What Happens To Viññā A in The Cessation Attainment - An Exegesis of M.I. 295-296 (OCR)
What Happens To Viññā A in The Cessation Attainment - An Exegesis of M.I. 295-296 (OCR)
What Happens To Viññā A in The Cessation Attainment - An Exegesis of M.I. 295-296 (OCR)
in
who do not mab that equation , such as for instance Buddhaghosa, have
to find another mode of reasonmg to answer the q uestion implied in the
title of this paper, as we shall demonstrate later.
As already stated above, there 1s no consensus of opinion among
contemporary scholars as to whether Nirvana is the same as SVN or is
something totally other. A preliminary assessment of the two opinions
about it could be quite helpful in achieving the main focus of our
investigation, which is to ascertain whether the canonical texts say
anything definite about the survival or cessation of uihnarJa in the s tate
of SVN .
Although the ultimate answer to this question must come from
practice and experience (patipatti and patiuedha) , we haue euery right to
probe into the matter within the restricted area of scriptural study
(pariya tti). Hence, 1 insist that SVN is not the object of my study because
it is beyond my competence. My focus, I repeat, is on what the texts say
or do not say about what happens to uiimiiri in the SVN . This invariably
includes also the dispute about what the texts say or do not say about the
identity or the difference between Nirvana a nd SVN.
The Pali exegctea when commenting on the relevant texts have subscribed
to the theory that Nir vana and SVN are entirely two different things.
They have also discovered two sharply defined conceptual tools which
would serve them as "precision instruments" to present t heir case with
absolute clarity:
(a) the notion of sabhlluadhamma (a positively existing reality) as
opposed to asabhlluadhamma (a privative state defined by the
absc!nce of a positive existing reality) ;
(b) the notion of nipphann.a, namely, that which is produced or created
- 44 -
3. Nirvana and the NS: The Posit ion of the Canonical Authors
Hence this critical comment made on Griffith's opinion must be directed
also against Wijesekera 's equivocal understanding of nirodha I nirujjhati
( in a passage l am going to quote below) , where he does not seem to have
perceived the difference between nirodha predicated of Nirvana and
nirodha predicated of SVN.
The same observation may be valid with regard to other
contemporary scholars who rigorously maintain that in the Pali Canon
Nirvana and NS are considered to be one and the same thing. The late Ven.
Yakka(juve Pai'inaramall and the late Ven. Palahane Vajiran8.Qa,.., can be
cited as two eminent examples. This s hows that the two opinions on this
matter continue to divide the scholars of our own times.
How does one account for the persistence of this disagreement to this
day? One explanation would be to take 0.C. Panda's lead and suggest
that it is the ambiguity in the Canonical texts themselves that allows for
both interpretations. For instance, in M.1.295 ( the Sutta passage under
investigation, he~e), as also in S.IV.294 (and Vsm 703-704), according to
Pande, "the description of 'nirodha-samapatti' comes nearer that of
catalepsy than of sambodhi" .'0 But elsewhere, e.g. in S.U.146, NS seems to
presuppoae the attainment of the andgdmi as well as the arahan st.ate, the
implication being that it could also occur after Nirvana or Full Release.If)
ln other passages, however, Pande thinks that the tendency is to "equate
Nirvanic experience to Nirodhasamipatti" .111
-46 -
- 48 -
scrutiny reveals t hat the Sutta compilers have exercised a discreet silence
on the matter we are discussing: textus tacet. This silence, presumably, is
an eloquent testimony to a pre-textual history yet to be discovered.
The way I read M.1.295-296, as explained below, has suggested to me
that the controversy about the fate of uiiiiilif}a in t he cessation
attainment, in aU probability, predates the compilation of that passage.
This remote origin of the controversy, however, lies beyond the present
state of scholarship. But one can quite comfortably locate the proximate
origin of the controversy in the Sutta itself. This distinction between the
immediate and the remote context will not sound overly speculative when
our investigation is completed.
The technical phrase for the cessa tion attainment, as I have already
noted, is saiiiid-uedayita-nirodha, namely, cessation of ideation a nd
sensation. Now saiiiid and uedanii. a re not identical with uifliiar)a
(o r cit ta), but are said to be aspects of t he latter and hence they are
classed as cetasikii., "concomitant constituents of citta", that is to say,
phenomena associated with consciousness, a nd not the phenomenon of
consciousness as such. Thus the technical phrase for cessation attainment
consistently mentions only the arrest of ideat ion and sensation, and not
that of consciousness as such. The cessation of uinnlu')a is therefore not
explicitly mentioned in t his scriptural phrase. Does the Mahavedalla Sutta
(M .1.296) offer an explicit teaching a bout it ?
This text mentions three kinds of activities that cease at the NS: kii.yasarrr.khii.rii. (bodily activities), uaci-sarrikhii.rii (verbal activities) and manosarrr.khii.rii. ( mental activities). In t he very next Sutta (Cullavedalla Sutta,
M.l.301) , these three terms are explained as follows :-
1. bodily activities
3. ment a l activities
unambiguous in
bis
-so-
Sutta begins the discussion on the difference between death and the
cessation trance almost immediately after establishing the mutual
dependence between iiyu, usmii and the paiicindriyan.i. The mind is
explicitly excluded here. Hence the triad O.yu-usmii-indriyimi ( m Paradigm
A) , taken in the context of the Sutta, clearly refers to "life, heat and the
PARADIGMS
AT DEATH
LIFE (ayu)
EXHAUSTED
(parikkhir)il.)
NOT EXHAUSTED
( aparikkhu)a)
HEAT (usma)
COOLED
( uipasanna)
NOT COOLED
(auipasanna)
SENSES (indriyani/
pasddani)
DISINTEGRATED
(uiparibhinnani)
BRIGHTENED UP
( uippasanna)
LIFE (ayu)
DURING NS
HEAT (iuma)
CONSCIOUSNESS
(uiMal:ia)
ayu-usma-uiiiMJi ARE
THE THINGS
(dhamma)
THAT LEAVE
(pajahanti )
THE BODY AT DEATH
BODILY
ACTIVITIES (kii.ya8afTl/thlud)
VERBAL
CEASE ANO SUBSIDE CEASE AND SUBSIDE
ACTlVITIES ( uaci&arfl/thiira)
Niruddhb., patippassaddhb. NiruddM, patippassaddM
MENTAL
ACTIVITIES (cittalafTl/chiira)
I
- 53 -
- 54 -
- 55 -
Though this second inference cannot be directly derived from M.I. 295296 but demonstrable from other scr iptural loci, Wijesekera seems to
mean much more than what he says in the sentence above. He is probably
assuming another theory which is not evident in this Sutta-passage. This
other theory which seems to have influenced his eisegesis [' reading into a
text') of M.1.295-296, is that uiiliiarJ is Ma process other than mental
activity in s uch a way as to be separable from the latter. Put in another
way, what he understands by wother t han" seems to be that the mind is so
distinct from mental activities as to be able to continue in a 'pure' st.ate
in the NS where the mental activities have ceased. If transposed into the
Abhidhammika terminology, what this theory presumes is that there can
be a citta without cetasikii. For without implicitly accepting this
presupposition, one cannot interpret the text the way Wijesekera has done.
Whether or not Wijesekera has revisited M.I.295-296 in his later
writings I cannot say for the moment. But one notes that two decades
later he had undertaken a study of the canonical occurrences of uin.Tiiir)a,
and has reached the conclus ion that there are three clearly distinguishable
senses in which the Canonical writers have employed this term: a) in the
cognitive sense, b) as a medium of re-becoming and c) as a medium of
meditative trances. Referring to this third meaning, he demonstrates that
all the jhanic states prior to the cessation attainment are each a uinfulr)athiti, i.e., an abiding place or a foot-hold of consciousness a nd therefore
cannot be equated with the Mfinal state of emancipation or Nibbana".
Then - appa rently implying that the cessat ion t rance is equivalent to
Nirval)ahe concludes as follows:
The Vii'liiiil)a ceases to manifest itself altogether (n irujjhati) only in
the final state of ' the cessation of all conceptual and empirical
experience (saiiiia-uedayita-nirodha).' Nirujjhati literally means
'checked' and this can best be taken as referring to the checking of t he
flow ( sota) of Vini'lal)a, that is to say, the stopping of t he continuity
of Vii'li\aoa. In the previous states the ViiiiiS(la could find some
abiding place (thiti) but in the state of Nirodha it obtains no such
- 56 -
11>
M.1.295-296.
-58-
-59 -
-60-
is
functioning)
and
sound
sleep
( when
the
sees dreams
neither when fully awake nor when fully asleep, but in the interval
between falling asleep and reachmg the Unconcious (bhavail6a) State:
- 61 -
reached the Unconscious State, ceases even while the body remains
(alive); the mind of the o ne who has reached cessation [attainment]
ceases even while the body continues to be [alive] . 171
The implication is too obvious to restate here. The appauatta-citta in
the cessation attainment is put on a par with the appauatta-citta
identified as bhavaitgagata-citta. This would mean that the Mind of a
Nirodhasamapanna is in a fully dormant or noetically inactive state. lo
other words, the mind of such a person persists in the body minus the
mental activities. In the dead person, as we havo seen from t he canonical
texts, not even an inactive mind can exist; in death t he uiiiiWJJ.a simply
leaves the body.
If this conclusion is valid, we have to admit that there was a school
of though that advocated the existence of an inactive mind, a state of
consciousness (citta) , wherein the concomitant phenomena (cetasi/ca),
which constitute the manifold activation of the mind, do not function at
all. According to this view, the phrase sanna-uedayita-nirodha would
point to a mind which is noetically and conatively inactive, i.e., a
dormant mind or "a mind that has ceased to function" (appauatttJ/Tl
cittarri) as' Nagasena puts it. In other words, the possibility of an inactive
mind, an acetesika-citta, so to say, cannot be ruled out from the theory of
consciousness advocated ih t he Milindapai'lha. This, as I have shown
above, is exactly the position that Buddhaghosa had rejected as absurd
and, therefore, untenable.
This may also explain why Buddhaghosa does not cite the Milindapai'lba, a text ~ revered in the Southern School of Buddhism, when
arguing against that very position upheld there. To hold an opinion that
militates against such an authoritative source as the Milindapai'iha would
have been temerarious. After all, the same Buddhaghosa does allude to
this Milindapai'lha passage in AA Ill 316-318 while discussing t he
phenomenon of dreams in a context where Nigasena's reference to NS is
not relevant, and , therefore, does not require to be cited. The other locus
- 62 -
where this happens is VinA III 520-522 where he explains how the release of
sperm by a person who is dreaming does not amount to a conscious
release of sperm" (sa-cetanikii sukkha-uisatthi). Here, too, Nagasena is
quoted in support of this position in a context where the reference to NS
does not come in.
By contrast, MA I1 351 (discussed above) where Nagasena's equation
of the bhauanga-gata citta with an appauatta-citta requires to be quoted
at least as an opinion to be refuted, there is a deafening silence on the
part of Buddhaghosa! Does this suggest that there is a remote pre-textual
context wherein the possibility of an 'acetsi.aka-citta' has been a moot
point, which may account for the persistence of two divergent opinions in
later times, with Nagasena representing one stream within t he Pali
Abhidhammika tradition, and Buddhaghosa the other ?
In the Vibhanga Commentary, attributed to Buddhaghosa, we once
more see the same approach as the one adopted by Buddhaghosa in a
variant version in AA III 317. There is a rather long excursus on the nature
of the wakeful state, the dreaming state and dreamless sleep in VibhA 406409 ( repeated verbatim also in VinA III 521). We are warned that to say
sutto supati ("the person who is sound asleep sees dreams") would run
counter to the teaching of the Abhidhamma because "one sleeps with the
Unconscious Mind (bhauangacittena supati) while, on the other hand, to
say patibudd.ho [supinam] passati ("one who is awake sees dreams")
would contradict the teaching of the Vinaya where what one does during
dreams is not regarded as morally imputable (supinafTI. passantena pana
hate uitikkame ekantaJTI. aniipatti eua). Now, the Abhidhammika basis for
this position, as explained by the Commentator, is that during the dreamstate the mind has not reached the noetic level of jauana or perception
which is required for any action to be ethical (kusliikusala). 1
Therefore, deep sleep is a total absence of consciousness where even
the anoetic sentience or mere sensation (such as dassana-matta) is nil. If
that is so, then Nagasena's statement cited above certainly ensures that
-63-
- 64 -
- 65 -
What Happens to
VlnnW}a
nirodhasamapatti.
13) Pande, 536-537. For the relevant passages from the Majjhima Niklya, see
16) MA IV 9().91.
17) Varn 702: Tattha Ira nirodhasamflpatu ti yd anupubba-nirodhaIJCJ$tna
cittaceuu1Jrtuia1Tl dhamm{J/l(;&.fTl appauaw.
18) 0. H.do A. Wijesekera, vitalism and Bocoming . Umvtrsity of Ceylon
Review, April 1943, 57:- "But on the question or a vital pr inciple in the
sa1T1sAric individual, tho position of early Buddhism is made clear in a
passage which has never so far boon discussed in this connection.
19) Ibid.
20) Rune Johansson, The Psychology of Nirvana, George, Allen and Unwin
24) Accordin1r to Varn, 142, 530-531, etc., vitalcka and uicdra are conative
functions (cetand) or the mind occurring in the spoechdoor, the former
d rivinii the mind to the object, the latter fixing it on that object.
25) Wiieaekera, loc.aupra cit.
26) Ibid.
27) 0. H.de A. Wi1eaekera,
The
- 66 -
Paul Griffith (op.cit., 7) t.o mean something qui~ absurd: lhat the person
who had attained the NS would incur immediate retribution for killinr a
parent or arahan I
nibbdbadhdtuya parinibbwasadiso.
KL~aya111
566.
39) I have diacusaed this in my article "Life, Death and Murder: An AbhidhA
rmika Perspective" (pro manu1cripto) published in Sinhala as "Jivitaya,
Maraoaya hi OhAtanaya: Abhidharmika Vicrahayak in Aaanra
Tilakaratna, Editor, Abhidharmika Adhyana, Colombo, 1996, 189-205.
- 67 -
articles
on
Buddhism
include:
Ill
1974.
"Colophon
lO
the
1999).
- 68 -