Darren Ambrose - Deleuze & Bacon: Triptychs, Eternity and The Spirituality of The Body
Darren Ambrose - Deleuze & Bacon: Triptychs, Eternity and The Spirituality of The Body
Darren Ambrose - Deleuze & Bacon: Triptychs, Eternity and The Spirituality of The Body
the Body
Abstract
This paper develops a detailed reading of Deleuze’s philosophical study
of Bacon’s triptychs in Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation. It
examines his claims regarding their apparent non-narrative status, and
explores the capacity of the triptychs to embody and express a spiritual
sensation of the eternity of time.
Keywords: Gilles Deleuze, Francis Bacon, triptychs, eternity, spiritual
realism, rhythm
One of Deleuze’s ambitions in Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation is
to outline an experimental conceptual analogue of Bacon’s paintings that
demonstrates a genuine fidelity to the specificity of his work. His book
produces a philosophy of painting where Bacon is conceived as one of
the great painters of immanence, a painter of the body without organs.
His figural paintings are understood to repeatedly explore the vital
intensities and sensations associated with the dynamisms of becoming,
processes of individuation and the destratification of the organism,
subject and individual. Deleuze suggests that a brutal form of realism
is manifested by Bacon’s art, but it is not a realism associated with
the violence of appearance but a violence of sensation associated with
a spiritual realism of the body. Bacon’s paintings depict, he claims,
a visceral topography of embodied sensation that is profoundly non-
representational and spiritual.
One of the most complex and creative sections of the book is his
philosophical analysis of the triptychs. In just a few dense pages he
arguably provides one of the most powerful accounts yet written about
triptychs in relation to the questions of what they are, how they function,
and what operative principles govern their production. In this paper
I wish to develop a reading of Deleuze’s philosophical understanding
of the triptychs that incorporates his arguments regarding their
260 D. C. Ambrose
rather than stories, are distributed across the separated panels. Each
triptych operates like an infernal machine producing novel circulations
and rhythmic interplays of these characters, forces and sensations.
Somewhat enigmatically, Deleuze identifies a mysterious, unifying force,
which is captured by the arrangement of the triptychs but which is also,
simultaneously, the force operating to structure and unite the triptychs.
This force acts to separate figures, both within and across the panels, and
the panels themselves. Deleuze suggests that this unifying and separating
force is the force of eternal time.
Before progressing with an analysis of Deleuze’s complex reading
of the triptychs, I think it is necessary to question the legitimacy of
his emphasis on the non-narrative status of Bacon’s triptychs. One
might take the view that Bacon’s insistence, when in conversation with
Sylvester, on there being no explicit straightforward narrative is in
fact mendacious, that it is part of his effort to control and conceal
inconvenient biographical truths and sources in favour of constructing
an elaborate mythological artistic persona. Whilst this is probably
the case, it remains possible that his broader non-narrative ambitions
indicate a more significant philosophical and artistic ambition that is
indeed worth taking seriously. For Deleuze, Bacon’s work instantiates
a profoundly anti-narrative spiritual dynamic of matter. Nevertheless,
by focusing on the non-narrative element I do not believe that Deleuze
is altogether denying residues of narrative content that might be clearly
present and form an important factor in fully understanding a specific
composition. Bacon’s deeply personal obsessions, experiences and
inspirations form and shape the voluntaristic intentions that guide his
hand at a primary pre-pictorial level and at the ‘first level’ of figuration
on the canvas.3 Deleuze is not necessarily denying the existence of this
type of intentionality, rather he is bracketing it off, suspending explicit
consideration of it, in order to concentrate upon the ‘involuntaristic’
aspect of Bacon’s practice or the ‘second order’ of figuration. It is here,
within what he calls ‘the diagram’, that Bacon’s particular range of visual
motifs are injected into a metamorphic, transformative and liberating
realm (or experimental amphitheatre) of paint on the canvas.
A significant clue to understanding Deleuze’s attitude towards specific
narrative residue emerges from his treatment of religious painters whose
figurative innovations are linked to Bacon’s own. When discussing the
structural and historical underpinnings of Bacon’s practice, Deleuze
discusses one of Bacon’s operative propositions (a proposition derived
from André Malraux) that is almost a truism within modern art, and
would seemingly necessitate a move within painting towards a form
262 D. C. Ambrose
But why is it an act of vital faith to choose ‘the scream more than the
horror’, the violence of sensation more than the violence of the spectacle?
The invisible forces, the powers of the future – are they not already upon
us, and much more insurmountable than the worst spectacle and even the
worst pain? Yes, in a certain sense – every piece of meat testifies to this. But
in another sense, no. When, like a wrestler, the visible body confronts the
powers of the invisible, it gives them no other visibility than its own. It is
within this visibility that the body actively struggles, affirming the possibility
of triumphing, which was beyond its reach as long as these powers remained
invisible, hidden in a spectacle that sapped our strength and diverted us. It is
as if combat had now become possible. The struggle with the shadow is the
only real struggle. When the visual sensation confronts the invisible force that
conditions it, it releases a force that is capable of vanquishing the invisible
266 D. C. Ambrose
force, or even befriending it. Life screams at death, but death is no longer
this all-too-visible thing that makes us faint; it is this invisible force that life
detects, flushes out, and makes visible through the scream. Death is judged
from the point of view, and not the reverse, as we like to believe. Bacon, no
less than Beckett, is one of those artists who, in the name of a very intense
life, can call for an even more intense life. He is not a painter who ‘believes’
in death. His is indeed a figurative misérabilisme, but one that serves an
increasingly powerful Figure of life. . . In the very act of ‘representing’ horror,
mutilation, prosthesis, fall, or failure, they have erected indomitable Figures,
indomitable through both their insistence and their presence. They have given
life a new and extremely direct power of laughter. (Deleuze 2003: 61–2)
with Sylvester from 1979, Bacon said: ‘I don’t really think my pictures
out, you know; I think of the disposition of the forms and then I watch
the forms form themselves’ (Sylvester 1987: 136). This auto-formation
of forms explains the type of emergence of the attendant rhythmic
character in triptychs that Deleuze indicates. Attendant function might
subsequently emerge from figures in full context which, if isolated
from the entire composition, might actually appear to have either
active or passive rhythms. For Deleuze this is why some of the prone
sleeping characters in the triptychs have an odd trace of activity or
passivity – so although explicitly situated across the horizontal they
retain a certain heaviness or vivacity, relaxation or contraction, that
comes from elsewhere. Equally, attendants can be seen as assuming other
functions – as on the brink of turning to an active rhythm or passive
rhythm – thus linking themselves to one or the other and ceasing to be
an attendant.8 This fluid autonomy creates not only great tension and
instability but is also indicative of an extraordinary mobility within
triptychs, what Deleuze terms their ‘great circulation’. It is as if the
triptychs function like musical machines possessing a range of different
rhythmic permutations.
Having introduced the attendant rhythmic character, Deleuze
proceeds with an explanation of the two vertical directions of active and
passive rhythms. The simplest variation consists of descending or rising
opposition (for example, Triptych – Three Studies for a Crucifixion,
1962) or perhaps a diastolic/systolic opposition. Occasionally the
opposition at play is between being naked or clothed, or an
augmentation/diminution of the flesh. Throughout different triptychs
there exists an extraordinarily subtle and diverse process of additions
and subtractions. The example which Deleuze talks about in most
detail is Bacon’s Triptych – August, 1972 depicting George Dyer, which
he claims is Bacon’s most ‘profoundly musical painting’. Across this
triptych Bacon uses figural mutilation and prostheses in ‘a game of
added and subtracted values’ (Deleuze 2003: 79). The triptych is like an
assemblage of hysterical sleepings and wakings affecting diverse parts of
the body. Here, the attendant couple in the centre panel are accompanied
by organic elongations and a clear and well defined mauve oval. On
the left panel the figure has a diminished torso, having had a significant
portion of its body subtracted; while on the right the figure is in the
process of being built up or added to. However, everything changes
if one looks at the legs. In the left panel one leg is completed while
the other is being subject to further addition and definition, while in
the right panel, it is just the opposite – one leg has been amputated
Triptychs, Eternity and the Spirituality of the Body 269
Having set out these formal laws, Deleuze concludes by claiming that
they broadly embody a profoundly irrational logic, a logic of sensation,
that constitutes the art of painting in general. By stressing the power
and vitality of this non-normative logic and non-voluntaristic means
of composition, Deleuze instinctively aligns his own account again and
again with Bacon. In 1979 Bacon told Sylvester:
One of the things I’ve always tried to analyse is why it is that, if the formation
of the image that you want is done irrationally, it seems to come on to the
nervous system much more strongly than if you knew how you could do it.
Why is it possible to make the reality of an appearance more violently in
this way than by doing it rationally? Perhaps it’s that, if the making is more
instinctive, the image is more immediate. (Sylvester 1987: 121)
the images simpler and more complicated. And for this to work it can
work more starkly if the background is very united and clear. I think
that probably is why I have used a very clear background against which
the image can articulate itself’ (Sylvester 1987: 121).
Deleuze observes that if this unity and clarity of light or colour
immediately incorporates and unifies the relationship between Figures
and the Field, the result is that Figures also attain their maximum
separation in light and colour. A force of separation or division
sweeps over them, placing them within an almost spiritual milieu of
eternity. This separation is therefore the unique principle of the triptychs
(their pictorial fact) – maximum unity of light and colour for the
maximum division of Figures. It is the force of this separating light and
colour that engenders the distinct yet interrelated, rhythmic characters.
The separation of bodies in universal light and colour becomes the
common fact of the Figures – their overall rhythmic being – a disjunctive
synthesis – a union that separates. A joining-together acts to separate the
Figures and colours. Such, Deleuze claims, is the quality of light. Figures
separate while falling into black light; colour fields separate while
falling into white light. In the triptychs everything becomes aerial – the
separation itself is in the air. Here time is no longer simply expressed in
the apparent chromatism of bodies via the broken tones across flesh – it
has become a monochromatic eternity. In the triptychs an immense
space-time unites all things as if in a fourth temporal dimension. Deleuze
writes of how triptychs, evacuated of any straightforward narrative
linkage, unite things only by introducing between them
Notes
1. It is the ‘revelation’ of the ‘spirit’ immanent to the body which Deleuze suggests
as the entire ‘spiritual’ thematic of Bacon’s work. This point is clarified in
the chapter on ‘Hysteria’ where Deleuze links the spiritualism of Wilhelm
Worringer’s Gothic Line to Artaud’s Body-Without-Organs: ‘It [the Gothic Line]
attests to a high spirituality, since what leads it to seek the elementary forces
beyond the organic is a spiritual will. But this spirituality is a spirituality of the
body; the spirit is the body itself, the body without organs’ (Deleuze 2003: 46–7).
2. This text first appeared in Artforum in January 1984, and is republished (with
minor emendations) as a preface to the English translation of The Logic of
Sensation.
3. See Deleuze’s remarks in The Logic of Sensation (Deleuze 2003: 97–8) regarding
first and second order figuration in Bacon’s work.
4. This would seem to call for a rigorous study of Hegel’s remarks on the history and
development of Christian painting in the second volume of his Aesthetics. When
writing of how certain painters had depicted Christ’s suffering on the cross, he
notes how ‘some masters discovered an entirely peculiar tone of colour which
is not found in the human face. They had to disclose the night of the spirit,
and for this purpose fashioned a type of colour which corresponds in the most
splendid way to this storm, to these black clouds of the spirit that at the same
time are firmly controlled and kept in place by the brazen brow of the divine
nature’ (Hegel 1975: 824). Hegel writes at length about how painters had to
betray the verisimilitude of representation in order to express ‘spiritual’ depths
Triptychs, Eternity and the Spirituality of the Body 273
and sensations. Deleuze’s own remarks on what he calls the ‘accident’ and the
depiction of Christ’s body in the history of Christian painting recall Hegel’s
remarks. Deleuze notes how ‘Christ is besieged, and even replaced by accidents’
(Deleuze 2003: 124).
5. This differentiation is marked in Deleuze’s text with the capitalised form of
‘Figure’.
6. Note Deleuze’s use of the specifically religious notion of ‘revelation’.
7. In a footnote to this passage Deleuze cites Luciano Bellosi’s work on
Michelangelo, which ‘has shown how Michelangelo destroyed the narrative
religious fact in favour of a properly pictorial or sculptural fact’ (Deleuze 2003:
196).
8. Of particular note here are the two spectral figures in the left panel of
Triptych – Three Studies for a Crucifixion, 1962. These two figures hover and
resonate with an ambiguous rhythmic character that is extremely disturbing and
affective.
References
Deleuze, Gilles (2003) Francis Bacon: The Logic of Sensation, trans. Daniel W.
Smith, London: Continuum.
Deleuze, Gilles (2006) Two Regimes of Madness: Texts and Interviews 1975–1995,
ed. David Lapoujade, trans. Ames Hodges and Mike Taormina, New York:
Semiotexte.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1975) Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, Volume II, trans. Malcolm
Knox, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Spinoza, Baruch (1992) Ethics, trans. Samuel Shirley, Indianapolis/Cambridge:
Hackett Publishing Company.
Sylvester, David (1987) The Brutality of Fact: Interviews with Francis Bacon, third
revised edition, London: Thames and Hudson.
DOI: 10.3366/E1750224109000634