Dharmakirti On The Existence of Other Minds
Dharmakirti On The Existence of Other Minds
Dharmakirti On The Existence of Other Minds
maintained,
2.
equal footing with the problem concerning the existence of the external
world. Within his idealist framework, other minds enjoy the same status as
objects in general. But one important difference needs to be marked here.
While other objects exist as direct representations - their independent
existence being unacceptable to Dharmakirti -, cognition of the existence of
other minds becomes possible through the representations in consciousness
of the outward physical movements and purposive actions of others. That is,
the existence of other minds is inferred from the representations of others'
56
bodily states by virtue of an analogy with (the representations of) our own
bodily behaviour. Inference for Dharmakirti can yield valid cognition only
on the basis of the invariable concomitance
two terms, and in this case between overt bodily behaviour and consciousness.
It is clear that the inference in question cannot be deductive. For the sound
ness of the dedcution will depend upon our knowledge of the premiss, "That
person is experiencing," but if that premiss is known, no further argument
will be required to prove the existence of other mind. Of course we are
familiar with the idea of what is it to have experiences or thoughts, but the
element of ownership intervenes. Thus the starting point can only be the ideas
of one's own self and one's own thoughts. And this position is acceptable to
the realist (as also to Dharmakirti). We will note that we also have an idea of
body, even other bodies, and we also further know that while our own body
has some intimate relationship to our mind, another body does not bear the
same special relationship to our mind. This leads the realist to claim that
the conviction of the body as expressing our conscious acts or mental states
is first obtained in case of one's own self, and then with this correlation
between mind and body once established, the way is cleared for the inference
of other minds on the basis of other bodies. 3 The other person's feelings and
thoughts which get manifest in his bodily behaviour are never experienced
in our consciousness, for had they been so felt, they too would have been
known as belonging to our self. Not only that, in that case the other's inten
tions would also have been expressed in the same manner as our own, viz.,
"I go," "I speak", etc. 4 And since this is not the case, the other's existence
stands automatically proved. As an extension of the argument, the realist
places the other in external space as something distinct from my own body,
and occupying a different space from what my body does. And that is why,
he continues, we say "He goes", "He speaks", etc.5 This spatial separateness
of bodies, already assumed in respect of our relation to externally given
objects, posits, for interaction between my consciousness and the other's
consciousness, my body and his body as mediating agencies. The resultant
situation is one where the proposition "other minds exist" already seems
presupposed before it begins to be established, and then through a verbal
legerdemain we are persuaded that these minds and their activities are ex
pressed through 'expressive' bodily behaviour. That this latter is susceptible
of intelligible communication and can be formulated in a judgement like "He
goes", "He speaks", is cited as a further proof.
57
marks (physical movements, purposive actions, etc.) are caused by, and hence
express, other consciousness, and that this conviction rests on what turns out
to be the case in respect of one's own self. Otherwise, he too feels, the marks
of other's conscious motivations will have to exist independently of the
latter.6 And since this does not hold true in one's own case, it cannot be
maintained in respect of others. Accepting the 'argument from analogy,' he
goes the whole hog with the realist in assuming the spatial distance that
separates the other's body from one's own, and also further accepts that the
judgement like "He goes", "He speaks", is basically different from the
judgement "I go'', "I speak", etc. 7 At the same time, however, Dhannakirti
seeks to subsume this argument under his 'representation theory'. The other
person's bodily movements as expressive of his consciousness are also given to
us in representations much like our own bodily behaviour. Knowing the
former set of representations as not caused by our conscious will, in contrast
to our experience of the representations of our own bodily acts as caused by
our volitions, we infer that these must have been actuated by a consciousness
other than our own;8 else, we are faced up with a none-too-agreeable situation
of having to have representations which remain unaccounted for. In other
words, Dharmakirti regards himself quite justified in inferring to the actual
existence of other minds on the evidence not of the actual external bodily
movements but of the representations of them.
4. Now at this point it seems necessary to remark that our appreciation of
Dharmakirti's approach and his arguments for other minds is greatly hand
icapped by his total denial of the reality of the external world. The task
becomes particularly hazardous when one has to reckon with a doctrine
which sees all subject-object distinction as arising from within consciousness
itself and ultimately traceable to
any reference to the extra-mental world. This view of the external world which comprises not only obejcts but also other spirits - makes Dhannakirti's
refutation of solipsism less than convincing not only with regard to the
arguments employed but also with regard to his professed belief. It should
be obvious from the nature of the problem that, whatever procedure one
ultimately adopts for establishing other minds, their reality as independent
existents has to be admitted. And if the procedure be analogical reasoning
as in the present case, other bodies too will have to be granted this status.
58
5.
But this is not the end of the matter. Dharmakirti has other important
things to say which require careful attention. From his initial premise of the
invariable concomitance between consciousness and bodily behaviour
(which holds in respect of all individuals), he leaps to another drastic conclu
sion, viz., that while presentations of physical movements and speech etc.
must have their source in conscious motivations, both of these need not
belong to the same individual. Thus he conceives of presentation of move
ments in external space as not belonging to the body of the person whose
conscious will alone should normally cause such movements. Likewise there
can be movements of our own body but not caused by the activity of our
consciousness. And the obvious paradigm representing such cases is the
hypnotic situation.11 Actions of a person under the influence of hypnosis are
59
involuntary, but have been caused by our conscious will in case we are the
hypnotizing agency in question. Contrariwise, in a situation of somebody else
rocking me, though the movement is mine, it is not caused by my conscious
will.12 Thus it is not some specific consciousness which is inferred on the
basis of external marks - presence of bodily actions and speech - but con
sciousness in general, in other words, the 'essence of consciousness'. This
has the inevitable consequence that purposive activity and verbal marks
are deprived of their particularity in so far as it consists in being connected
with some particular body. Thus, in one stroke, through the operation
of hypostatic abstraction, all meaningful distinction between one's own
body and another body, between one's own consciousness and another
consciousness is removed. What now remains is not some body and some
consciousness but a body and a consciousness. In a like manner, the 'argument
from analogy' is also rendered infructuous. Analogy was seen as proceeding
from certitude in regard to the invariable causal relation between conscious
ness and its outward mainfestation obtained first in one's own case; and
since my movements and speech can now have their cause in somebody else's
conscious will, analogy goes by default.
The external 'ideal' space which was earlier supposed to separate two
bodies or two consciousnesses now gets filled in a mysterious way, so that
now my conscious intentions do not necessarily need my body but any
body to get expressed and in fact even inferred. In observing someone's
bodily movements I may not be necessarily inferring his mind but any mind.
Likewise, in feeling my own bodily states I am not necessarily cognizing my
own mind but any mind, because who can tell that my bodily movements
were not caused under the spell of some conscious will other than mind. We
have thus moved full circle and find that we remain where we are. The
invariable relation between consciousness and bodily behaviour now stands
eviscerated of all such subjective conviction on which rested analogical
reasoning, with the result that even the certainty of this relation now comes
under question.
6. Taking now the problem to a different plane, it can be asked, what sort
(svapnavat). The exterior world having been denied any reality at the waking
60
plane, and the dream-state being no different in this respect, the question that
naturally presents itself is: If inference of a foreign mind at the waking plane
is grounded in the evidence of the other's body which so to say corresponds
to its representation (in consciousness), in what way can the other's mind be
apprehended in the dream in the absence of the other's body (corresponding
to its representation)? The dreams, the opponent can urge, after all constitute
a different order of reality in the sense that there appear no external objects
including foreign bodies in this state. In such a situation, he is afraid, the
operation of analogical reasoning in inferring other minds gets drastically
restricted, or in case of its applicability, which is what the idealist himself
maintains, the dream-objects should also be granted the same status as they
enjoy in the waking state.
To these posers, Dharmakirti's reply is somewhat strained and ingenious.
Maintaining that the inference of other mind in the dream takes place, as in
the waking state, on the basis of images of the other's purposeful bodily
behaviour etc., he points out that while the waking images of foreign motions
and purposeful acts are directly dependent upon other minds, this dependence
in dreams is mostly indirect. Now, what is it that Dharmakirti means by
61
Now without entering into the full question of dreams versus waking
life - a recurrent theme in Indian philosophy - we can briefly note that
Dharmakirti's own admission of a distinction between the two in terms of
indirect and direct dependence impinges not only on the asserted functional
identification of the two states but also on his approach to the problem of
other minds in particular and the external world in general. The concession
takes away much of the force of his argument, and no amount of logical
sophistry can make his basic standpoint any the more respectable.
7. Now in the course of his attempt to rebut the charge of solipsism levelled
not agree to the proposition that his representations of the other's behaviour
are in any way the real marks of the other's mind. What are, then, the real
marks of mind? And the idealist seems to take recourse to a desperate ma
noeuver which only further undermines his position. According to him, only
such representations in which appear our own movements and verbal acts can
be regarded as the real marks of mind. In regard to the marks of other mind,
other consciousness is the regulating (indirect) cause.17 Or, differently,
the marks of other mind are so only conventionally and are regarded as
such owing to the association in the form of resemblance with our own
(representations of our own marks).18 Now if this indeed is the case, and if
the listener does not perceive the representations of the speaker and vice
versa (since they are given separately to themselves alone as subjects), what
becomes of the fate of the agreement on the strength of which both, without
62
8.
own
the external manifestations of the other's mind are for us its marks only
conventionally. Furthermore, is not even the 'argument from analogy' pre
viously accepted by Dharmakirti as a method common to both the realist and
himself being given a short shift? The severe strains to which Dharmakirti' s
position is subjected and the desperate lengths to which he has to go become
apparent in some other ways also. In his attempt to save the communication
situation in which speech plays a vital role, Dharmakirti cites the instance of
two persons under the influence of the same eye-disease who are convinced
that
Here, according to him, each one experiences his representation (in which
two moons appear) independently of the other; and the conviction on the
part of both of them that the other is also perceiving the same object, viz. two
moons, is because of the accidental coincidence 20 of their representations.
But how to account for the fact that the said conviction, reciprocal in a
way, is not only in respect of the same cognized object, but also and more
63
9.
Given these disparate and diverse moves, the question is: what is it that
64
if the existence of the other's mind is to be the object of cognition then its
form also must be cognized. And since this latter in its uniqueness remains
inaccessible, what sort of mind does the realist aim at cognizing through
inference? That is, since the essence of other mind is unqualifiedly beyond
our cognitive reach, its real existence cannot become the object of inferential
knowledge. And if it be maintained, as the realist does, that what inference
cognizes on the basis of logical connection is only the general concept and
not the individual form, that is, in other words, the object of inferential
cognition is only mind in general and not any particular one, Dharmakirti
points out the fallacy underlying this view. Formulating three possible
alternatives on this score, viz., identity (of the general concept of mind with
the other's mind), difference, and both identity and difference, he rules
as out of order the last two options for they do not admit of cognition,
through inference, of other mind.21 As to the first view of identity, he
repudiates it on the ground that if identity were indeed possible, the other
mind too would then have become known to us in the same form as it really
exists. 22 Furthermore, admission of identity in the present case would
deal a deathblow to the distinction between sensual cognition and rational
cognition which is crucial to Dharmakirti's ontology and epistemology.
(Dharmakirti, we may recall, draws a radical distinction between perceptual
or sensual cognition (pratyaka) and inference (anumana) and no overlapping
between the two is allowed.23 Perception yields absolutely indeterminate
cognition of the essence of a unique particular
individual existence is
65
neglects the obvious distinction between perception and inference and thereby
renders the own-status of inference as a source of knowledge vulnerable.
1 0.
Now it can be seen that, despite the logical rigour which Dharrnakirti
brings to bear upon the subject, his treatment on the whole leaves something
important out of ac.count, leaves back certain ambiguities unexplained, and
blurs out certain other distinctions crucial to at least an understanding of
the problem if not its final resolution. Foremost of these is of course the
difficulty, as indicated above, connected with Dharrnakirti's view of inference
which according to him provides us access to the object in its generality or
universality. Without claiming competence to pronounce judgement on this
highly complicated and controversial issue, I may state that cognition of mind
in general (to which inference leads) remains incompatible with the intended
activity which is undertaken in respect of some particular person. If I judge
someonw as walking, or respond communicatively to someone speaking to
me, it is always some particular person (or consciousness) I am having in
mind and not consciousness/otherness in general. Again, how can
inferential
some relationship
between our representations of the other's bodily acts and the other's mind.26
Why should the operation of analogical reasoning be halted midway?
Something also needs to be briefly said about Dharmakirti's view about
the cognition of other minds in dreams. Maintaining, and correctly so, that
within the dream itself nothing appears baffling or contradictory (despite
66
11.
the analogical approach taken in its more abstract form and as free from
features specific to any particular philosopher's rendering of it. The analogical
reasoning as a general hypothesis rests broadly on two basic assumptions:
(1) that
(2) that
states get manifested through our visually perceivable bodily states and
behaviour; that there exists a special intimate relation between our mental
states and the corresponding bodily acts, certitude about which is firstly
gained through our observation of the same in our own case 27 (and from this
one can proceed to infer to other minds through the mediation of other
bodies which look like and behave in a similar way as our own). Now so far
as the first assumption is concerned, it makes very sound sense; in fact a
better and more true assumption seems inconceivable.28 However, the second
assumption, viz., that the correlation between psychic events and their bodily
expression is firstly known to us in our own case, need not be regarded as a
natural and necessary entailment of the first assumption. (The fact that the
second assumption is nevertheless implied in the analogical approach is a
67
the existence
of others.
knowledge
there
68
to serve as its symbol. The net result of this epistemological approach then is
that my knowledge about the existence of other minds can never be more
than probable just as my knowledge about the existence of other objects is
always at best probable. It therefore remains an open question whether the
other even exists as a body, let alone as a mind.
The above implication only serves to usher in by the back door the demon
of solipsism. Implicit in any repudiation of the solipsist position is the sup
position that the other, the not-me, too exists, like myself, as a subject, as
a "centre" of experience, as one who is not only seen by me but also sees
me in turn. This is what, to use Husserlian language, constitutes the radical
otherness of the Other, what sets him qualitatively apart from the rest of the
mundane objects, which latter although also existing as not-me lack precisely
this radicalness. The recourse to the same cognitive technique in the case
of other minds as in the case of objects therefore renders both the realist
and the idealist open to the charge of misplaced 'optimism'. In the case of
Dharmakirti this charge becomes particularly severe since he totally repudiates
the reality of the world including other centres of experience and thereby
eliminates whatever possibility is there for the other's subjecthood to be
grasped. The analogical reasoning may be inadequate as a means to establish
the existence of other minds and here Dharmakirti's failure would be as
much as anybody else's. But the disconcerting aspect is that on his view of
consciousness, even his professed belief in the existence of others comes
under question.
Dept. of Sanskrit,
University of Delhi, India
NOTES
1 The article is based on Dharmakirti'sSanttintintara-siddhi with VinHadeva's commentary
({fka} thereon, translated into Russian by Th. Stcherbatsky from Tibetan, and further
translated from Russian into English by H. C. Gupta and published in Papers of Th.
Stcherbatsky in the Soviet Indology Series No. 2 (Calcutta: Indian Studies, Past and
Present, 1969) under the general editorship of Debi Prasad Chattopadhyaya. Since in
spite of my efforts I have not been able to lay hands on the Sanskrit rendering of the
Tibetan version ( which till today remains the only available version), and since I have no
knowledge of the Tibetan language nor for that matter of the Russian, I have had to
exclusively rely, for my exposition and critique, on the English translation by H. C.
69
Gupta. This situation naturally has its inherent limitations and shortcomings. However,
my access to some of Dharmaki rti's other works which are available in Sanskrit helped
me in following his essential argument contained in Santtintintara-siddhi. I am not
however assuming that it can be a real substitute for one's direct access to the original
text. All the references to Santtintintara-siddhi and the Vinitadeva's commentary are to
the translation by H.C. Gupta.
2 According to Dharmakirti, consciousness in its various forms - i.e. cognitions - does
not involve any reference to the external world. The diversity of cognitions cannot be
accounted for in terms of the plurality of external objects, but rather owes its existence
to mental dispositions or forces (vtisantis). The subject-object distinction, although also
ultimately illusory (avidyal, arises from within consciousness itself under the influence
of vtisanti. See Dharmakirti, PramiiT}aVtirttika (hereafter cited as PV) with the com
mentary (vrtti) of Manorathanandin, critically ed. Dwarikadas Shastri, Bauddha Bharati
Series No. 3 (Varanasi: Bauddha Bharati, 1968), II. 354: "avibhtigo 'pi buddhyaatma
viparyasitadarsanailgrahyagrahakasamvittibhedavtin iva lakyatell Also see Manorathan
andin's commentary thereon. Also Ibid., II. 357-363.
Thus consciousness of anything (say, of blue) does not refer to anything (blue)
existing outside itself. See commentary on PV II. 326: "tasmtid vedyarahita tasya
jfltinasya sa nfltidinlpa titmti anubhava. sa ca anubhavo na anyasya kasyacid biihyasya."
70
external world has its genesis in and is in perfect accord with universal or transcendental
illusion. See further SS, 58 and !fkti thereon. Also see note 1 above. In situations of
delusions and dreams, objects are perceived which are just not there in reality. Picking
up a few cases of delusions, and taking their cue from what the case is about dreams,
the Buddhist idealists established the equation: illusions= dreams = waking life. It seems
that for these thinkers it is not only possible but true that our waking life is, to use
Russell's words, "a persistent and recurrent nightmare." For the explicit statement of
Vijfianavadin Buddhists on the subject, see Madhyanta-Vibhariga, tr. Th. Stcherbatsky
(New Delhi: Oriental Reprint, 1978; first published in 1936 as Vol. XXX of Bibliotheca
Buddhica Series), Chapters II & IV.
15 SS, 60.
16 SS, 61 and tfkti thereon.
1 7 SS, 63. Comenting on this, Vinitadeva
19 SS, 65.
20 Tfkti on SS, 65.
21 SS, 71.
22 SS, 72.
23 Admitting only two prarnaf)aS - pratyaka and anumana-, Dharmakirti sets up two
separate objects as their prameyas, and thus roots the distinction between the two in the
(ontologically) different nature of the objects of knowledge. The object of pratyaka
is the unique particular (svalakf)a), while that of anumana is the general concept
(stimanyalakf)a).As Dharmakirti says in PV, ll. 1: "manam dvividham, viayadvaiv
idhytit, $aktya$aktital:z arthakriytiytim .. ." Manorathanandin comments: "viayasya
svalakf)OSlimlinyalakf)OriiPatayti dvaividhytit ... viayas ca svasamanyalakaf)tid
atirikto na asti.tatas tadviayatve pratyakInumanataiva." This object-wise demarcation
of the two prarna')Os leaves little room for overlapping or encroachment. As Manora
thanandin says (PV, II. 2): "anayos ca anyo 'nyavyavacchedariipatvtid na rtisyantaram,"
and further (Ibid., II. 1): "na hy ekasya viruddhtiv iva dharme yujyete." This schematiza
tion is technically called pramti')avyavasthti.On role of inference (anumana), further see
SS, 73-75 and tfkti thereon.
24 SS, 76. "Thugh inference does not actually reveal the real existence of an object,
it is still the source of cognition of truth, for it leads to the attainment of the desired
aim." Also, Ibid., 19. "Having known, through this inference, the existence of other
mind, the mind as subject successively produces the effects which lead to the desired
aim." See f fkti thereon. Dharmottara commenting on Nytiyabindu 1.1 says: "anumanam
tu limgadarantid niscinvat pravrttiviyam darsayati." Dharmottara, Nyaya-bindu-(ikti,
with Nytiyabindu of Dharmakirti, ed. and trans. Shrinivas Shastri (Meerut: Sahitya
Bhand.ar, 1975).
2 5 Tikti on SS, 80.
26 SS, 61-63.
27 That there may be
71
commitment of wide implications,and yet I feel this theory is indispensable for any
plausible account of subjectivity or consciousness. The theory briefly means that the
way we become directly and priviledgedly aware of our own mental states and realities
is not available to us in case of our knowledge of the mental states of others. And vice
versa. While some and even sound intimation of what goes on in the other's mind - his
sadness, anxiety, etc. - can be had through various means,no awareness of the other's
experiences is possible in the same way as the other himself has of them in the mere fact
of suffering them. In other words, there is an essential interiority to our mental lives
which cannot be given away or taken over at will. It is precisely because we are so
privileged in respect of our own mental lives and not so privileged in respect of others,'
that there is the problem of the Other.