Habermas - Justification and Application
Habermas - Justification and Application
Habermas - Justification and Application
J iirgen Habermas
translated by Ciaran Cronin
Contents
Preface
VII
Translator's Note
IX
Translator's I ntroduction
x1
1
19
113
133
147
Notes
177
Index
189
Preface
With this book I continue the investigations set forth in Moral Con
sciousness and Communicative Action ( 1990). The background to the
discussion is formed primarily by objections against universalistic
concepts of morality that can be traced back to Aristotle, Hegel, and
contemporary [ethical] contextualism. Going beyond the sterile op
position between abstract universalism and a self-contradictory rela
tivism, I endeavor to defend the primacy of the just (in the
deontological sense) over the good. That does not mean, however,
that ethical questions in the narrow sense have to be excluded from
rational treatment.
It is my hope that these essays reflect a learning process. This holds
at any rate for the explicit distinction between moral and ethical
discourses. It is worked out for the first time in the Howison Lecture
[which appears here under the title "On the Pragmatic, the Ethical,
and the Moral Employments of Practical Reason"] delivered at Berke
ley in 1988 and dedicated to my daughter Judith. Since then it would
be more accurate to speak of a "discourse theory of morality," but
I retain the term "discourse ethics," which has become established
usage.
The "Remarks on Discourse Ethics" consutute the main text and
derive from notes made during the years 1987 to 1990. They rep
resent a confrontation with competing theoretical programs and are
offered as a global critical evaluation of the relevant literature.
viii
Preface
Translator's Note
Translator's Introduction
xii
Translator's Introduction
xiii
Translator's I ntroduction
xiv
Translator's I ntroduction
XV
Translator's Introduction
xvi
Translator's Introduction
xvii
Translator's Introduction
'
'
'
xviii
Translator's Introduction
XIX
Translator's I ntroduction
II
XX
Translator's Introduction
XXI
Translator's Introduction
xxii
Translator's Introduction
xxiii
Translator's Introduction
XXIV
Translator's Introduction
XXV
Translator's I ntroduction
XXVI
Translator's Introduction
xxvii
Translator's Introduction
xxviii
Translator's Introduction
Notes
1. The most important systematic exposition of his approach is "Discourse Ethics:
political thought is marked by "a movement from the view that morality must be
imposed on human beings towards the belief that morality could be understood as
human self-governance or autonomy." "Modern Moral Philosophy," in P. Singer, ed.,
A Companion to Ethics (Oxford, 1991), p. 147.
6. Cf. below pp. 55-56, 145-146, 162-163.
7. Cf. Habermas "What is Universal Pragmatics?" in Communication and the Evolution of
Society, trans. T. McCarthy (Boston, 1979), pp. 65-68. For an illuminating discussion
8. Cf. his criticisms of moral intuitionism and value ethics, DE, pp. 50-57 and Mural
Consciowness, p. 196. Bernard Williams's discussion of the objectivity of ethical judg
ments in terms of the question of the possibility of ethical knowledge is also open to
this criticism-d. Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass., 1985), pp. 132
ff.
9. Hence Habermas's insistence that the validity clajm raised in moral judgments, while
not a claim to truth, is analogous to a truth claim-see DE, pp. 57-62. Discourse ethics
rejects the opposition governing the recent metaethical debate in analytic ethics con
cerning realist and anti-realist interpretations of moral discourse by implying that the
question of whether or not there exist moral 'facts' described in moral judgments
presupposes a mistaken interpretation of the logic of moral discourse on the model
of factual discourse. See, for example, Michael Smith, "Realism," in Singer, ed., Com
panion, pp. 399-410, and G. Sayre- McCord, ed., Essays on Moral Realism (Ithaca, 1988).
xxix
Translator's Introduction
10. Habennas elaborates this fundamental insight in his theory of the 1ifewor1d-cf.
The Theory of Communicative Action Vol. 2, trans. T. McCarthy (Boston, 1987), pp. l l 3
ff. and Philosophical Discourse, pp. 298-299, 342ff.
11. There are, of course, other possibilities. Interaction may be broken off altogether
an option of limited scope given the practical imperatives of communal coexistence
or it may continue on a curtailed consensual basis, where disputed factual issues are
bracketed or a compromise is negotiated concerning disputed normative issues. Alter
natively, belief and compliance can be assured through various forms of deception or
coercion (e.g. , propaganda, psychological manipulation, or straightforward threats),
but such pseudo-consensus, apart from being morally and politically objectionable, is
inevitably an unstable basis for ongoing interaction.
12. While communicative action and discourse are very closely interrelated-Habermas
describes discourse as a reflective form of communicative action-only in discourse is
the issue of validity thematized in a universalistic manner that transcends the limits of
a particular community. Cf. Habermas, Moral Consciousness, pp. 201-202 and ''justice
and Solidarity: On the Discussion Concerning 'Stage 6'," in Michael Kelly, ed . , Her
meneutics and Critical Theory in Ethics and Politics (Cambridge, Mass., 1990), p. 48.
13. An important feature of Habermas's account of validity claims often overlooked
by critics is how it combines a nonrelativistic defense of the objectivity of truth and
normative rightness with a thoroughgoing fallibilism concerning particular factual and
normative claims, however well supported by real argumentation. This applies to his
own theoretical claims as well: he explicidy ties the fate of discourse ethics to recon
structions of implicit knowledge and competences that he acknowledges are fallible,
and hence contestable, in principle. Cf. Habermas, Moral Consciousness, p. 119 and
"Justice and Solidarity," n. 16, p. 52.
14. DE, p. 65.
1 5. Cf. Charles Taylor, "The Validity of Transcendental Arguments" in Proceedings of
16. On the logical status of this "transcendental-pragmatic" argument, see DE, pp. 8386.
17. Cf. DE, pp. 77ff.
18. On the concept of communicative action, see Habermas, "Remarks on the Concept
of Communicative Action," in Gottfried Seebass and Raimo Tuomela, eds. , Social Action
(Dordrecht, 1985), pp. 1 5 1-178 and The Theory of Communicative Action Vol. 1, trans.
T. McCarthy (Boston, 1984), pp. 94- 10 1 .
19. Cf. Habermas, Moral Consciousness, p. 130, and this volume, pp. 3 1, 83-84.
20. On the justification of 'U', cf. DE, pp. 86ff. , and William Rehg, "Discourse and the
Moral Point of View : Deriving a Dialogical Principle of Universalization," in Inquiry
34 (1991), pp. 27-48.
21. This construction represents a synthesis of Mead's notion of ideal role-taking and
Peirce's discursive notion of truth. On the notion of ideal role-taking, see Habermas,
"Justice and Solidarity," pp. 38-40.
XXX
Translator's Introduction
22. See the first essay of the present volume, "On the Pragmatic, the Ethical, and the
Moral Employments of Practical Reason . "
23. See, respectively, "Kantian Constructivism i n Moral Theory," journal of Phirosophy
77 (1980), pp. 520-522, and ':Justice as Fairness: Political not Metaphysical," Phirosophy
and Public Affairs 14 (1985), pp. 236-237.
24. For Habermas's views on Rawls, see chapter 2, pp. 25ff., 92ff. This emphasis on
public discourse is a development of a theme already present in his early historical
sociological account of the bourgeois public sphere (now belatedly available in English),
The StnJ.t:tural Transf01'71UJtion of the Public Sphere, trans. T. Burger and F. Lawrence
(Cambridge, Mass., 1989). In it he analyzes the legitimating function of public discus
sion concerning matters of general interest in the bourgeois public sphere which
developed in seventeenth-century England and eighteenth-century France and traces
its internal contradictions and vicissitudes up to its occlusion with the emergence of
the social-welfare state in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries.
25. For present purposes the term neo-Aristotelian is used to designate ethical positions
structured by recognizable successors to the fundamental orientations of Aristotle's
ethics: the central role accorded communally shaped ideals of character and the human
good, the distinction between theory and practice, and the distinctions between praxis
and poiesis and between phronesis and techne. On this use of the term, see Herbert
Schnii.delbach, "What is Neo-Aristotelianism?" Praxis Intemational 7 (1987188), pp. 225237.
26. Cf. After Virtue (Notre Dame, I nd., 1984), especially chapter 2.
27. For a concise statement, see Habermas, Philosophical Discourse, pp. 342-349.
perception and which does not admit of codification in terms of general rules or
criteria of judgment. On this dimension of Aristotle's account of practical reason, see
David Wiggins, "Deliberation and Practical Reason," in Needs, Values, Truth (Oxford,
1 991), pp. 215-237.
29. Cf. Williams, Ethics, pp. 52-53, 67-69. Such criticisms as Sandel's against Rawls
that contemporary liberalism repeats the error of its classical predecessors in presup
posing "unencumbered" selves do not apply to discourse ethics, which views indivi
duation from the outset as a product of socialization; but far from prejudging the
issue against an ethics and politics of autonomy, Habermas argues, the social embed
dedness of the subject demands that individual autonomy be reconceptualized in
intersubjective terms.
30. Habermas rejects Macintyre's and Williams's criticisms of attempts to derive a
moral principle from the structure of human action as such on the grounds that they
are based on a version of the argument (i.e. Alan Gewirth's) that remains tied to an
individualistic notion of agency and a correspondingly restricted conception of prac
tical reason. Cf. Macintyre, After Virtue, pp. 66ff. and Williams, Ethics, pp. 55ff.
3 1 . See chapter 2, pp. 35ff. In clarifying this distinction he draws on Klaus Gunther's
study Der Sinn fur Angemessenheit (Frankfurt, 1988). For a summary of the argument
of that work, see Gunther, "Impanial Application of Moral and Legal Norms: A
Contribution to Discourse Ethics," in David Rasmussen, ed., Universalism vs. Commu.
nitarianism: Contemporary Debates in Ethics (Cambridge, Mass., 1990), pp. 199-206.
xxxi
Translator's I ntroduction
4 1 . Habermas, Theory of Communicative Action Vol. 2, p. 96; cf. also Philosophical Dis
course, pp. 344-345.
1
On the Pragmatic, the Ethical, and the
Moral Employments of Practical Reason
For judith
2
On the Employments of Practical Reason
4
On the Employments of Practical Reason
5
On the Employments of Practical Reason
6
On the Employments of Practical Reason
8
On the Employments of Practical Reason
10
O n the Employments o f Practical Reason
tical reason. Only a will that is guided by moral insight, and hence is
completely rational, can be called autonomous. All heteronomous
elements of mere choice or of commitment to an idiosyncratic way
of life, however authentic it may be, have been expunged from such
a will. Kant confused the autonomous will with an omnipotent will
and had to transpose it into the intelligible realm in order to conceive
of it as absolutely determinative. But in the world as we experience
it, the autonomous will is efficacious only to the extent that it can
ensure that the motivational force of good reasons outweighs the
power of other motives. Thus, in the plain language of everyday life,
we call a correctly informed but weak will a "good will."
To summarize, practical reason, according to whether it takes its
orientation from the purposive, the good, or the just, directs itself in
turn to the choice of the purposively acting subject, to the resolute
ness of the authentic, self-realizing subject, or to the free will of the
subject capable of moral judgment. In each instance, the constellation
of reason and volition and the concept of practical reason itself
undergo alteration. Not only the addressee, the will of the agent who
seeks an answer, changes its status with the meaning of the question
"What should I do?" but also the addresser, the capacity of practical
deliberation itself. According to the aspect chosen, there result three
different though complementary interpretations of practical reason.
But in each of the three major philosophical traditions, just one of
these interpretations has been thematized. For Kant practical reason
is coextensive with morality ; only in autonomy do reason (Vernunft)
and the will attain unity. Empiricism assimilates practical reason to
its pragmatic use; in Kantian terminology, it is reduced to the pur
posive exercise of the understanding (Verstand). And in the Aristo
telian tradition, practical reason assumes the role of a faculty of
judgment ( Urteilskraft) that illuminates the life historical horizon of a
customary ethos. In each case a different exercise is attributed to prac
tical reason, as will become apparent when we consider the respective
discourses in which they operate.
III
11
On the Employments of Practical Reason
12
On the Employments o f Practical Reason
that one's own past can be accepted in the light of existing possibilities
of action as the developmental history of the person one would like
to be and continue to be in the future. The existential figure of the
"thrown projection" (geworfener Entwurf ) illuminates the Janus-faced
character of the strong evaluations justified by way of a critical ap
propriation of one's own life history. Here genesis and validity can
no longer be separated as they can in the case of technical and
strategic recommendations. Insofar as I recognize what is good for
me, I also already in a certain sense make the advice my own; that is
what it means to make a conscious decision. To the extent that I have
become convinced of the soundness of clinical advice, I have also
already made up my mind to transform my life in the manner sug
gested. On the other hand, my identity is only responsive to-even
at the mercy of-the reflexive pressure of an altered self-understand
ing when it observes the same standards of authenticity as ethical
existential discourse itself. Such a discourse already presupposes, on
the part of the addressee, a striving to live an authentic life or the
suffering of a patient who has become conscious of the "sickness unto
death." In this respect, ethical-existential discourse remains contin
gent on the prior telos of a consciously pursued way of life.
IV
13
On the Employments of Practical Reason
14
O n the Employments o f Practical Reason
The empirical will that has split off from the autonomous will plays
an important role in the dynamics of our moral learning processes. 1 2
The division o f the will is a symptom o f weakness o f will only when
the moral demands against which it transgresses are in fact legitimate
and it is reasonable (zumutbar) to expect adherence to them under the
given circumstances. In the revolt of a dissident will, there all too
often also come to expression, as we know, the voice of the other
who is excluded by rigid moral principles, the violated integrity of
human dignity, recognition refused, interests neglected, and differ
ences denied.
Because the principles of a will that has attained autonomy embody
a claim analogous to that associated with knowledge, validity and
genesis once again diverge here as they do in pragmatic discourse.
Thus, behind the facade of categorical validity may lurk a hidden,
15
On the Employments o f Practical Reason
16
On the Employments of Practical Reason
able will, new problems arise. This reality of the alien will belongs to
the primary conditions of collective will formation.
The fact of the plurality of agents and the twofold contingency
under which the reality of one will confronts that of another generate
the additional problem of the communal pursuit of collective goals,
and the problem of the regulation of communal existence under the
pressure of social complexity also takes on a new form. Pragmatic
discourses point to the necessity of compromise as soon as one's own
interests have to be brought into harmony with those of others.
Ethical-political discourses have as their goal the clarification of a
collective identity that must leave room for the pursuit of diverse
individual life projects. The problem of the conditions under which
moral commands are reasonable motivates the transition from mo
rality to law. And, finally, the implementation of goals and programs
gives rise to questions of the transfer and neutral exercise of power.
Modern rational natural law responded to this constellation of
problems, but it failed to do justice to the intersubjective nature of
collective will formation, which cannot be correctly construed as in
dividual will formation writ large. Hence, we must renounce the
premises of the philosophy of the subject on which rational natural
law is based. From the perspective of a theory of discourse, the
problem of agreement among parties whose wills and interests clash
is shifted to the plane of institutionalized procedures and commu
nicative presuppositions of processes of argumentation and negotia
tion that must be actually carried out. 13
It is only at the level of a discourse theory of law and politics that
we can also expect an answer to the question invited by our analyses:
Can we still speak of practical reason in the singular after it has
dissolved into three different forms of argumentation under the
aspects of the purposive, the good, and the right? All of these forms
of argument are indeed related to the wills of possible agents, but as
we have seen, concepts of the will change with the type of question
and answer entertained. The unity of practical reason can no longer
be grounded in the unity of moral argumentation in accordance with
the Kantian model of the unity of transcendental consciousness, for
there is no metadiscourse on which we could fall back to justify the
choice between different forms of argumentation. 14 Is the issue of
whether we wish to address a given problem under the standpoint
17
On the Employments o f Practical Reason
of the purposive, the good, or the just not then left to the arbitrary
choice, or at best the prediscursive judgment, of the individual?
Recourse to a faculty of judgment that "grasps" whether a problem
is aesthetic rather than economic, theoretical rather than practical,
ethical rather than moral, political rather than legal, must remain
suspect for anyone who agrees that Kant had good grounds for
abandoning the Aristotelian concept of judgment. In any case, it is
not the faculty of reflective judgment, which subsumes particular
cases under general rules, that is relevant here but an aptitude for
discriminating problems into different kinds.
As Peirce and the pragmatists correctly emphasize, real problems
are always rooted in something objective. The problems we confront
thrust themselves upon us; they have a situation-defining power and
engage our minds with their own logics. Nevertheless, if each prob
lem followed a unique logic of its own that had nothing to do with
the logic of the next problem, our minds would be led in a new
direction by every new kind of problem. A practical reason that saw
its unity only in the blind spot of such a reactive faculty of judgment
would remain an opaque construction comprehensible only in phe
nomenological terms.
Moral theory must bequeath this question unanswered to the phi
losophy of law ; the unity of practical reason can be realized in an
unequivocal manner only within a network of public forms of com
munication and practices in which the conditions of rational collective
will formation have taken on concrete institutional form.
2
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
Discourse ethics has met with objections directed, on the one hand,
against deontological theories generally and, on the other, against
the particular project of offering an explication of the moral point
of view in terms of universal communicative presuppositions of ar
gumentation . Here I here take up some of these objections and
discuss them in a metacritical fashion by way of explicating once
again, though in an unsystematic fashion, the theoretical program I
share, in its essentials, with Karl-Otto Apel.
In the following sections I shall refer to theses of Bernard Williams,
John Rawls, Albrecht Wellmer, Klaus Gunther, Ernst Tugendhat,
Stephen Lukes, Charles Fried, Charles Taylor, Apel, Thomas Mc
Carthy, Alasdair Macintyre, and Gunther Patzig, discussing in succes
sion the following topics :
respect.
20
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
vtew.
8. The distinction between negative and positive rights and duties.
9. The attempt to develop a postmetaphysical ethics of the good .
21
Remarks o n Discourse Ethics
22
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
23
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
24
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
25
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
26
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
27
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
28
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
29
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
30
Remarks
on
Discourse Ethics
31
32
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
33
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
34
someone who acts against his better judgment must not only face the
moral rebukes of others but is also prey to self-criticism, and thus to
"bad conscience." Hence Wellmer is simply asserting a consequence
of the cognitivist understanding of morality, and not making an
objection against discourse ethics, when he asserts "that the effective
ness of moral arguments remains dependent on preconditions which
are not only cognitive, but also affective in nature. . . . A rational
equivalent to a moral agreement supported by sacred or religious
authority is only possible in so far as a successful adaptation to con
ditions of mutual recognition between persons-in both cognitive and
affective terms-has taken place. " 19
The uncoupling of moral judgment from moral action may initially
appear counterintuitive because judgments of obligations, like asser
toric judgments, are associated with an unconditional validity claim.
We say that moral commands are "right" or "wrong" and understand
this in a sense analogous to truth. It is no coincidence that we speak
of "moral truths" to express the categorical character of normative
validity, but with this validity claim, reason affects a will whose con
tingency consists in its ability to choose to act differently. A will that
lets itself be bound by moral insight, though it could choose otherwise,
is autonomous. Kant mistakenly identified this quality with the act of
liberating the will from all empirical motives. This residuum of Pla
tonism disappears once we abandon the idealistic conception of the
catharsis of a will purging itself of all earthly impurities. Then the
autonomous will is not eo ipso a repressive will that suppresses incli
nations in favor of duties.
Since Schiller, the rigidity of the Kantian ethics of duty has been
repeatedly and rightly criticized. But autonomy can be reasonably
expected (zumutbar) only in social contexts that are already themselves
rational in the sense that they ensure that action motivated by good
reasons will not of necessity conflict with one's own interests. The
validity of moral commands is subject to the condition that they are
universally adhered to as the basis for a general practice. Only when
this condition is satisfied do they express what all could will. Only
then are moral commands in the common interest and-precisely
because they are equally good for all-do not impose supererogatory
demands. To this extent rational morality puts its seal on the abolition
of the victim. At the same time, someone who obeys the Christian
35
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
36
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
37
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
38
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
39
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
40
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
41
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
42
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
43
Remarks
on
Discourse Ethics
44
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
45
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
46
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
47
central feelings of shame and guilt, which are coeval with outrage
and contempt, are not secondary phenomena to the extent that they
are reactions to the violation of legitimate expectations grounded ul
timately in the reciprocity of the structures of recognition underlying
communities in general. In short, Tugendhat confuses genesis and
validity. He is misled by the observation that in the process of social
ization, conscience is formed through the internalization of external
sanctions to suppose that, even from the participant perspective of the
conscientious individual who has been socialized in this manner, be
hind the moral "ought" there is concealed a sanction, the inner
sanction of loss of self-respect, instead of the unforced force of the
good reasons in terms of which moral insights impress themselves on
consciousness as convictions.
The understanding of postconventional morality that Tugendhat
proposes itself reveals the cognitive meaning of the mode of validity
of moral norms, which cannot be analyzed in terms of inner sanctions.
In traditional societies, moral norms are indeed so closely bound up
with religious worldviews and shared forms of life that individuals
learn what it means to enjoy the status of membership in a community
thus founded through identification with the contents of this estab
lished concrete ethical life. But in modern societies, moral norms
must detach themselves from the concrete contents of the plurality
of attitudes toward life that now manifest themselves ; they are
grounded solely in an abstract social identity that is henceforth cir
cumscribed only by the status of membership in some society, not in
this or that particular society. This explains the two salient features
of a secularized morality that has transcended the context of an over
arching social ethos. A morality that rests only on the normative
content of universal conditions of coexistence in a society (founded
on mutual respect for persons) in general must be universalistic and
egalitarian in respect of the validity and sphere of application of its
norms ; at the same time, it is formal and empty in the content of its
norms. But from its formal and empty character there follows a
consequence that is incompatible with a noncognitivist understanding
of morality.
The generalized structure of the reciprocal recognition of subjects
who confront each other simultaneously as nonreplaceable individ
uals and as members of a community henceforth amounts only to
48
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
49
are given their due and can be taken into consideration from the
viewpoint of the participants themselves. The privileged position,
which initially appears to be advantageous because it promises to
liberate the observer from the perspectival interpretations of the
disputing parties, has the disadvantage that it isolates him in a mon
ological fashion from the interpretive horizons of the participants
and denies him hermeneutic access to an intersubjectively shared
moral world that reveals itself only from within.
One who wishes to examine something from the moral point of
view must not allow himself to be excluded from the intersubjective
context of participants in communication who engage in interper
sonal relations and who can understand themselves as addressees of
binding norms only in this performative attitude. Controversial ques
tions of normative validity can be thematized only from the first
person plural perspective, that is, in each instance "by us" ; for nor
mative validity claims are contingent on "our" recognition. We cannot
attain an impartial standpoint by turning our back on the context of
linguistically mediated interaction and by abandoning the participant
perspective completely, but only by extending the individual partici
pant perspective in a universal fashion. 39 Each of us must be able to
place himself in the situation of all those who would be affected by
the performance of a problematic action or the adoption of a ques
tionable norm. What G. H. Mead recommends with his notion of
ideal role taking cannot be performed privately by each individual
but must be practiced by us collectively as participants in a public
discourse.
Once it becomes clear that the goal of such an inclusive process of
communication (uncoerced agreement) can be achieved only through
the mediation of good reasons, the reflective character of what Mead
calls "universal discourse" takes on sharper contours. It should not
be conceived simply as a kind of net of communicative action that
encompasses all potentially affected. On the contrary, as the reflective
form of communicative action, it is a form of argumentation in the
strict sense.
Viewed in this way, Mead's construction loses the quality of a mere
projection, for in every real process of argumentation the participants
unavoidably undertake such a "projection." They must make a prag
matic presupposition to the effect that all affected can in principle
50
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
51
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
52
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
53
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
54
55
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
56
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
57
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
58
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
59
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
60
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
61
Remarks o n Discourse Ethics
62
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
63
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
64
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
65
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
66
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
67
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
68
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
69
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
singly. . . . It is also like a single thing we all share, like the common
thread that runs through each bead in a string. There are aspects of
common humanity which we share because of the efforts of others
to produce them : the fruits of common labour, the security of civil
society, the riches of culture and civilization, the fact of language. "55
If we take these reflections seriously and elaborate them through a
theory of communication, we will no longer accord negative rights
and duties privilege over positive rights and duties on account of
their allegedly categorical character, the determinateness of their
content, or the lack of ambiguity concerning their addressee and his
undifferentiated duty. It is quite sufficient to appeal to a common
process of discursive will formation that subjects all norms to the
same standard-the capacity to command general assent-and se
cures the deontological force of their validity against an unlimited
orientation to consequences by admitting only regulations that are
equally in the interest of all. Only the universalistic privileging of
what is equally good for all brings the moral point of view to bear in
the justification of norms.
9. Thus far I have assumed that the deontological distinction between
the right and the good, as well as the primacy of what is morally
right or obligatory over what is ethically desirable or preferable, are
unproblematic. But this involves a prior determination against the
possibility of construing morality as one aspect of a more compre
hensive ethics of the good and of grounding it within this framework.
This decision may reflect a specifically modern prejudice-thus, at
any rate, argue defenders of classical approaches. Charles Taylor, for
example, claims that the modern morality of justice is based on a
selective understanding of modern identity. Once we grasp the latter
in its full complexity, the underlying ethical strata of competing
fundamental goods, in which the modern principles of justice and
solidarity are rooted in turn, will be uncovered. 56 From this perspec
tive the right loses its primacy over the good ; indeed, the deontolog
ical distinction between questions of justice and questions of the good
itself becomes problematic. By endeavoring to revive the claims of
an ethics of the good under modern conditions, Taylor is disputing
not the universalistic claim of the morality ofjustice but the autonomy
of rational morality. At the same time, he raises the issues of the
70
71
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
72
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
of reasoning, around which they draw a firm boundary. They then are led
to defend this boundary all the more fiercely in that it is their only way of
doing justice to the hypergoods which move them although they cannot
acknowledge them. (88.)
73
74
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
dilemma and knows it. His goal is not merely to describe modern
identity by exploiting the resources of the history of ideas but to
justify the identity outlined as a formation of fundamental orienta
tions that is ineluctable and authoritative for us (and for all other
moderns). An ethics of the good that discloses the order of consti
tutive goods as a publicly accessible reality can realize this ambitious
argumentative goal. But under the premises of postmetaphysical
thinking, this route is closed to us. Arguments will not suffice to open
the eyes of the "value-blind" children of modernity to the efficacy of
the highest goods; that requires the world-disclosing power of an
evaluative language that first lifts the scales from our eyes: "There is
no coherent place left for an exploration of the order in which we
are set as a locus of moral sources, what Rilke, Pound, Lawrence and
Mann were doing in their radically different ways . . . . The order is
only accessible through personal, hence 'subjective', resonance" (5 1 0).
Thus philosophy must pin its hopes on art. Only in aesthetic expe
rience, freed from the spell of anthropocentric thinking, do we en
counter something objective capable of awakening our sense for the
good : "The great epiphanic work actually can put us in contact with
the sources it taps" (5 1 2).
The reflections summarized under (a) through (d) point to a divi
sion of labor among philosophical ethics, art, and aesthetics. But this
evasion reveals the epistemological impasse in which a metaphysical
ethics of the good finds itself. The aesthetic considerations that Taylor
adduces are themselves problematic. In the wake of Adorno and
Derrida, what can be accomplished by modern art can scarcely any
longer be construed as "epiphany. "59 Moreover, Friedrich Schlegel
already saw that what is distinctive of modernity is that the "aesthetic"
tears itself loose from the good and the true. Modern art can no
longer be tapped as a source of the moral. But even if we could
accept an aesthetics that still believes in the ethical relevance of the
world-disclosing power of modernism , its implications for philosophy
would be of a renunciatory nature: it would either have to resign itself
to the role of aesthetic criticism or itself become aesthetic. At any
rate, it would have to abandon any pretension to convince on the
basis of its own arguments. Adorno faced a similar conclusion and
responded to it by developing a negative dialectics. But that does not
75
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
76
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
77
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
78
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
79
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
80
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
81
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
82
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
83
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
84
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
85
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
86
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
87
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
88
Remarks
on
Discourse Ethics
89
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
90
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
his view, a third element comes into play with the will formation of
a pluralistic society, the legitimate compulsion that he illustrates only
by reference to the legal form of an institutionally regulated major
itarian process of decision making. As grounds, he cites primarily the
incommensurability of standards of evaluation, worldviews, evalua
tive languages, and traditions that set narrow limits to the general
ization of interests undertaken in justificatory moral discourses:
The success of Habermas's universalization principle in getting from multi
farious "I want's" to a unified "we will" depends on finding "universally
accepted needs." The argument just sketched suggests that this may not be
possible when there are fundamental divergences in value orientations. The
separation of formal procedure from substantive content is never absolute:
we cannot agree on what is just without some measure of agreement on what
is good. But practical discourse is conceived by Habermas to deal precisely
with situations in which there is an absence of such agreement, that is, when
there is a need to regulate matters concerning which there are conflicting
interests and values, competing conceptions of the good.80
McCarthy knows how this objection could be met within the frame
work of discourse ethics. Need interpretations are not an ultimate
given but depend on intersubjectively shared evaluative languages
and traditions that are not anybody's personal property. Hence, crit
ical revision of the vocabulary in terms of which we interpret our
needs is a public and, where appropriate, discursively negotiable
affair. In modern societies, we are confronted with a pluralism of
forms of life-and a progressively greater individualization of life
projects-that is not only unavoidable but even desirable; and this
makes it ever more improbable, as McCarthy emphasizes, that we will
agree on shared interpretations in such disputes. We can draw less
and less on experiences and straightforward examples that have the
same significance for different groups and individuals. We can count
less and less on the same reasons having the same weight for different
individuals and groups within different systems of relevance.
This fact, however, supports rather than undermines the univer
salistic approach of discourse ethics. The more that principles of
equality gain a foothold in social practice, the more sharply do forms
of life and life projects become differentiated from one another. And
the greater this diversity is, the more abstract are the rules and
91
Remarks o n Discourse Ethics
92
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
93
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
94
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
first instance to the basic structures of society alone; and second, that
it formulates the characteristic political values independent of non
political values and indeed of any specific relationship to them" ( 1 33).
The other presupposition is of a conceptual nature and in this context
deserves special consideration. A postmetaphysical concept of justice
is not compatible with all comprehensive doctrines, only with non
fundamentalistic worldviews : "While an overlapping consensus may
obtain between not unreasonable comprehensive doctrines, when is
a comprehensive doctrine not unreasonable or simply reasonable? A
reasonable doctrine must recognize the burdens of reason" ( 1 39).
Modern world views must accept the conditions of postmetaphysical
thought to the extent that they recognize that they are competing
with other interpretations of the world within the same universe of
validity claims. This reflective knowledge concerning the competition
between equally valid warring "gods and demons" creates an aware
ness of their fallibility and shatters the naivete of dogmatic modes of
belief founded on absolute truth claims. Recognizing the "burdens
of reason" entails knowing that proponents and opponents in the
contest between substantive worldviews may (for the time being) have
equally good grounds for their inability to reach a consensus and for
leaving contentious validity claims undecided. This fallibilism is
grounded in the indeterminacy of discursive procedures, in local
limitations on available information and reasons, and, in general, in
the provinciality of our finite minds regarding the future. Under
these conditions there is no guarantee that a rationally motivated
consensus could always be attained. The idea of "reasonable disagree
ment" permits us to leave truth claims undecided while simulta
neously upholding their unconditional character. One who, with this
in mind, accepts the coexistence of competing worldviews by no
means resigns himself to a mere modv.s vivendi; while upholding his
own validity claims, he simply postpones the possibility of consensus,
kept open in principle, to an indefinite future.
The model that Rawls has in mind is not that of competing para
digms governed by the standards of scientific rationality, and thus
not the fallibility of the empirical sciences, but the uncoupling of
religious creeds from the sanctioning power of the state and their
coexistence under conditions of religious tolerance. But although this
principle can indeed be justified in the original position, it is not the
95
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
one that Rawls must presuppose. What Rawls in fact prejudges with
the concept of an "overlapping consensus" is the distinction between
modern and premodern forms of consciousness, between "reasonable"
and "dogmatic" world interpretations. Modern forms of conscious
ness do not involve renunciation of interpretations of the world as a
whole, and thus of "comprehensive doctrines" as such. They are set
apart by a form of reflexivity that enables us to adopt an external
perspective toward our own traditions and bring them into relation
to other traditions. Whether we can in this way transcend the tradition
in which our identity has been formed depends on a strong premise
that is far from trivial and affords the contextualist an occasion to
make his objection more pointedly. There must be a common basis
on which mutual understanding among alien cultures, belief systems,
paradigms, and life-forms is possible-that is, a translation between
different evaluative languages and not merely communication among
members of the same language group relying on reciprocal observation
of alien cultures. The languages and vocabularies in which we inter
pret our needs and communicate our feelings must be mutually
permeable; they should not be so deeply rooted in monadically self
enclosed contexts that cannot be transcended from within that they
imprison the subjects who have been born and socialized into them.
Rawls can defend the thesis of the primacy of the right over the
good with the concept of an overlapping consensus only if it is true
that postmetaphysical worldviews that have become reflexive under
modern conditions are epistemically superior to dogmatically fixed,
fundamentalistic worldviews-indeed, only if such a distinction can
be made with absolute clarity. Otherwise the disqualification of "un
reasonable" doctrines that cannot be brought into harmony with the
proposed "political" concept of justice is inadmissible. This differ
entiation between a modern and a traditional understanding of the
world is possible only if competing interpretations of the world are
not utterly incommensurable, if we at least intuitively accept context
transcending assumptions concerning rationality that first make pos
sible translations from one context into another. But this is precisely
what is disputed by a strong contextualism for which there is no
single "rationality." On this conception, individual "rationalities" are
correlated with different cultures, worldviews, traditions, or forms of
96
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
97
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
98
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
99
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
1 00
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
101
1 02
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
103
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
1 04
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
1 05
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
1 06
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
actions are directed not only to subjects capable of speech and action
but also to animals. Patzig has the merit of confronting pressing
ecological questions of the protection of animals and the preservation
of species without overstepping the limits of an "ethics without meta
physics." As with the extension of the spectrum of issues of justice to
include questions of the good life, here it is also a matter of supple
menting moral questions in the narrow sense-limited to rational, or
at least potentially rational, subjects-with questions of another kind.
Is there such a thing as responsibility toward nature independent of
responsibility for present and future humanity? What, in particular,
is the nature of our obligation to protect animals?86
Patzig describes the predicament in which an anthropocentric
moral theory finds itself when it attempts to justify the protection of
107
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
with us." But what, then, is the status of duties that impose a deter
minate responsibility on us as addressees of valid norms, not only for
or in respect of animals but toward these animals themselves, if animals
for their part do not belong to the domain of possible addressees of
norms?
Patzig summarily dispenses with the symmetry between duties and
rights that is a conceptually necessary consequence of the reciprocal
recognition of at least potentially free and equal subjects and defines
the status of duties toward animals in an asymmetrical manner: "An
imals do not have duties toward humans, but humans have duties
toward animals. "89 At the same time he opens up the possibility of a
gradation of duties incompatible with the binary encoding of the
mode of validity of strict duties. The greater the sensitivity to pain
of the animals, the more onerous duties should be. But this amounts
to a transformation of the concept of duty; it is no longer a question
of duties in the deontological sense but of the relative preferability
of goods. This suggests that questions of environmental ethics, as
well as ethical questions of how to live one's life, should be treated
from a different perspective-a teleological one-and that only ques
tions of the well-ordered coexistence of persons should be treated in
a deontological manner.
Now the exclusion of ethical questions from the sphere of moral
questions or questions of justice no doubt makes sense because the
question of what is good for me or for us, all things considered, is
already formulated in such a way that it invites an answer whose
claim to validity is relativized to prior life projects and forms of life.
Identity-constitutive values and ideals cannot obligate us in the same
sense as moral norms; they lack the unconditionality of a categorical
ought. But we have a sense of being under categorical obligations
toward animals. The horror inspired by the torment of animals is, at
any rate, more closely related to outrage at the violation of moral
demands than to the pitying or condescending attitude toward people
who, as we are wont to say, have made nothing of their lives or are
failures by their own standards of authenticity. We "ought" not to
neglect animals callously, much less cruelly torment them.
In an attempt to do justice to these intuitions, Patzig tries to connect
the injunction to protect animals, grounded initially in utilitarian
terms, to the deontological theory: "Our theory of rational morality
1 08
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
1 09
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
1 10
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
role (if not completely filled) of a second person, one whom we look
upon as if it were an alter ego. We can adopt a performative attitude
toward many animals, though not toward plants. In that case, they
are no longer objects to be observed by us, or even just objects of
our empathy, but beings who, in their interaction with us, make their
distinctive mode of being felt in a manner different than a rock does
its mineral hardness or a plant does the osmotic interaction of an
organism with its environment. To the extent that animals participate
in our interactions, we enter into a form of contact that goes beyond
one-sided or reciprocal observation because it is of the same kind as an
intersubjective relation.
In making such statements, we must be wary of mystifications.
Interactions between humans and animals are mediated by nonlin
guistic gestures, and the injuries that human beings are capable of
inflicting on an animal do not affect anything resembling a personal
identity-rather, they are a direct assault on its psychophysical integ
rity. Again, an animal does not experience its pain reflexively like a
human being, who in suffering is cognizant of the fact that he i in
pain. These and similar asymmetries characterize the way in which
animals participate in our interactions. At the same time, the inter
actions must satisfy the condition that we should not confront animals
in the objectifying attitude of a third person, nor just communicate
about animals but with them. We must be able to ascribe characteristics
of agents to animals, among others the ability to initiate utterances
and to address them to us. Then we have duties that are analogous
to our moral duties, because like the latter they are rooted in the
presuppositions of communicative action. Of course, they are anal
ogous to moral duties only to the extent that the asymmetries in the
interactions admit comparison with relations of recognition between
persons.
If this justification of interactive duties toward animals by appeal
to a theory of intersubjectivity is not completely wide of the mark,
we can also explain why animals, on the one hand , are rendered
particularly dependent on human beings and in need of protection
by the asymmetrical structure of possible interactions, but why, on
the other, they can enjoy this moral protection only within the inter
subjective horizon of our modes of interaction. Human beings always
find themselves already within this horizon and as persons can never
Ill
Remarks on Discourse Ethics
leave it, whereas animals belong to other species and other forms of
life and are integrated into our forms of life only through partici
pation in our interactions. The limits of our quasi-moral responsibility
toward animals are reached once humans, in their role as members
of one species, confront animals as exemplars of another. However,
it is a tricky moral question to determine in which situations this is
permissible. I do not wish to preclude a priori that some vegetarians
exhibit a moral sensibility that may prove to be the correct moral
intuition under more auspicious social circumstances. In that case
animals would come to be recognized in all situations as possible
participants in interaction, and the protection to which we feel obli
gated in our interactions with animals would be extended to include
protecting their existence.
Human responsibility for plants and for the preservation of whole
species cannot be derived from duties of interaction, and thus cannot
be morally justified.95 Nevertheless, I am in accord with Patzig in
believing that, aside from prudential considerations, there are good
ethical reasons that speak in favor of the protection of plants and
species, reasons that become apparent once we ask ourselves seriously
how, as members of a civilized global society, we want to live on this
planet and how, as members of our own species, we want to treat
other species. In certain respects, aesthetic reasons have here even
greater force than ethical, for in the aesthetic experience of nature,
things withdraw into an unapproachable autonomy and inaccessibil
ity ; they then exhibit their fragile integrity so clearly that they strike
us as inviolable in their own right and not merely as desirable ele
ments of a preferred form of life.
3
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
l l4
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 15
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 16
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 17
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 18
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 19
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
act in accordance with self-imposed laws) are singled out as the sole
morally relevant determinations. The moral point of view necessitates
differentiating between the right and the good. All goods, including
the highest good of my life project or of the form of life to which
we collectively aspire, are deprived of their moral status and are
lumped together with things designed to satisfy contingent needs and
wants ; henceforth, goods fulfill only subjective preferences. In con
trast to the ethics of the good, the morality of justice sets duty and
inclination in conflict with one another. From this opposition there
follow two disturbing consequences:
(a) Viewed from the perspective of classical ethics, practical reason
completely loses its point if moral judgment is restricted to interper
sonal obligations, so that the question of how we should live-as
individuals and members of a community-must be left up to blind
decision or sheer impulse. It was precisely these issues of individual
life projects and collective ways of life that philosophy once promised
to illuminate through reflection. What was held to be essential to
philosophy was that it should help us to lead a reflective life. Must
philosophy now renounce this preeminent task in favor of that of
submitting just one subset of practical questions, questions of justice,
to a more clear-cut standard of judgment?
(b) Second, once the bond between the right and the good is
broken, the question of why one should act morally at all can no
longer be answered satisfactorily. Classical ethics sought to demon
strate that striving for the highest good is compatible with both our
obligations and our true interests. But in Kant's view, free will is
constituted by moral insight alone ; he conceives of autonomy as a
subject's capacity to bind his will and to be guided in action by moral
judgment alone. However, motivation by insight into what is morally
required extends no further than the motivating power of good
reasons. Hence Kant must invest practical reason with the higher
authority of an intelligible world. But if we reject Kant's metaphysical
background assumptions concerning the noumenal and the phenom
enal realms, the question of why we should make the moral point of
view our own, even when it is not in our interest, becomes unavoid
able. The question "Why be moral?" remains open: "The I that stands
back in rational reflection from my desires is still the I that has those
1 20
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
121
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
(3) Seen from the moral point of view, issues of moral cognition
take precedence over questions of practical orientation; problems are
shifted from the existential plane of the concrete practical concern
of socialized individuals regarding their individual and collective lives
to the abstract level of the reflection of isolated subjects on what all
could accept as a law governing their actions. Kantian practical reason
transcends the sphere of validity of traditions and institutions that
are constitutive of the particular life-form of a given collectivity with
its specific practices and customs and concrete virtues and duties.
From this abstraction there follow in turn two unfortunate
consequences :
(a) First, an atomistic conception of the person is presupposed,
since each individual who examines his maxims from the moral point
of view finds himself compelled to go beyond the context of his own
form of life in foro interno if he is to encounter all others as Others,
that is, as isolated individuals. Free will operates in a vacuum, dis
engaged from the social bonds that first invest ethical life with mean
ing. To the atomistic concept of the person who relates to himself as
his own private property there corresponds a contractualist concept
of society that denies any inherent moral quality to a life reduced to
calculations of self-interest: "For a society to be a community in this
strong sense, community must be constitutive of the shared self
understandings of the participants and embodied in their institu
tional arrangements, not simply an attribute of certain of the partic
ipants' plans of life."s
(b) Furthermore, from a contextualist perspective, it is doubtful
whether any concept ofjustice can claim universal validity. Lifeworlds
are totalities that exist only in plural form. But if ethical life is tied
to the specific characteristics of a certain form of life, then every
concept of good and evil, however abstract, is affected and shaped
by the intu itive preunderstanding embodied in the concrete totality
of moral conceptions dominant in a particular place. Concepts of
justice cannot be separated from the complex totality of a concrete
ethical life and a particular idea of the good life. This is why in
Macintyre's view "the Enlightenment project of justifying morality"
had to fail. 9 The conceptions of an autonomous morality developed
by Rousseau and Kant in the eighteenth century also seem to remain
tied to the period from which they arose. Already in their basic core
122
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 23
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelia nism
1 24
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 25
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 26
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 27
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 28
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 29
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 30
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
131
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
1 32
Lawrence Kohlberg and Neo-Aristotelianism
4
To Seek to Salvage an Unconditional Meaning
Without God Is a Futile Undertaking:
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
1 34
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
1 35
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
1 36
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
137
Reflections o n a Remark o f Max Horkheimer
The rational sublation of theology and its essential contents : how can
this still be accomplished in the present day, in the light of the
irreversible critique of metaphysics, without destroying the import of
religious doctrines or of reason itself ? With this question Hork
heimer, the pessimistic materialist, appeals to Schopenhauer, the
pessimistic idealist. On Horkheimer's surprising interpretation, Scho
penhauer's enduring importance lies in the fact that his thorough
going negativism salvages the "spirit of the Gospels." According to
Horkheimer, Schopenhauer accomplished the improbable feat of
providing an atheistic justification of the morality underlying theol
ogy, and thus of preserving religion in the absence of God.
In the world as will and representation, Horkheimer discerns, first,
the sterile Darwinian operation of instrumental reason degraded to
a tool of self-preservation, which-up to and including a globally
objectifying scientific intellect-is dominated by a blind and indefa
tigable will to life that pits one subject against another. On the other
hand, precisely this reflection on the abysmally negative ground of
being is supposed to awaken in subjects who seek remorselessly to
dominate one another some inkling of their common fate and an
awareness that all manifestations of life are pervaded by an identical
will : " If the realm of appearances, sensible reality, is not the work of
1 38
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
1 39
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
140
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
141
Reflections o n a Remark o f Max Horkh eimer
1 42
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
143
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
1 44
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
for us-in other words, a reconciliation that does not efface differ
ences. Horkheimer is by no means deaf to this promise of reconcili
ation inherent in language itself. At one point he puts it trenchantly:
"Language, whether it wants to or not, must lay claim to truth."25 He
also recognizes that we have to take into account the pragmatic di
mension of language use, for the context-transcending truth-claim
of speech cannot be grasped from the blinkered perspective of a
semantics that reduces utterances to propositions : "Truth in speech
is not properly predicated of detached, naked judgments, as though
printed on a piece of paper, but of the conduct of the speaker toward
the world that is expressed in the judgment and concentrates itself
in this place."26 What Horkheimer has in mind is clearly the theolog
ical tradition, extending from Augustine through logos mysticism to
radical Protestantism, that appeals to the originary character of the
divine Word and to language as the medium of the divine message
to man : "But theological metaphysics is in the right against positivism,
because no proposition can avoid raising the impossible claim, not
merely to an anticipated result, to success, as positivism maintains,
but to truth in the proper sense, regardless of whether the speaker
reflects on it or not."27 Prayer, in which the believer seeks contact
with God, would lose its categorial difference from incantation and
regress to the level of magic if we confused the illocutionary force of
our assertions with their perlocutionary effects, as does the unreal
izable program of linguistic nominalism.
But these insights remain sporadic. Horkheimer fails to treat them
as clues to a language-pragmatical explanation of the unconditional
meaning associated with unavoidable truth claims. His skepticism to
ward reason is so thoroughgoing that he can no longer see room for
communicative action in the world as it is now constituted : "Today
talk has become stale and those who do not want to listen are not
altogether wrong . . . . Speaking has had its day. Indeed so has action,
at least insofar as it was once related to speech. "2 8
v
His pessimistic diagnosis of the times is not the only reason that
Horkheimer refrains from seriously entertaining the question of how
something we accomplish on a daily basis-orienting our action to
1 45
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
1 46
Reflections on a Remark of Max Horkheimer
5
Morality, Soc iety, and Ethics : An Interview
with Torben Hviid Nielsen
Torben Hviid Nielsen: The main topic of discussion will be your views
on moral theory and ethics, particularly in the form they have as
sumed since the publication of Theorie des kommunikativen Handelns in
1 98 1 . 1 In the first part we will concentrate on the concept of morality
and the relation between justice, law, and care. The second part will
deal with questions concerning the universal-pragmatic justification
of discourse ethics. The focus will be on the validity of norms, the
status of the so-called ideal speech situation, and the differentiation
between the justification of norms and the procedure of democratic
will formation. And in the third part we will discuss morality and
ethics in relation to the notions of system and lifeworld.
I
THN: How should we understand the development that has led you
from the sociological critique of the pathologies of modernity in The
Theory of Communicative Action to the moral theory developed in Moral
Consciousness and Communicative Action2 and the subsequent series of
articles and lectures? Can discourse ethics be seen as a philosophical
answer, from the perspective of the individual, to the sociological
question of the proper, nonpathological relation between system and
lifeworld in the modern world? Why have you concentrated since
1 98 1 on issues in philosophical ethics rather than on this sociological
question left open in Theory of Communicative Action ?
148
Morality, Society, and Ethics
149
Morality, Society, and Ethics
1 50
Morality, Society, and Ethics
151
Morality, Society, and Ethics
1 52
Morality, Society, and Ethics
I agree entirely with this statement though not with the con
sequences Walzer wishes to draw from it.
That a norm is just or in the general interest means nothing more
than that it is worthy of recognition or is valid. Justice is not some
thing material, not a determinate "value," but a dimension of validity.
Just as descriptive statements can be true, and thus express what is
the case, so too normative statements can be right and express what
has to be done. Individual principles or norms that have a specific
content are situated on a different level, regardless of whether they
are actually valid.
For example, different principles of distributive justice exist. There
are material principles of justice, such as "To each according to his
needs" or "To each according to his merits" or "Equal shares for all."
Principles of equal rights, such as the precepts of equal respect for
all, of equal treatment, or of equity in the application of the law,
address a different kind of problem. What is at issue here is not the
distribution of goods or opportunities but the protection of freedom
and inviolability. Now all of these principles of justice can be justified
from the perspective of universalizability and can claim prima facie
validity. But only in their application to particular concrete cases will
it transpire which of the competing principles is the most appropriate
in the given context.
This is the task of discourses of application. Within the family, for
instance, conflicts of distribution will tend to be decided on the prin
ciple of need rather than on the principle of merit, whereas the
situation may well be the reverse in cases of conflicts of distribution
at the level of society as a whole. It depends on which principle best
fits a given situation in the light of the most exhaustive possible
description of its relevant features. But I find the idea of a universal
correlation of principles of justice with spheres of action highly prob
lematic. The kinds of considerations Walzer entertains could be ac
commodated in discourses of application, but then they would have
to prove themselves in each particular instance in its own right.
JH:
1 53
Morality, Society, and Ethics
the good life and as such admit of rational treatment only within the
horizon of a concrete historical form of life or an individual life
history). But do you in fact exclude the possibility of congruence
between justice and the good life? John Rawls, who also maintains
the priority of the right over the good, presupposes the possibility of
such congruence at least under the conditions of a "well-ordered
society." He takes the view that a moral theory should specify how
the right and the good are related to each other.9
1 54
Morality, Society, and Ethics
155
Morality, Society, and Ethics
]H:
1 56
Morality, Society, and Ethics
1 57
Morality, Society, and Ethics
158
Morality, Society, and Ethics
1 59
Morality, Society, and Ethics
1 60
Morality, Society, and Ethics
161
Morality, Society, and Ethics
162
Morality, Society, and Ethics
to you in an interview with the New Left Review and that has remained
unanswered: "How do you conceive the relation between philosoph
ical and scientific truth-claims? Are philosophical truth-claims cog
nitive claims, and would a rational consensus ultimately guarantee
the truth of a consensus theory of truth itself ?"16
163
Morality, Society, and Ethics
1 64
Morality, Society, and Ethics
1 65
Morality, Society, and Ethics
1 66
Morality, Society, and Ethics
place you have explained how your expression norm{ree sociality has
led to misunderstandings. Even after the modern uncoupling of
system and lifeworld, system integration remains indirectly connected
with the lifeworld through the legal institutionalization of the steering
media. You claim only that the integration of the subsystems is not
"in the final instance" dependent on the socially integrative accom
plishments of communicative action. You write: "It is not the illocu
tionary binding effects [of speech acts] but steering media that hold
the economic and administrative action systems together."22 This an
swer makes your position more flexible, but you still maintain that
the media of money and power demand that the agent adopt a
strategic attitude. I have my doubts about this.
Your picture of the economic actor shares important traits with
the model of neoclassical economic theory. Why do you neglect the
arguments developed by institutionalist economic theory to demon
strate that the model of purely strategic and utilitarian action died
out at the latest with Adam Smith's "invisible hand"? Amitai Etzioni's
most recent book offers numerous arguments and copious evidence
for the claim that "the most important bases of choices [also in the
market] are affective and normative. That is, people often make non
or subrational choices, first because they build on their normative
affective foundations, and only secondly because they have weak and
limited intellectual capabilities."23
]H: I think that this is a misunderstanding. I use "system" and
"lifeworld" as concepts for social orders that differ in their mecha
nisms of societal integration, that is, in the intermeshing of interac
tions. In "socially integrated" spheres of action, this interlinking or
sequential ordering is achieved either through the intentions of the
agents themselves or through their intuitive background understand
ing of the lifeworld ; in "systemically integrated" spheres of action,
order is generated objectively, "over the heads of the participants" as
it were, through the functional interlocking and reciprocal stabiliza
tion of consequences of action of which the agents need not be aware.
The concept of the lifeworld must be introduced in the context of a
theory of action. But only if the concept of system were introduced
in a similar manner could one establish the dear, reversible relation
167
Morality, Society, and Ethics
THN: You have taken over the concepts of the state as a system
and power as a medium from Talcott Parsons, both of which entail
the separation of politics and administration. Thomas McCarthy has
criticized this separation as contrary to both empirical investigations
and your own concept of democracy: "If self-determination, political
equality, and the participation of citizens in decision-making pro
cesses are the hallmarks of true democracy, then a democratic gov
ernment could not be a political system in Habermas's sense."24 You
have emphasized that the democratic state cannot be reduced to
positive law. I n the case of civil disobedience, legality must even be
abrogated in favor of those who must ultimately safeguard the legit
imacy of government-the citizens.25 But how can civil disobedience
be interpreted in this way without abandoning the separation of
politics and administration underlying the concepts of the state as
system and of power as a medium?
]H: I do not regard processes of legitimation per se as part of the
administrative system regulated by power; they unfold in the political
public sphere. Here, two opposed tendencies meet and intersect:
communicatively generated power proceeding from democratic pro
cesses of opinion formation and will formation (Hannah Arendt)
runs up against the production of legitimation by (and for) the ad-
1 68
Morality, Society, and Ethics
THN: How can power be compared with money, even if the former
is understood as a steering medium? In The Theory of Communicative
Action you enumerate (again following Parsons) differences in mea
surement, circulation, and storage that exist between the two media
but then maintain that both would equally make action coordination
independent of the resources of the lifeworld. Yet the mode of in
stitutionalization of power in the lifeworld exhibits significant dissim
ilarities from that of money. Thus, obedience is the appropriate
attitude toward administrative power, whereas the market calls for
an orientation to enlightened self-interest. The respective attitudes
1 69
Morality , Society, and Ethics
JH: The contradictio n you have just set forth can be resolved as
follows. The two media, money and power, function in a symmetrical
fashion insofar as they serve to hold together differentiated, self
regulating action systems independent of any intentional effort, and
thus of the coordinating activity, of actors. They behave asymmetri
cally in respect of their mode of dependency on the lifeworld, though
both are legally institutionalized and hence anchored in the lifeworld.
Whereas the capitalist economy also subsumes the production pro
cess, including labor power (as the substrate that generates exchange
values), the democratic state apparatus remains dependent on the
repeated provision of legitimation over which it can never gain com
plete control through the exercise of administrative power. Here com
municatively produced power constitutes a substrate that can never
be cut off from the roots of discursive-and to that extent, admin
istratively nonregulable-processes of public opinion formation and
will formation to the same extent that production steered by market
forces can be severed from lifeworld contexts of active labor.
On the other hand, this asymmetry should not mislead us into
thinking that the administrative system can be subsumed under life
world categories. It is indeed a necessary condition of the possibility
of making demands on the administrative system in the name of
imperatives originating in the lifeworld; and the latter, in contrast to
consumer decisions, do not have to be formulated from the outset in
the language of the steering medium in question, that is, in prices
and institutional directions, in order to become "comprehe nsible" to
the corresponding system. This can be seen from the different atti
tudes that politics and admini stration take toward law-respectively,
a normative and a more instrum ental one. 26 The a dministrative sys
tem treats law primarily in an instrumental fashion; what counts from
the perspective of administrative power is not the practical reason
employed in the justification or application of norms but rather ef
ficiency in the implementation of a program in part laid down and
in part developed by the ad ministrative system itself. The normative
1 70
Morality, Society, and Ethics
171
Morality, Society, and Ethics
172
Morality, Society, and Ethics
1 73
Morality, Society, and Ethics
their orientatio n from the telos of one's own life."30 You also intro
duce maxims of action as a kind of bridge between morality and
ethics "because they can be judged alternately from ethical and moral
points of view."3 1 How are maxims related to normative validity
claims? Don't maxims somehow claim empirical and normative valid
ity simultaneously?
1 74
Morality, Society, and Ethics
THN: You defend ethical cognitivism against skeptics but leave the
consideration of moral feelings to one side. But these come into play
once more, at the very latest, in the application of norms. What is
the status of moral feelings? Don't feelings and "habits of the heart"
have intrinsic worth? Or do they merely have a catalytic function in
the development of moral consciousness and become superfluous
once a certain level of moral competence has been reached?
JH:
1 75
Morality, Society, and Ethics
1 76
Morality, Society, and Ethics
Chapter l
l . Ursula Wolf, Das Problem des moralischnl Sollens (B erli n , 1984).
2. Hans Albert, Treatise on Critical Reason, trans. M. V. Rorty (Prince ton , N.j., 1985).
3. Charles Taylor, "The Concept of a Person," in Philosophical Papers (New
1:97ff.
York, 1985)
in Probleme
8. Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. L. W. Beck (New York, 1959),
p. 42 [425]. [Numbers in brackets in quotations from Kant refer throughout to the
pagination of the Prussian Academy edition-Trans.]
9. Cf. Tullio Maranhao, Therapeutic Discourse and Socratic DitJWgue (M adison , Wis.,
1986).
10. Karl-Otto A pe!, "The a priori of the Communication Community and the Foun
dations of Ethics," in Towards a Transformation of Philosophy, tra ns . G. Adey &: D. Frisby
(London, 1980), pp. 225ff.
1 78
Notes
13. Here I part company with Karl-Otto Apel and his "principle of complementarity"
(cf. below, chapter 2, pp. 84ff.); see also Jiirgen Habermas, "Volkssouveriinitat als
Verfahren," in Forum fUr Philosophie (ed.), Die ldeen von 1 798 in der deutschen Rezeption
(Frankfurt, 1 989), pp. 7-36.
1 4. This objection is raised by Martin See) in Die Kunst der Entzweiung (Frankfurt,
1 976).
Chapter 2
I . Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. L. W. Beck (New York, 1959),
p. 20 [403-404] .
2. Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass., 1 985).
3. Williams, Ethics, p. 163.
4. Williams, Ethics, p. 200.
5 . See the remarks on the type of discussion pursued on the basis on mutual trust in
Williams, Ethics, pp. 1 70f.
6. Williams, Ethics, p. 172.
7. Williams, Ethics, p. 1 52. For criticism of Williams's conception of science, cf. Hilary
Putnam, Realism with a Human Face (Cambridge, Mass., 1 990), pp. 1 63- 1 78.
8. John Rawls, A Theory ofJustice (Cambridge, Mass., 1971).
9. john Rawls, "Kantian Constructivism in Moral Theory," Journal of Philosophy (Sep
tember 1 980), p. 5 1 9.
1 0. john Rawls, ''justice
as
11. "[I]t was an error in Theory [of Justice] and a very misleading one, to describe a
theory of justice as part of the theory of rational choice, as on pp. 16 and 583. What
I should have said is that the conception of justice as fairness uses an account of
rational choice subject to reasonable conditions to characterize the deliberation of the
parties as representatives of free and equal persons." Rawls, ':Justice as Fairness,"
p. 237, n. 20.
1 2. Rawls, "justice as Fairness," p. 223. With the shifting of normative premises from
the procedure to the concept of the person already undertaken in the Dewey Lectures,
Rawls presents an unprotected flank to the familiar neo-Aristotelian objections. Cf.
Michael I. Perry, Morality, Politics, and Law (Oxford, 1 988), pp. 57ff.
1 3 . For a discourse-theoretical interpretation of Rawlsian constructivism, see Kenneth
Baynes, The Normative Grounds of Social Criticism: Kant, Rawls and Habermas (New York,
1 99 1 ) , pp. 68-76.
1 4. Gadamer makes the connection between philosophical hermeneutics and a histor
ically informed Aristotelian ethics : " U ber die Moglichkeit einer philosophischen
1 79
Notes
Ethik," in Kleine Schriften I (Tubingen, 1 967), pp. 1 79ff. ; cf. Ernst Tugendhat, "Antike
und Modeme Ethik," in Probleme der Ethik (Stuttgart, 1 984), pp. 33ff.
1 5 . Albrecht Wellmer, The Persistence of Modernity, trans. D. Midgley (Cambridge, Mass.,
1 99 1 ), p. 1 85.
1 6. For a critical discussion of important aspects of Wellmer's study, see Lutz Wingert,
"Moral und Gemeinsinn" (Dissertation, Frankfurt, 1 99 1 ).
1 7. In the original edition of Moralbewufttsein und lwmmuniMtives Handeln (Frankfurt,
1 983), pp. 1 02f., I employed an overly strong notion of normative justification. This
error has been corrected in subsequent German editions and in the English edition :
Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action, trans. C. Lenhardt and S. W. Nicholsen
(Cambridge, Mass., 1 990), pp. 92f.
1 8. A detailed proposal for carrying through this justification is outlined by William
Rehg, "Discourse and the Moral Point of View: Deriving a Dialogical Principle of
Universalization," Inquiry 34 ( 1 99 1 ) , pp. 27-48.
1 9. Wellmer, Persistence, p. 225. The same holds of the well-founded objection that
Gunther Patzig raises against the more comprehensive claims of K. 0. Ape!; cf. Patzig,
"Principium diiudicationis und Principium executionis," in Gerold Prauss, Handlung
stheorie und Transzendentalphilosophie (Frankfurt, 1 986), pp. 204ff., especially pp. 2 1 4ff.
20. Wellmer, Persistence, p. 1 55.
2 1 . Cf. Klaus Gunther, Der Sinn fur Angemessenheit (Frankfurt, 1 988), pp. 23-1 00.
22. Gunther, Der Sinn, p. 62.
23. Gunther, Der Sinn, p. 50.
24. Gunther, Der Sinn, p. 53.
25. Gunther, Der Sinn, pp. 55ff.
26. Cf. also Gunther, "Ein normativer Begriff der Koharenz fUr eine Theorie der
juristischen Argumentation," Rechtstheorie 20 ( 1 989), pp. 1 63-1 90.
27. Gunther, "Ein normativer Begriff," p. 182.
28. On Durkheim, cf. Jurgen Habermas, Theory of Communicative Action, trans. T.
McCarthy (Boston , 1 987}, 2 :43ff.
29. I have discussed Tugendhat's Gauss Lectures in another context (Habermas [ 1 990] ,
pp. 68ff.). Here I refer t o the "Retractions" in Tugendhat, Probleme der E thik, pp. 1 321 76, and to his contribution to the Fahrenbach Festschrift, "Zum Begriff und zur
Begrundu ng von Moral," in C. Bellut and Muller-SchOll (eds.), Mensch und Moderne
(Wurzburg, 1 989}, pp. 1 45- 1 63. The transitional view between the earlier and later
positions is represented by an interesting manuscript, "A New Conception of Moral
Philosophy" ( 1 987).
30. Tugendhat, "Zum Begriff und zur Begrundung von Moral," p. 1 46.
1 80
Notes
3 1 . Tugendhat, "Zum Begriff und zur Begrii ndung von Moral," p. 147.
32. Tugendhat, "Zum Begriff und zur Begrundung von Moral," p. 1 63.
33. Tugendhat, "Retractions," pp. 1 56ff.
34. Cf. the thoroughgoing critique developed by Wingert, "Moral und Gemeinseinn."
35. Cf. Tugendhat, "A New Conception of Moral Philosophy."
36. Tugendhat, "Zum Begriff und zur Begriindung von Moral," pp. 1 58f.
37. Tugendhat, "Zum Begriff und zur Begrundung von Moral," p. 1 57.
38. Tugendhat, "Zum Begriff und zur Begrundung von Moral," p. 1 59.
39. The first-person plural perspective cannot be replaced, or even circumscribed, by
an alternation between the first- and third-person perspectives. Thomas Nagel, whose
thought is situated within the theoretical framework of the philosophy of the subject,
confuses the standpoint of impartial judgment of moral questions with the "external
standpoint" of an observer in The View from Nowhere (Oxford, 1 986), pp. 1 38ff. This
premise generates a dilemma between an objectivistic neutralization of the spheres of
value-" If we push the claims of objective detachment to their logical conclusion, and
survey the world from a standpoint completely detached from all interests, we discover
that there is nothing-no values left of any kind : things can be said to matter at all
only to individuals within the world" (p. 1 46)-and the subjectivistic dissolution of
commands and values into preferences. Nagel believes that he can escape this dilemma
through a procedure of expanding the subjective perspective by reflective integration
of objective knowledge: "We simply aim to reorder our motives in a direction that will
make them more acceptable from an external standpoint. Instead of bringing our
thoughts into accord with an external reality, we try to bring an external view into the
determination of our conduct" (p. 1 39). But preserving the connection to the first
person perspective prejudices the view in favor of ethical issues and closes off the
dimension of moral judgment. Nagel cannot deal with the "obscure topic of deonto
logical constraints" (p. 1 75), as can be seen from his counterintuitive treatment of the
example on pp. 1 76ff.
40. See, for example, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, p. 48, n. 1 4 [430].
4 1 . Cf. Karl-Otto Apel, Charles S. Peirce: From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism, trans. J. M .
Krois (Amherst, Mass., 1 98 1 ), and "Sprachliche Bedeutung, Wahrheit und normative
GUitigkeit," Archivio di Filosofia 55 ( 1 987), pp. 5 1-88; also C. J. Misak, Truth and the
End of Inquiry (Oxford, 1 99 1 ).
42. Cf. Robert Alexy, "Probleme der Diskurstheorie," Zeitschrift fur Philosophische For
schung 43 ( 1 989), pp. 8 1-93.
43. Stephen Lukes, "Of Gods and Demons," in John B. Thompson and David Held
(eds.), Habermas-Critical Debates (Cambridge, Mass., 1 982), p. 1 4 1 .
44. Williams, Ethics, p . 1 97.
45. Cf. B. Peters, Rationalitiit, Recht und Gesellschaft (Frankfurt, 1 99 1 ), pp. 227ff.
181
Notes
46. Cf. R. Alexy, "Nachwort" to the new edition of Theorie der juristischen Argumentation
(Frankfurt, 1 99 1 ), pp. 399ff. [In English: A Theory of Legal Argumentation, trans. P.
Adler and N. McCormick (New York, 1 989).]
of life while, on the other, linking the coeXIStence of these life-forms to forms of
communication in which it is not difficult to discern the existence of a moral principle,
whose neutrality Perry nevertheless denies: "If one can participate in politics and law
.
1 82
Notes
1 83
Notes
83. John Rawls, "Justice a s Fairness : A Briefer Restatement" (ms 1 989) (page refer
ences in parentheses are to this text). Cf. also Rawls "justice as Fairness."
.,
84. Alasdair Macintyre, Whose justice? Which RationalityP (Notre Dame, Ind., 1 988) .
Page references to this book are noted parenthetically in the text.
85. Gunther Patzig, Ethik ohne Metaphysik, 2d ed. (GOtti ngen 1 983), p. 132.
,
86. D. Birnbacher, "Sind wir fii r die Natur verantwortlich?" in Okologie und Ethik
(Stuttgart, 1 980), p. 72.
87. Gunther Patzig, " O kologische Ethik-innerhalb der Grenzen blo8er Vernunft" in
H. J . Elster (ed.), Umweltschutz-Herausforderun unser Generation ( Stdienzentru m
Weikersheim, 1 984), 67. In Ethik ohne Metaphysik Pawg defends a Kanban approach
in ethics that incorporates utilitarian arguments.
88. Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Government (Oxford,
1 789), chap. 1 7, I, sec. 4, footnote.
89. Patzig, " O kologische Ethik," p. 74.
90. Patzig, " O kologische Ethik," p. 7 3.
9 1 . Patzig, " Okologische Ethik." p. 7.
92. Gunther Patzig, "Der wissenscha ftliche Tierversuch unte r ethischen Aspekten" in
W. Hardegg and G. Preiser (eds.), Tierversuch und medizinische Ethik (Hildesheim, 1 986),
p. 77.
1 84
Notes
93. Cf. Joel Feinberg, "The Rights of Animals and Unborn Generations," in William
T. Blackstone (ed.), Philosophy and Environmental Crisis (Athens, Ga., 1 974), pp. 43-68.
Chapter 3
1 85
Notes
23. Klaus Gunther, Der Sinn fur Angemessenheit (Fra nkfurt, 1 988), pp. 255ff.
24. Alan Gewirth, Reason and Morality (Chicago, 1 978).
25 . Robert Selman, The Growth of Interpersonal Understanding (New York, 1 980) ; "ln
terpersonale Verhandlungen," in W. Edelstein and J . Habermas (eds.), Soziale lnter
aktion und soziales Verstehen (Frankfurt, 1 984), pp. 1 1 3ff.
3. GS, 7 :393.
4. Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. J.
Cumming (New York, 1 972), p. 1 1 8.
1 2 . GS, 7 : 1 78.
1 3. "Theismus-Atheismus," GS, 7 : 1 85ff.
Notes
1 4 . GS, 7 : 1 84.
1 5. "Religion und Philosophie," GS, 7 : 193.
16. "Die Aktualitiit Schopenhauers," GS, 7 : 1 36.
17. Schmidt, Die Wahrheit im Gewande der Liige, p. 1 2 1 .
1 8 . "Religion und Philosophie," GS, 7 : 1 9 1 .
1 9 . "Die Aktualitat Schopenhauers," GS, 7 : 1 38f.
20. GS, 7 : 1 35f.
2 1 . "Schopenhauers Denken," GS, 7 : 252.
22. "Pessimismus Heute," GS, 7 :227f.
23. Horkheimer and Adorno, Dialectic, p. 1 0 1 .
24. "Psalm 9 1 ," GS, 7 : 2 1 0.
25. Horkheimer, Notiun, p. 26.
26. Horkheimer, Notiun, p. 1 72.
27. "Die Aktualitiit Schopenhauers," GS, 7 : 1 38.
28. Horkheimer, Notizen, p. 26.
Chapter 5
1 87
Notes
9. Cf. John Rawls, A Theory ofJustice (Cambridge, Mass. , 1 97 1 ), pp. 446, 567ff.
1 0. Cf. Carol Gilligan, In a Different Voice (Cambridge, Mass. , I 982) .
I I . Seyla Benhabib, "The Generalized and the Concrete Other," in Seyla Benhabib
and Drucilla Cornell (eds.), Feminism and Critique (Minneapolis, I 987), pp. 77-96.
12. Cf. Benjamin Lee Whorf, Language, Thought and Reality (Cambridge, Mass. , I 973).
I3. Wolfgang Schluchter, The Rise of Western Rationalism (Berkeley, I 98 I ) , pp. 6ff.
I 4 . Cf. Anne Colby and Lawrence Kohlberg, The Measurement of Moral Judgment (Cam
bridge, 1 987), vol. I .
I 5 . Cf. Habermas, Communication and the Evolution of Society, trans. T. McCarthy (Bos
ton , I 979), p. I 20.
I 6. Cf. Habermas, Autonomy and Solidarity: Interviews with Jilrgen Habermas, ed. Peter
Dews (London, I 986), p. 1 60.
17. See Habermas, Moral Consciousness, p. 80.
1 8. Habermas, Moral Consciousness, p. 92.
1 9. Habermas, "Theory of Communicative Action," 2 : I 49-I 50.
20. Cf. Wolfang Schluchter, Religion und Lehensfilhrung. Studien zu Max Wehers Kultur
und Werttheorie (Frankfurt, I 988), I : 322-323.
2 1 . Cf. Habermas), Vorstudien, p . I 26 n. 94 ; also "A Reply to My Critics," in John B.
Thompson and David Held (eds.), Habermas-Critical Debates (Cambridge, Mass., I 982),
pp. 26 1 .
22. "A Reply," in Axel Honneth and Hans Joas (eds.), Communicative Action (Cambridge,
Mass., I 9 9 I ) , p. 257.
23. Cf. Amitai Etzioni, The Moral Dimension (New York, I 988), p. 90.
24. Thomas McCarthy, "Complexity and Democracy, or the Seducements of Systems
Theory," New German Critique (Spring, I 985), p. 44.
25. Cf. Habermas, "Civil Disobedience : Litmus Test for the Democratic Constitutional
State," Berkeley Journal of Sociology 30 ( I 985), p. I 06.
26. Cf. Jiirgen Habermas, "Volkssouveranitiit als Verfahren," in Forum fiir Philosophie
(ed.), Die ldeen von 1 798 (Frankfurt, I 989), pp. 28f.
27. Cf. Habermas : " U ber Moralitat und Sittlichkeit," in H. Schnadelbach (ed.), Ration
alitii.t (Frankfurt, I 984), p. 228; also Moral Consciousness, pp. 207ff.
28. Habermas, "On the Concept of 'Practical Reason,"' Howison Lecture, ms. (Uni
versity of California, Berkeley, I 988), p. I 9. This lecture appears as the first chapter
of this book (cf. above p. I 3).
1 88
Notes
29. Cf. Klaus Gunther, "Ein normativer Begriff der Koharenz," Rechtstheorie 20 ( 1 989):
163-1 90.
30. Cf. p. 6.
3 1 . Cf. p. 7.
32. Habermas, Autonomy and Solidarity, p. 1 60.
logic of, 29
modeJ of, 27
moriD, 1 6, 24, 33, 1 29, 158
network of, 89
normative content of, 30
normative presuppositions of, 33
participants in, 5 7
practice of, 67
presuppositions of, 32, 59, 77, 82, 8486, 1 3 1 , 1 64
procedure of, 58
rationality assumptions of, 3 1
rules of, 32, 76, 1 59
self-clarification of, 80
self-referential, 79, 83
self-reflexive, 93
shifting terrain of, 30
and social roles, 1 60
spontaneous, 57
transcendental constraints on, 3 1
transcendental-pragmatic, 77, 83
and truth claims, 59
universal presuppositions of, 50, 1 63
world-disclosing, 79
Argumentative praxis, 1, 77, 1 3 1
Arguments, deductive, 59
Aristotelian ethics, 1 1 8, 1 25
Aristotle, 1 0, 1 7 , 2 1 , 24, 96, 1 1 6- 1 1 7,
1 32, 1 50, 1 73
Art, 73-74
1 90
Index
191
I ndex
intersubjective, 6, 23, 47
and normative validity, 1 1 9- 1 22
plurality of, 22
prefiguration of, 1 64
of real individuals, 92-93, 95-97
and universalism, 1 5
universally valid , 8
utopian, 79
Formalism, 1 22 , 145
Frankena, William, 1 1 5
Free will, 27, 40, 1 2 1
Freedom, 1 , 1 5 , 42-43 , 6 1 , 66-68, 1 39
French revolution, 1 39
Fried, Charles, 1 9 , 65-66, 68
Gadamer, Hans-Georg, 1 04- 1 05
Gehlen, Arnold, 22
Genealogy, 7 1
Genetic structuralism, 30
Gert, Bernard, 62, 65, 67
Gewirth, Alan, 1 50
Gilligan, Carol, 1 53-1 54
Goals, 3, 1 1
God , 73, 1 3 7
Go od , 2, 4, 2 1 , 73, 1 1 9
Good life, 2, 4, 1 1 7 , 1 2 1 , 1 26
Guilt, 1 4 , 40, 47
Gunther, Klaus, 19, 36-38, 1 72
coherence concept of, 39
on impartiality, 58
Der Sinn fur Angemessenheit, 1 54
Habermas, Jiirgen, 89, 90
Howison Lecture of 1 988, 1 72
Legitimation.sprobleme im Spatkapitalismus,
1 48
Moral Consciousness and Communicative
Action, 1 47-1 48, 1 63, 1 7 1
The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity,
1 49-1 50
on suppressed generalizable interests,
1 48
on system, 167
The Tlieory of Communicative Action, 14 71 48, 1 50, 1 63 , 1 68, 1 70
Hare, R. M., 1 1 5
Hegel, G. W. F., 1 , 1 30, 1 36, 149, 1 65 ,
171
Heidegger, Martin, 30
Heller, Agnes, 1 76
History, 39, 85
Hobbes, Thomas, 7 , 27
Horkheimer, Max, 1 33- 1 46
The Dialectic of Enlightenment (with
Theodor Adorno), 142
on the good, 1 34
1 92
Index
1 93
I ndex
1 94
Index
legal, 88
moral, 47
noncoercive binding force of, 4 1
obligatory character of, 3 3
Objectification, 22, 25
Objectivity, 13, 26
Obligation, 4 1
Ontotheology, 1 36
Orwell, George, 1 40
Paine, Thomas, 1 1 4
Paradigm shift, 99
Parsons, Talcott, 1 67- 1 68
Participant perspective, 22, 49
Participation, 68
Patzig, Gunther 1 9, 1 05, 1 08, 1 1 1
on duties towards animals, 1 07
on ecological questions, 1 06
Peirce, Charles Sanders, 1 7 , 29-30, 50,
52-53, 58, 1 1 3, 1 30, 1 45, 1 65
on pragmatics of language, 1 45
on truth, 53, 1 45
Perelman, Chaim, 54
Performative attitude, 1 3 , 25, 49, 55, 66,
131
Performative self-contradiction, 33, 56,
1 00, 1 38, 1 62
Perlocutionary effects, 1 44
Person, 23, 60, 62, 66-68
atomistic conception of, 1 2 1 , 1 30
concept of the, 28, 60, 1 30
Philosophy, 23, 74, 1 1 9, 1 37, 1 46, 1 50
classical claims of, 70, 72, 1 23
of consciousness, 82
critical task of, 1 33, 1 76
ethical task of, 79-80
and existential concerns, 75
of history, 85, 1 36, 1 40
limits of, 2 1
moral, 1 1 4
postmetaphysical, 75
and religion, 1 34
of science, 1 00, 1 1 6
and self-referentiality, 83
self-understanding of, 1 32
transformation of, 82
Phromsis, 2 1 , 25, 1 1 7, 1 20, 1 23- 1 24
Piaget, Jean, 30, 1 1 5, 1 3 2
Plato, 1 02 , 1 25, 1 32, 1 3 8
Platonism, 34
Pluralism, 1 5 1
Polis, 6
Politics, 88, 93
Positivism, 1 35, 144
1 95
Index
1 96
Index
197
Index
Guy Oakes, Weber and Rickert: Concept Formation in the Cultural Sciences
Claus Offe, Contradictions of the Welfare State
Claus Offe, Disorganized Capitalism: Contemporary Transformations of Work and
Politics
Dennis Schmidt, The Ubiquity of the Finite: Hegel, Heidegger, and the
Entitlements of Philosophy
Carl Schmitt, The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy
Carl Schmitt, Political Romanticism
Carl Schmitt, Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty
Gary Smith, editor, On Walter B enjamin: Critical Essays and Recollections
Michael Theunissen, The Other: Studies in the Social Ontology of Husser[,
Heidegger, Sartre, and Buber
Ernst Tugendhat, Self-Consciousness and Self-Determination
Georgia Warnke, Justice and Interpretation
Mark Warren, Nietzsche and Political Thought
Albrecht Wellmer, The Persistence of Modernity: Essays on Aesthetics, Ethics and
Postmodernism
Thomas E. Wren, editor, The Moral Domain: Essays in the Ongoing Discussion
between Philosophy and the Social Sciences