Review of Weeks Boehme
Review of Weeks Boehme
Review of Weeks Boehme
Dia/ogue
I will not be coy, making you guess whether or not I liked this book. I liked it.
Weeks has written both an important and a good book. In order to explain why
this is a good book, however, I must first explain why it is an important book.
In Boehme scholarship, there have traditionally been several types of interpre
tation. First, many writers consciously or unconsciously have regarded Boehme
as proto-Hegelian.' While Hegel certainly knew about Boehme, and discussed him
in his History of Philosophy, there is doubt about how much of Boehme Hegel
actually appropriated. Nevertheless, the point is that later interpreters sometimes
have a tendency to think that Boehme's dialectic is basically the same as Hegel's,
only expressed more figuratively.
The problem with this position is that it obscures and distorts elements of
Boehme's dialectic. For instance, Boehme had a type of concern for the ontologi
cal status and knowledge of individuals that is not easily found in Hegel. He did
not historicize his dialectic the way Hegel did. He invested a great deal in the
beginning of the dialectic, whereas Hegel seems more concerned about the ulti
mate end of the dialectic. This is not to say, of course, that Boehme is better than
Hegel, but only different.
A second tendency is what might be called the "metaphysication" of Boehme.
Some writers2 interpret Boehme as constructing a metaphysical system, and as
such are inclined to downplay the fluidity and dynamism of Boehme's dialectic. In
fact, Boehme's system was conceived as an antidote to metaphysics. The Ungrund
that is at the core of the dialectic is explicitly not a grounding for all else, but rather
a Chaos that challenges the complacency of metaphysical entities. For Brinton (for
instance), Boehme's system is evolutionary; for Boehme, however, there is no Auf
hebung, no progress or development that builds on what went before and at the
same time negates it. Boehme holds that individuals manifest themselves by a free
choice of their imagination to co-operate with Ungrund, but this never negates
Ungrund. The result for Boehme is that individuals are constantly chalIenged by
the chaos that lies at their core. Metaphysicians, on the other hand, consider that
negative core to be the same as the positive grounding of (for instance) an Aristo
telian metaphysic.
A third (loosely defined) group of interpreters has chosen to emphasize
Boehme's voluntarism. Drawing more on Schelling's appropriation of Boehme
than Hegel's,) these interpreters (the most important of whom are Nicolas Ber
dyaev in Russia and Alexandre Koyre in Francet emphasized the dynamism of
Boehme's dialectic. Berdyaev sees Boehme as a proto-existentialist, while Koyre
emphasizes the historical development of Boehme's work. Both avoid metaphysi
764
Dialogue
of Signature Rerum, he does not notice that the work seems to be an amalgam of
three smaller sections, since it starts its project anew in Chapters 1,9 and 13).
This selectivity, however, does not damage this intellectual biography. Weeks set
out to write a book that "examines [Boehme's] writings work by work and relates
them to his life and times, in order to survey and, where necessary, revise his stand
ing in intellectual history" (p. xi). In this task he has succeeded, and if he has not
done everything he might have done, we should not let the minor problems distract
us from the major achievement.
Notes