He likes to do what is
right, but in part
he does it to make men love him. Always the hidden motive. All human life
is
perpetual temptation by the senses, by curiosity, by vainglory (the striving
to be feared and loved). And we are unaware of it. I cannot know and
understand myself. Whatever part of myself I
explore, I encounter some-
thing I cannot fathom. Augustine inaugurated the psychology that unmasks
AUGUSTINE Sg
the soul of man. He observed that there was no end of it and cried out to
God: "Greatly I fear my hidden faults that Thine eyes know, but not mine.**
him that the will does not will unequivocally. For him the will was the center
of existence, life itself. "When I willed or did not will something, I was
wholly certain that it was not someone other than I who willed or did not
will it." And here, at the center of his being, he experienced a
frightening
thing (he describes this situation as the state preceding his conversion) : "I
did not that which with an unequaled desire I longed to do, and which
shortly when I should will I should have the power to do. ... For in such
things the power was one with the will, and to will was to do, and yet was
itnot done; and more readily did the body obey the slightest wish of the
soul . . than the soul obeyed itself."
.
"Whence is this monstrous thing? and why is it? The mind commands
the body, and obeys forthwith; and mind commands itself, and is re-
it
decide (whether to act thus or thus, whether to act or not to act) and of
among, will and ability arc not the same thing. I decide and act to the best
of my ability, but always in respect to particulars. It is otherwise when the
decision involves my whole being. Then my will and my ability are the same,
but this will comes to me incomprehensibly. I cannot will this will, but
I do not look on at my decision. I do
through it, because of it, I can will
not bring it about. While deciding, I am already decided. In this decision
I do not have myself in hand; I am dependent on God, who gives me to
myself.
But if I have thus become aware of my nature as a whole, if then, sacrific-
ing my freedom, I conclude that I am eternally doomed to be thus and
cannot become otherwise, Augustine replies: Corruption by original sin
is
dependent on the grace of redemption and gains hope through faith.
freedom that has been given me, not my own. I cannot boast of my free-
dom. It is pride
(superbia) to claim credit for what I owe to God. The
appropriate attitude is humility in freedom. If I credit myself with what
comes from God, I am cast back into my own darkness. It is
pride to take
pleasure in myself as my own work. Humility is the attitude underlying the
truth of all good actions.
action as good. But such awareness is the beginning of pride. Without knowl-
edge cannot
I become good; without knowledge I cannot remain pure. And
humility itself, once conscious of itself, is no longer humble but becomes the
pride of humility.
The reason for this self-love. He cannot
man's
is
escape from it, except
incomprehensibly through the help of God, which enables him to do good
without becoming proud, which enables him to experience in the utmost
freedom his being given to himself by God. God's help gives him the full
freedom with which to attain to God.2
F. Against the Stoics: Augustine knows their doctrine. Man is free and in-
(autarky). And the Stoic does not doubt that we are indeed master of our
own thoughts. He believes we can demonstrate such mastery by guiding our
attention and carrying out our resolutions. Our freedom has no ground, but
is itself a ground. It is identical with reason. The
opposite of freedom is
outward constraint. Hence the more independent I am of outside things,
and the fewer my needs, the freer I shall be. I remain free if I adapt myself
naturally to the world around me. But if, despite my self-sufficiency, I am
nevertheless struck by some outward constraint and such constraints are
inevitable in this life I need not inwardly comply. I become unfrec only if
I allow my composure to be disturbed. Accordingly, freedom is imperturb-
able peace of mind (apatheia). Through it I remain free even under the
most violent constraint from without, even as a slave under torture, even in
the most painful sickness. And in extreme cases, I have the freedom to take
my life.
G.Against the Pelagians: In this last point Augustine opposed Pelagius. For
Pelagius man, because created free, is by God's will independent of God.
Man has freedom of decision (Ubertas arbitrii). He has the possibility of
sinning and of not sinning. Even if he has already decided to sin, there re-
mains a possibility of conversion and hence of freedom. If he wants to, he
2 The on the nature of man are universal. This might be shown
great fundamental ideas
in a general history of ideas, devoted to the fundamental questions and answers of world
philosophy. Here I should merely like to point out an analogy to the sublime ethical attitude
just recorded. Chuang-tzn: "No worse thief than virtue and awareness ... he who considers
himself is lost.'* "The worst is not ID get away from oneself." "One does not speak of the
great Tao. . . . Great goodness does not set itself up as goodness. . . . The Tao that gutters
is not Tao."
can always follow the commandments of God; even after the wickedest life
he can always make a new start.
his mind, man can do evil by him-
Augustine takes a different view. To
but not "The in me is Thy work and Thy gift, the evil in
self, good. good
me is my guilt and Thy judgment" In doing evil the will is free (though
it needs God. "From
not trulyfree, but free to be unfrce) ; in doing good
the bottom of my heart Thou hast removed the muck of corruption. This
means that I no longer will what I will, but will what Thou willst But
where in all these long years was my free will, and from what deep and
dispels the lusts by its reality. This reality can do what it will, because its
pious and purposive, first in the framework of its own people, later
identified
with the world mission of eternal Rome to ensure the peace and well-being
94
half after Plotinus, Augustine stands before us in the flesh. Here is the per-
sonality of a man who dared to bare the ugliest corners of his soul in order
to help his fellow believers on their way to God. With him the exploration
of the self took on metaphysical depth.
No philosopher before Augustine had concerned himself with the un-
certainty of freedom, the ground of its
possibility or the question of its
actual meaning. But Augustine, thanks understanding to his of St. Paul,
considered these matters with an enduring force of conviction.
B. LOVE
love, but to purify it: "Guide toward the garden the water that is flowing
into the sewer." "Love, but take heed what you love." "Love what is worthy
of love."
B. True love: Worthy of love is that beyond which we can find nothing
That is God. All true love is love of God. And to God we attain only
better.
through love. What is loved in the love of God? The permanent and un-
changing, the life that does not die, the good that can and should be loved,
not for the sake of something else but for itself; that in the possession of
which all fear of losing it ceases, so that there is never grief over its toss and
the joy of possession is indestructible.
But all this is put negatively. The highest good itself is not expressed, but
designated as that from which fear, care, uncertainty, toss, and death in the
world are absent. All the dangers of kve in the world have vanished. Are
the contents of our love in the world preserved, freed from their deficiencies
and confirmed from another source? Or if not, what is the positive clement
in what we love as God?
It is uttered only in effusive, identical propositions, not in terms of some-
96
thing else: to love God is to love Him gratuitously (gratis) and not to seek
a reward apart from God. "Beseech Him for thy salvation; and He will be
thy salvation; beseech not salvation from elsewhere." And consequently:
"What were everything Thou gavest me, apart from Thee! That is to say:
love God gratuitously: hope to receive God from God; hasten to be filled
with God, sated by God. For He will suffice thce; beside Him nothing can
suffice thee."
The love of God is unique, in this world and for all eternity. Faith and
hope belong to this existence in time; but love remains: "For even if a man
has attained to eternal life and the other two virtues have ceased, love [that
is, the love of God] will still be present, in increased degree and with greater
certainty."
c. Love determines the nature of man: A man's essence is in his love. "To
ask whether a man is good, is not to ask what he believes or hopes, but
what he loves." "A good man is not one who knows what is good, but one
who loves what is
good."
Where there is love of God, love has an object on which it can rely. The
man who is filled with it will everywhere see the good and do what is right.
To him it may be said: Love and do what thou wilt (dilige et, quod vis, foe).
For he who sees God becomes so small in his love of Him that he prefers
God to himself not only in judgment but in love itself. Here it becomes im-
possible to sin. From this love man cannot backslide into self-compla-
cency.
Once
discerned, this great good "is so easily attained, that the will is the
possession of what is willed." For nothing is so easy for the good will as
to have itself, to have what it wills.
directed at objects in the world, and consequently not a pure love of God.
The fundamental distinction in our loving lies therefore in the direction of
movement, either toward God (cantos) or toward the world (cupiditas).
Cantos, the love of God (amor Dei), loves what alone can be loved for
its own sake, and loves
everything else for the sake of God. Cupiditas, love
of the world {amor mundi), strives for
temporal things. Without relation
to God, this love is perverse, it is called libido; it is love of the flesh
(camalis cupiditas).
Either the movement of love is toward an
object of desire that I have not,
or else I have arrived at my goal and am in
possession of it. On the way, I
love something for the sake of
something else; at the goal, I love it for
itself. On the way, I can use (ft) something for the sake of something else;
at the goal I can it for itself.
enjoy (frui)
But since only God is worthy to be loved for Himself and the only true
love is the love of God, the frui is justified only in connection with God,
AUGUSTINE 97
while in connection with earthly things only an uti is in order. Thus the
essence of all perversion of love is to use what should be enjoyed and enjoy
what should be used. In other words: love for people and things in the
world is
they are loved for the sake of God, not for their own
true only
if
love of God and worldly love arc combined in the right way. This order
implies that uti and frui must not be confused, that all things in the world
should be loved only in the sense of an uti, not enjoyed for their own sake.
It turns out, however, "that God, even here in the world, gives us goods
which arc desirable for their own sake," such as wisdom, friendship, while
others are necessary for the sake of something else, such as doctrine, food,
drink. We cannot do otherwise: This frui is cum delectauone uti, an uu
with enjoyment. When the object of love is present, it necessarily brings joy
with it. In the Retractationes, Augustine explicitly modifies his original
judgment: He had said that to love the visible body was alienation from
God. But it is no alienation from God to love corporeal forms in praise
of God.
Or stated differently: All things in the world are worthy of love: "As
with the beauty of the body, so it is with every creature. Insofar as it is
good, it can be loved in a good or evil way, in a good way if the order is
thing more than the body does not mean to hate the body.
Augustine employs the parable of the wayfarer to indicate what love in
the world means; to show how, because of its drive to go farther, it can
yield satisfaction but not fulfillment. Loved ones shelter us when we are
weary and needful of rest; they refresh us, but then they send us on our
way toward God, who alone is lasting peace. The foot rests when the way-
farer lies down; this gives his will a respite and provides a certain well-being,
but that is not what he is striving for. The resting place is a source of true
God should not love himself. Moreover, one whom God loves loves
himself,
but he who loves God more than himself loves himself in the
right way.
According to Augustine, love of our fellow men is next in importance
after self-love. For who is closer to man than man? We
are all descended
from Adam and are related by lineage. Revelation speaks to us all
through Christ, and we are one in faith.
But if love of our neighbors, our fellow men, is to be true
love, it
must take the form of cantos, not of cupiditas. Caritas is the
bright, serene
love of one soul for another
(sercnitas dUcctionis)-9 cupiditas is the tumultu-
ous night of instinct (caligo libidinis).
Love is reciprocal. The lover "burns the more
ardently the more he sees
the other soul seized
by the same fire." There is "no stronger power to
awaken and increase love than to see oneself loved if one did not or love, to
hope to be loved in return if one was the first to love." Love always strives
to bind two together. From general benevolence, it becomes friendship
(amicitid) : "I felt that my soul and the soul of friend had become one
my
soul in two bodies."
These are rare sentences in
Augustine. Christian-Augustinian love is di-
rected wholly toward one's
neighbor, toward every neighbor as a man. Man
is not loved as an individual God loves
the man whose love is reflected in
self-love. Love of my fellow men me and
spursguides me to the love of
God. It includes the sinner and
my enemy. "For in him thou lovest not what
he is, but what thou wishest him to be"
(non quod est, scd quod vis, ut sit) 9
namely his love of God that makes him lovable.
G. Characterization: In the
history of the philosophy of love (Plato, Dante,
Bruno, Spinoza, Kierkegaard) Augustine's
thinking takes an essential
place. Like all philosophy of love, he
taps the source that is essential to man,
the absolute,
unrestricted, transcendent on which all fullness and meaning
depend, by which everything is measured
In Augustine's caritas three elements
converge: the perfection of an
acosmistic feeling of love; the
having (frui) that no longer desires; active
Help and succor. All this is impersonal, it can be
accomplished in the human
community, the corpus mysticum of Christ. To love God
implies: awareness
of eternity,
through which and in which everything is not mere confidence
in being, but a conscious affirmation
of being as
being a happiness without
object.
Certain critical questions
may be asked: (i) Is this a fundamental aware-
ness of the fullness of
being or is it an escape from hopeless misery to an
exaltation and intensification of the self?
(For does not Augustine say that
our greatest peace here below is
"not so much
joy in happiness as consolation
:
in
unhappiness ?) (3) Does real love in the world tend in
Augustine to
tonsform itself into an extramundane love
that is
the world? Is the love which is consequently unreal in
possible in the world, which in historic form
AUGUSTINE 99
punishment? Does this mean that world and other world are divided into
two realities?
These questions are hard to answer in relation to Augustine, From him
come impulses that we regard as true, but often a clear sign degenerates into
opaque objectivity and the result is a perpetual narrowing. Such conceptions
of future and other world can be true they need not be materialized into
reality or result in the separations of which we have been speaking. But,
on the other hand, such degeneration can easily take place.
C. WORLD HISTORY
A. Augustine's schema and its consequences: The history of mankind is the
story of Creation and man's original estate, of Adam's fall and the original
sin that came with it, of the incarnation of God and the redemption of man.
Now we are living in a period of indeterminate duration, to be concluded
by the end of the world, after which there will remain only hell and the
kingdom of heaven.
The
intervening history is essentially of no importance. All that matters
isthe salvation of every soul. But the great realities of the Roman state and
the Catholic Church are present. After the conquest of Rome by Alaric
(410), the pagans blamed the Christians for the catastrophe. Because they
have forsaken the old gods, the gods have forsaken Rome. Augustine under-
took to vindicate them in his great work, The City of God, in which a view
of history plays an important part. From the beginning, since Cain and
Abel, there have been two states, the worldly state (cwttas terrena), which
goes back to Cain and sin, and the divine state (cimtas Dei), which
goes back to Abel and his life that was pleasing to God. Since Christ these
states have been manifest.
All human existence is twofold. The fall of Adam ushered in a society
based on natural reproduction, in which men are dependent on one another
and have combated one another since Cain. Men form communities that
wage war. They organize the sinful life. Yet at the same time each in-
dividual exists as a creature of God, in an immediate relation to God. These
individuals gather together in the community of faith. They encourage one
another to lead the true life according to the will of God; however, in so
700
doing they depend not on each other but only on God, that is, on revelation
and the Church.
For Augustine the concrete consequences of these two aspects of human
existencewere Church and state, the Catholic Church and the Roman
Empire. All history was a struggle between the divine state and the worldly
state.
had elapsed, over against infinity any enumerable period of time would
be like a drop of water beside the ocean.
In seeking to explain why any particular historical event occurred, Augus-
tine declares that human knowledge cannot fathom God's purposes: God
confers the Empire on Augustus and Nero alike, on Constantine the Chris-
tian and Julian the Apostate. Or else he suggests possible interpretations:
Constantine was granted great success as a Christian ruler as a demonstration
to men that the worship of pagan gods was not necessary for a brilliant
rule; other Christian rulers were unsuccessful, lest Christianity be regarded
as a safeguard against earthly failure. Nevertheless, it is the greatest good
fortune for mankind if a truly pious ruler also possesses the art of govern-
glory, though these were the pagan virtues of men who knew no
higher realm than their earthly fatherland. Furthermore, the Empire
was an example by which Christians might learn how to love their heavenly
fatherland and incur great sacrifices for its sake.
The
study of political history is held to be meaningless, since faith knows
everything we do not understand. The
that God's will is responsible for
events of the secular Empire are said to merit no interest but are
judged
nevertheless. Empires, when justice is absent, are
nothing more than great
robber bands, just as bands of robbers, when
they grow strong, are empires.
"The Roman Empire grew by injustice alone. It would have been small if
itsneighbors had been peaceful and righteous and had not provoked war
by their wrongdoing. Then, for the happiness of the world, all countries
would be small and live in neighborly harmony." As we see, Augustine
accepts the Roman theory that die wars of Rome were just, that the injustice
was with the others.
However, following the analogy of the six days of Creation, Augustine
AUGUSTINE 101
sees the structure of history in the sequence of epochs marking the progress
of the kingdom of God in the world: from Adam to the Flood, from the
Flood to Abraham, from Abraham to David, from David to the Babylonian
captivity,
from the Babylonian captivity to Christ, from Christ to the end
of the world. With his meager insight into political trends, he did not regard
Alaric's conquest of Rome as final. Rome had survived many catastrophes
and would no doubt outlive this one.
His general view of history is never based on investigation but solely
and explicitly on Biblical revelation, A modem reader notes, however, that
it also reflects Augustine's own experience: his personal conversion
and
its consequences. The events of the individual are those of the world,
and
Events of long duration are at the same time immediately present
conversely.
The great Christian thinkers saw their own history as one with Christian
history.
c. Historicity: This made possible for the first time an essentially his-
belief
of nature). For now the past is binding and makes man what he is. But the
essence of the human past is sin, which makes political life necessary and
valid. But, paradoxically, it is the sinful past that must be wholly transcended
and eradicated along with political life. This comes about through the divine
state, the City of God, where, thanks
to the revelation of Christ, the individ-
uals making up the community of faith first perceive the historical fact
the fall of man and enduring even after the incarnation, and
augurated by
will be saved through his faith in the incarnation, an event that occurred
at a definite historical time. Both states arc historically grounded, one
in the
fall of man, the other in revelation. What was hidden from the beginning
was made manifest with Christ.
historic character of man has other
Apart from the two states, the dual
love on the one hand the love of God, on
consequences: the two modes of
the other, world love and self-love and the two modes of human equality,
the one rooted in a common faith and the other in a common, sinful past.
has
D. Characterization of Augustine's philosophy of history: Augustine
been regarded as the founder of the Western philosophy of history. And
indeed it was he who first clearly formulated the question of the whence
and
whither of history. He aroused an awareness of the transcendentally
historical manifestation.
702
discover facts and limits which philosophy interprets. The new view of
history thus developed has vastly broadened and critically secured our em-
pirical knowledge of history,
and it is still advancing over paths whose end
is not in sight. But the speculative schemata have lost their restrictive power.
symbols begins when an attempt is made to claim absolute validity for them
in the wrong place, that is, in a context where they lead to nothing. It
does not spring from any conclusive universal knowledge that is com-
pelled on theoretical grounds to decide for one or the other. Such a total
decision is as
meaningless philosophically as it is scientifically impossible. It
denotes an inept, empty form of rationalistic philosophy that delights in
pseudosdentific argumentation. Argumentation of this sort may have been
more justified at a time when consciousness as a whole had not yet been
illumined by the universally scientific attitude of our day and when the
authentic philosophical impulses had not yet been reawakened.
are left questioning. His nature seems to disclose noble and commonplace
traits. His thinking moves in the most sublime speculations and in rationalis-
sustained by lofty Biblical ideas of God and succumbs
tic platitudes; it is
worldly wisdom, Ms untiring practical activity. In all his writings, the mood
is from that of the Great Awakeners: his passion was accompanied
different
3. Ecclesiastical Thinking
A. Augustine's greatness and limitation lie in the originality of his concep-
tion of ecclesiastical authority. Dissatisfaction with philosophy made him a
ing was free only by virtue of his faith in divine revelation. For him there was
no a priori antagonism between authority and reason, faith and knowledge.
In Augustine's experience free philosophy was empty and conferred no
happiness. He abandoned it in favor of revealed faith, whose meaning and
blessing he conceived to be embodied in theological dogma. But for Augus-
unlike later dogmatists, theology was still in
tine, process of development.
He did not deduce his ideas from dogmatic
principles. For he was still
faced with the task of elaborating the
dogmatic contents of faith, of develop-
ing the unclear sources into a definite faith. His thinking is often inde-
pendent, philosophical, original, though moving in the area and atmosphere
of revealed faith. It is a thinking that
penetrates and makes for awareness.
It is
philosophy.
As a Christian, Augustine became a
philosopher who interpreted the
Church and the Bible. He did not. forsake reason but used it to build
up a
knowledge rooted in faith. With him the authoritarian which we
thinking
are boundto regard as
opposed to philosophy, becomes philosophical, that is
to say, original. His attitude raises
questions that are still alive today, only
seemingly solved. Even when philosophy opposes this attitude, even when it
AUGUSTINE io5
B.For Augustine the authority of the Church was supreme because initiated
by the Creator of all things in His revelation. It was also a source of security
in the most reliable of communities, based not on human contract but on
God's incarnation. For this reason all men belong to it. The proof of its
truth is that it embraces the whole world from Spain to the Orient (the
ancient idea of a consensus gcntiutri)\ such heretics as the Donatists were
a purely local phenomenon. Only folly or stubborn malice could reject the
claim of catholicity, for which reason it was permissible to reinforce proof
with universal coercion. This proof of catholicity has been historically re-
futed. But even today there remains a vestige of it in the sense of community
that animates the Catholic believer, that enables him to regard his Church
and his cult as a home in every part of the earth.
It must never be forgotten
that all Augustine's ideas arc grounded in his
unshakable confidence in the authority of the Church, which alone leads to
Christ and through Him alone in turn to God. Augustine gave magnificent
expression to propositions and movements of thought embodying a funda-
mental self-certainty and certainty of God. But after his conversion, it
pendence. He
needed and desired something other, something coming from
outside, to which he could hold. This other, the Church, is so powerful in
Augustine because he did not find k ready-made, but helped with his
thinking to construct it. It was his
freedom that supplied the movement
of truth in this thinking.
B. By his philosophy
Augustine contributed appreciably to three charac-
teristics of the Church:
its power, its methods of
thought, its magic.
(i) He believed that God's sovereignty as embodied in space and time
should be unlimited Paradoxically, an experience of man's
helplessness gave
AUGUSTINE 707
Augustine was part and parcel of the vast spiritual and political develop-
ment of this institution that dominated the Western world until the begin-
ning of the modern era. And in this development the inwardness of the
beginnings was astoundingly reversed: Contempt for the world became
domination of the world; contemplation became an undeviating will; free-
dom through profound reflection became union through coercion; the
knowledge and speculation grounded in nonknowledge became a body of
doctrine; the temporal movement of searching became the world of dogma,
immutable, subject to no doubt, no longer an object of penetrating thought
but a presupposition.
Self-submission engendered a tendency to repression; self-sacrifice led men
to demand the same sacrifice of others. And the enduring uncertainty (for
tranquillity of systematic
total knowledge, far too much interested in the
the totality otherwise than in God's unfathomable
particular to perceive
unity and in die universal love of God. But in his many systematic opera-
tions and in the actual contradiction that extends to every sphere of his
tive tools.
all men, its corporeal manifestations must
(3) If the Church is to embrace
meet all needs. By his ecclesiastical thinking, Augustine increased the cur-
E. Along with its world renunciation, the model of life provided by Augustine
signified a striving toshow all men the way to eternal salvation, to work
for them as a priest, and through the authority of the Church to rule over
them. Augustine said yes to the world at the end of the Creation, God
saw that it was good but never to the point of experiencing worldly
actuality,even the worldly actuality illumined by transcendence, as a ful-
fillment (except for the things of the Church) ; he never went so for as to
glory in devotion to the state, but these remained beyond the pale of
beatitude. He did not see or know human warmth and loyalty, human love
and friendship. For him the individual was replaceable, not before God,
but for other men. Community existed only in faith or the duty of mutual
aid. Each man alone, because he is himself only through God
is utterly
and with God, not with and through another human self. Loneliness is
overcome not by communication, but through God. Self-love comes before
love of others.
Communication itself becomes subject to the conditions of authority. In
an early work, Augustine expresses his desire to convince rather than to
command. When he spoke with the Manichaeans, he insisted that, if the
dialogue were to have any meaning, neither party must claim to be in
definitive possession of die truth. But nothing remained of these intimations
of another possibility.
F. In the reality of Augustine and the Church there lies an immense ques-
tion. For through them the striving for the truth which binds and brings
peace not only attested but also perverted. The great striving is attested
is
the claim to sole possession of the truth, that is, the one valid revelation of
the One God, led within Christendom to fanatical, self-destructive conflict
among the "denominations" and, on the outside, to wars of
conquest, the
Crusades. Every lust for power was justified as standing in the service of
God. This is not the place to describe what followed. But it is perhaps the
strangest note in our Western history that so much depth in the exploration
of every humanly possible question, so much noble humanity, so much
authentic piety should have been so closely allied with the evil forces they
were striving to combat.
Anoutsider can never fully understand the reality of true ecclesiastical
faith. Of course we can see the outward phenomenon. We
see the structures,
the methods of exerting power, from the sublime forms that overwhelm the
soul to the crude forms that the political power of the Church has often
taken. We do not see what the religious martyr experiences in death, alone
with God. Psychologically, such experience is as inaccessible to us as the
enthusiastic obedience, the self-sacrifice and death of so many Communists.
We confront a power that breaks off communication, withdraws into itself,
speaks always on the assumption that it alone possesses the one truth, and
in decisive moments employs the force which it otherwise humbly con-
demns, sometimes to the point of exterminating whole peoples and cultures
in God's name (the Albigensian Crusade), of loving its enemies by
massacring them,
4. Contradictions in Augustine
A. The source of evil: Augustine rejected the two primordial powers of the
Manichaeans. For God is one. But what then is the source of evil?
is nothing. Because ynan is made out of nothing, he is sinfuL But
Evil
thisnothing that can have no influence (for if k could, it would be some-
to God.
thing) becomes at once a stupendous power. Nothing stands opposed
Evil is man's freedom, which through the fall of Adam and the re-
sultant original sin turns against God in every man. It is not God who
brings about evil, but man. But God has permitted it.
God immutable and this implies that evil is not But the overwhelming
is
reality of evil compels us to recognize its existence and try to explain its
no
origin. According to
the situation, Augustine took now one, now the other
of these positions. The contradiction is evident.
men have tried to sharpen and clarify this
In interminable discussions,
contradiction: on the one hand, evil is a mere clouding of the good, a
shadow, a deficiency; on the other hand, it is an enormously effective power.
But no one has succeeded in resolving it. Various arguments have been
brought forth: Granted, evil in itself is nothing, but it is not nonexistent.
It is nothing because no divine Idea corresponds to it. But since evil is
cufidttas, sin-grace.
c. The Church is the kingdom of heaven, "we are its citizens," "all the good
faithful are elect." The civitas Dei is the congregation of the faithful, that
is, of the saints. But the Church as it
actually is includes non-saints and even
unbelievers. Thus Augustine conceives of an invisible, true Church in con-
trast to the visible Church. It becomes possible to conceive of saints, members
of the City of God, living outside the Church.
The between the two Churches is sharpened by the idea of
distinction
complete certainty; the authority of the Church sheltered him and sustained
him, gave him peace and happiness. But in reflecting on God's eternal, in-
scrutable decision, the immutable predestination of every individual cither to
6. The Personality
not have been possible without Augustine's youth; hence it was determined
by his early life. His conversion is so essential to many of his ideas that
without it they lose their truth. Those who have not experienced such a
conversion cannot find a model in Augustine,
The life of one born into the Catholic faith and raised in it from early
childhood is bound to be more natural, more tranquil, less problematic
tb?n that of Augustine. Thus, among born Catholics, it is
only the priest
or the monk who can fully perceive Augustine's reality and the radical
thing strange in Augustine's attitude toward it. For what he was seeking
is
what he subsequently found in the universal Church. It was not the friend-
ship of a philosophizing in common. For later it becomes perfectly
clear
that for Augustine friendship had its source in the solitude of self-love
before God and was nothing more than a meeting in the common faith.
course).
Like certain pagan sects and a few passages in the New Testament, Au-
gustine considered sexuality as such
to be evil. He knew an unbridled
sensual desire isolated from any higher feeling and later on an ascetic
Augustine lived during the decline and shortly before the end of the
Western Empire. The Roman Empire still existed with its temples and
works of art, its rhetoric and philosophy, its and theaters.
public games
AUGUSTINE II5
Africa was a relatively rich province, and Carthage was a large city, rife
with luxury. But decay was everywhere. There was no organic solution to
the rising discontent (the schismatic Christian Donatists were in league with
pillaging rebels, the Circumcelliones), and the Empire lacked the power to
withstand the barbarian invaders (the Vandals were besieging Hippo at
the time of Augustine's death). Amid the political and economic decline
of the Western Roman world, it is as though Augustine, at the last moment,
laid the spiritual foundation of an utterly new future.
great He was the last
weapons. Augustine himself did not live and think within the world-
dominating Church of the Middle Ages.
Both as a philosopher and as a Christian, Augustine belonged to an
immense tradition. Effective greatness has never risen singly from the void,
but is always sustained by a great tradition that sets its tasks. It is new
because no one else has done what it succeeds in doing. It is old because it
works with materials that were already there, available to all It is a mistake
to exaggerate Augustine's originality, for he is great precisely because of the
essentials that he took over from the past; he was sustained by the spiritual
whole that was there before him and made up his environment. It is equally
wrong to underestimate his originality, for he could not have been fore-
seen: he melted down the ideas he found and in recasting them breathed new
life into them. His original religious experience seems to lend new weight
when the original impetus of philosophy had long been lost in mere repeti-
as the ground of his philoso-
tion, Augustine, taking the Christian faith
phizing, seized upon what was then the original possibility. Awakened by
the intellectual vitality of pagan philosophy, he brought to Christian thinking
independence. No pagan philosopher
his of his time or of the
supreme
the same breath with him.
following centuries can be mentioned in
With Augustine the development of dogmatic theology passed from the
Orient to the West, The spiritualism of the Eastern Christian thinkers re-
mained a power, but now it was reinforced by realistic practice. In the
West, the great tension between negation of the world and accomplishment
in the world became a driving force. The world renunciation embodied in
monasticism (which spread through the Western world in Augustine's time
and which he himself strongly favored) did not paralyze an infinitely patient
still to guide all things toward the
activity in the world. The intent was
eternal kingdom. However, this was to be accomplished not only by se-
cluded meditation but also by practical work in the world. This was the
passion of Augustine the ecclesiastic. He created the formulas
and arguments
that justified this work in the world. This was the beginning of a road that
led from the Christian Orient to a steadily increasing activity of many kinds,
2. Influence
aspect of his thinking provided lasting impulses for a free, original philoso-
phizing. His acceptance of Church authority, on the other hand, gave the
Church every right to claim Augustine for its own in nearly all its great
spiritual and political struggles. Both lines of influence are well grounded:
the first in the particular ideas and movements of thought to which Au-
gustine gave strength, the second in his frin^anvnta! and dominant mood.
AUGUSTINE 117
position and completion. But the influence of St. Thomas was limited to
the Catholic world Augustine was no less a force among Protestants than
among Catholics.
When we speak of Augustinism in special historical contexts, we are re-
ferring to particular doctrines, as, for example, predestination and the cor-
responding doctrine of grace (Luther, Calvin, the Jansenists) in contrast to
the Semipclagianism of the official doctrine; or the "illumination theory of
knowledge" in contrast to the Aristotelian theory of abstraction; or the
foundcst meaning. He did not know the evil that the Church as a political
nB
powers. Through him we can discern at the highest level the eternal opposi-
tion that has run through the whole He of the Church: between catholicity
and reason, between monolithic authority and the openness of freedom, be-
tween the absolute order in the world as the actuality of transcendence and
the relative orders in the world as existence with its many compatible possi-
bilities, between cult and free meditation as the center of life, between the
outward community of prayer, in which each man shuts himself up in his
solitude to find God, and the loneliness before God, which strives to tran-
scend itself in communication with men, through the never-ending process
of loving self-fulfillment
But for us there is something more essential: From Augustine we gain
the fundamental positions in our thinking of God and freedom, in the
passed, not in a rational freedom that seeks its way without guarantee in
the mere hope of help if it earnestly docs what it can, but in the certainty
of grace, guaranteed by ecclesiastical authority and its one exclusive truth.
The greatness of Augustine for those who philosophize resides in the fact
that the truth heawakens in us is no longer Augustine's Christian truth.
For independent philosophy, thinking with Augustine means: to experi-
ence the thematic and existential coincidence of his movements of
thought
with those of original philosophy. It raises the critical
question as to whether,
detached from their ground in Christian faith, these movements of
thought,
though no longer the same, can still be true and effective.
We
experience a constant sense of strangeness in dealing with Augustine.
Even if in his awareness of God we recognize our own, we find it (unless
we merely consider a few pages out of context) in a strange form that
repels us and lends a quality of the incredible tosomething that has just
spoken to us from the depths.
Through the grandeur of his thought, Augustine remains the most im-
pressive representative of those who, human themselves, dare to claim that
they can instruct others about God, and then go on to cite as their witnesses
to an absolute truth men as far as we can
who, were without
know, exception
human beings, no less subject to error than we are. While this claim attests
a love of man for man, a joy in sharing his certainty with others, it also
AUGUSTINE 119
independently.
A strange atmosphere of arrogant humility, of sensual asceticism, of
perpetual veiling and reversal, runs through Christianity more than any
other faith. Augustine was the first to perceive all this. He knew the torment
of inner disharmony, of false and hidden motives the dogma of original sin
made this evil absolute in regard to worldly existence and in a manner of
speaking justified it. The
self-penetration that set in with Augustine con-
tinued down through the Christian thinkers to Pascal, to Kierkegaard and
Nietzsche.
BIBLIOGRAPHY
EDITOR'S NOTE
The Bibliography based on that given in the German original. English translations
is
are given wherever possible. Selected English and American works have been added;
these are marked by an asterisk.
Plato
SOURCES:
Platonis Opera, ed. by John Burnet. 5 vols. in 6. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1902-10.
The Dialogues of Plato, trans, by Benjamin Jowett 2 vols. New York, Random
House, 1937.
by H. N. Fowler,
Plato, trans, W. R. M. Lamb, R. G. Bury. (Loeb Classical Library.)
10 vols. London and New York, Win. Heinemann, Ltd., and G. P. Putnam's
Sons, 1919-29.
Plato: The Republic, trans, by Paul Shorey. (Loeb Classical Library.) 2 vols. London
and New York, Win. Heinemann, Ltd^ and G. P. Putnam's Sons, 1930-35.
Plato: The Dialogues, trans, by Floyer Sydenham and Thomas Taylor. 5 vols. Lon-
don, printed for Thomas Taylor by R. Wilks, 1804.
Plato's dialogues (in roughly chronological order, no certain sequence having been
established, English translations other fhan those listed above are given).
Ion.
Hippias Minor.
Hippias Motor ( ?) .
Protagoras, Benjamin Jowetr*s trans^ rev. by Martin Qstwald, ed. by G. Vlastos,
New York, Liberal Arts Press, 1956.
Apology, in Euthyphro, Apology, Crito and Symposium, Benjamin Jowetfs trans.,
rev. by Moses Hadas. Chicago, H. Regnery Co, 1953.
Crito, in Euthyphro, Apology, Crito and Symposium, Benjamin Jowetr*s trans*,
rev. by Moses Hadas. Chicago, H. Regnery Co., 1953.
Laches.
Charmides.
Euthyphro, in Euthyphro, Apology, Crito and Symposium, Benjamin Jowett's
trans., rev. by Moses Hadas. Chicago, H. Regnery Co., 1953.
Lysis.
Gorgtas.
Menexenos.
Meno, in Protagoras and Meno, trans, fay W. EL C. Guthrie. (Penguin Classics.)
Harmondsworth, Penguin Books, 1956.
121
122 Bibliography
Euthydemus.
Cratylus.
Phaedo, trans, with introduction and commentary by Reginald Hackforth. Cam-
bridge, Cambridge University Press, 1955.
Symposium, trans, by Walter Hamilton. (Penguin Classics.) London and Bald-
more, Penguin Books, 1952.
The Republic, trans, by Francis Macdonald Cornford. New York, Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1956.
Phaedrus, trans, by Reginald Hackforth. Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1952.
Parmenides, in Plato and Parmenides: Parmenides' Way of Truth and Plato's
Parmenides, trans, with introduction and running commentary by Francis Mac-
donald Cornford. New York, Liberal Arts Press, 1957.
Theaetetus, in Plato's Theory of Knowledge: the Tkeaetetus and the Sophist of
Plato, trans, with running commentary by Francis Macdonald Cornford. (Liberal
Arts Library.) London, Routledge and Kcgan Paul, 1951.
Theory of Knowledge: the Theaetetus and the Sophist of Plato,
Sophist, in Plato's
trans, with running commentary by Francis Macdonald Cornford. (Liberal Arts
SECONDARY WORKS:
Apelt, Otto: Platonische Aufsatze. Leipzig and Berlin, Teubner, 1912.
*Barker, Ernest: Gree% Political Theory: Plato and His Predecessors. 5th printing.
London, Methuen, 1957.
: The Political Thought of Plato and Aristotle. London, Methuen, 1906.
*Bluck, Richard Stanley Harold: Plato's Life and Thought. London, Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1949.
Buroct, John: Early Gree^ Philosophy. New York, Meridian Books, 1957.
*Cheroiss, Harold Frederick: Aristotle's Criticism of Plato and the Academy. Balti-
more, Johns Hopkins Press, 1944.
Cornford, Francis Macdonald, see above under Sources (The Republic, Parmenides,
Theaetetus, Sophist Timaeus) .
Dodds, E. R.: The Parmenides of Plato and the Origin of the Neoplatonic *One',"
Classical Quarterly, XXII (London, 1928), 129-42.
Else, Gerard F.: "The Terminology of Ideas," Harvard Studies in Classical Philology,
XLVn (1936), 1755.
Bibliography 12$
*Foster, Michael Beresford: The Political Philosophy of Plato and Hegel. New York,
Oxford University Press, 1935.
Frank, Erich: Plato und die sogenannten Pythagoraer. Halle, Max Niemeyer, 1923.
Frankel, Hermann: Wege und Formen jruhgriechischen Den^ens. Munich, Beck,
1955-
Fricdlander, Paul: Plato, trans, by Hans Meyerhoff. VoL I. New York, Pantheon
Books (Bollingen Series LIX), 1958.
Hoffmann, Ernst: Platon. Zurich, Artemis Verla& 1950.
Jaeger, Werner Wilhelm: Pcddeia: the Ideals of Gree\ Culture, trans, by Gilbert
Highet. 3 vols. New York, Oxford University Press, 1944.
: The Theology of the Early Gree% Philosophers, trans, by E. S. Robinson. New
York, Oxford University Press, 1947.
Kriiger, Gerhard: Einsicht und Leidenschaft: das Wesen des platonischen Den^ens.
Frankfurt am Main, Vittorio Klostermann, 1939.
*Koyr, Alexandre: Discovering Plato, trans, by Leonora Cohen Rosenfield. New
York, Columbia University Press, 1945.
Lcisegang, Hans: "Platon," in Pauly-Wissowa, Rsalencyclopadie. Stuqgart, J. B.
Metzler, 1950.
Natorp, Paul: Platos Ideenlehre; eine Einfuhrung in den JdeaHsmus. Leipzig, F.
Meiner, 1921.
Reidemeister, Kurt:Das exalte Denfyen der Griechen: Beitrage zur Deutung tfon
Euclid, Plato, Aristoteles. Hamburg, Claassen & Govern, 1949.
*Robinson, Richard: Plato's Earlier Dialectic, 2d ed Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1953.
Ross, Sir William David: Plato's Theory of Ideas. New York, Oxford University Press,
1951.
*Shorey, Paul: Platomsm, Ancient and Modern. Berkeley, University of California Press,
1938.
Stenzel, Julius: Zahl und Gestalt bet Platon und Aristoteles. 3d ed. Bad Homburg
vor der Hohe, H. Gentner, 1959.
*Stewart, John Alexander: Plato's Doctrine of Ideas. Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1909.
*Taylor, Alfred Edward: Plato: the Man and His Wor\. 6th ed. London, Methuen,
1952.
* :
4
*Forms and Numbers: a Study in Platonic Metaphysics," Mind (new series),
XXXV (1926), 419-40; XXXVI (1927), 12-33.
Wilamowitz-Moellendorft Ulrich von: Platon. Berlin, Weidemann, 1948.
Wilpert, Paul: Zwei aristotfUsche Fr&hschriften uber die Ideenlehre. Regensburgi J.
Habbal, 1949,
Zeller, Eduard: Outlines of the History of Cree\ Philosophy, I3th eoL, rev. by
Wilhelm Nesde and trans, by L. R. Palmer. New York, Meridian Books, 1955.
Augustine
SOURCES:
Opera Omnia, vols. 32-47 in Patrohgiae cursus completus (Series Latma), ed by
Cain, 99 Homer, 51
Callicles,54
lamblichus, 63
Calvin, John, 116, 117
Christ, see Jesus
Jesus, 66, 78, 82, 83, 86, 88, 92, 98,
Chuang-tzu, gin
101, 106, 117
Cicero, 65, 67
Julian the Apostate, Emperor, 65, 100
Codrus, King, 3
Constantine I, Emperor, 100
Kant, Immanuel, n, 19, 40, 61
Cornford, Francis Macdonald, 4/1
Kepler, Johannes, 63
Cratylus, 62
Cudworth, Ralph, 63 Kierkegaard, Soren, 98, 103-104, 119
Protagoras, 24
Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, 63
Weber, Max, 40
Pythagoras, 12 Wilpert, Paul, 58
Xenocrates, 62
Schltiermacher, Friedrich Daniel Ernst, 64 Xenophanes, 12
Scotus, see Erigena, John Scotus
Xenophon, 10
Shaftesbury, Anthony Ashley Cooper,
Earl of, 64
ZeUer, Eduard, 7
PLATO
Pkto came from the high Athenian aristocracy. His mother's family traced
itsdescent to Solon's brother, his father's legendary genealogy went back
to King Codrus. He was profoundly attached to Athens, the polis that had