Immanuel Kant's Theory of Knowledge
Immanuel Kant's Theory of Knowledge
Immanuel Kant's Theory of Knowledge
CHAPTER TWO
2.1 Introduction
mind was his profound concern over a problem that the philosophy of his day could not deal with
successfully or adequately. The elements of his problem are suggested by his famous comment
that “two things fill the mind with ever new and increasing admiration and awe…the starry
heavens above and the moral law within”. Kant is sometimes introduced as the philosopher who
synthesized rationalism and empiricism. This does not mean that Kant simply adopted the central
views of both schools of thought, for even within the empiricists and rationalists, there are major
disagreements. Also, there are fundamental disagreements between the two schools of thought;
while the rationalists hold that humans possess some ideas that are not derived from any
experience, the empiricist insist that all our ideas must be derived solely from experience. Here,
Kant selected certain doctrines of the rationalists and certain doctrines of the empiricists and put
them together into his own philosophy. He profoundly transformed those views themselves, in
such a way that their meaning and implications were deeply altered, and by rejecting both
rationalism and empiricism, he incorporates elements of rationalist and empiricist thought into a
The rationalists all held that humans can have knowledge of non-empirical reality – a
realm of things that can exist but yet cannot be perceived by the senses or accessed by
introspection. They all maintained that we can have knowledge of certain entities (such as God,
immortal souls and substances underlying thing’s properties) that are not objects of any possible
experience, that is, that can never be presented to us either in sense perception or in
1
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
introspection. Kant rejected this claim and he sought to show that there can be no human
knowledge at all of any non-empirical reality. In this respect, Kant is as much of an empiricist as
David Hume.
Although Kant rejects the claim that humans can have knowledge about any non-
empirical reality, he does not deny that the existence of such a reality is a legitimate topic of
human concern. He believes that there are three specific topics of rationalist metaphysics that are
legitimate, important and even inevitable topics of human concern – God, immortality of the
human soul and human freedom. His position here is that granted that we cannot know whether
God, immortality of the soul and freedom exists, we may believe that they do. This was in his
attempt to place religion outside the vicious attack of reason. “I have found it necessary to deny
The fundamental principle of empiricism is that all our ideas must come from experience,
that is, from sense perception or the introspective awareness of our own states of mind. Kant
does not accept this principle, for he sees the development of empiricism from Locke to Hume,
and especially Hume’s work, as showing that the principle leads to skepticism – to the
impossibility, not only or rationalist metaphysics but also of scientific knowledge and everyday
knowledge against Hume’s skeptical empiricism. In his attempt to liberate science form the
skepticism of Hume, Kant posits that there are special concepts that do not originate in
experience but have what he calls ‘objective validity’ – “Pure Concepts” or “Pure Categories of
Understanding” as Kant names them. Kant’s basic argument here is that all our knowledge
2
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
After a thorough study of the works of Descartes, Leibniz and Spinoza (Continental
rationalists) on one hand, and Locke, Berkeley and Hume (British empiricists) on the other hand
as well as other philosophers before him, Kant’s study of philosophy and metaphysics eventually
led him to ask one question: “How do we know that metaphysics, as a pure science, is valid?”.
This question, and his search for the ability to do logically valid philosophy, led Kant to publish
one of his two most famous works, “The Critique of Pure Reason”. In this volume where his
epistemology lies, Kant deals with questions about how science is possible, what makes
mathematics work, and whether the same reasoning can be applied successfully to philosophy,
specifically metaphysics. His answers to these questions led a new groundwork for philosophy
and gave startling insights into how we perceive the world around us and how nature works.
Immanuel Kant was born on April 22, 1724, in Konigsberg, East Prussia, Germany. He
was the second son, and the sixth of nine children, born to Johann Georg Kant, a humble saddler
(or leather-worker) of very modest means, and Anna Regina Reuter, daughter of a member of the
same saddler's guild.1 He was the child of poor but devout followers of Pietism, a Lutheran
revival movement stressing love and good works, simplicity of worship, and individual access to
God. Kant's promise was recognized by the Pietist minister Franz Albert Schultz, and he
received a free education at the Pietist gymnasium. At sixteen, Kant entered the University of
Königsberg, where he studied mathematics, physics, philosophy, theology, and classical Latin
literature. His leading teacher was Martin Knutzen (1713-51), who introduced him to both
Wolffian philosophy and Newtonian physics, and who inspired some of Kant's own later views
1
Graham Bird, p. 10.
3
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
and philosophical independence by his advocacy of physical influx against the pre-established
Following from his father's death in 1746, Kant left the University to support himself as
tutor, serving in households near Konigsberg for the next eight years. 2Although Kant began
lecturing at the University of Königsberg in the fall of 1755, he was practically destitute,
depending on fees from tutoring and lectures. After several unsuccessful applications for
professorships in logic and metaphysics, he received his first salaried position in 1766 as
assistant librarian at the palace library not until 1770, at the age of forty-six, was Kant awarded
the professorship he desired. In 1747 he completed his first work, Thoughts on the True
between Leibnizians and Cartesians over theories of physical forces. Until the 1760s Kant was a
devotee of Leibniz through the teachings of Christian Wolff. In 1768 he published the short
Kant took his first step toward the critical philosophy; the theory presented in his three
Critiques, in his Inaugural Dissertation of 1770, On the Form and Principles of the Sensible and
Intelligible World. Here he radically distinguished the sensibility from the intellect, arguing that
Leibniz view that the intellect has access to noumena, the reality behind the appearances. Later,
Kant had come to see that he needed a more systematic treatment of the intellect, in both its
theoretical and practical activities.3 In fact he did not produce the first edition of the Critique of
Pure Reason until 1781, almost twelve years after conceiving the project. Unfortunately the work
initially drew negative responses, both for its obscurity and its conclusions. Eventually opinion
2
GUYER, PAUL (1998, 2004). Kant, Immanuel. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. London:
Routledge. Retrieved March 20, 2009, from http://www.rep.routledge.com/article/DB047SECT14
3
Jill Vance B, p. 4
4
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
shifted, and the Critique began to exert its influence in Germany and elsewhere. In 1786 Kant
was made a member of the Berlin Academy of Sciences; in 1794 he was inducted into the
Petersburg Academy, and in 1798 into the Siena Academy. Once engrossed in developing his
critical philosophy, Kant became a recluse and led a celibate life throughout his lifetime. This is
the only explanation for his enormous output from 1781 to his death in 1804. These are the major
works in that period: The Critique of Pure Reason, first edition (1781), The Prolegomena to Any
Future Metaphysics (1783), The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), The
Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (1786), The Critique of Pure Reason, second
edition (1787), The Critique of Practical Reason (1788), The Critique of the Power of Judgment
(1790), The Metaphysics of Morals (1797), Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View
(1798).4
During this period Kant also wrote many shorter essays, among them are The Idea for a
Universal History with Cosmopolitan Intent (1784), What is Enlightenment? (1784), Religion
within the Bounds of Reason Alone (1793), On Eternal Peace (1795), and The Conflict of the
Faculties (1798). On October 8, 1803, Kant became seriously ill for the first time. He died four
knowledge. Before him, philosophers had identified the a priori knowledge and a posteriori
knowledge and had been divided over them as to the sure way of knowledge acquisition. The
rationalists insisted that man’s knowledge is a priori and of an analytic judgment, as against the
empiricists who claimed that man’s knowledge was a posteriori and of a synthetic judgment.
4
The Shorter Routledge Encyclopedia to Philosophy, ed. Edward Craig, p. 491
5
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
Kant’s terminology rests on two different contrasts – one between analytic and synthetic
judgments, and one between a priori and a posteriori knowledge. In practice, with two sets of
distinctions, it looks as if there could be four kinds of judgments: analytic a priori, analytic a
posteriori, synthetic a priori, and synthetic a posteriori. In fact, however, only three kinds of
judgments are possible. At A7/B11 Kant discusses the possible combinations and explains the
problematic character of synthetic a priori judgments. First he notes that there are no analytic a
since determining their truth values requires appealing only to logical form or meanings of
terms.5 From here, I would proceed give an account the possible combinations Kant accepted.
experience”6. For Immanuel Kant, humans possess a faculty that is capable of giving us
knowledge without an appeal to experience. He agreed with the empiricists that our knowledge
begins with experience, but he added that “though our knowledge begins with experience, it does
not follow that it all arises out of experience”. This was the point Hume had missed, for Hume
had said that all our knowledge consists of a series of impressions, which we derive through our
senses. Yet we clearly possess a kind of knowledge that does not arise out of experience even
though it begins with experience. 7 Examples of a priori knowledge include, ‘every change must
have a cause’, ‘all bachelors are unmarried men’ Kant went further to assert that examples of a
5
Jill Vance Buroker, Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: An Introduction, p. 31.
6
Georges Dicker, Kant’s theory of knowledge; an analytic introduction, p. 7
7
Samuel Stumpf, Philosophy History And Problems, p. 303.
6
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
propositions…are always judgments a priori, not empirical; because they carry with them
Kant offers a criterion for identifying a priori knowledge: strict universality and
necessity. “Necessity and strict universality are therefore secure indications of an a priori
cognition, and also belong together inseparably”(B 4).9 Necessary truths are just those that obtain
in all possible worlds; the universal truths are those that express generalizations about all entities
of a particular kind. To see how this criterion is supposed to work, consider the proposition
“every even number is divisible by two”. Its truth is necessary because there cannot be any
counterexamples, and strictly universal because there are not only ‘are not’ but there ‘cannot be’
any exceptions to it. Strict universality entails necessity, but not vice versa, and that necessity is
the fundamental criterion. Kant’s adoption of necessity as the fundamental criterion of the a
priori knowledge accords with his often-repeated and important claim that no proposition that
rests on experience can be necessary. As he puts it: “Experience tells us, indeed, what is, but not
Having clarified the a priori knowledge, an epistemological term which has to do with the
way in which a proposition can be known, Kant went further to assert that all a priori knowledge
are analytic. The term analytic has to do with what makes a proposition true or false. In analytic
judgments, the predicate is already contained in the concept of the subject. The judgment that ‘all
bachelors are unmarried men’ is an analytic judgment, for the predicate ‘unmarried men’ is
already contained in the subject ‘bachelors’. Because the predicate is already implicit in the
subject of an analytic judgment, such a predicate does not give us any new knowledge about the
subject and hence, tautological. An analytic judgment is true only because of the logical relation
8
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. by Norman Kemp Smith, (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1965),
p. 52.
9
Paul Guyer, The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy, p. 37
10
Ibid., p. 9 – paul guyer, the Cambridge companion to kant
7
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
of the subject and predicate. To deny an analytic judgment would involve a logical
contradiction.11
experience’12. The phrase ‘can be known only by experience’ requires some clarification, for it
does not mean, as one might think, ‘can be known just by experience’ or ‘can be known by
experience alone’. Kant had rejected the Humean doctrine that all our knowledge is derived from
knowledge, Kant referred to knowledge which begins from experience and has roots in them. At
least some a posteriori statements require reasoning, well as experience, in order to be known;
for example, our knowledge of scientific laws rests not only on observations but also on complex
inferences or extrapolations from those observations. This point implies that all knowledge
requires conceptualization, which is a form of thought that philosophers often contrast with the
raw data of experience. Examples of a posteriori knowledge include ‘the building is tall’, ‘the car
into action did not objects affecting our senses partly of themselves
11
Samuel Stumpf, P. 304.
12
Georges Dicker, Kant’s theory of knowledge; an analytic introduction, p. 7
8
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
knowledge begins”13
At this, point Kant brings a new element into philosophy. Before him, the empiricists
held that all a posteriori knowledge are synthetic judgments. A synthetic judgment is one whose
predicate is not contained in the notion of the subject. Thus, in a synthetic judgment the predicate
adds something new to our concept of the subject and thus gives us a new and productive
knowledge; it is not tautological and denying the truth of a synthetic judgment would not involve
a logical contradiction. Kant’s point of variance with the empiricists is on their insistence that
‘all posteriori knowledge are synthetic’. Rather, Kant argues that synthetic judgments are for the
most part a posteriori, that is, they occur after an experience of observation. He posits that
besides analytic a priori, and synthetic a posteriori, there exists the synthetic a priori. And it was
by the possibility of the synthetic a priori that Kant sought to show how knowledge is possible.
Kant’s immediate target is the division, found in Leibniz and Hume, of all our knowledge
into two fundamental classes, knowledge that is necessary and a priori, and knowledge that is
contingent and a posteriori. Leibniz divides knowledge into truths of reason (derivable from
logical principles and so necessary) and truths of fact, contingent propositions known through
experience. He classifies metaphysical knowledge as a truth of reason, along with geometry and
mathematics. Correspondingly, Hume divides knowledge into relations of ideas (which can be
13
Epistemology: Contemporary Readings, ed. Michael Huemer, p. 142 citing Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure
Reason
9
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
discovered ‘by the mere operation of thought’ and include geometry and mathematics) and
matters of fact, distinguished by the conceivability of their contradictory. Hume bases his
metaphysical propositions to either class (causal relations are not relation of ideas, since the
contradictory of any causal judgment is always conceivable, and necessity is not given in sense-
experience). Kant aims to challenge the bipartite picture of knowledge and thereby undermine
Kant’s first step was in his formulation of the following puzzle: “If metaphysical
judgments are a priori, how is it possible for them to extend our knowledge, as they are intended
to do?”14 Any extension of our knowledge would seem to require experience (Hume’s view
being that, for that very reason, metaphysics cannot extend our knowledge). With a view to
answering this question, Kant introduces a new distinction between analytic and synthetic
judgments. Leibniz and Hume would expect all necessary and a priori judgments to be analytic,
and all contingent and empirical judgments to be synthetic; their accounts of the sources of
knowledge allow no alternative. Unlike Hume and Leibniz’s distinction, Kant however maintains
that the two distinctions do not correspond. Metaphysical judgments, whilst being a priori, are
not analytic but synthetic. Consider ‘every event has a cause’. Because it is necessary, it must be
a priori. But it is not analytic, for the concept of the predicate is not contained in the concept of
the subject; the concept of an event does not contain that of an effect. This makes the judgment
synthetic. To say that metaphysical judgments are synthetic a priori is to say that they cannot be
derived from either logic (since they are synthetic) or sense experience (since they are a priori).
14
A. C. Grayling ed., Philosophy 2: Further through the subject, (New York: Oxford University Press Inc., 1998)
Sebastian Gardner, p. 580
10
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
Kant argues that mathematical propositions and geometry are synthetic a priori
judgments. Arithmetical judgments such as 7+5=12 cannot be regarded as analytic; the concept
of the sum of 7 and 5 does not contain the concept of the number 12; a synthesis is required to
establish their connection. The same synthetic status is assigned by Kant to geometrical
judgments, such as that a straight line is the shortest distance between two points.
It is on this ground, that Kant admits the possibility of a synthetic a priori judgment in
general and it follows that in order to account for the possibility of mathematics and geometry,
we must reject Leibniz and Hume’s division of knowledge into two fundament types, and install
in its place a tripartite division, the third class consisting of synthetic a priori judgments.
Metaphysics is not, therefore, derivable from logic, as Leibniz supposed; but nor can Hume have
been right to reject it on the basis that it is grounded neither on logic nor on sense-experience. 15
Synthetic a priori judgments are prior to experience, yet they are not tautological. They cannot be
contradicted by experience, they are not derived from experience, yet they give information; we
learn something new from them. Thus they are both a priori and synthetic.16
Kant solved the problem of the synthetic a priori judgment by substituting a new
hypothesis concerning the relation between the mind and its objects. It was clear to him that if
we assume, as Hume did, that the mind, in forming its concepts, must confirm to its objects,
there could be no solution to the problem. Hume’s theory would work for our idea of things a
posteriori. But a synthetic a priori judgment cannot be validated by experience; if I say, for
example, that every straight line is the shortest way between two points, I certainly cannot say
15
A. C. Grayling ed., Philosophy 2: Further through the subject, (New York: Oxford University Press Inc., 1998)
Sebastian Gardner, p. 581-582
16
Joseph Omoregbe, Epistemology: A Systematic And Historic Study, (), p. 33
11
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
that I have had an experience of every possible straight line. If as Hume believed, the mind is
passive and simply receives information only from the objects, it follows that the mind would
have information only about that particular object. But the mind makes judgments about all
objects, even those that it has not yet experienced, and in addition, objects do in fact behave in
the future according to these judgments we make about them. This scientific knowledge gives us
reliable information about the nature of things. But since this knowledge, which is both synthetic
and a priori, could not be explained on the assumption that the mind conforms to its objects (as
in the case of how it could conform to every straight line…every change), Kant was forced to try
a new hypothesis regarding the relation between the mind and its objects.
Kant’s new hypothesis was that it is the objects that confirm to the operations of the
mind, and not the other way around. He came to this hypothesis with a spirit of experimentation,
explaining the movements of the heavenly bodies on the supposition that they all revolved round
the spectator, he tried whether he might not have better success if he made the spectator to
revolve and the stars to remain at rest”. 17 Seeing an analogy here with his own problem, Kant
says,
Hitherto it has been assumed that all our knowledge must conform
therefore, make trial whether we may not have more success in the
12
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
the objects, I do not see how we could know anything of the latter
a priori; but if the object (as object of the senses) must conform to
Kant did not mean to say that the mind creates objects, nor did he mean that the mind
possesses innate ideas. His Copernican revolution consisted rather in his saying that the mind
brings something to the objects it experiences. With Hume, Kant agreed that our knowledge
begins with experience, but unlike Hume, Kant saw the mind as an active agent doing something
with the objects it experiences. The mind, says Kant, is structured in such a way that it imposes
its way of knowing upon its objects. By its very nature, the mind actively organizes our
experiences. That is, thinking involves not only receiving impressions through our senses but
also making judgments about what we experience. Just as a person who wears coloured glasses
sees everything in that colour, so every human being, having the faculty of thought, inevitably
thinks about things in accordance with the natural structure of the mind.
Kant’s transcendental aesthetic contains his doctrine of the human sense perception. The
senses include, for Kant, not only the five outer senses (the eyes for sight, ears for hearing, nose
for smell, skin for touch and tongue for taste) but also the inner sense (imagination, memory,
common sense, and instinct)19. In conscious opposition to the dominant rationalist and empiricist
tenets of his day, Kant agreed that human beings have distinct sensory and intellectual faculties.
But in opposition to Aristotle and the Scholastics he insisted that neither can yield knowledge on
18
Immanuel Kant, Op. cit., p. 22.
19
Kant’s empirical account of human cognition
13
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
its own. For Kant, our senses are insufficient for the perception of particular objects. Perception
only occurs when the information acquired by the senses is recognized as an instance of an
object of a certain kind. This necessarily involves a concept (the concept of a kind of object) as
well as an act of judging that the sensory information falls under the concept. Kant insists that
apart from this characteristically discursive operation, which invokes concepts and hence
involves the intellect, we can still be affected by objects and can still have sensory experiences,
but insofar as we do not categorize these experiences, we know nothing. “Thoughts without
content are empty, intuitions without concepts are blind”.20 Consequently, rather than identify the
senses and the intellect as the capacities to know particulars and universals, Kant identified them
by how they work. His critical theory begins with a fundamental distinction between a lower-
order capacity to receive impressions through the senses, and higher-order capacities of the
intellect and imagination to process this data. Broadly, this is the distinction between the
sensibility and the intellect. The senses are passive. They only supply us with representations
Before making this argument on pure intuition, Kant defines the key technical terms:
intuition, sensibility, sensation, appearance, the distinctions between matter and form of
object is given to us; but this in turn, [at least for us humans] is
20
Jill Vance Buroker, p. 37 citing Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason
21
Graham Bird ed. A Companion to Kant, p. 141.
14
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
Having defined and explained the terms – intuition, sensibility, sensation, appearance,
and the matter and form of intuition in the opening chapter of this long essay, I would proceed
with Kant’s distinction and characteristics of the outer and inner sense.
From his distinction between the matter and form of appearances, Kant argues that while
its form must be a priori. Consequently, there must be intuitions that do not contain anything
belonging to sensation and provide the form of appearances; these are pure intuitions, as opposed
to empirical intuitions. The form of appearances is, Kant tells us, space and time. He classifies
space as an outer sense and time as an inner sense. While the outer sense is our ability to be
affected by objects distinct from us, the inner sense is our capacity to be affected by the states of
ourselves. He claims that we can think of space and time as continuing to exist even were
everything else in the world annihilated, but that nothing else can be represented without being
located somewhere in space, with the exception of my own mental states, which must occur at
some time. From this he inferred that the representation of space and time is necessary for the
22
Immanuel Kant, Op. cit., p. 65.
15
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
representation of other things, but that the representation of other things is not reciprocally
Since the function of the senses is to receive representations, and space and time are
orders in which various elements can be disposed, it follows that our senses must be so
constituted as to receive representations over space and time, and hence that space and time must
be the ‘forms’ of sensory experience. What items are disposed where is of course not something
that can be anticipated (a priori). But that the space they are disposed in has a certain geometry
and the time a certain topology is something that can be known, because to know that is simply
to know how our own senses are constituted, not what things there are in the world outside us.24
Kant holds that space is not an empirical concept that has been drawn from outer
characteristics. We could not in fact acquire any representation of space by means of experience
because any representation of sensations as spatially related already presupposes a capacity for
spatial representation. He also argues that space is a necessary representation, a priori, which
underlies all outer intuitions. It ‘underlies’ all outer intuitions because ‘one can never form a
representation of the absence of space, though one can very well conceive that no objects are to
be found in it’.25 It is therefore the condition for the possibility of appearances. That is, no
objects can be represented except as in space (although Kant accepted that we can think of an
‘empty space’). Since space is required for the very possibility of appearances (of objects), it is a
necessary representation whose spatial and temporary structure doesn’t arise from the intellect.
23
Graham Bird (ed.), A Companion to Kant, p. 144.
24
Graham Bird, ibid., p. 147.
25
Paul Guyer (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Kant and modern philosophy, (New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2006) p.
16
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
hence is not empirical but a priori. The many outer objects and the many parts of space neither
exemplify space nor fall under it, but rather are in it. “Therefore, the original representation of
space is an a priori intuition, not a concept”. 26 He goes on further to say that the representation of
space is an intuition, a singular representation. “Space is not a discursive or, as is said, general
concept of relations of things in general, but a pure intuition”. 27 There’s only one space – “if one
speaks of many spaces, one understands by that only parts of one and the same unique space –
and the concept of space is a basic one”. 28 It is not a representation of a definite description that
is mediated by the concept of a kind or sort of thing. Hence, it’s not ‘discursive’ in the sense of
having the kind of internal conceptual complexity that could make it possible for propositions of
In essence, Kant’s account of time exactly parallels his account of space. In his
conceptual analysis of the concept of time, he argues, first, that the representation of time holds
universally and necessarily of experience, and so is not derived from experience but rather given
a priori, and, second, that it is not a discursive or general concept but rather an intuition, a
singular representation. Like space, time is a necessary unitary intuition and has only one
dimension, and that different times are not simultaneous but successive. This last principle, Kant
predicates in one and the same object, for instance, the being and
26
Immanuel Kant, Op. cit., p. 70.
27
Immanuel Kant, Op. cit., p. 69.
28
Ibid., p. 66.
17
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
the not-being of one and the same thing in one and the same place.
and the same object, namely, one after the other. Thus our concept
Kant concludes, then, that, just as in the case of space, time is neither a (Newtonian)
container nor a (Leibnizian) collection of empirical relationships among events, but the form of
inner sense. In his very words, “Time is nothing other than the form of inner sense, that is, of the
intuition of our self and inner state”. Since our ‘inner state’ includes all our representations of
‘outer things’, however, time turns out to be an a priori condition of all appearance in general,
‘the immediate condition of inner intuition and thereby also the mediate condition of outer
appearances’.30
Kant argues for the transcendental ideality and empirical reality of space and time. From
the fact that space and time are pure intuitions, Kant concludes that they are merely forms of the
subject’s intuition. This is the basis of the transcendental ideality and empirical reality of space
and time.
In the concluding sections of the Transcendental Aesthetic, Kant claims that space and
time do not represent properties or relations of things in themselves; that they do not provide
29
Immanuel Kant, Op. cit., p. 76.
30
Immanuel Kant, Op. cit., p. 77.
18
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
information about properties or relations of things in themselves. From here, he argues that space
and time must be subjective conditions of sensibility, or the forms of outer and inner sense.
From the above conclusions, Kant develops his theory; that space and time are
transcendentally ideal means that they are nothing more than conditions of human sensibility. In
objects of sensibility.31
He makes similar remarks about time. But if space and time are only subjective
representations, then all spatiotemporal appearances are likewise subjective in the same sense.
are not in themselves what we intuit them to be, nor are their
31
Jill Vance Buroker, Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason: An Introduction, p. 51 citing Immanuel Kant, Critique of
Pure Reason
19
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
The transcendental ideality of space and time means that were there no perceivers with
these forms of intuition, space and time would not exist; neither, consequently, would the
spatiotemporal properties of things. It follows that things in themselves, whatever they are, are
non-spatial and non-temporal. Here Kant clearly rejects the theory of absolute space and time,
according to which (in Kant’s terms) space and time are transcendentally real, since they exist
independently of perceivers.
Despite their ideality, however, Kant also maintains that space and time are empirically
real. By this he means that they are not illusory, that the objects that appear to us really are given
in space and time. Since Kant as argued that space and time are necessary features of
appearances, it follows that all objects of intuition are temporal, and all outer objects are spatial.
He also describes space and time as objectively valid, as in his conclusions on time, ”Our
assertions accordingly teach the empirical reality of time, i.e., objective validity in regard to all
objects that may ever be given to our senses. And since our intuition is always sensible, no object
can ever be given to us in experience that would not belong under the condition of time”. Here
there is a connection between objectively validity and truth values; that space and time are
objective valid implies that we can make true or false judgments about them as well as about
spatiotemporal objects. In connecting empirical reality with objective validity, Kant relativizes
the notions of an object and objective truth. Empirical realism entails that what counts as an
object for us, and therefore what counts as objective truth for us, is relative to our cognitive
capacities. The Aesthetic establishes those conditions from the side of human sensibility while in
32
Ibid., , p. 51 citing Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason
20
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
the Transcendental Analytic Kant examines the contribution of the understanding to the objective
conditions of cognition.33
In the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason, Immanuel Kant breaks a
new ground, arguing that the most fundamental categories of thought as well as the forms of
perception are themselves human products which are necessary conditions of the possibility of
experience. All our cognitive achievements, and so, in particular, our experiences of the natural
world, arise from the conjoint exercise of two complementary faculties, “the reception of
are “given”, and the “faculty for cognizing an object by means of these representations
33
Jill Vance Buroker, p. 60
34
Immanuel Kant, Op. cit., p. 105.
21
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
Kant here makes clear his disagreements with both Descartes and Hume. Contrary to
Descartes’ views, Kant concludes that reason alone cannot yield any sort of knowledge of the
natural world, that is, the world that we encounter in experience. Without sensory intuitions to
give our concepts empirical content, our thoughts could not be about the world. They would be
“empty”. But experience is also, as Hume thought, simply a matter of passively receiving
experience: On the sensory content of our intuitions, we impose a spatio-temporal form, and to
the cognitions of objects and events in the world evoked by those sensory impressions, we
Just as he earlier undertook to identify the contributions to our experience which flow
from our capacity for sensible intuition, Kant now proposes to identify the contributions to our
experience which flow from our capacity for conceptual thought. His point of departure for this
project is a radically new theory of concepts, which, in turn, rests on two fundamental insights:
That concepts are the principle of unity and that all consciousness that something is the case is
‘judgmental’ consciousness (has propositional form). The distinctive activity of the mind is to
synthesize and to unify our experience. It achieves this synthesis by imposing on our various
experiences in the ‘sensible manifold’ certain forms of intuition; space and time. ‘Synthesis’,
here, consists in the ‘action of putting different representations together with each other and
comprehending their manifoldness in one cognition’. Kant calls the principle of unity of the
35
Jay F. Rosenberg p. 92.
22
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
Kant’s categories are simply the forms of judgment, specialized to cognitions of sensibly
intuited objects. More precisely, given the forms that judgments can take, the categories
(collectively) functionally specify the sorts of concepts of sensibly intuited items that are suitable
to serve as the judgments about objects in space and time. According to Kant, the faculty of
thinking or understanding is also the faculty of judgment. Since to think is the same as to judge,
if can discover the functions of judgment we shall have thereby discovered the functions of
understanding, and if we can find out the different kinds of judgment we will be able to discover
the categories of understanding.36 Kant goes on to classify the forms of judgment into four
Table 1.1
totality, quality, reality, negation, limitation, relation, inherence and subsistence, causality and
necessity and contingency.37 The Table of Categories thus reflects operations of the
Table 1.2
23
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
The categories reveal the structure of the understanding since they are the a priori
principles according to which human understanding or the faculty of thinking operates. They are
the a priori concepts by means of which we think or understand anything. They are the principles
or rules of thinking and understanding. In other words, it is only through these categories that
any object can be thought about, or conceived and known. This means that it is only through the
categories that knowledge can be acquired or that any object can be known.38
In the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant concludes his chapter on the
discovery of all the pure concepts of the understanding with a few structural observations
regarding the Table of Categories at which he has arrived. He observes that the three entries
under the main headings in the Table of Categories in each case themselves stand in an
interesting relationship, namely, that ‘the third category always arises from the combination of
the first two in its class’.39 Thus he suggests that when we regard a ‘plurality’ as a ‘unity’, we
treat it, so to speak, under the aspect of ‘totality’ (i.e., in its totality). When ‘reality’ is combined
with ‘negation’, what results is ‘limitation’ – the limits or boundaries of something real are
marked by its absence, i.e., where it’s not. ‘Community’ is the reciprocal causal determination of
substances by each other. And finally, ‘necessity’ is nothing but existence that is given by
possibility itself. Kant insists, however, that these relationships do not make the third concept
merely derivative, since the combination of the first and second in order to bring forth the third
concept requires a special act of the understanding (in Kantian terms, understanding is
The most significant of these is that the four groups of categories divide into classes. The
24
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
The latter subsumes the categories of Relation and Modality and is referred to as ‘dynamical’.
The four sets of corresponding principles are labeled axioms of intuition, anticipations of
The axioms of intuition deal with how mathematics is applied to the world. Based on the
principle of axioms of intuition, that “all intuitions are extended magnitudes”, Kant argues that
our inquiries about sizes or areas are always appropriate when we are dealing with things that
occupy space since every such thing can be regarded as an aggregate of parts produced by the
Under the anticipations of perception, Kant is concerned with the question of the
applicability of mathematics to sensations. What guarantee have we, he asks, that every sensation
will turn out to have a determinate degree, in principle quantifiable? Might we not find, for
instance, that an object is colored but with no precise depth of saturation, or a smell present in a
room but with no specific magnitude? Kant attempts to rule out such possibilities by attention to
the formal properties of sensations. We cannot anticipate the matter of sensation, but we can say
in advance of experience that every sensation will have intensive magnitude, that is, a
determinate degree, because it is possible to think of any given sensation as fading away until it
is imperceptible, and conversely as being built up by continuous transitions on a scale from zero
In the analogies of experience, Kant deals with the permanence of substance and
causation. The principle of permanence of substance is that, “in all change of appearances
substance is permanent; its quantum in nature is neither increased nor diminished”. To believe in
the permanence of substance is to believe that, whatever happens, nothing goes completely out of
existence and nothing totally new is created: All change is transformation. Kant justifies the
25
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
acceptance of this presupposition (which in his view, it should be remembered, applies only to
things phenomenal) by arguing that without it we could not have a unitary temporal system. Kant
argues that if things could go completely out of existence, so that it would make no sense to ask
what became of them, the establishment of connections between one part of experience and
another would be impossible. Experience would be (or at least might be) full of unbridgeable
gaps, with the result that no one set of happenings could be integrated with another, and the unity
of time would be totally destroyed. Like David Hume, causality for Kant is a relation between
successive events; a cause is an event that regularly precedes its effect. But whereas Hume is
content to treat the occurrence of regular sequences as an ultimate and entirely contingent fact,
Kant believes that without the presumption of sequences that are regular (determined by a rule)
there could be no knowledge of objective succession. His reason is that we have to distinguish
successions that happen only in ourselves, successions merely in our apprehension, from those
that occur in the objective world and are independent of us. We can do this only if an objective
sequence is defined as a sequence happening according to a rule. The objective world is a world
of events in which each occurrence determines the precise place in time of some other event. But
though events are necessarily connected in this way, we must not conclude that causal
connections can be established a priori; for Kant as for Hume causal propositions are one and all
synthetic and empirical. All we can know a priori is that there are such connections to be found,
Under the postulates of empirical thought, Kant explains of the notions of possibility,
actuality, and necessity from the critical point of view. By “really possible” Kant means “that
which agrees with the formal conditions of experience, that is, with the conditions of intuition
41
Robert Audi (ed.) et. al., The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, (Cambridge University Press, 1999 ), pp. 464-
465
26
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
and of concepts”. A two-sided figure enclosing a space is not really possible, though its concept
is not self-contradictory, because such a figure does not accord with the formal conditions of
intuition. Telepathy and precognition are not real possibilities; they “cannot be based on
experience and its known laws”, presumably because their actuality would violate some principle
of the understanding. The notion of real possibility is for Kant intermediate between logical and
empirical possibility. We need it and can use it only because the world we have to deal with is a
world that is not independently existent, but has its being in essential relation to consciousness.42
From here Kant goes to show that our conceptual intuiting necessarily embody the
categories. That is, recalling that the categories are meta-conceptual classifications; that the
concepts under which we intuit spatio-temporal items belong to the classes of concepts
functionally picked out by the categories. He argued that our sensory intuitions necessarily fit (or
answer to) the categories. That all the items which we intuit as in space and time in fact fall
under concepts belonging to the classes picked out by the categories. Thus, the categories can
In the first part of the “Analytic” Kant has much to say not only about concepts,
judgments, and the understanding but also about the imagination. For example, he remarks in a
cryptic passage:
27
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
properly so called.43
The contrasting and, in places, overlapping roles of understanding and imagination are
among the most puzzling features of Kant’s exposition. The reason why they are both introduced
is related to the fact that, in the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason in particular, Kant
was concerned with two quite distinct questions. He first asked himself what conditions have to
be fulfilled if any sort of discursive consciousness is to have objective knowledge; he then went
on to put the question as it relates to the human discursive consciousness, which not only intuits
data passively, but does so under the particular forms of space and time. When the first question
is uppermost Kant tends to speak of the understanding; when the second is to the fore, he brings
in the imagination as well. The passage quoted above, typical of many, suggests that it is the
business of the imagination to connect, whereas that of the understanding is to make explicit the
principles on which the connecting proceeds. But in one chapter, “Schematism of the Pure
2.6.3 Schemata
The problem of the chapter on what Kant called “schematism” is the central problem of
the analytic: How can concepts that do not originate in experience find application in
experience? At first Kant speaks as if there were no comparable difficulty in the case of concepts
originating in experience, although he later makes clear that there are schemata corresponding
both to empirical and to mathematical concepts. To possess the concept triangle is to know its
formal definition, to be able to frame intelligible sentences containing the word triangle, and so
43
Immanuel Kant, Op. Cit., p. 112.
28
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
on; to possess the schema corresponding to the concept triangle is to be able to envisage the
variety of things to which the word triangle applies. Thus for Kant a schema is not an image, but
a capacity to form images or (perhaps) to construct models. Pure concepts of the understanding
are such that they “can never be brought into any image whatsoever”; the thought they embody,
springing from the pure intellect, cannot be pictured or imagined. Yet there must be some
connection between the abstract idea and the experienced world to which that idea is expected to
apply; it must be possible to specify the empirical circumstances in which pure concepts of the
understanding can find application. Kant thinks that for the categories this requirement is met by
the fact that we can find for each of them a “transcendental schema,” which is, he explains, a
“sense and significance,” except in a logical (verbal) way. With it, use of the categories is clearly
restricted to the range of things that fall within time - meaning, for Kant, restricted to
phenomena. The meaning of this baffling doctrine can perhaps best be grasped through Kant’s
It emerges from these cryptic sentences that the transcendental schema is something like
an empirical counterpart of the pure category. It is what the latter means when translated into
44
Immanuel Kant, Op. Cit., p. 184.
29
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
phenomenal terms. In Kant’s own words, the schema is “properly, only the phenomenon, or
sensible concept, of an object in agreement with the category” 45. A category without its
Insofar as he argues that schematization is the work of the imagination, Kant has found a genuine
This distinction is found in the “Transcendental Aesthetic” to explain our having a priori
knowledge of the properties of space and time, and is invoked again in the “Transcendental
Analytic” to account for “pure physics”. A major impact of Kant’s critical philosophy was his
insistence that human knowledge is forever limited in its scope. This limitation takes two forms.
First, knowledge is limited to the world of experience, and second, our knowledge is limited by
the manner in which our faculties of perception and thinking organize the raw data of experience.
Kant did not doubt that the world as it appears to us is not the ultimate reality. He
distinguished between the world as it appears to us or the world as we experience it and the
world as it is in itself, which is purely intelligible, or nonsensual; the ‘phenomena’ and the
‘noumena’. He argues that our knowledge is limited to the phenomenal reality – things that could
be the subject of experience. For only things that are experienced are subject to the categorizing
and unifying activity of the mind. To be experienced, objects must be in space and time, be
related to one another by cause and effect, and otherwise be subject to the principles of
cognition; but we cannot apply these categories and principles to things “as they are in
themselves” – noumena, or things that exist outside experience. 46 Concerning this noumenal
45
Immanuel Kant, Op. Cit., p. 186.
46
Brooke N. Moore and Kenneth Bruder, Philosophy: The Power of Ideas, (New York: The McGraw Hill
Companies, Inc., 2005), p. 142
30
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
world, skepticism is unavoidable, for Kant. When rules that apply to the world of experience are
applied to a reality beyond experience, contradictions and mistakes result. Kant argued that there
are three regulative ideas that we tend to think about; ideas that lead us beyond sense experiences
but about which we cannot be indifferent because of our inevitable tendency to try to unify all
our experience. These ideas are of the self, the cosmos and of God. They are transcendental and
are not produced by intuition but by pure reason alone. They at least, point to possibilities in the
Kant’s use of these regulative ideas exemplifies his way of mediating between dogmatic
rationalism and skeptical empiricism. With the empiricists, he agrees that we can have no
knowledge of reality beyond experience. These transcendental ideas cannot give us any
theoretical knowledge of realities corresponding to these ideas. As solely regulative ideas, they
give us a reasonable way of dealing with the constantly recurring questions raised by
metaphysics. To this extent, Kant acknowledged the validity of the subject matter of rationalism.
His critical analysis of the scope of human reason, however, led him to discover earlier
rationalists had made the error of treating transcendental ideas as though they were ideas about
actual beings.47
The Transcendental Analytic shows that there cannot be a world of mere appearances,
mere objects of sense that do not fall under any categories or instantiate any rules. But we cannot
conclude from this that there is a non-sensible world that is established by the intellect alone. To
accept the existence of extra-sensible objects that can be studied by the use of pure reason is to
enter a realm of illusion, and in his ‘transcendental dialectic’ Kant explores this world of
enchantment.
47
Samuel Stumpf and James Fiesser, Op. Cit., pp. 310-311.
31
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
analytic - as if its sole purpose were to expose the illusions generated when dogmatic
philosophers, unaware of the sensuous conditions under which alone we can make successful use
of a priori concepts, attempt to apply them outside the sphere of possible experience. In fact a
large part of the section titled “Dialectic” is devoted to the exposure of metaphysical sophistries.
But insofar as Kant recognizes in this part of his work the existence of a further set of intellectual
operations involved in scientific inquiry, he seeks to show that the faculty of theoretical reason as
At the end of the section of the Critique of Pure Reason devoted to the transcendental
analytic, there is a passage that can be taken as summarizing the second stage in Kant’s
within which alone objects can be given to us. Its principles are
32
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
Kant thus repudiates the possibility of knowledge through pure concepts of things as they
really are. Having disposed of ontology, Kant needed to consider, to complete the negative side
of his work, the tenability of the remaining parts of metaphysics (rational psychology, rational
speculative metaphysics as simply an illusion, and its claim to be able to provide man with
2.7.2 Reason
Most of the conclusions of the “Dialectic” follow directly from those of the “Analytic,”
though there are new points of interest. As in the “Analytic,” Kant’s views are expressed inside a
framework that is heavily scholastic. Kant claimed that human beings have an intellectual faculty
in addition to the understanding. This additional faculty is reason, and it is equipped with a set of
a priori concepts of its own, technically known as ideas of reason. An idea of reason can have no
object corresponding to it in sense experience, for the ambition of reason is to arrive at absolute
totality in the series of conditions for the empirically given, and in this way to grasp the
unconditioned that falls outside experience altogether. However, this ambition can never be
realized, and the only proper function for reason in its theoretical capacity is to regulate the
operations of the understanding by encouraging it to pursue the search for conditions to the
maximum extent that is empirically possible. All human knowledge, he says, begins with the
33
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
employed in applying the a priori concepts (the categories) of human understanding beyond the
sphere of phenomena. Any such application is illegitimate and illusory, and the result can be
Kant’s handling of the “psychological idea” at the beginning of the main part of the
“Dialectic” is exceptionally brilliant. He maintains in the “Analytic” that what he there calls the
“I think,” or the unity of apperception, is the ultimate condition of experience, in the sense of
being the logical subject of experience or the point to which all experience relates. All
experience is experience for a subject; whatever thoughts or feelings I have I must be capable of
recognizing as my thoughts or feelings. But the subject here referred to is not something
substantial; it is merely a logical requirement, in that nothing follows about the nature of my soul
or self from the fact that I say “I think.” So far from being “an abiding and continuing intuition”
(the sort of thing Hume vainly sought in the flow of his inner consciousness), for Kant the
“representation ‘I’… [is] simple, and in itself completely empty … we cannot even say that this
is a concept, but only that it is a bare consciousness which accompanies all concepts. Through
this I or he or it (the thing) which thinks, nothing further is represented than a transcendental
49
Immanuel Kant, Op. Cit., p. 300.
34
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
subject of thoughts ”.50 The same view is expressed in an earlier passage in the Critique, where
Kant says that “in the synthetic original unity of apperception, I am conscious of myself, not as I
appear to myself, nor as I am in myself, but [I am conscious] only that I am. This representation
These subtleties are unknown to the exponents of rational psychology, who develop the
whole of their teaching around a “single text,” which is “I think.” From the fact that I am the
subject of all my thoughts they infer that I am a thinking substance; from the fact that the “I” of
apperception is logically simple they conclude that I am, in substance, simple and not composite.
The proposition that “in all the manifold of which I am conscious I am identical with myself” is
distinguishing my own existence as a thinking being from that of other things, including my own
body, is put forward as proof that I am really distinct from such things and so could in principle
exist in complete independence of them (as simple, immaterial, permanent substance, the subject
of the act of thinking). None of these inferences is justified, for in each case a move is attempted
transcendental ego which is in the noumenal world, beyond sense perception. We can know
nothing about it except as the unity of consciousness and the subject of thinking. It is simply an
idea, a conception and since we can never know it, any science that claims to be able to provide
man with knowledge about it is a pseudo science, an illusion. Hence speculative psychology is
50
Donald M. Borchert, Op. Cit., p. 22, citing Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason
51
Ibid., p. 22, citing Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason
35
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
Speculative cosmology claims to be able to provide man with objective knowledge about
the world taken as the totality of phenomena. But this involves the invalid and illegitimate
application of the categories of human understanding beyond the sphere of phenomena, and the
inability of the mind ever to do so successfully is indicated by what Kant calls the ‘antimonies’
into which we fall. Kant examines four of such antimonies, each consisting of a thesis and an
antithesis.
The first antimony is that the world is limited in time and space, or that it is unlimited.
The second antimony is that every composite substance in the world is made up of simple parts,
or that no composite thing in the world is made up of simple parts since there nowhere exists in
the world anything simple. The third antimony is that besides causality in accordance with the
laws of nature there is also another causality, that of freedom, or that there is no freedom since
everything in the world takes place solely in accordance with the laws of nature. The fourth
antimony is that there exists an absolutely necessary being as a part of the world or as its cause,
the two doctrines in each pair contradict one another directly, and have been vigorously defended
with valid arguments by philosophers before Kant. Kant produces for each pair what he regards
as watertight proofs of both sides of the case, maintaining that if we adopt the dogmatic
standpoint assumed without question by the parties to the dispute, we can prove, for example,
both that the world has a beginning in time and that it has no beginning in time, both that
“causality in accordance with laws of nature is not the only causality” and that “everything in the
52
Samuel Stumpf and James Fiesser, Op. Cit., pp. 311-312.
36
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
world takes place solely in accordance with laws of nature.” Thus Kant exhibits in systematic
form the famous contradictions into which, as he notes, reason precipitates itself when it asks
for the fact that they provide an additional argument for the saying that the world of space and
time is phenomenal only and that such in a world freedom is a coherent idea.
. The only way to avoid these antinomies, in Kant’s opinion, is to adopt his own (critical)
point of view and recognize that the world that is the object of our knowledge is a world of
appearances, existing only insofar as it is constructed; this solution enables us to dismiss both
parties to the dispute in the case of the first two antinomies, and to accept the contentions of both
parties in the case of the other two. If the world exists only insofar as it is constructed, it is
neither finite nor infinite but indefinitely extensible and so neither has nor lacks a limit in space
and time. Equally, if the world is phenomenal we have at least the idea of a world that is not
phenomenal; and natural causality can apply without restriction to the first without precluding
the application of a different type of causality to the second. This is admittedly only an empty
hypothesis so far as theoretical reason is concerned, but Kant argues that it can be converted into
something more satisfactory if we take account of the activities of practical (moral) reason.53
Kant criticizes all the traditional arguments for the existence of God used by past
philosophers as invalid. There are, Kant argues, only three ways of proving God’s existence on
the speculative plane. First, we can proceed entirely a priori and maintain that the very idea of
God is such that God could not not exist - since God is the absolutely perfect and necessary
53
Edward Craig (ed.), The Shorter Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (New York: Taylor and Francis Group,
2005), p. 499.
37
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
being, and existence is a perfection, to deny his existence would be self contradictory: This is
the method of the Ontological Argument. Second, we can move from the bare fact that the world
and all it contains exists to the position that God is its ultimate cause, as in the First Cause – the
Cosmological Argument. Finally, we can base our contention on the particular constitution of the
world, especially as it manifests order, harmony, wisdom and purposefulness as the product of an
intelligent being who is responsible for it - the “physico - theological proof” (the Argument
from Design).
Kant argues that all three types of proof are fallacious. The Ontological Argument fails
because it treats existence as if it were a “real predicate,” whereas “it is not a concept of
something which could be added to the concept of a thing. It is merely the positing of a thing, or
predicate. The Cosmological Argument fails on several counts: because it uses the category of
cause without realizing that only in the schematized form is the category significant; because it
assumes that the only way to avoid an actually infinite causal series in the world is to posit a first
cause; finally and most important, because it presupposes the validity of the Ontological Proof,
in the step which identifies the “necessary being” or First Cause with God. The Argument from
Design makes all these mistakes and some of its own, for even on its own terms it proves only
the existence of an architect of the universe, not of a creator, and such an architect would possess
In spite of Kant’s criticisms of the classical arguments for God’s existence, he is neither
an atheist nor an agnostic. He both believes in God and holds that the belief can be rationally
justified. Although speculative theology is, broadly, a tissue of errors, moral theology is perfectly
possible. But the moral proof of God’s existence differs from the attempted speculative proofs in
54
Donald M. Borchert, Op. Cit., p. 23.
38
Chapter Two: Immanuel Kant’s Theory of Knowledge
at least two significant respects. First, it begins neither from a concept nor from a fact about the
world, but from an immediately experienced moral situation. The moral agent feels called upon
to achieve certain results, in particular to bring about a state of affairs in which happiness is
proportioned to virtue, and knows that he cannot do it by his own unaided efforts; insofar as he
commits himself to action he shows his belief in a moral author of the universe. Affirmation of
God’s existence is intimately linked with practice; it is most definitely not the result of mere
speculation. Again, a proof like the cosmological argument claims universal validity; standing as
it does on purely intellectual grounds it ought, if cogent, to persuade saint and sinner alike. But
the moral proof as Kant states it would not even have meaning to a man who is unconscious of
moral obligations; the very word God, removed from the moral context that gives it life, is
almost or quite without significance. Accordingly Kant states that the result of this proof is not
objective knowledge but a species of personal conviction, embodying not logical but moral
certainty. He adds that “I must not even say ‘It is morally certain that there is a God …,’ but ‘I
am morally certain’” (B 857). In other words, the belief or faith Kant proposes as a replacement
for discredited metaphysical knowledge can be neither strictly communicated nor learned from
another. It is something that has to be achieved by every man for himself. His purpose was to
deny the possibility of rational knowledge – about God, about the way things are in themselves
39