Vilfredo Pareto Mind and Society Part 3 Theory of Derivations
Vilfredo Pareto Mind and Society Part 3 Theory of Derivations
Vilfredo Pareto Mind and Society Part 3 Theory of Derivations
This book should bcretai-fiecl on or Dc(l/rc the date la^t marked bdkw.
THE MIND AND SOCIETY
The Mind and Society
VOLUME I
NON-LOGICAL CONDUCT
VOLUME II
ANALYSIS OF SENTIMENT
(THEORY OF RESIDUES)
VOLUME III
SENTIMENT IN THINKING
(THEORY OF DERIVATIONS)
VOLUME IV
[
Trattato di Sociologia generate
]
BY VILFREDO PARETO
VOLUME THREE
Theory of Derivations
JONATHAN CAPE
THIRTY BEDFORD SQUARE
LONDON
First published,
Jonathan Cape Ltd., 30 Bedford Square, London
and pi Wellington Street West, Toronto
XL PROPERTIES OF RESIDUES
Chapter AND DERIVA-
TIONS 1 120
(Theory of Derivations)
CHAPTER IX
Derivations
1397. We
now come to derivations as defined in 868. They
account for the production and acceptance of certain theories, so
these we shall now be considering from the "subjective"
standpoint
( 13). We
have already come upon derivations in large numbers,
though we have not always used that term for them. We shall con-
tinue to find them whenever we centre our attention on the ways
in which people try to dissemble, change, explain, the real character
of this or that mode of conduct.
1
Human beings are persuaded in
the main by sentiments (residues), and we may therefore foresee,
as for that matter experience shows, that derivations derive the
force they have, not, or at least not exclusively, from logico-experi-
2
mental considerations, but from sentiments. The principal nucleus
1
*397 I n Chapter III we went at some length into the reasonings with which
people try to make conduct that is non-logical seem logical. Those were derivations,
and we classified a few of them from that particular point of view. We met others,
again, in Chapters IV and V, considering them from other points of view.
2
1397 Jeremy Bentham condemns political orators for using sophistries and fal-
lacious arguments: Traitc des sophistries politiques (Dumont text), Vol. II, pp. 129,
2I 3> 3 [As is well known, nothing in Bentham's Boo^ of Fallacies (Worlds, Vol. II,
pp. 375 f.) exactly corresponds to Dumont's French, this form of Bentham's thought
being known in English only in translation. A. L.] Says Bentham: "Fortunately,
an orator of that sort, however brilliant and talented, will never hold the forefront
in a legislative body. He may may have a momentary
dazzle, he may astonish, he
success, but he inspires no whom he pleads. The
confidence even in those for
greater the experience one has with political bodies, the more clearly one realizes
the soundness of Cicero's definition of the orator as an honest man trained in the
art of public speaking: vir bonus dicendi peritus" If Bentham means, as he seems
to mean, that only the honest, loyal, straightforward orator achieves success, we
get a proposition which experience belies a thousand times over, and the very case
of Cicero might be cited in proof. Bentham heaps praises on Fox for the qualities
mentioned; but Fox unquestionably was defeated in the English Parliament. His
case would rather disprove the contention. If Bentham is thinking of the esteem
that certain "good" people may have for an orator, he may or may not be right,
according to the meaning one attaches to the term "good." That, however, would
be shifting the point at issue, which is the basis of success in politics. [Bentham
forgot, and Pareto overlooked, the fact that the celebrated definition of the ideal
orator referred to is not Cicero's, but is attributed to the younger Cato by Quintilian,
Institutio oratoria, XII, i, i: "Sit ergo nobis orator is qui a Marco Catone fini-
. . .
885
886 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1398
in a derivative (a non-logico-experimental theory) is a residue, or
a number of residues, and around it other secondary residues cluster.
That group is
produced, and once produced consolidated, by a
is
powerful force: the need that the human being feels for logical or
pseudo-logical developments and which manifests itself in residues
of the l- type. It is in those residues therefore in combination with
others that derivations in general originate.
1398. Some distance back (Chapter II) we studied a large
group
of derivations that were designed to "explain" certain manners of
tur: vir bonus diccndi peritus." A. L.] Elsewhere 'Bentham condemns politicians
for opposing ministers in power and attacking measures which they themselves
recognize as good, on the ground that it is their duty to remove from power per-
sons whomthey consider harmful to the country. "If the men you are attacking
are what you say they are, they will not be long in supplying you with opportunities
for fighting them without prejudice to your sincerity. If such legitimate opportuni-
ties fail you, your charges of incapacity or malpractice would seem to be either false
or premature. If such measures are more often bad than good, public opinion must
necessarily turn in your favour. [What a fine thing, but how imaginary, such a
public opinion!] There can be no doubt that a bad measure is much easier to attack
than a good one." That may be true in some ideal universe where everything makes
for the best in a best of all possible worlds; but it seems not at all to square with
experience in our real world. Bentham writes a whole book on political sophistries
and is now and then he himself unwittingly falls into the
not aware that every
fallacy of mistaking effusions of his own sentiments and inclinations for conquests
of experience. "The sophistry,'* he says, "supplies a legitimate presumption against
those who use it. Only for lack of sound arguments does one resort to it. [That is
based on the implicit assumption that logically sound arguments are more convinc-
ing than fallacies. Experience is far from showing that.] As regards measures that
are in themselves sound it is useless, or at least it cannot be indispensable. [The
same implicit assumption, and experience, again, in no sense concords with it.]
The sophistry presupposes in those who use it, or in those who adopt it, either
lack of sincerity or lack of intelligence." Bentham's assumption is that the person
who uses a fallacy recognizes it as such (insincerity) or that, if he fails so to recog-
nize it, he is wanting in intelligence. As a matter of fact many fallacies that are
current in a given society are repeated in all sincerity by people who are exceed-
ingly intelligent and are merely voicing in that way sentiments which they con-
sider beneficial to society. Also implicit in Bentham's sermon is the assumption that
lack of sincerity and lack of intelligence are uniformly harmful to society; whereas
there are plenty of cases to go no farther than diplomacy where too much sin-
cerity may be harmful, and other cases where a highly intelligent man may go
wrong and do incalculable harm
by forcing certain logical policies upon
to a society
it; whereas a stupid individual instinctively following beaten paths that have been
*
1399 It was from this point of view that we considered a number of deriva-
and V, though we were not then calling them derivations.
tions in Chapters III, IV,
2
1399 To the question of utility we shall come in Chapter XII. In any event, to
get a complete theory of derivations from the first two standpoints, Chapters III,
IV and V have to be taken in conjunction with our argument here. Deduction re-
THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1400
1400. Derivations will be
differently classified according to the
standpoint from which they are considered ( 1480). Just here we
are thinking of the subjective character of the
"explanations" that
are given, through derivations, of certain behaviour, certain
ways
of thinking; and of the persuasive force of such
explanations. We
shall therefore
classify derivations according to the character of the
explanation. Where there is no explaining there is no derivation;
but the moment an explanation is given or sought, a derivation comes
into play. The animal does not reason, it acts
exclusively by instinct
( 861). It uses no derivations therefore. The human being, however,
wants to think, and he also feels impelled to
keep his instincts and
sentiments hidden from view. Rarely, in
consequence, is at least a
germ of derivation
missing in human thinking, just as residues are
rarely missing. Residues and derivations can be detected every time
we look at a theory or argument that is not strictly logico-experi-
mental. That was the case in Chapter III ( 325), where we came
upon the derivation in simplest form, the pure precept, with no
its
(or others do as they do) because that is what is usually done in our
community." Then comes a derivation somewhat more complex in
that a show is made of accounting for the custom, and one says:
"We do thus and so because that is what one ought to do." Such
derivations are simple assertions. Let us
put them in a class by
themselves, Class I. But already in the second of the derivations
mentioned an indefinite, somewhat mysterious entity, "duty," has
pher, all alike; and we go from the childish answer of the plain
man to the abstruse, but from the logico-experimental standpoint no
better, theory of the metaphysicist. first A
step is taken by appealing
to the authority of maxims current in the
community that happens
to be involved, to the authority of individuals, and, with new elabo-
Among them
are to be counted theologies and systems of meta-
physics. Suppose we put them in a Class III. But we have still not
exhausted our supply of derivations. Still remaining is a large class
where we find proofs that are primarily verbal, explanations that are
1
purely formal but pretend to pass as substantial Class IV.
1401. Suppose we go back for a moment and translate into the
1400
1
We shall see as we go on ( 1419) that these classes subdivide into genera,
and we shall deal specially with each such genus in turn. But before we come to
that, we had better consider other general aspects of derivations and derivatives.
890 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1402
1402. Now the only things of which we have any direct knowl-
of the social equilibrium. For us, in these volumes, they figure only
as manifestations, as indications, of other forces that are the forces
which really determine the social equilbrium. Very very often,
hitherto, the social sciences have been theories made of residues up
and derivations and furthermore holding in view the practical pur-
tinctly, so
that it has never been given a complete theory and its im-
portance has never been accurately evaluated and that for various
rather, ought not nourish a grudge for too long a time. If that
long a time. Therefore man mustnot nourish wrath for too long a
time." The assertion that "a mortal must not nourish wrath for too
long a time" at once calls attention to the weak point in the argu-
ment. It had better be suppressed, therefore, to avoid the danger
that its fallacy may be perceived, and so the enthymeme is used
instead of the syllogism. That procedure is all the more useful in
the Aristotelian sense of the enthymeme. If on asserting a judgment
we limit ourselves to stating the reason that provokes, or apparently
formities, 1068) is called in: the single case, that is, is represented
as the
general rule.
1410. In his System of Logic, Book V, Chap. I 3 (p. 513), John
Stuart Mill mentions but rather by way of eliminating them from
his purview two other sources of error in addition to the logical
interest to him, for they elicit no very wide response among men.
But the fallacious, or for that matter the sound, theories that enjoy
wide acceptance are of the greatest concern to him. It is the province
of logic to tell
why a reasoning is false. It is the business of sociology
to explain wide acceptance.
its
1412.
According to Mill there are, in the main, two sources of
ethical error: first, indifference to knowledge of the truth; and
then, bias, the most common case being "that in which we are
biased by our wishes," though after all we may accept agreeable and
ments if the primary aim is to satisfy the hankering for logic in the
individuals who are to be influenced; by heaping up residues if the
with the residues R' /?" JR'" . . . and working up to the derivations
R'rB, R'tB, R'vB. ... In the case of a moral theory, the purpose,
let us say, is to establish the precept forbidding homicide. That
due, and get to the point desired by way of a literally huge number
of derivations.
1415. Theologians, metaphysicists, philosophers, theorists of poli-
tics, law, and ethics, do not ordinarily accept the order indicated
( 1402). They are inclined to assign first place to derivations. What
we call residues are in their
eyes axioms or dogmas, and the purpose
is
just the conclusion of a logical reasoning. But since they are not
as a rule inany agreement on the derivation, they argue about it till
they are blue in the face and think that they can change social con-
ditions by proving a derivation fallacious. That is all an illusion on
their to realize that their hagglings never reach the
fail
part. They
majority of men, who could not make head or tail to them anyhow,
and who in fact disregard them save as articles of faith to which
1 2
they assent in deference to certain residues.
x
1415 Political economy has been and largely continues to be a branch of litera-
ture, and as such falls under anything that may be said of derivations. It stands as a
matter of plain fact that economic practice and economic theory have followed
altogether divergent paths.
2
1415 Bayle, Dictionnaire historique, s.v. Augustin: "To anyone examining the
question without prejudice and with the necessary competence, it is so evident that
896 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1416
1416. What we
have just been saying leads to very important
conclusions with reference to that "logic of sentiments" to which we
alluded in 480.
1. If the basic residue from which a derivation develops disappears
1
and is not replaced by another, the purpose also disappears. That
is the usual case in logical reasonings based on experimental
premises: that is to say, a scientific theory is discarded in the light
of new facts. However, even in such a case it is often possible for a
conclusion to hold its
ground if the erroneous premises can be re-
tirely,
but merely weakens it, saps its
vitality.
The ideal remains but
is
accepted with less fervour. It has been observed in India that
native converts the morality of their old religion without
lose
the doctrines of St. Augustine and Jansenius, Bishop of Ypres, are one and the
same, that one can hardly keep one's temper at the thought that the Court of Rome
could boast of condemning Jansenius and meantime keep the Saint secure in all his
glory. The two things are altogether incompatible. Not only that: in condemning
Calvin's doctrine of free-will, the Council of Trent necessarily condemned the doc-
trine of St. Augustine. There are people who regard it as a very happy circum-
. . .
stance that the masses at large take such little interest in the vicissitudes of doctrine,
are in fact incapable of doing so. If they did, they would be rising more often
against theologians than against usurers. 'If you do not know,* they might say to
them, 'that you are deceiving us, your stupidity deserves your being sent to till the
soil. If you do know what you arc doing, you deserve prison on bread and water
for your wickedness/ . . .
[In that Bayle is mistaken. A person may be as intelli-
along the beaten paths; and even if they wanted more than that, they would not be
capable of mastering the subject. Their daily occupations have not permitted them
to acquire sufficient competence for that."
*
1416That is a particular case of the general theory of the reciprocal influence
of residues and derivations upon each other. That theory we shall elaborate in
1735 *
1416 LOGIC OF SENTIMENT 897
falls. But in an unscientific reasoning, if one form of derivation is
reason for its acceptance. Sometimes again the proof and the reason
A
may coincide. precept may be demonstrated by appeal to authority
and accepted in deference to the same authority, but then again the
two things may be altogether at odds. When a person proves a
proposition by taking advantage of the ambiguity of some term in it,
he most assuredly does not say: "My proof is sound because of the
trickery involved in my juggling of words." But the person who
accepts the derivation is
unwittingly taken into camp by that verbal
trickery.
1420 DERIVATIONS 899
Kremsier, they are, respectively, 2, 19, 12, 669, 343, pp. i, 4, 3, 157, 69. A. L.]
1426 BIBLICAL COMMANDMENTS 901
obtained. It is a non-scientific derivation of the if the con-
I-/? type
opus est asse carum est.' ("Buy not what you need but what you have to have.
What you do not need comes dear at a farthing" Reliquiae, 4 (8), p. 17.) So with
the responses of oracles or things of that kind, such as 'Tempori parcel' 'Te nosci.'
What proof do you require when someone quotes to you lines such as: 'Iniuriarum
'
remcdium cst oblivio,' Audentes jortuna iuvat,' 'Piger ipse sibi obstat'? Such max-
ims need no advocate. They touch us in our inner emotions and stimulate us by
their own natural force. [So Pareto. "Nattira vim suam exercente proficiunt": perhaps
"by force of our very natures"; Gummere: "because nature is exercising her proper
function"; Morell: "Let nature exert her own power, they cannot but do good."
A. L.] The seeds of all nobility lie in our souls, and they are stirred to life by the
admonition, much as a spark when gendy fanned unfolds its inner flame.'* To be
quite exact the last sentences need retouching: "The seeds of certain things lie in
our souls, and they are stirred to life by simple assertions, much as, etc." Seneca goes
on to say: "Some things moreover are present in our souls but in a state of slug-
gishness, and they become supple and active (in expcdito) when they are expressed
in words. Some things lie scattered about so that an untrained mind cannot bring
them together; andso they have to be assembled and organized before they can be
useful and inspiriting to the soul." That is all very sound and well describes the
effects of simple assertions.
902 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1427
through Moses, Jehovah now and again exclaims as it were by way
of re-enforcement: "I am the Lord your God." 1 Frequent in our
time are assertions to the effect that this or that measure means
"progress" or "democracy" or that it is
"broadly human" or "makes
for a better humanity." The assertion is less a derivation, in just that
purposes a derivation.
1427. The simple assertion also figures in the taboo without sanc-
tion, to which we have already alluded (32if.). Simple deriva-
tions of that sort can be detected in a great many compound deriva-
tions rare, indeed, the concrete derivation that fails to contain one.
The arbitrary assertion generally finds some little place among exper-
imental assertions; or else it creeps into an argument or dissembles
its
presence there to usurp for itself the assent that is accorded to the
other propositions among which it lurks.
1428. I-/3:
Assertion of sentiments. The assertion may be an in-
direct manner of expressing certain sentiments, and it is accepted as
an "explanation" by people who share those sentiments. In such a
case, therefore, it is a mere manifestation of the secondary residues
that go to make up the derivation.
1429. When a uniformity or precept is derived from an individual
sentiment, the residue brought into play for purposes of derivation is
the one that transforms subjective facts into objective realities (resi-
due II-, 888) along, oftentimes, with residues of sociality (Class
IV). A man sees other people run and he runs. That is an instinctive
act, a reflex action such as is observable in animals. He hears some-
one shout, "Run!" and he runs. We are still in the same case. Ask
him, "Why did you run?" and he answers, "Because I heard people
'Run!' and I thought that one ought to run." In that we get
shouting
a first glimmer of the derivation, which will become more compli-
cated if the man undertakes to give a reason for the "ought." man A
reading a poem exclaims, "It is beautiful!" Were he to say, "It seems
beautiful to me," he would merely be stating a subjective fact. Using
the language, "It is beautiful!" he makes the subjective fact objective.
1426
1
-
Lev. 14:3, and passim: "And ye shall fear every man his mother and his
father and keep my sabbaths: I am the Lord your God/*
1431 DERIVATIONS I-/2 ! ASSERTIONS OF SENTIMENTS 903
Furthermore, anyone hearing the exclamation has a feeling that
anything that is reputed beautiful ought to make an impression of
beauty upon him, a residue of sociality interposing. That is the reason
why people as a rule share the tastes of the
community in which they
live.
1430. An
assertion is accepted and gains prestige through the
sentiments of various kinds which it excites in those who hear it, the
sentiments so acquiring status as "proof." It convinces because it is
( "57)-
1431. The
causes that account for the persuasiveness of the asser-
tion fall into three categories: i. A
vague feeling that a person who
expresses himself in such a form must be right. In that the derivation
is reduced to a minimum and is to be taken as the distinctive
type
of the I-/3 variety. 2. A feeling that such a select form is authoritative.
In that the derivation somewhat more evolved and belongs to
is
Class II (and see below, 1434 f-, authority). 3. The more or less
vague notion that the authority is justified. The derivation still be-
longs to Class II ( 1435), and may develop to the point of yielding
a logical reasoning.
One might guess, in the abstract, that the sentiments in 3 gave
rise to the sentiments in 2, and those in 2 to those in i : that first, in
ity;
that then the authority is accepted in general terms; and that,
finally,
and quite apart from any authority, comes a feeling of
reverence for the manner of expression used. That may sometimes
be the process; but in reality the three groups are often independent,
each having a life of its own; and when a relation does exist be-
tween 2 and 3, it is the reverse of the one indicated. In many cases
strate, we
get a derivation. In the case where a person takes his
opinions from the newspaper that he habitually reads, there figure,
along with the I-(3 derivation, a cumulus of other derivations and
residues, notable among which are residues of sociality (Class IV) :
tively rare, sentiments justifying the authority also come into play
( 1432). But as a rule a person first has the sentiment of authority,
and then goes looking for ways to justify it.
derivations, the residues that are used for purposes of deriving are
residues of group-persistence (Class II), II- residues that represent
sentiments as objective realities
being supported by residues of other
kinds, as, for instance, II-/3 residues (surviving authority of a dead
tion and we need not linger on it. But there are other kinds of der-
ivations in which the individual's competence is not experimental.
It
may be assumed to exist from misleading evidence or be alto-
least remote from the logico-experi-
gether fictitious. In the case
mental situation the authority is presumed on grounds that may or
may not be sound, it
being a question of a greater or lesser degree
of probability ( 1432). Next to that would come the case where
the competence is stretched, through sentiments of group-persist-
906 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1436
ence, beyond the limits within which it is
experimentally valid. The
situation dealt with in the familiar maxim, "Cobbler, stick to your
1
last" Sutor, ne ultra crepidam is of all times and places.
1436. Because he is a first-class politician, Theodore Roosevelt is
hope of progress for the peoples of Asia; and since such a thing is inconceivable,
the superstition has to be rejected. That is one of the usual confusions between the
question of the utility of a doctrine and its accord with experimental facts.
a
1436 [And yet why not George Washington, as well as some other modern? For
the phrase has no classical authority. Vegetius, De re militari, III, proemium, said,
"Qui desiderat pacem, praeparet bellum"; and Cicero, Philippicae, VII, 6, 19, "Si
pace jrui volumus bellum gerendum est." A. L.]
1436 DERIVATIONS II-a: AUTHORITY 907
those considerations were not operative there was plenty of admira-
tion for Roosevelt's fatuous chatter. The feeling was that there was
a man who was man enough to get himself elected to the presi-
dency of the United States and to make a terrible noise in that office,
and that therefore he must surely be competent in any matter re-
lating to the historical and social sciences. It was the feeling also
that a man who is competent in one thing is
competent in every-
thing; along with a sentiment of generic admiration, which prevents
people from distinguishing the respects in which a man is
competent
1
from the respects in which he is not.
In a day gone by the prestige of the poet intruded upon every
field of human many cases with some slight logico-ex-
activity, in
mothers that they ought to suckle their children. That wins him
loud applause from hosts of men and women of no great brains.
Anatole France a novelist of the very first rank, a great stylist,
is
disputed. And then, one fine day, he takes it into his head to extend
that authority to matters about which he knows much less. He sets
out to solve questions of politics, economics, religion, history: he
becomes Dreyfusard, Socialist, theologian, historian; and people
flock in throngs to him in all of those varied metamorphoses. The
sentiment of authority re-enforced by political passions was so strong
in his case that it resisted all proofs to a contrary in itself more plau-
1
1436 The public attentions showered on Roosevelt were to a certain extent logi-
cal actions. It was believed at the time in Europe that Roosevelt would again be
President of the United States, and the idea was to work for favours from him.
Those calculations went amiss, however: Roosevelt was not re-elected. To counter-
balance such fawning, the Pope refused to receive Roosevelt, a Genoese nobleman
denied him entrance to his palace, and Maximilian Harden wrote an article lam-
pooning German adulators of Roosevelt.
908 THE MIND AND SOCIETY M37
sible. Andrew Lang,
in his time, called attention to the serious and
gold." Lang informed France before the definitive publication of the Jeanne d'Arc
that "for the tax to have reached such a sum, we should have to assume that Dom-
remy had as large a population as Orleans. ... I had already called M. France's
attention to this error, but it has not been corrected in the revised edition. . . .
M. France obstinately maintains that a certain young woman whose son was god-
son to Jeanne 'ridiculed her because of her devoutness,' mentioning the testimony
of the woman as proof. Now there is not a suggestion of any such thing in the
woman's testimony; and I am not alone in having called M. France's attention to
that fact. That is how he bases his work on 'the most reliable sources/ to use the
words of his new preface, and 'interpreting them with all the insight of a real
scholar,' to believe his good-natured critic, M. Gabriel Monod!" Lang notes other
errors of minor importance but which go to show that France took the writing of
his book not overseriously: "In a short passage from the celebrated letter of Gerson,
her frivolousness and shrewdness . . .'! In the sentence next following Gerson al-
ludes to the words of the Apostle, 'Non oportet servum Dei litigare,' and M. France
"
translates, 'It is not meet to involve the servant of God in this question.' Noting
another important error on France's part, Lang comments: "While M. France was
finding in Dunois's testimony things that were not there, it was quite natural that
he should fail to observe that D'Aulon was a member of the Royal Council and
had been summoned by the King along with the other Councillors to pass on
Jeanne's first petition a thing that must surely strike us as altogether natural. But
it is very regrettable that after his attention had been called to these points by the
even that support, and keep afloat no one knows how, without a
shadow of foundation, whether experimental or otherwise. Exam-
ples without end might be mentioned. Open any book of ancient
times and one will soon be encountered, and the chances are just
as good among modern writings. We
have seen many specimens
already. Let us look at just one more. St. Augustine, De civitate Dei,
XXI, 2, sets out to prove against unbelievers that the torment of
hell-fire will really be visited upon the damned. He has been met
with the objection that it is incredible that flesh should burn on
for ever without being destroyed, and that a soul should suffer so
much without dying. That difficulty he meets with the rejoinder
that things just as marvellous have happened and that they would
be incredible if they were not certainly true; and he mentions a long
list of them. We need not go into the major issue, the argument
outset that M. Lang is often right in his criticisms of M. France, though he is in-
clined to attach a great deal of importance to small matters.*' But he concedes, p.
320, that France did not rectify errors that had been called to his attention: "In
spite of the improvements M. France has made, his book is still very inaccurate.
Perhaps we oughtto assume that M. France shared his labours with others, using
what we call a negre' and not a very trustworthy 'negre! " As regards the Cato
'
proverb in dispute between Lang and France, France should have remembered that
in the Distica Catonis, a work well known and gready admired in centuries past,
the proverb reads, III, 2:
("So long as you live rightly, give no thought to the words of the malicious. It is
not within our power to control what people say.")
Maimbourg, Histoire de I'Arianisme, Vol. I, pp. 17-18: "I am well aware
X
1437
that one is not always obliged to believe in the extraordinary things called visions,
especially when they are not vouched for by some celebrated author whose name is
in itself genuine proof. But I am also not unaware that history, leaving us full lib-
any other force except ram's blood. When a diamond is set beside a loadstone the
latter no longer attracts iron. But the unbelievers still stand adamant and will have
the reasons for the miraculous things described by the Saint: "But when we assert
divine miracles past or future and are unable to demonstrate them tangibly (ex-
pcricnda) before their eyes, the unbelievers insist on our explaining
the reasons for
them; and since we are unable to do that, surpassing as they do the powers of the
human mind, they conclude that what we say is false. But in that case suppose they
that we see or may see if we
try themselves to account for all the wondrous things
choose." So far the Saint is right. The fact that we do not know the cause of a
thing proves nothing as to its reality. But the existence of the thing still has to be
proved by direct observation. That is where St. Augustine falls short. Nearly all the
things he represents as authentic facts are purely
fantastic: i. When the salt of Agri-
is thrown into fire it melts as in water. In water itcrackles as in
gentum (Sicily)
2 (Bostock-Riley, Vol. V, p. 505),
fire. Pliny's account, Historia naturalis, XXXI, 41,
is somewhat different: "Agrigentinus ignium patiens ex aqua
cxsilet" (resistant to
(Opera, Vol. V, p. 371; Whitson, Vol. V, p. 315). 7. In Persia there is a stone that
catches fire if it is pressed hard between the hands. For that reason it is called
"pyritis." Cf. Solinus, Op. 16 (Leipzig, p. 227) ; Pliny, XXXVII, 73
cit., XXXVII,
(Bostock-Riley, Vol. VI, p. 460): "Pyritis, though a black stone, burns the fingers
when rubbed by them." 8. Also in Persia is a stone called "selenite." It has an
inner brilliancy that waxes and wanes with the Moon. Cf. Pliny, Op. cit., XXXVII,
67, i (Bostock-Riley, Vol. VI, p. 456) "Selenitis is white and transparent with a re-
:
flected colour like that ofhoney." 9. In Cappacodia mares are fertilized by the wind,
but their foals live not more than three years. (Cf. 3
927 .) 10. The island of Tilon
in the Indies is blessed above all others, because the trees there do not lose their
foliage. This last statement is the only one of the that has the slightest probabil-
list
ity of being true, provided it be taken as applying not just to one island but to all
the tropics.
28
The Saint continues: "Hosts of things are recorded in books [Explicit
1438
derivations of authority.] not as having been done and then having
passed away,
but as still existing in their various localities, so that if anyone were minded and
able to go there, he could see for himself whether they be true." There the deriva-
tion of authority is implicit. To say that anyone might go and see whether such
wonderful things were true is equivalent, in that context, to saying that "it was
believed" that such a verification was possible. As a matter of fact, a person actu-
ally going on such a mission could not possibly have verified facts that were not
facts. But the obstinate unbelievers lay a trap for the Saint as regards the written
record: "To this, perhaps, they will straightway answer that these wonders do not
exist, that they do not believe in them, that those who have spoken and written of
them have spoken and written falsely; and they argue that if such things are to be
believed then one ought also to believe the other things that are described in those
same books, such as the story that there was, or is, a certain temple to Venus where
one may see a candelabrum with a lamp standing out in the weather, but which
no storm, no rain, can extinguish." In that argument the Saint's critics were trying
to place him in the dilemma either of denying the miracle of Venus and so dis-
crediting the evidence he had adduced in behalf of his own wonders, or of admit-
ting the existence of the gods of paganism. But he wriggles free by pointing out
that he is not obliged to believe everything the heathen writers say: "non habemus
necesseomnia credere quae continet historia gentium"; for, as Varro notes, they are
at variancewith one another on many points. We believe, he says, the things that
they do not dispute ("quae non adversantur libris") and which we can prove by
1439 LUCIAN ON THE MARVELLOUS 913
ised to return after deathand communicate with their friends, the
wife of Euchrates had returned from the other world to have a talk
with her husband. The philosopher Arignotus tells of even more
marvellous things, and the incredulous Tychiades, betraying the fact
that he does not take overmuch stock in them, is
adjudged a man
good witnesses. He does not name his witnesses, however, any more than the wor-
shippers of the modern goddess Science name theirs when they assert the equality
or solidarity of all men. The Saint now resumes the offensive. With the miracle of
the lamp of Venus he associates the many miracles of magic, which cannot be de-
nied without offence to the authority of Holy Writ: "Either the lamp in question
is devised
by human art, with asbestos; or what is seen in the temple is the work
of magic; or else a demon, going under the name of Venus, has wrought with such
efficacy that this prodigy has been made manifest before all men and has endured."
And he concludes that if magicians can do that much, we should be all the more
ready to believe that God, who is so much more powerful than any magician, can
work greater wonders still: "quanta magis Deus potens cst jacere quae infidelibus
stint incredibilia sed illius facilia potestati" since He was the creator of that stone
(asbestos) and of the virtues of other things, of the intelligence of the men who use
such virtues in wondrous ways and of the angelic natures, which are far more
powerful than all earthly creatures. But that is all a reasoning in a circle, a manner
of thinking seldom missing in concrete derivations of the Augustinian type. To
offer the testimony of the Scriptures to people who deny their authority, the mira-
cles of a devil Venus to people who deny miracles, the might of the Christian God
to people who deny His existence, is to take the conclusion of one's arguments for
the premise.
4
1438 As for St. Augustine's doubts: "I do not ask that these facts which I have
mentioned be accepted out of hand (tcmere) as true. I do not believe them myself
to the extent that no doubt whatever is left in my mind, except as to those things
which I have experienced myself or which it would be easy for anyone to verify."
An excellent resolve, to which unfortunately the Saint docs not remain very faith-
ful! In addition to wonders that are only partially true, he takes exception to two
of the less credible marvels, the story about lighting the torch in the spring in Epi-
rus, and the story about the fruit at Sodom. As for the spring in Epirus he con-
fesses that he had known no eyewitnesses; but he had met people who had seen a
similar spring at Gratianopolis (Grenoble). "As for the fruit-trees of Sodom, not
only are they vouched for by books altogether trustworthy, but so many writers
speak of them of their own experience that I cannot doubt them." Interesting the
Saint'sway of giving and taking back at the same time, a common device in many
such derivations. It arises from the need of influencing sentiments, disregarding
contradictions, which would become apparent enough in a logico-experimental
argument. St.Augustine begins by representing his wonders as facts. He says indeed
that anyone who chooses may verify them, and in the matter of the diamond he
calls the jewellers of his city to witness. Then, when the effect of that has sunk in,
he ventures a certain amount of doubt that he may save both the goat and the cab-
to a solidarity-fact:
bages. So nowadays worshippers of solidarity begin by pointing
and then when that has done its work, they deign to admit that their solidarity-fact
a famous, nay an inspired, sage, began telling such talcs, there was not one in the
company who did not call me a lunatic because I took no stock in them. Imagine!
Things vouched for by Arignotus! But I, without that much respect for his shaggy
locks and great renown, I cried: 'O Arignotus, so you too you promise us truth,
and feed us prattle! You make the proverb come true, "We seek a treasure and
*
ashes we 'Very well,* answered Arignotus, 'if you believe not my words, nor
find."
who do not believe it, seeing that all the peoples on earth and all antiquity stand
in agreement in the matter. Not only did Herodotus write of it 2,200 years ago
[Historiae, IV, 105], and 400 years before the time of Homer, but there is Pom-
ponius Mela \De situ orbis, II, i, 13], there is Solinus, there is Strabo, not to men-
tion Dionysius Afer, Marcus Varro, Virgil, Ovid, and countless others." Father Le
Brun, Histoire critique des pratiques superstitieuses, Vol. I, p. 118, tries to steer a
middle course. One ought not, certainly, believe everything, but "obstinacy in un-
belief ordinarily comes of an excessive pride that inclines one to esteem oneself
higher than the most respectable authorities and to prefer one's own lights to the
wisdom of the greatest men and most
judicious philosophers." Following just such
principles Don Calmet remarks, Dissertations sur les apparitions, p. 63, that "Plu-
tarch, a man of recognized seriousness and wisdom, often speaks of spectres and
apparitions.He says, for instance {Theseus, 35], that at the famous battle of Mara-
thon, against the Persians, several soldiers saw the shade of Theseus fighting with
the Greeks against their enemies."
1440 DERIVATIONS Il-ot! AUTHORITY 915
*
or aperitif." There is no reason to suppose that the author of the
text-book did not believe precisely what he says otherwise the ex-
ample would be truly deplorable in a text-book on "morals"! He
believesand his reader must believe by virtue of his authority
that to swallow "a single drop of brandy or cordial" will impair
one's health. It is a very easy matter to test the assertion and see
whether be true that after drinking a single drop of liquor one
it
capacity to nurse a child and that capacity is irremediably lost for the following
generations. [This gentleman may know little enough about the past, but he has
learned all about the future probably through some trance medium.] So with
moderate drinkers (less than one litre of wine or two litres of beer per diem), the
alcoholization of the father is the main cause of the woman's inability to nurse her
"
children.' There must be mighty few women in Germany who are able to nurse
their children; for few the men in that country who do not drink as much as two
litres of beer a day. As usual derivations serve equally well to demonstrate the pro
916 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 144!
1441. And here is another gentleman who
finds peo-says and he
ple to believe him that a pint of wine or a quart of beer will dimm-
ish capacity for mental work by from 25 to 40 per cent. If that were
tained in about half a litre of wine or two litres of beer was enough to diminish
capacity for mental work by from 25 to 40 per cent. The falling-off is due to the
paralyzing, stupefying effects of alcohol. They arc observable for several days after
1446 ALCOHOL AND MENTAL CAPACITY 917
1444. From
the logico-experimental standpoint the soundness of
the proposition A=
B is independent of the moral qualities of the
person who asserts it. Suppose tomorrow it should be discovered
that Euclid was a murderer, a thief, in short the worst man that
ever lived. Would such a thing in the remotest degree affect the
validity of the proofs in his geometry ?
1445. Not so, however, from the standpoint of authority. If the
statement A=
Bis accepted only in view of the authority of the
individual who asserts it, anything that discredits that authority will
also discredit the proof that A
B. One of the tricks of the de-
bater, furthermore, is to locate in the field of authority a proposi-
tion that properly belongs in the logico-experimental field.
1446. For the very reason that they have no logico-experimental
force such devices lose their effectiveness when they are used too
freely. We know
in our late day that when one theologian says of
another that he is a rogue and ought to be in jail, all it means is
that the two men have different opinions. When a newspaper calls
a man
in public life a malefactor, it means simply that the paper
has reasons of personal or partisan interest for combating him, or
even a different opinion. That method of discrediting authority may
be an utter failure in politics at the present time.
the absorption of the poison. Dr. Audeaud's results are the fruit of long years
. . .
from Mainz stood on the table. Someone mourned the absence of beer. 'No harm!'
cried Bismarck. 'Too much beer-drinking is deplorable from every point of view.
It makes one stupid, lazy, good for nothing. Beer is responsible for all these demo-
cratic idiocies that are being passed around the tables in the cabarets. Take word my
"
for it, a good rye-whiskey does much less harm.' Ibid., Vol. Ill, p. 280 (English,
Vol. II, p. 519), Mar. 22, 1890: On his fall from power, Bismarck retires to Fried-
"
richsruh and commissions Busch to move his effects thither: 'There,' he said, 'are
my maps. Put the letters inside and roll them up. ... They will go along in the
moving van with the other things. I have some three hundred trunks or boxes and
more than thirteen thousand botdes of wine.' He told me he had a lot of fine sherry
that he had bought when he was rich." Palamenghi-Crispi, Carteggio di Francesco
Crispi, p. 446: "Otto von Bismarcl^ to Crispi, Friedrichsruh, Jan. 7, 1890: 'Dear
Friend and Colleague: I was deeply touched by the new proof of your friendship
on learning that you have shipped to me a case of your splendid Italian wine. I
appreciate it all the more since the high quality of last year's vintage leads me to
look forward to all that it will be. A
good wine is never without its influence on
"
the quality of the drinker's statesmanship.' Poor Bismarck! What a pauper in
prefers. The first three derivations derive their persuasiveness from certain meta-
physical sentiments (III-c); the last four, from tradition (II-/3). Obviously still other
derivations of the kind might be found they are the variable element in the phe-
nomenon. The need of purification (residues V-y, restoration of integrity) and the
instinct of combinations (residues Class I) are the constant element, and it is the
more important one, the variable element deriving from it. Note further that
within the constant element the need of purification, of restoring integrity, is the
main thing, the combinations designed to satisfy it being secondary. So we get
as a whole: i. Residues made up of, a, main residues (purification) and, b, sec-
the tradition, the accord persisting in mere forms. That has been the
case with sects of Christianity.
many
1450. Derivations, as we
repeatedly remarked, are on the
have
whole flexible, and derivations by tradition present that trait to a
very conspicuous degree. In the book that creates a tradition one
can find anything one pleases. The Greeks found everything imag-
inable in Homer, and the Latins, in Virgil. So Italians today find
many things in Dante. The case of the Bible and the Gospels is
truly remarkable. What has not been found in those books would
be hard to imagine. Different and even contradictory doctrines have
been based on them in vast numbers; and they furnish proofs for
and against with equal ease.
1451. Of course every sect is convinced that it has the one "true"
ple who criticize the Bible as history but otherwise fall on their
1
knees before it and worship it. Derivations change, residues endure.
1455. Numbers of good souls in our time have imagined that
they could destroy Christianity by proving the historical unreality
of Jesus.They have made many fine holes in the water. They do
not observe that their disquisitions never get beyond a very small
circle of scholars, never reach the
public at large, nor even the major-
ity
of believers. Ordinarily
they persuade people who are already
persuaded.
1456. So there have been people to imagine that by proving that
Joan of Arc was a hysteric or a lunatic, they could destroy Catholic
patriotism in France and so contribute to the stability of M. Clemen-
ceau's bloc and the
Radical-Socialist regime. They caught the ear
only of the public that was already of their opinion. Far from dimin-
is a book rich in learning and
*
1454 Gauticr's Introduction a I'Ancicn Testament
historical criticism. Now in his "conclusion," Vol. II, p. 507, he is replying to
critics who have censured him on one point or another: "I wish finally to deal with
one last continually recurring in the dispute now raging: [Higher]
notion that is
already had occasion to say that it is important before anything else to under-
stand what one means by the word 'authority.' If one means external authority
[A euphemism for objective statements.], the charge mentioned is well founded;
but if the authority is of the domain of the inner life, of the spiritual order [Eu-
phemism for subjective propositions. That language helps to conceal the petitio
principii involved in the believer's believing in the Bible only what he reads into
it, only what is already in his own mind.], one may baldly assert that the
authority of the Bible is in no way compromised. [Quite so! tautology is neverA
false.] Everything depends on our being clear on one fundamental point, that the
authority in religious matters is the authority of God, and in the more special
sphere of evangelical truth, the authority of Christ. [Quite so! But now we must
be shown how those two wills are to be recognized: if by criteria extrinsic to
us, they be independent of anything we think or say; if only by criteria
may
we are merely baptizing our wills with the name of divine will.]
intrinsic to us,
That authority is exercised upon heart and conscience, though at the same time
appealing to the whole sum of our faculties in virtue of the very unity of our
being. It is something quite above discussions of a literary or historical order. It
can neither be shaken nor consolidated by purely intellectual arguments. [Quite
so, but only in the sense that residues are independent of logic. But we still
have to be shown that they are "divine." And what if there were one or two
"diabolical" ones among them, as certain heretics claim?] It is in no way affected
deity, without splitting hairs very finely as to the reasons for his
conduct or, at the most, adding some few words on one's duty to
respect it. That gives our present variety, Il-y. 2. Or a person may
obey the divine will out of fear of some punishment that threatens
transgressors of divine commandments. There individual interest
comes and we get actions that are logical consequences of the
in,
divine will out of love for the deity, from a desire to act in accord
with sentiments that the deity is assumed to feel, or on the belief
that such conformity in itself and regardless of its consequences is
figure like any other, and the problems raised in connexion with the minuter
details of her life are of very scant significance.
922 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1459
thesis of the concrete. Concrete derivations in which a supernatural
being figures very very often combine the first two types just men-
tioned, and in such a way indeed that it is difficult to distinguish
them. Often also they bring in the third type; but that is already
on the road to metaphysics and is more commonly the case with
thinkers. Many individuals have a complex feeling of reverence,
fear, and love for the supernatural being and they themselves would
not be able to analyze it into simpler elements. Catholic controver-
sies with
regard to "contrition" and "attrition" are not unrelated to
such distinctions as we have just been making between varieties of
1
derivations.
fear." Canones et decreta Concilii Tridentini, sessio XIV, 4 (Richter, p. 77; Schaff,
Vol. II, pp. 144-46) "Contrition ... is the sorrow and detestation of the soul for
:
the sin that has been committed, accompanied by a resolve not to sin again. . . .
But as regards that imperfect contrition which is called attrition, since it is com-
monly conceived either in consideration of the disgrace (turpitudinis) of sin or in
fear of punishment in the other world, it [the Council] declares that if it pre-
cludes the desire to sin through hope of [God's] forgiveness it not only does not
make man a hypocrite and a greater sinner but is a gift of God and an impulse
from the Holy Spirit with the help of which the penitent opens a way for
. . .
himself to holiness (justitia)" Gury, Casus conscientiae, Vol. II, pp. 182-83: "Con-
fession finished, Albert is asked by his confessor just why he feels sorry for his sins.
The penitent answers: 'I am sorry for my sins because I am afraid that God will
punish me in this life with tribulations or sudden death, and in the life to come
with eternal torments.' Tell me, child,' says the confessor, 'was that the reason
why you were sorry for your sins heretofore when you came to confession?' Albert
nods. Whereupon the confessor adjudges those confessions invalid as wanting in
divine love and inspired by nothing but fear. . Whence our Question I: As to . .
whether attrition be sufficient. And the answer is: Attrition is sufficient, and
. . .
Really they invent such a will as a result of their acting in that way.
"It is God's will" ("Dicu le veut"), cried the Crusaders of old.
Really they were under the sway of a migratory instinct such as the
ancient Germans felt a longing for adventure, a passion for some-
ver. In our day the same thing is done, but always in the name of
"Vital Interests," and the new way represents, it is said, a great im-
casuistry of derivations
can see offhand that there is a world of dif-
ference between the two. So far "Vital Interests" has made few con-
verts among footpads and other exponents of private initiative in
brigandage. They are satisfied with a humbler divinity, and justify
their exploits by saying that they are trying "to live their own
1
lives."
Tacitus, Germania, 14: "If their home tribe (civitas) grows humdrum (torpeat)
through a long period of peace and inactivity, not a few nobles and young men
move on to other tribes which are at the time engaged in some war or other."
Michaud, Histoire dcs croisades, 1877 e(^-> Vol. I, p. 28 (Robson, Vol. I, pp. 54-56):
"Certainty of impunity, hope of a better lot, licentious hankerings and yearning for
relief from most sacred burdens, attracted multitudes to the standards of the
Crusade. Personal ambitions were not altogether stranger to their devotion to the
cause of the Lord Jesus. If religion held out its rewards to those who went to
fight in its behalf, fortune also promised worldly wealth and power [To such as
were knights.]. Crusaders returning from the East spoke in glowing terms of the
wonders they had seen, of the rich countries they had visited. It was generally
known that two or three hundred Norman pilgrims had conquered Apulia and
Sicily from the Saracens. .Robert of Friesland, second son to the Count of
. .
Flanders and therefore destined not to share in the property of his house, said
to his father: 'Give me men and ships and I will go and conquer a state for
myself from the Saracens in Spain.' That sort of harangue is common enough in
the fiction of the Middle Ages and faithfully reflects prevailing states of mind:
'Beau sire, baillez-moi hommes suffisans pour me jaire cstat ou royaume.' 'Beau
"
fils, aurez ce que demandez.'
1463 PROGRESS 925
of the poorer classes and prevents the children of the poor from
romping and playing in the streets. It fills the homes of poor farmers
and country-dwellers with dust. All that is tolerated in deference to
the god Progress (in appearances at least; in reality the interests of
is
commonly found in other religions: the individual is blamed for
what actually is a consequence of the general order of things. An
accident occurs. Actually it is a consequence of the great speed at
which automobiles are allowed to run. But the blame is laid on the
chauffeur, who
appropriately rebaptized for the occasion as a
is
chauffard. In that way the real cause is kept out of sight and the
danger of any reform avoided. So in countries where political
cor-
1
1463 Says Emile de Saint-Auban in Figaro (reprinted, Gazette de Lausanne,
Mar. 29, 1912): "Let a school-teacher cuff a sulking schoolboy and he looks like a
savage today: he has violated the rights of the brat and the citizen. He is a sinner
against our accepted type of civilization. He is more vigorously denounced than
his associate next door who denies his country in open class-room. But the hit-
and-run driver (ecraseur), who cultivates the sevcnty-miles-an-hour average in
contempt of the insignificant pedestrian, is guilty of just a peccadillo. There is
absolution, or almost that, for the automobile whose sins are mortal only for the
silly people it kills. I personally witnessed the exploit of the tremendous auto-bus
that went zigzagging down the rue Notre-Dame-des-Victoires like a drunk on a
tear (comme un pochard) and hit two children. Some who saw it were enraged.
But one gentleman could not understand that: 'It's not the bus's faultl' he pro-
tested. 'That man
learning to drive!' The auto-bus was just going to school!
is
may make his conduct conform with the sentiments, real or as-
sumed, of human beings, or of mind in the abstract ("the mind"),
out of simple reverence for the opinion of the majority or of experts
who are spokesmen for "the mind." That gives us derivations of the
III-cc variety. 2. Or an individual may act as he acts out of fear of
(Class IV).
1467. With this III-a variety accord with the sentiments of the
author of the derivation are also to be classed. He reasons not ob-
strictly,
to Class IV.
1468. In concrete cases the three attitudes distinguished in 1466
are often combined; but the second (fear of consequences), which
is
very important when
divine personifications are involved, is often
find that exact definition, and it often takes the form of an assertion
that the accord in ideas is identical with an accord in the objects cor-
responding (594-95). The contention more or less is that "if a
notion exists in the minds of all men, or of the majority of men, or
in mind in the abstract (in 'the mind'),
it
necessarily corresponds
to an objective
reality." Often, however, that is not stated it is tac-
itly
taken for granted: in other words it is left implicit, not made
explicit,
no verbal form being given to the II- residue to which it
corresponds. Sometimes it is stated, now in one form, now in an-
what exists in every human mind was put there by God and must
therefore necessarily correspond to an objective reality. That is the
favourite procedure of theologians, though it is used by other
a
1468 That is the answer to the question raised in 597-98 (as to the reasons
for the wide-spread acceptance of certain metaphysical theories that are in them-
selves meaningless). Here we must confine ourselves chiefly to accords of senti-
ments that may be taken as operating of their own intrinsic force (III-a).
928 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1470
thinkers too. Then the very pretty theory of "reminiscence,"
there is
cept on the human mind, which now in its turn reveals it to us; or,
working the other way round, one may start with the concept and
1
in virtue of some
metaphysical principle conclude that God exists.
"Greeks and Barbarians," says Sextus Empiricus, "recognize that
a
there are gods"; and Maximus of Tyre, Dissertationes, XVII, 4-5
(Taylor, Vol. pp. 6-7), adds to the list: "That is admitted by
I,
graved upon all minds by the Creator Himself or that it is a remnant of a tradition
going back to the origins of the human race, since it is found at all times as
"
well as in all countries of the Earth.* Gousset, Op. cit., p. 309: "Prophecies are
possible . . The Jews and the Christians have always believed in prophecy.
.
The and the heathen held the same belief. All peoples have preserved
patriarchs
some memory of predictions foretelling a Messiah to whom the nations could look
forward. The possibility of prophecies must therefore be conceded. The peo-
. . .
ples would never have agreed in believing them possible if the belief did not rest
on tradition, experience, reason." It is the same with prophecy as with miracles.
Ibid., pp. 342-43: "Belief in the immortality of the soul goes back to the infancy
of the world ... it has been a fundamental dogma of religion with the Hebrews,
the Christians and the patriarchs. The same belief is to be found among other
peoples, even the most uncivilized peoples. And that belief has been handed
. . .
down to the moderns. When European travellers discovered America and other
far-away countries, they found no race of people that did not have its conception
of a life to come."
a
1470 Contradictiones, IX, Adversus physicos II, De diis, 60 (565) (Opera, Vol.
II, P- 565)-
1471 EXISTENCE OF THE GODS: ANCIENT VIEWS 929
many people there were at that time who were far from seeing eye
2
to eye with Maximus of Tyre!
1471. Maximus of Tyre tries to answer an objection that is
gen-
erally raised in such cases: that, as a matter of fact, from the
"all"
who are said to hold certain views quite a few persons who do not
hold them have to be excepted; and he extricates himself from the
order of the world; the third is the absurd um into which those who deny gods
are drawn; the fourth and last is the confutation of those who deny. And they
argue from common opinion, for all men, Greeks and Barbarians, believe that
there are gods." Sextus's second reason is based on a Class II residue (group-
amends "the whole world" to "the whole Christian world." A. L.] According to
Plutarch,De placitis philosophorum, I, 6, 9 (Goodwin, Vol. Ill, p. 117), the idea
of worshipping gods came from three sources: from the
philosophers, through
nature; from the poets, through poetry; and from the consensus of the practices
of the cities.
930 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY I
47 I
"In course of time," he says, Op. cit., XVII, 5, "there may have been
two or three abject and stolid atheists, whose eyes see crosswise and
whose ears hear amiss spiritual eunuchs, idiots, sterile, fatuous peo-
ple, so many lions without courage, so many bulls without horns,
so many birds without wings! But even from them you will learn
that the divine exists." Abuse of one's adversaries is fatuous from
the logico-experimental point of view. It may be very effective in-
1 2 3
deed from the standpoint of sentiments. (For footnote 3 see page
93I-)
*
1471 The argument is common enough even today, as examples in
circular
surfeit e.g., Tolstoy, The Four Gospels, Vol. I, Preface, p. xx: "I have found
show;
good people, not in one, but in all churches and sects, and saw how they were all
guided in their lives by one and the same idea, that had its foundation on the
teaching of Jesus." Who arc these "good people"? If Tolstoy is using the words in
their ordinary meanings, he cannot be unaware that there are plenty of "good
people" who are far from agreeing with him and who in particular withhold
their assent from such of his doctrines as condemn all war, incite to evasion of
"good." First they exclude from the category of "good people" all individuals
who have different notions. They, necessarily, are "bad people." On the other
hand they believe, or imagine, that they are deriving their notions from the teach-
ings of a man whom they revere, love, admire: really, they are making his teach-
ings over to fit notions of their own. In the case of Tolstoy and his followers the
man happens to be Jesus; but it would make no difference if he were some other
person Buddha, Mohammed, Socrates. Tolstoy's statement simply means: "By
'good people* I mean people who subscribe to doctrines in which I think I
recognize the teaching of Jesus as I choose to conceive that teaching."
2
1471 Plato, like Maximus of Tyre, gets out of the same predicament by
abusing his adversaries: De
le gibus, X. There were those who denied gods and
therefore made it
necessary for him to prove their existence. He calls them insuf-
ferable people, properly to be hated. Wroth as he is against them, he musters his
self-control and tries to give the floor to such corrupt, sensuous, and silly persons,
some of whom go so far as to say that the stars are not divinities but masses of
earth and stone! A fine example, that, of the difference between that knowledge
1472 DERIVATIONS Ill-a! ACCORD WITH SENTIMENTS 93!
1472. The assertion that all peoples had some conception or other
of gods was not left unanswered. It was doubted or even flatly de-
nied. The question itself has little bearing on the matter here in
hand. We need simply note that, as usual, "gods" and "God" are
not very sharply defined terms. One can find or not find the concept
1
in the mind of this or that people as one chooses.
of "things in themselves," which the divine Plato had and which his modern
imitators after him possess, and the experimental knowledge of modern astron-
omers. Nco-Hegelians would confer a great favour on us by explaining just how
they reconcile the "absoluteness" of their knowledge with such changes in science.
Or is it, perhaps, that they still hold to Plato's conception and think the stars
are gods?
8
1471Bayle, Continuation dcs Pensees diverses, 18, quoting Father Rapin,
intelligences of his time, but who with advancing age became so partisan in his
views as to see in Tolstoy only an unfortunate who had gone morally bankrupt
and was worthy at the most of pity." We are therefore placed in the dilemma
either of accepting Tolstoy's theories, which many people regard as not at all
sound, or of being declared "partisan." But why do people use such cardboard
artillery? Evidently because there are other people who are as afraid of it as of
the real, and who, instead of laughing
as they ought, feel of their ribs at every
detonation to make
sure they have not been hurt.
x
1472 Cicero, De natura deorum, I, 23, 62-63. Velleius had taken general con-
sensus as proof of the existence of the gods. Cotta replies: "You say that the fact
that that has been the opinion of all races and nations of men is sufficient reason
for us to admit that there are gods. That would be a trifling argument even if it
were not false. In the first place, how do you know what the ideas of the various
races are? For my part I imagine that there are many people so barbarous that
no conception of deity is to be found among them. And how about Diagoras,
who was called an atheist, and after him, Theodorus? Did they not openly deny
divinity (nonne aperte deorum naturam sustulerunt)?" Diodorus Siculus, Bibli-
otheca historica, III, 9, 2 (Booth, Vol. I, p. 156), asserts that some few Ethiopians
denied the existence of gods. Miot remarks on the point in his notes to his trans-
lation of Diodorus, Vol. II, pp. 478-79: "The ancients believed that there was no
people on the surface of the Earth that professed atheism, and the unanimous con-
sensus of all peoples on the point has always been taken as one of the main proofs
932 THE MIND AND SOCIETY I
473
1473. A drawn between "all peo-
further distinction seems to be
between simple souls who represent general opinion and certain in-
dividuals who are for ever splitting hairs. The atheists would fall
within the latter group, and their opinions could then legitimately
be met with the good sense of the majority.
1474. Again as usual, the derivation answers both "yea" and
"nay"; and the failure of universal consensus has been used by some
to impugn the existence of the gods and of moral laws. Plato accuses
the Sophists of doing that. What in brief they seem to have said is
that the gods did not exist by nature but by "art," being different
say, it
seems to be so obvious that things stand thus and so that one
assumes, without feeling called upon to say as much, that things
must seem thus and so to all men, or to the majority. Sometimes
consensus is
put forward explicitly as proof ( 592 f.). Then again
it is in its turn demonstrated by reference to some other metaphys-
Such reasonings have ever been met in vain with the
ical principle.
place Strabo is very guarded in his assertion: "some say," "are deemed." Then
even if he were altogether positive there would still be the question of his authori-
ties.
Finally and it is the weightiest consideration the existence or non-existence
of universal consensus proves nothing.
*
1475 Cicero uses both methods (offering consensus as proof, and proving the
consensus with a metaphysical adjunct). Velleius says in De natura deorum, I,
17, 44: "That to which all men by nature consent is necessarily true (De quo
autem omnium natura consentit id verum esse neccsse est)" That might be suffi-
cient in itself. Since he began by saying that all men have some notion of gods,
1476 EXISTENCE OF THE GODS! ANCIENT VIEWS 933
1476. Analysis of nearly all concrete derivations yields a deriva-
tion of universal consensus or a consensus of the majority, the hon-
est, the wise, of the human mind, of Right Reason, of the balanced,
sensible man, and so on. Very very often it is implicit: then again
it is
disguised under one form- or another in impersonal expressions
such as "It is believed," "It is understood," "It is thought," and the
the conclusion logically follows: "Therefore it must be admitted that there are
gods (Esse igitur deos confitendum cst)" But Velleius is not satisfied with that
much: he wants further to explain, I, 16, 43, how and why men came by the
notion, and he praises Epicurus for demonstrating the existence of the gods in an
experimental manner that quite contrasts with the senseless vagaries of other
philosophers: "For he was the first to see that there were gods from the fact that
Nature herself had imprinted the concept of divinity on the minds of all men
(Solus cnim vidit primum esse Deos, quod in omnium animis eorum notionem
impressissct ipsa natura)" He would be saying exactly the same thing had he
said simply that the notion of divinity is present in the minds of all men; but he
drags in our old friend Dame Nature, because that metaphysical entity gives a
semblance of authority to his assertion. However he does not stop there: the
notion is a
"pre-notion," loc. cit.: "For what race, what family of men, is without
as it were a foreknowledge of the gods quite apart from any learning? That
is what Epicurus calls Tr^A^c ,
in other words, a notion of a thing that is
held in advance (anfceptam) by the mind and without which nothing can be
known and no investigation, no argument, is possible." From that, and from the
principle that everything enjoying universal consensus is true, Velleius goes on
to infer, I, 17, 45, that the gods are immortal and live in bliss, just as he could
infer any other pretty thing, if he chose: "From that we therefore conclude that the
gods are blessed and immortal; for that same Nature which gave us our knowledge
of the gods [Dame Nature is an accommodating soul and will say anything one
would have her say.] has also graven it upon our hearts that they are eternal and
blissful.'* Balbus repeats, II, 4, 12, that the main issue is agreed upon by "all men
of all nations; for the belief that gods exist is innate in all men and as it were
engraved upon their souls.*' The existence of the gods, he avers, II, 2, 4, is self-
evident. Opinions differ as to what they are like, II, 5, 13, but no one denies their
existence: "Quales sint, varium est: esse nemo negat" However he allows himself
to be enticed into giving a proof, II, 9, 23: "But though I began otherwise . . .
and held that the point did not need discussion, since it was self-evident to every-
one that the gods exist, I should nevertheless prefer that it be corroborated by
reasons of physic." Cotta then makes a remark that should be repeated in every
similar situation that Balbus keeps bringing on new proofs because he feels that
his demonstration has not been conclusive, III, 4, 9: "You have seen fit to prove the
existence of the gods with those many arguments because you are not sure that
it is all as obvious as you would like to have it." And he goes on flatly to deny
majority.
1477. III-/?:Accord with individual interest. To induce a person
to do a certain thing A, which he would not do of his own accord,
various devices may be used and not all of them are derivations.
1478. Not derivations are the following: i. The person does not
know that it would be advantageous for him to do A. He is shown
that would be. To show just such things is the function of experi-
it
doing of A is
required by the person's own temperament so that
1
failure to do it
brings him remorse or sorrow.
1479. Derivations, instead, are the following: 4. The blunt asser-
tion that doing A
will be advantageous (in reality it will not be)
to the person in question and that refraining from doing will be A
1
detrimental to him. This device corresponds to i above, provided
the inferences are not logico-experimental. The typical case is the
taboo with spontaneous sanction inherent in the taboo. The residues
exploited in such derivations are those, on the whole, that are used
in derivations of assertion (Class I) and authority (Class II). 5.
each in turn.
1481. Device 4: Pseudo-experimental demonstration. The type is
the taboo with sanction. We
have already discussed the taboo with-
out sanction ( 321 f.). The idea is that violation of the taboo ex-
always manage to get together to guarantee the full inviolability of the taboos.
The chiefs are for the most part arifa themselves. At the very least the aritys are
closely connected with the chiefs by ties of kinship or marriage."
1484 TABOOS AND THEIR SANCTIONS 937
*
1482. Reinach is inclined to think that the biblical injunction to
honour father and mother was a taboo. In its primitive form it was
something to probably: "Insult not (strike not
this effect .) thy . .
In inaugurating the reform the taboo that affected women was first dealt with.
The King waited for a general holiday when the natives gathered in throngs about
the palace to attend the royal banquet. The rugs being arranged and the foods
appointed for the men set thereon, with the food for the women on other rugs,
the King came up, selected a number of delicacies that were forbidden the women,
went over to their side, and began to eat of them and to invite the women to
share. Straightway loud cries of horror arose on all sides: 'Taboo!' 'Taboo!' But
Rio-Rio paid no attention and continued eating. The priests came hurrying from
the morai, whence they had been summoned by the crowd. That in fact is a
manifest violation of the taboo,' they said. 'But why do the offended gods not
inflict their own vengeance? Either they are good-for-nothing gods or false
. . .
gods.' 'Come, ye people of Hawaii,' cried the chief priest at this point, let us
have done with this annoying, absurd, and barbarous form of worship!' And he
took a torch and himself set fire to the principal moral." The missionaries, says
De Rienzi, applauded. But could they have been sure that their own taboos
would have stood the test of experiment any better? Draper, History of the Conflict
between Religion and Science, p. 77: "Though her [Rome's] military renown
was thus recovered [after the victories of Heracleus], though her territory was re-
gained, there was something that the Roman Empire had irrevocably lost. Re-
ligious faith could never be restored. In face of the world Magianism had insulted
Christianity by profaning her most sacred places Bethlehem, Gethsemane, Calvary
by burning the sepulchre of Christ ... by carrying off, with shouts of laughter,
the cross. Miracles had once abounded in Syria, in Egypt, in Asia Minor: there
was not a church which had not its long catalogue of them. Very often they were
displayed on unimportant occasions and in insignificant cases. In this supreme
moment, when such aid was most urgently demanded, not a miracle was worked.
Amazement filled the Christian populations of the East when they witnessed these
Persian sacrileges perpetrated with impunity. ... In the land of miracles, amaze-
ment was followed by consternation consternation died out in disbelief." And
see 1948 \
1488 DERIVATIONS HI-/?: ACCORD WITH INTERESTS 939
as regards definiteness, to leave nothing to be desired. "I am a be-
1
liever," says Bentham, "in the principle of 'utility' . . . when I use
the terms 'just/ 'unjust/ 'moral/ 'immoral/ 'good/ 'bad/ as collective
terms standing for the concepts of certain pains and certain pleas-
ures, without attaching any other sense to them, I want it distinctly
understood that I take the words 'pain' and 'pleasure' in their ordi-
approbation into the balance. That gets the altruistic principle in!
But it is not enough. It has to be reconciled with the first
principle
(absolute selfishness). So Bentham points out that the disapproba-
tion of others is harmful to the individual, so that it is to his advan-
1
tage to avoid it. And with that he has withdrawn the concession
*
1486 Traite de legislation civile et penale (Dumont), Vol. I, p. 4 (Atkinson,
Vol. I, p. 4).
1486
2
He goes on to say, Ibid., Vol. I, p. 317 (Atkinson, Vol. I, p. 268): "It is
absurd to talk of human happiness save in terms of the desires and sensations that
human beings actually feel. It is absurd to try and show by computation that a man
ought to be happy when he knows that he is miserable." Yet that is the very thing
that Bentham does. And cf. Deontology, Vol. II, p. 121: "Every man is able to
form the best estimate of his own pleasures and his own pains."
*
1488 Deontology, Vol. I, p. 84: ". . . It might happen that the act which
promises the present pleasure might prove prejudicial to others in the society to
which you belong, and they, having sustained an injury at your hands, would,
if prompted by self-preservation alone, seek to avenge themselves by the inflic-
940 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1488
he has made. If a thief is told, "If your theft is discovered, you will
be disliked and suffer from it," he can answer: "Weighing the pleas-
ure I will get from the thing I want to steal against the probable
pain I
may suffer, I find the pleasure greater than the pain." In that
case we can make no answer without going counter to the principle
we posited, that "pain and pleasure are what each person feels as
happy. "2. Social sanction. Timothy had a sister, deeply interested in his happiness.
She reproved him at first, then neglected, then abandoned him. She had been to
him a source of pleasure it was all swept away." But what if he had had no
sister? Or suppose he had one and she had stood by him? And what if she were
the sort of person whom it is better to lose than to keep? Walter, instead, has a
brother who has been indifferent to him but who eventually becomes very fond
of him. "3. Popular sanction. Timothy was a member of a club which had money
and reputation. He went thither one day in a state of inebriety. He abused the
secretary and was expelled by an unanimous vote. The regular habits of Walter
had excited the attention of his master. He said one day to his banker: 'That
young man is fitted for a higher station.' The banker bore it in mind and on the
1489 BENTHAM'S "GREATEST HAPPINESS" PRINCIPLE 941
1489. So proof is not very convincing, and its
this first line of
1
weakness seems not to have escaped Bentham altogether; for he
resorted thereafter to a second proof, utilizing another principle,
"the greatest happiness of the greatest number," and so calling into
2
play our residues of sociality (Class IV). In many connexions this
first opportunity took him into his service. He rose from one distinction to an-
other and was frequently consulted on business of the highest importance by men
of wealth and influence." One begins to suspect that Bentham must have been
living in Cathay or the land of Cockaigne, where all well-behaved individuals were
rewarded in that way. "4. Legal sanction ." Timothy is sentenced to deporta-
. .
tion. Walter becomes a judge. It is now certain that Bentham was living in
Cathay, or some other blessed country where sin is always punished and virtue
recompensed. There are countries where things do not run that smoothly. "5. Re-
ligious sanction." Timothy lives in fear of the life to come. Walter looks forward
to it with feelings of hope and peace. [For the Mark Twain allusion, see Index,
s.v. Clemens. A. L.]
*
1489 Deontology, Vol. I, p. 52: "By accident, no doubt, good repute may
attend upon ill-desert, and ill-repute upon good. But if this disastrous state of
things be possible, if it sometimes be witnessed, its continuance is of rare occur-
rence. Were there even more truth in it than there argument
is, the use of such an
litde becomes a moralist." So then, even must not be pressed; and
if it is true, it
that may very well be; but, in that case, Bentham ought to decide what he is
lector and publisher of Bentham's works, appends to the first volume a "History of
the Greatest Happiness Principle." Says he: "Dr. Priestley published his Essay on
Government in 1768. He there introduced, in italics [p. 17], as the only reason-
able and proper object of government, 'the greatest happiness of the greatest
"
number/ [The epithets "proper" and "reasonable" carry us back into the meta-
physics that Bentham thought he was avoiding.] That theory went "beyond all
notions that had preceded it. It exhibited not only happiness, but it made that hap-
piness diffusive. It associated it with the majority, with the many." [Asso-
ciated? It replaced one happiness with the other. For it is obvious enough
that this second principle is in many cases antithetical to the first.] "The phrase
'greatest happiness of the greatest number' was first employed by Mr. Bentham in
1822, in his Codification Proposal (Worlds, Vol. IV, pp. 535 f.). Every suggestion
there put forward is made to turn upon the requirements of the 'greatest happi-
"
ness of the greatest number.' Well and good, but that being the case, why do
you pretend that every man is sole judge of his own happiness; or that one "may
wear out the air with sonorous and unmeaning words: those words will not act
upon mind: nothing will act upon it but the apprehension of pleasure and
the
pain." However, Bentham seems not to have been entirely satisfied with his new
formula: "In the later years of Mr. Bentham's life the phrase 'greatest happiness
of the greatest number' appeared on closer scrutiny to be wanting in that clearness
and correctness which had originally recommended it to his notice and adoption
. .but though it ... did not satisfy Mr. Bentham, one may doubt whether
.
there be sufficient grounds for rejecting it." [Priestley's actual phrases, referred
942 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1490
new principle is antithetical to the first. By using the two principles
together one eliminates but does not solve the ethical problem that
Bentham had finding a way in such cases to reconcile
set himself, of
good sense and humanity by personal interest readily admit the ad-
vantages of liberty over slavery." But Bentham had banished "good
sense" and "humanity." What are they doing here ? And besides, if
the slave-owner were "humane," that alone would suffice to abolish
to by Bowring above, are: "the good and happiness of the members, that is of
the majority of the members, of any state"; and, in italics, "the good of the whole"
A. L.]
1489 We shall dispel the fog in due course (Chapter XII) by trying to reduce
8
pp. 269-73). He had said just previously, p. 318: "In any case if slavery were estab-
lished in such proportions that there would be but one slave for each master, I
might hesitate before pronouncing on the balance between the advantage of the
one and the disadvantage of the other. It might be that all considered the sum of
happiness by that arrangement would almost equal the sum of pain. But that is
not the way things go. The moment slavery is established it becomes the lot of the
greatest number. The advantage is all on the side of the one, the disadvantage
. . .
on the side of the multitude." On that principle one might find a majority can-
nibalism defensible. The disadvantage would belong to the few, the advantage to
the many.
1493 DERIVATIONS in-/?: ACCORD WITH INTERESTS 943
slavery and no theory based on strict
personal interest would be re-
2
quired.
Bentham's stumbling-blocks are primarily two: i. He tries
1491.
to make all conduct logical, and so loses touch with
reality, many
1
human actions being non-logical. 2. He tries to reconcile
by logic
principles that are logically antagonistic, the egoistic and altruistic
principles.
1492. The logico-experimental value of Bentham's theory is very
*
slight; and yet it enjoyed a great vogue. Why? For the same reason
that other theories of the kind have met with similar success: be-
cause it combines residues of personal integrity with residues of so-
ciality.
That is enough for people and they are not very particular
as to just how
they are brought together as to the derivation, in
other words. Bentham is inclined to include animals in his "greatest
number"; and so also is John Stuart Mill, who believes that "the
persons of the same mind (naturd) come together, they form an in-
dividual twice as strong as either. Nothing, therefore, is more useful
to man than man. Men, I say, can choose no course better calculated
to preserve their being than to agree all in everything." If two men
are starving and there is one loaf of bread, they would discover right
2
1490 In Op. cit., Vol. I, p. ii (Atkinson, Vol. I, p. 10), Bentham disenfran-
chises the "arbitrary principles" of sympathy and antipathy, and condemns appeals
to "Conscience or Moral Sense" and "Common Sense." At the time of his Intro-
duction to the Principles of Morality and Legislation (Works, Vol. I), Bentham
admitted the principles of sympathy and antipathy. He changed his mind later on
and rejected them.
*
1491 Deontology, Bowring's Preface, Vol. II, p. n: "There are, properly speak-
ing, but two parties in morals or politics and in religion. The one is for the un-
limited exercise of reason, the other is against it. I profess myself of the former."
*
1492 I have not the remotest intention of dealing with the intrinsic merits of
Bentham's theory or any other in these volumes ( 1404). I touch on the question
of its accord with the facts only for the light it throws on the subject of derivations.
2
1492 Deontology, Vol. I, pp. 13-15. For Mill, see his System of Logic, Bk. VI,
Chap. 12, 7 (p. 658). For a theory of Herbert Spencer designed to reconcile the
egoistic and altruistic principles see my Manuale, Chap. I, 29.
*
1493 Ethica f IV, 18, scholium (Latin, p. 216; Willis, p. 575).
944 THE MIND AND SOCIETY M94
away that nothing is more detrimental to a man than another man.
And the same sentiment would be shared by the man who found
that the woman he loved had another
Both lover and starving
lover.
man would suffer from the fact that other men were "of their same
mind (natura}" But Spinoza drives ahead and says that from his
principle it follows that "men who are governed by Reason [Need-
less to say anyone not agreeing with Spinoza is not
'governed by
Reason.'], that is to say, men who seek their own welfare under
guidance of Reason desire nothing for themselves that they do not
2
desire for other men, and so are just, honest and of good faith."
So the derivation changes in form, but the substance is still the
same: one achieves one's own welfare by achieving the welfare of
others. The same argument recurs in other writers of the eighteenth
3
century and turns up again in the modern doctrine of "solidarity."
Burlamaqui begins by finding a sanction for natural laws
1494.
in the harm that comes in natural course upon those who violate
them. That is a derivation like Bentham's. But, shrewd soul that
he Burlamaqui has a feeling that one should not trust Dame Na-
is,
ture too implicitly to enforce her laws, the good lady having fits of
absent-mindedness at times. So he brings in the sanction of a super-
natural and, stepping outside the experimental world, evades
life,
1
the objections that might be urged against him within it.
2
1493"&' cnim duo, exemplo gerendo, eiusdem prorsus naturae individua in-
vicem iungnntitr individttum component singulo duplo potentius. Homini igitur
nihil homine utilius; nihil, inquam, homines praestantius ad suum csse conservan-
dum optare possuntquam quod omnes in omnibus ita conveniant ex quibus
. . .
sequitur homines qui Ratione gubernantur, hoc cst, homines qui ex ductu Rationis
suum utile quaerunt, nihil sibi appetere quod reliquis hominibus non ctipiant, atquc
adeo eosdem iustos fidos atque honestos esse!'
3
1493 C/. Holbach, Systemc de la nature, Vol. II, p. 436: Chap. IX, "The True
Meaning of the System of Nature": "The purpose of man is self-preservation and to
lead a happy life. Experience teaches him that other people are necessary to him.
It shows him how he can make them useful to his designs. He sees what is ap-
proved and what causes displeasure. Such experiences give him a notion of
what is just. Virtue, like wickedness, is not founded on convention but on
relationships obtaining between the members of the human race. The mu-
tual obligations of men derive from their need of using means apposite to the
scrupulously to respect the rights of one's neighbours, is the only one that conforms
to realities. [No one of course has ever been known to get rich except by strictly
moral means!] . . . Every time a working-man uses violence to exact a wage
946 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1496
1496. The fallacy lies: i. In disregarding amounts of gain or loss,
on the assumption that all individuals are to act in one way or all
in another, and in not considering the case where some individuals
are to act in one way and some in another, 2. In going to extremes
along the line of the above and considering gains only, or losses
only. In fact, let us adopt the premise that if all individuals refrained
higher than the natural market-price [What on earth can such a natural market-
price be?], he robs himself. Every time an employer uses violence to force on the
worker a wage lower than the natural market-price, he robs himself. Try to imag-
ine what the world would be like if men should find it more in conformity with
their interests not to rob their neighbours and to refrain from doing so under any
form whatsoever! From that moment there would be no more locks, no more
strong-boxes, fortresses, battle-ships, no more watchmen, no more judges, lawyers,
police, no more soldiers by land or by sea ([In a note]: I am speaking of civil
actions of course there would still be crimes of passion). In such a society there
would be no litigations, no strikes, no sabotage, no lock-outs, no shady specula-
tion. ... In a word, in a non-robbing society, there would be the greatest and
most rapid production that can possibly be attained on this earth, and wealth,
therefore, would reach its culminating point. Now wealth, comfort, happiness, and
interest are synonymous terms. But then again, morality and absolute respect for
the rights of one's neighbour are also identical concepts. Since, therefore, our
interests are best satisfied when our manner of conduct is the most moral, how can
the identity of morality and interest be disputed? [The fallacy of the argument in
general becomes strikingly apparent in a particular case:] Is it really to a judge's
interest to accept a bribe? Certainly not, and when he does accept one, it is from
his failure to understand that there is no advantage in his doing so. ... Ex-
perience shows that judges draw the highest salaries in the very countries where
they do not sell their consciences. .
Incorruptibility on the part of judges con-
. .
tributes very considerably to increasing social wealth, and the greater the social
wealth, the better paid can public officials be. So a judge who is ill informed thinks
that he will get a larger return by selling justice. A judge who is well informed
knows that it is just the contrary. But a judge who knows that he will get larger
returns by avoiding corruption understands that it is to his interest to avoid cor-
ruption." Suppose we adopt the somewhat arbitrary premise that judges are better
paid when there is no corruption, and keep to the logical errors in the argument.
i. The dilemma assumed by Novicow does not exist. We are not necessarily con-
fined to a choice between a situation where
judges are corrupt and a situation
all
where no judges are corrupt. There are intermediate situations. If all judges but
one are incorruptible, the one enjoys the general advantage plus the individual
profits of his corruption. If all but one are corrupt, the one suffers the general loss
plus the particular loss of the profits of his corruption. 2. It is not enough to show
that honest judges are better paid than corrupt judges. It must also be shown that
the general gain is greater than the particular gain from the corruption. Honest
judges receive, let us say, $10,000 a year, corrupt judges $2,000. But one of the
corrupt judges is offered $30,000 for a decision. He would be the loser if he refused
the money on the remote, in fact the very remote, and uncertain chance of some
day being advanced to $10,000 a year.
1496 DERIVATIONS III-/? : ACCORD WITH INTERESTS 947
from doing A, every individual as a member of the community
would derive a certain advantage. But now if all individuals less one
continue refraining from doing A, the community loss is very slight,
whereas the one individual doing A makes a personal gain far
greater than the loss that he incurs as a member of the community.
The fact that the fallacy is not recognized at once is due to a residue
which usually interposes in such arguments implicitly and gives rise
to the first half of the fallacy. It is assumed, but not stated, that all
individuals are to act like the individual doing A. In such a case the
loss is distributed, while the direct gain, in great part at least, is
1496
*
Ajest that is variously recounted by various writers appears among the
facetiae of Poggio Bracciolini as follows, II, 158: "A usurer of Vicenza kept
urging a monk of great reputation who was regularly preaching to the people to
deliver some strong sermons on the subject of usury and roundly to condemn such
a great vice, which was especially rife in that city; and he pestered the monk
to the point of annoyance. One day, in surprise that he should be so insistent on
having a trade by which he himself lived rebuked, a certain person asked him the
reason for his great solicitude. And he: 'So many people are plying the trade of
the usurer in this town that I am getting very few customers and am earning
948 THE MIND AND SOCIETY *497
1497. A similar derivation was for some time used in defence of
izes his own welfare at the cost of B, C. The wolf realizes its . . .
nity.
A certain number of politicians want something for themselves.
They ask for it in the name of party, city, country. Certain factory-
hands want better conditions. What they demand is a betterment in
the conditions of the "proletariat" or the "working-classes." group A
of manufacturers want a favour from the government for their par-
ticular industry. They ask for it as a help to business in general or as
a benefit to the working-classes. For more than a half-century past,
nothing. If the others could be persuaded to go out of business, all their earnings
"
would come to me.' [Cf. Bandello, Novelle, Pt. Ill, no. 53, on the usurer Tom-
masone, this time at Milan. A. L.]
a
1497 For the detailed refutation see my Systemes socialities, Vol. II, pp. 225 f.
I5OI PROSECUTIONS OF ANIMALS 949
1499. Examples of that sort of derivation turn up before one has
read very far in any article written in support of a protective tariff,
or of an increase in public expenditures, or of one of the
many
measures whereby the "speculators" get their hands on money be-
longing to people who live on fixed, or virtually fixed, incomes
( 2235). I*1 politics all ruling classes have at all times identified their
own interests with the "interests of the
country." When politicians
are afraid of a too rapid increase in the number of proletarians,
they
are for birth-control and show that Malthusianism is to the interests
of public and country.
instead, they are afraid a population may
If,
tually all
commonly brought under it, on the
other derivations are
only ones known to us, we would not be able to say whether jurid-
ical actions were ever extended to animals. But, lo and behold, in
*
1501 Darembcrg-Saglio, Dictionnaire , s.v. Noxalis actio: "The proprietor is, in
certain cases, responsible for damage done by his animals. According to the Twelve
rule to damage caused by bipeds. The victim was authorized to prosecute the
proprietor of the animal through a special action called de pauperie [damage done
by an irresponsible party]. The proprietor had two options: either to give up the
animal (de ditto noxulis) or to repair the damage. The option of surrendering the
animal applied the principle that the owner of a thing that had caused a damage
could not be held liable beyond the value of the thing." In his Manuel elementaire de
droit romain, p. 393, note 4, Girard well points out how the theorists of Roman
law tried to remedy by derivations certain consequences of that group-persistence
which were considered harmful: "It is interesting to note the fruitless efforts of
jurists under the late Republic to adapt those old procedures to more modern no-
tions of responsibility, deciding that the damage must have been caused
by the
animal contra naturam and applying to fights between animals the
principles of
legitimate self-defence." Surrender of the animal still obtains under Burgundian
law: Lex Burgundiorum, XVIII, i (Canciani, Vol. IV, p. 19): "If a horse has killed
a horse or if an ox has gored or a dog bitten an ox so that it is
incapacitated
(debilitetur), the animal or dog against which the damage has been proved shall
be handed over to the man who has suffered the
damage."
2
1501 Beauchet, Histoirc du droit pnve de la republiquc athcnicnnc, Vol. IV,
p. 391: "In Athens the action called /Md/tyf
[corresponding to the action de pan-
pene of the XII Tables] seems to have been brought rather against the animal
than against the owner and with a view to
permitting the victim of the tort to
exercise the vindicta privata on the animal itself." The Athenian law
requiring
transfer of the offending animal to the offended
party was ascribed to Solon.
See Plutarch, Solon, 24, 3 (a biting dog in question).
8
1501 Demosthenes, Contra Aristocratem, 645 (Auger, Vol. VII, pp. 62-63):
not lawful to deny a trial to things inanimate and without reason
"If, therefore, it is
which are subject to such indictment [homicide] . .".
952 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1501
4
side the boundaries of the state. The law like other ancient laws is
quoted on Laws, IX, 873 (Bury, Vol. II, p. 267),
in Plato's treatise
where animals as well as inanimate things are mentioned as guilty
of homicide. The corpse of a patricide had to be thrown outside the
boundaries of the state in exactly the same manner (Bury, Vol. II, p.
259). Pausanias, Pcriegesis, VI, Elis II, n, 5-7, relates that, at Thasos,
one of the rivals of the champion runner, Theagenes, was in the
habit of thrashing his statue every night, and that finally to punish
the man it fell upon him and crushed him "The children of the dead
:
man then brought action against the statue for murder, and follow-
ing one of the Draconian laws, the Thasians threw it into the sea."
But a blight fell forthwith upon their territory, and the Delphic
oracle declared that it was because the Thasians "had forgotten the
mock trial for the murder of an ox. Anox was made to eat offerings
of fodder that were deposited on an altar, and he was then killed.
Then a trial was held before a court that had jurisdiction over mur-
ders committed by inanimate objects. Each of the actors in the drama
in turn laid the blame for the murder on his neighbour, until only the
ax with which the ox had been slain was left. The ax was thereupon
6
condemned and thrown into the sea. Phenomena of totemism may
4
1501 Aeschines, In Ctesiphontem, 88, 244; Aeschylus, Septem adversi4s Thebas,
v. 197 (203) (Scholia prota, Butler, p. 53); Pausanias, Pericgesis, VI, Elis, II, n, 6;
Suidas, Lexicon, s.v. Nkwv. Cases of that sort were archaic and of a religious
character. They were tried, therefore, at the Prytaneum: Demosthenes, Contra
Aristocratem , 645. Pausanias, Periegesis, I, Attica, 28, n, mentions a common be-
lief that certain inanimate objects brought about punishment for certain crimes
tell the truth, nothing certain or even very probable can be known on such a
matter. To set out to guess at the combinations that underlie a given derivation
is altogether hopeless when there is no direct testimony, and hardly less so when
there is very little. For our purposes we can stop at the fact that a prosecution was
directed simultaneously against human beings and an ax, as codefendants. [And
cf. further Pausanias, loc. cit., 28, 10. A. L.]
"Polybius, who accompanied Aemilianus, states that when lions get old
7
1501
they attack human beings, since they are no longer strong enough to hunt wild
prey. In such circumstance they begin to infest the cities of Africa, and he says
that he and Scipio saw some that had been crucified that others might be deterred
from by fear of similar punishment."
their depredations
8
1501 Gen. 9:5: "And surely your blood of your lives will I require. At the hand
of every beast will I require it, and at the hand of man, and at the hand of every
man's brother will I require the life of man." The animal is prosecuted quite in-
dependently of the owner. The animal that kills a man is held culpable and punished
as such. The owner is innocent: Ex. 21:28: "If an ox gore a man or a woman that
they die then the ox shall be surely stoned, and his flesh shall not be eaten; but the
owner of the ox shall be quit." Lev. 20:15-16: "And if a man lie with a beast, he
shall surely be put to death: and ye shall slay the beast. And if a woman approach
unto any beast and lie down thereto, thou shalt kill the woman and the beast:
they shall surely be put to death: their blood shall be upon them." So then, both
the woman and the beast! That delightful soul, Philo the Jew, works out a very
pretty derivation to account for these prescriptions: he imagines that the animal
is killed that it may not give birth to a monstrous lineage such as sprang from
the passions of Pasiphae and the bull: De le gibus spccialibus, III, 8 (Cohn, Vol. V,
pp. 162-64; Yonge, Vol. Ill, pp. 314-15): "So, whether a man or a woman be with
a quadruped, they shall be killed, human beings and quadrupeds alike; the males
because they have overstepped the prescribed bounds in contriving new forms of
lust and seeking a loathsome pleasure in unspeakably foul ways: the females be-
cause they have lent themselves to such iniquities, and to prevent them from giving
birth to such abominations as are commonly born of detestable crimes of that char-
acter."
9
1501 Gregorovius, Geschichte dcr Stadt Rom im Mittelalter, Vol. Ill, p. 246.
954 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY I5O2
Pope was convicted and his punishment fixed. [Animals were con-
victed and sentenced in the same way.] The Synod signed the de-
cree of deposition and pronounced sentence of condemnation."
The Inquisition also conducted many prosecutions against people
who were dead. The purpose was to get possession of such property
as the dead heretics had left to their heirs; and the means, popular
beliefs and among which the feeling that the
superstitions, not least
bull, Comte deValois; 1386, a sow, Falaise; 1389, a horse, Dijon; 1394, a pig, Mor-
tain; 1633, a mare, Bellac; 1647, a mare, Parlement, Paris; 1679, a mare, Parlement,
Aix; 1690, caterpillars, Auvergne; 1692, a mare, Moulins; i7th century (end),
pigeons, Canada; 1741, a cow, Poitou. In all ninety-two cases!
2
1502 Cabanes, Les indiscretions de I'histoire, Ser. 5, pp. 34-35: "Action was
opened against the animal by criminal process and procedure developed as follows.
A crime being reported, the delinquent animal was arrested and taken to the de-
tendon prison of the criminal court before which the preliminary investigation was
1502 DERIVATIONS III- 5: JURIDICAL ENTITIES 955
procedure was on the whole the same; but in many cases the process
seems to be an afterthought, as a means of avoiding hitting innocent
creatures with the fulminations of the Church; and there are cases
where mention is made only of the condemnation and not of any
8
trial. Next, under
pressure of the sentiment extending juridical re-
to be conducted. Affidavits were drawn up ... and a thorough-going inquest
opened. The facts being established beyond reasonable doubt, the prosecuting
attorney, in other words, the official exercising the functions of state prosecutor
within the feudal jurisdiction concerned, asked for the indictment and trial of the
defendant. Witnesses were heard and after their testimony in the affirmative the
prosecutor made his plea. The judge then rendered his verdict, declaring the
animal guilty of murder and sentencing him to be strangled and then hung by
the hind legs to an oak-tree or to the public gallows, according to local custom.
. . . The formalities of criminal procedure were so strictly observed in some places
that sentenceswould not be executed till a warrant had been read to the animal
itself in its Beaumanoir, Coutumes de Beauvaisis, II, 1944: "Some have
prison.*'
[courts of] justice on their lands, and execute animals when they have killed
someone. For instance, if a sow or some other animal kills a child, they hang it
and drag it [at the tail of a horse]. But that amounts to nothing, for mute beasts
have no understanding of what is right and what is wrong, and for that reason
such justice is I' Islam,
p. 132, note: "There is a
wasted." Trumelet, Les saints de
story . . .onethat
day the Calif, Omar-ben-el-Khoththah, cousin thrice removed to
Mohammed, found a scorpion on the carpet that he used as his bed. He was seized
with a doubt as to his right to kill one of God's creatures, and ... to have peace
with his conscience, he went to consult the Prophet, his relative, stating the
case to him. After reflecting for some moments, Mohammed answered that he
could not claim such right of destruction till the insect had thrice disobeyed him,
that is to say, until he had bidden it thrice to be gone."
8
1502 Etienne de Bourbon, Anecdotes historiqtics, 303-05* "They say that
animals are afraid of the sentence of excommunication and avoid it, as a result
of example and divine miracles. I am told that at the time Pope Gregory IX was
Legate of the Apostolic See in Lombardy before he became Pope, he visited a town
where he found certain nobles (maiores) fighting, so that they interfered with his
journey. He therefore excommunicated the leader of the dissension who was alone
standing in the way of peace. That individual however snapped his fingers (con-
tempneret) at the excommunication. Whereupon the many cranes who had been
nesting on the towers and chimneys of his house departed thence and moved their
nests to the house of the other leader in the feud aforesaid, who stood ready to
obey the decision of the Legate. Seeing which the obdurate leader humbled his heart
to the extent of asking absolution and doing the will of the Legate." In that we
have a case of innocent animals shunning a person who has been excommunicated.
Here now are cases where animals are themselves excommunicated! "I
am likewise told that at Macon [in France] many sparrows were in the
. . .
habit of entering the Church of St. Vincent, dirtying the building and interfering
with mass. When there seemed to be no way of keeping them out, the Bishop in
that place excommunicated them, threatening them with death if they went
. . .
into the church again; whereupon they withdrew from the church and never
again entered it. [To tell the unadorned truth, the poor sparrows were excommu-
956 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1502
pests,
and they were not allow proceedings to drag
at all loath to
nicated without trial and Etienne himself is an eyewitness to the efficacy of the
sentence:] myself saw flocks of them nesting, flying, or sitting about the church,
I
but never a one did I see inside, and it is common opinion in the town that if
anyone catches a sparrow and takes it by force inside the church, it dies the mo-
ment it is inside. [The Bishop's excommunication is no whit more miraculous in
its effects than Rousseau's social contract, which continues to have believers though
it can boast no eyewitness.] I have also heard from a number of our friars that
there was once a certain Bishop in Lausanne who had fishermen on the lake.
One night he sent them out to fish for eels, and they set their nets in the lake
and caught snakes along with the eels. One of the men crushed their heads with
his teeth, thinking them eels, and in the morning when he saw that they were
snakes he was so horrified that he died of his disgust. Hearing which the
. . .
Bishop excommunicated the eels in case they should remain any longer in those
waters. However, they all departed thence and since that time, it is said, there
have been no eels in the lake."
4
1502 De I'origine, de la forme et de I'esprit des jugements rendus au moyen
age contre les animaux, pp. 7-23. It contains the record of a trial conducted in the
year 1587 against a certain insect ( Rynchites auratus grape-vine weevil) that was
ruining the vineyards at Saint-Julien near Saint-Jean de Maurienne. The same
record is summarized and in part reprinted in a volume called Curiosites des
traditions, des mceiirs, et des legendes, pp. 429-31. "The vines [at Saint-Julien] are
subject at certain intervals to depredations from a green beetle called the amble vin
(vine walker ?) or verpillon (green-worm ?)." Court records of the year 1587 "show
that forty-two years before (in 1545) a similar action had been entered between the
same parties, but the destroying insects having disappeared, the plaintiffs had not
seen fit to go on with the case. At that time a first hearing had been held for ar-
bitration purposes before the Honourable Francois Bonnivard, doctor of laws, Attor-
ney Pierre Falcon representing the insects, with Attorney Claude Morel as assistant
counsel. Negotiations failing, the syndics of Saint-Julien brought action before the
judge (Official) at Saint-Jean de Maurienne, and entered formal suit."
ecclesiastical
Expert testimony was heard, counsel on both sides summed up, "and the court is-
sued an order temporarily setting aside the petition of the inhabitants of Saint-Julien,
who had asked for the excommunication of the insects, and prescribing public
prayers. . . . The action of 1545, which had been left in abeyance for forty-two
years owing to the disappearance of the devastating insects, was reopened in 1587
1502 PROSECUTIONS OF ANIMALS 957
within our reach many of the derivations that came to the fore in
such trials. "An
action initiated in 1451 ... for the purpose of ex-
under penalty of the law. The insects failing to appear, the summons
when the unlucky Coleoptera had made a new invasion of the vineyards and per-
haps a more alarming one than usual. This new case is entitled [in Latin] 'Action :
of the Syndics of the Commune of Saint-Julien against brute animals, winged like
"
flies, and of a green colour, commonly called verpillons or amble vins! The syndics
"
request the Reverend Official 'at his pleasure to appoint a new attorney to replace
the former who had passed from this life by death, to designate in advance of trial
a competent commissioner to inspect the damaged vineyards, the defendant party
having been summoned to attend the inspection if it be his pleasure [No more, no
less!], whereafter procedure shall be taken for the eviction of said animals by way
of excommunication or interdict and all other due ecclesiastical censure, they, the
syndics, signifying their readiness to appoint to said animals, on behalf of the com-
"
mune, lands where they will have sufficient pasturage in future.' The action
develops. The attorneys present briefs. There are answers and rejoinders. Finally
"the syndics could not have had any great confidence in the soundness of their case
at law, since they saw fit to make a prime issue of the compromise that they had
suggested at the outset of the action in a wholly secondary way.*' They convoked a
meeting of the Commune " 'to the end of giving effect to earlier offers, by deeding
to the weevils a place where said little animals would find sustenance.' Each . . .
of those attending having expressed his opinion, all agreed to offer the weevils a
piece of land situate above the village of Claret ... 'of fifty-six acres (seterees)
more or less, and which attorneys representing said animals are willing to accept
. . . said piece of land being occupied by several sorts of trees, plants, and foliage,
such as ferns (P joulx), beeches (? alagniers), cherry-trees, oaks ... in addition
to grassand pasture, which are there in fairly good quantity.' In making that offer
the inhabitants of Saint-Julien thought best to reserve the right of thoroughfare
through said parcel of land for purpose both of reaching properties situate beyond,
'without however causing any damage to pasturage of said animals,' and of working
certain 'mines of colour' (ochre), situate near by. 'And since,' they add, 'the place
is a safe retreat in time of war, being well supplied with springs, which will also
be of use to said animals,' they further reserve the privilege of repairing thither in
case of necessary defence, promising on the terms specified to cause to be drawn
up 'in favour of the insects herein named* a deed to said parcel of land 'in regular
form and valid in perpetuity.' On July 24, Petremand Bertrand, attorney for the
plaintiffs, produced in duplicate a copy from the minutes of the resolution adopted."
"
He moves that, in case the defence fails to accept, 'it shall be the
pleasure of
TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1502
was usually repeated, sometimes as many as three times in order
that the contumacy might be better established. ... As one
may
well imagine, the defendants and a curator
always defaulted . . .
period of grace allotted them had been insufficient, that the court
should have taken into account not only the distance of the
places
but also the difficulties of the journey to court, a
difficulty aggravated
by the fact that cats were always on watch and were
blocking every
hole big and little. In short, combining Bible with
profane literature,
piling texton text, and exhausting every resource of the learned
of those days, he succeeded in
eloquence having their date of ap-
pearance deferred. The case made Chassanee a much-sought
attorney."
the Reverend Official to give judgment on the basis of his
contention, to the effect
that said defendants be ordered to quit said vineyards in the Commune, under in-
"
junction of never again trespassing thereon in future, under penalties of the law/
On Sept. 3, "Antoine Filliol, attorney for the insects, notified his refusal in behalf
of his clients to accept the offer made by the inasmuch as the land offered
plaintiffs,
was barren and of no yield (cum sit locus sterilis et nullitts rcdditus}, to which
Petremand Bertrand replied that far from being barren, 'said land abounded in
shrubbery and small trees well suited to the sustenance of the defendants.' The
Official thereupon orders the papers filed. The part of the sheet on which the
court's decision was entered has fallen prey to time; but enough is left to show that
before finally disposing of the action, the Official to report on the
appointed experts
serviceability of the land offered the weevils." The notion of assigning to the insects
a place where they could live is not confined to the action here in
question. There
are other examples. Hammerlein, a writer
quoted by Menabrea, states that after a
regular action at law, the inhabitants of Coire (Switzerland) provided certain
Cantharides (Spanish beetles) with a place where they could live. "Even
today,"
Hammerlein adds, "the inhabitants of the Canton make a formal annual contract
with the beetles, handing over to them a certain parcel of land. So true is it that
they are satisfied and never try to overstep the specified boundaries."
1504 DERIVATIONS III-5: JURIDICAL ENTITIES 959
1503. That all seems ridiculous to us; yet who can be sure that
some few centuries hence the disquisitions of our day on the subject
of solidarity will not seem equally ridiculous, and that M. Leon
thought that the procedures used against rational beings could not
be extended to brute creatures, and among the theologians stood
1
St. Thomas Aquinas, no less. But nothing of that sort could put an
end to such trials;
any more than in our time demonstrations of the
utter inanity of the "social contract," of "solidarity,"
"peace through
law," "Christian Science," and other such vagaries can put an end
to the use of their respective derivations. As usual,
everyone sees the
mote in his neighbour's eye, never the beam in his own.
1504. Derivations change in form to accommodate themselves to
circumstances, but the goal to which they are expected to lead re-
mains unchanged. Among the many theorists who have represented
human society as originating in some convention, pact, or contract,
not a few have talked as though they were describing a historical
incident: certain human beings not as yet living in society came to-
gether somewhere one fine day and organized human society, very
much as people in our day get together and organize a business
corporation.
a ae
1503
x
Summa
theologiae, II II , qu. 76, art. 2 (Opera, Vol. IX, p. 144:
Utrum creaturam irrationalem maledicere) "To curse irrational creatures as
liceat :
being creatures of God of the order of rational creatures (ad rationale creaturam
ordinatae) is blasphemy. To
them for what they are is illicit [i.e., sinful],
curse
since it is an Decretum Gratiani, pars 2, causa 15, quaestio I,
idle fatuous thing.*'
canon 4 (Friedberg, Vol. I, p. 747): "An animal with which a woman has had to
do is killed not as a culprit but as a reminder of the crime. Whence Augustine on
Lev. 20:74, i: The question is: how can an animal as an irrational creature in
animals were ordered killed because once contaminated by such a shame they would
"
ever be refreshing the distressing memory of it.' Menabrea, Op. cit., pp. 138-41,
reprints the Discours des monitoires avec un plaidoyer contre les insectcs by Gaspard
Bally of Chambery, a lawyer who lived in the second half of the seventeenth cen-
tury. contains model specimens of pleas for and against insects as well as for
It
to curse such animals if they be taken in themselves, we claim that in the matter
in hand we take them not as animals merely, but as causing harm to human beings
by eating and destroying the fruits that serve for their food and sustenance. But
why do we hesitate when there are precedents in quantity where Holy Authorities
"
have excommunicated animals that do harm to human beings?' The Official ends
"
his decision with the words: 'In the name and by the power of the Father, God
omnipotent, and the Son, by order to the purport of this sentence (a monitione in
vim sententiae huius) that they shall depart from the vineyards and lands of this
place, doing no further damage thereon nor elsewhere: if within the said number
of days said animals shall not have obeyed this order . . . when the six days have
and the authority of the Blessed Apostles Peter and Paul, along with that which
we exercise in this place, we serve warning in this script upon said worms and
caterpillars and said animals by whatever name they are called that within six . . .
"
days we herein place them under anathema and malediction.' It is interesting that
Sally's book, as he himself states, was printed with permission of the Senate of
Savoy, "having been seen and examined by the gentlemen of that distinguished
body and reported on with praise."
1505 *Essai d'une philosophic dc la solidarite, p. 46: "Then, it will be said, sol-
idarity is the social contract! I am willing! I will keep the expression [He is right:
they are all variationson the same musical theme.], on condition, however, that
our social contract be not mistaken for Rousseau's. Rousseau's hypothesis as he
thought of it was merely that, and not a fact of history."
1508 INTERNATIONAL "RIGHTS" 96 1
extreme poverty. From the standpoint of formal logic, therefore,
the argument cannot stand even in its new form.
1506. Nor is it easy to see why the contract should not hold just
as well for animal societies such as the ants and the bees. If we
assume that nothing but reasoning and logical thinking can hold
human society together and prevent its dissolution, how explain the
fact that the societies of ants and bees hold together and endure in
time ? But we say that such societies are grounded on instinct. How
deny that that instinct plays its
part in human societies as well ?
departure and the goal are fixed because they correspond to certain
residues that are the constant element in the movement. Only a
little
imagination required to find a derivation that will bring
is
the two points together. If one does not hit the mark, others will
be devised; and so only they tickle certain residues in the people to
whom they are addressed, there can be no doubt of their favourable
reception.
1508. Theories of "peace through law" must be classed with this
same variety (III-5). The
usual objection urged against them is that
law with no force to uphold it is worth little or nothing, and that if
force is used war, which was banished in one direction, comes back
from some other. The objection is valid only in part. In the first
place many norms of social life are enforced without any resort to
violence, and it is not absurd to think that some at least, if not all,
conquered. It settled the fate of the wretched inhabitants of the Aegean Islands,
and so on and so on. If Montenegro had been stronger than Austria, Austria would
not have compelled Montenegro to relinquish territory; Montenegro would have
compelled Austria to do so. What rule can one imagine to show with equal clarity
that Austria had a "right" to occupy Bosnia and Herzegovina and that Monte-
just as now some Greek poet might sing in Homer's language of the no less ad-
mirable feats of Austro-Italian "crabs" in "maintaining equilibrium" in the Adriatic
and other regions. A person judging the facts by the sentiments of nationalism will
say, if he is an and Greece "wrong," and if he is a Greek
Italian, that Italy is "right"
he will invert the terms. A person judging the facts by the sentiments of interna-
tionalism or pacifism will place in the wrong the party whom he considers the
aggressor, in the right the party whom he deems to be the victim of the aggression.
But a person resolved to stick to the objective field will simply see in such things
new instances of the struggles that have always raged between the peoples; and in
such judgments, the usual translations into terms of "right" of the fact that certain
things are in accord with certain sentiments, and into terms of "wrong" of the fact
that certain things are not in accord with certain sentiments. He will, in other
words, see just residues and derivations.
*
1510 Religious tradition may even be combined with the most advanced meta-
physics. "Christian Science" ( 1695 2 ), for instance, might be defined as a sort of
"biblical Hcgelianism."
964 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1512
Western countries at least, is
tending to revert from such abstractions
to personifications. It would of course be absurd to imagine that
any of our contemporaries picture "solidarity" as a beautiful woman,
the way the Athenians thought of the goddess Athena. All the same,
in the minds of our masses such entities as "Solidarity," "Progress,"
anyhow.
1515. The
question that comes into one's mind as one tries
first
not know beforehand what it contains, till the ulterior condition on which it rests
is put in my possession; but with the very conception of a categorical imperative is
given also its contents [And given the conception of a Jabberwock, I at once know
its make-up.], for the imperative can in this case contain only the law ordaining
the necessity of a maxim to be conformed to this law; and since the law is attached
to no condition which could particularize it, there remains no what [read whit]
except the form of law in genere to which the maxim of an act is to be conformed;
and this properly speaking, what the imperative represents as neces-
conformity is,
sary. The categorical imperative is therefore single and one: 'Act from that maxim
"
only which thou canst will [to become] law universal' [Kant's German: "Handle
nur nach derjenigen Maxime durch die Du zugleich wollen fynnst, dass sie ein
allgemeines Gesetz werde!'\
966 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1516
whether: (i) the "universal law" is dependent upon some condition;
or (2) whether it is unrestricted by any condition of any kind. In
other words, can the law be stated in either of the following ways ?
i.
Every individual who has the traits ought to act in a certain M
manner. 2. Every individual, regardless of his traits, ought to act in
a certain manner.
1516. If the first form of statement be adopted, the law itself
means nothing, and the problem then is to determine which traits
M it
permissible to consider; for if the choice of traits is left to
is
the person who is to observe the law, he will always find a way to
allow him to do exactly as he chooses without
select traits that will
course, the gentleman who is interpreting the law) and other men
are born to obey. If he wants to steal, he will say that it may very
well be a universal law that he who has less should take from him
who has more. If he wants to kill an enemy he will say that revenge
can easily be a universal law ;
and so on.
1517. To judge by the first
application that Kant makes of his
principle, he would seem to reject that interpretation. Making no
distinctions between individuals, he concludes that suicide could not
1
be a universal law of nature.
*
1517 Kant, Mctaphysi\ der Sitten, p. 48 (Semple, pp. 34-35): "An individ-
ual harassed by a series of evils and sickened with the tedium of life proposes to
commit self-murder but first inquires within himself to know if the maxim regulat-
ing such an act would be fit for law universal. [The reply would have to be in the
affirmative qualifications were admissible. One would say in fact: "All men
if
and they are in the great majority who prefer living to dying will try to remain
alive as long as they can; and those few who prefer dying to living will kill them-
selves." What is there to prevent that from being a "universal law"? So little to
prevent it what actually happens, and has always happened in the con-
that that is
crete. Kant draw any distinction between those two sorts of people and so
fails to
answers in the negative.] His intended maxim would be, to deprive himself of life
whenever existence promised more of misery than of pleasure; and the question is,
Can such a principle of self-love be regarded as fit for a universal law of nature?
and it is instantly observable that an order of things whose law it were to destroy
life [Note the impersonal mode of statement which is generally adopted by those
who are manipulating the cards. The man who contemplating suicide is not con-
is
cerned with life in general, but with his own in particular.] by force of the
life
sensation intended for its continuance [If that is to stand, all qualifications have
to be suppressed; for the function of the sensation in question might be to encour-
age continuance of living when its blessings outweigh its pains, and under no other
1519 DERIVATIONS III-e: METAPHYSICAL ENTITIES 967
1518. So let us look at the second
interpretation (where no dis-
tinctions or limitations in individuals are
recognized). Kant's reason-
ing might seem able to stand after a fashion. But there is another
trouble with it. Before it could stand, the whole human race would
have to constitute one homogeneous mass, without the least differen-
tiation in the functions of individuals. If distinctions are admitted,
it is
possible for some men to command and others to obey; but not
if distinctions are not admitted, for there can be no universal law
that all men should command and no one obey. A man wants to
tinctions are not allowed, if, as in the case of the suicide, one refuses
to divide individuals into classes, there can be no universal law that
all men should spend their lives
studying mathematics, if for no
other reason, for the very good one that they would starve; and
therefore no one could be allowed to spend his life in such mathe-
matical studies.
Such implications are not noticed, because people reason on senti-
ments and not with the facts before their eyes.
1519. As metaphysicists habitually do, after giving what he says
is to be a
single principle, Kant begins filling out with other prin-
ciples,
which come bobbing up no one knows from where. In a third
case that he considers, Op. cit., p. 49 (Semple, pp. 35-36), still "a third
conditions.] could not be upheld [It could not be if there were no qualifications;
it could be if there were qualifications.], but must return to chaos. Whence it re-
possible for any one to will that such should become a universal
law of nature, or were by an instinct implanted in his system [The
formula does not mention any such "instinct."]; for he, as [an]
all his faculties to become de-
Intelligent [being], of necessity wills
veloped, such being given him in order that they may subserve his
various and manifold ends and purposes." (Semple translation.)
Here we have a principle altogether new: that certain things are
given us (no one knows by whom) for certain ends and purposes.
In order to reason in that fashion one would have to modify the
terms in Kant's formula and say: "Act only on a maxim that it
would be your will at the same time to have become a universal
law. However, do not let yourself be deceived by the possessive
c
'your/ To
say your will' is just my way of saying. In reality it is
something that must necessarily exist in a man, full account being
taken of the capacities with which he is endowed, of his designs
and purposes, and of many other fine things that will be explained
to you proper time and place." That much granted, one might
at the
seeks, and one always finds, some aspect wherein A is different from
B and C, and the decision is based on that aspect and therefore given
an appearance of generality. That is
saying nothing of that much-
followed method of deciding in general and applying in particular,
now with, now without, indulgence. So all our codes contain a law
that, in the general, punishes assaults and batteries. But in the par-
ticular, the courts shut one eye, and even two, in cases of assaults
and batteries committed by strikers on non-unionized workers. In
Italy,
before the war of 1911 it waspossible to insult an army officer
without interference from the courts. A
certain Deputy was able
to slander an army officer on purely private grounds that had noth-
ing to do with politics; and though he was convicted in a criminal
court he did not spend a day in prison even after he had failed of re-
election to the parliament. Then the war with Turkey came and
the pendulum swung to the other extreme. At the Scala Opera
House in Milan individuals were abused and beaten with impunity
for mere failure to rise to their feet when the "Royal March" was
being played.
1521. Theologians scan the heavens for the will of God, and Kant
for the will of Nature. There is no escaping such speculations, which
are as alluring as they are difficult and imaginary. "As regards the
natural constitution of an organized being," says Kant, p. 13 (Sem-
ple, p. 5),
"a being, that is, that has been constituted with a view to
827, note: "Probably not a few of the arrangements that we deem useless or harm-
ful look that way to us because of our ignorance of the services they render; but
then again, just as probably, they may be as useless or detrimental as they seem to
be. In any case it is for those who deny that to prove what they say. [They have to,
if they are naturalists. Metaphysicists are privileged to assert without proof.] Most
species get along more or less badly, more or less well. They are far from being
what has been called an intricate machine where each part is perfectly adapted to
its place and work in the great mechanism of Nature. Some have had good fortune
in the sense that the variations by which they have been formed have created few
embarrassments for them. That is the case with the fly. It has only to fly about,
rest, rub its wings and antennae. It finds anywhere those nameless deposits from
which it can suck the little it requires for subsistence. But those same blind varia-
tions have created lives that bristle with difficulties. That is the case with the spider,
which is always faced with most perplexing dilemmas: no food without a web, and
no web without food. It must be in the light to catch the insect, it must stay in the
dark to escape the bird. Why so surprising then that under such conditions it came
to develop the absurd instinct that drives the female to devour the male after copu-
they ever came to be created: "As for those that are born from the bodies of living
creaturesand especially of the dead, it is altogether absurd to imagine that they
were created at the time when those creatures were created."
2
1521 [Pareto read: "in selecting reason as the executrix of her intentions," and
comments: "That might be favourable to a theory of non-logical conduct!' A. L.]
1522 DERIVATIONS 111-8 1 METAPHYSICAL ENTITIES 971
sentiments that are agreeably stimulated by that sort of metaphysical
portant not to stop at the form of a derivation, but to delve into the
substance that the form covers, to see whether residues with an in-
fluence on the social equilibrium may not be lurking in it. have We
seen many. Let us look at another and it will not be the last. In
proof.] And should her favoured creature have received reason over and above, and
in superaddition to it, such gift could only have answered the purpose of enabling
itto observe, admire, and feel grateful to the Beneficent Cause [Another very pretty
entity.]for the fortunate arrangement and disposition of the parts of its system.
... In a single word, nature [Alias Beneficent Cause.] would have taken care to
guard against reason's straying into any practical department. ... So far is this,
however, from what is in fact observed, that the more a man of refined and culti-
vated mind addicts himself to the enjoyment of life and his own studied gratifica-
tion, the farther he observed to depart from true contentment." Mark the word
is
"true." It means the contentment that Kant likes best: any other contentment would
be "false." Those who have made the most extensive use of reason and then calcu-
lated the benefits they have derived from the arts and even from the sciences ac-
knowledge that "they have felt a certain hatred of reason, because they could not
conceal from themselves that upon a deliberate calculation of the advantages arising
from the most exquisite luxuries, not of the sensory merely, but likewise of the
understanding (for in many cases science is no more than an intellectual luxury),
they had rather increased their sources of uneasiness than really made progress in
satisfactory enjoyment, and felt inclined rather to envy than think lightly of those
inferior conditions of life, where man comes nearer to the tutelage of instinct, and
is not much
embarrassed by suggestions of reason as to what ought to be pursued
or avoided. [How could Kant ever have compiled any such statistics? This part of
the derivation was designed to satisfy people (and they were numerous in Kant's
day) who admired the "natural man" and were ever declaiming against civilization.
Derivations have their eye on sentiments, not on facts and logic.] For, since . . .
TRUE END [Again mark the adjective "true," for there is a "false" end as well the
end that Kant does not like.] FOR WHICH REASON is IMPLANTED, is to produce a will
good not as a means toward some ulterior end, but good in itself."
972 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 15^3
that attracted wide "Here the Great Elector on
attention. Said he:
his own authority declared himself sovereign. Here his son placed
the royal diadem upon his head. Here again my grandfather, and
right to wear the Imperial crown. Considering the fact that our
. . .
*
1524 Speaking in the French Chamber, Jan. 24, 1913, Premier Briand said:
"The most urgent problem is election reform. At no time have I personally pro-
nounced anathema on the vote by districts. I have always recognized the services
that that system has rendered. I have always added that as a tool it was out of gear.
I do not regard election reform as a matter of principle: it is a matter of tactic.
The party in power must try to stay there in the interests of the country and the
974 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY T
525
to grant the ballot to women because they fear that women will
will." The extension of the franchise in Italy was certainly not un-
influenced by the hope of certain calculating politicians that they
could turn it to their own advantage. In Germany Bismarck ac-
ber, it might never have been possible to create the German Empire.
On October the Prussian Landtag rejected the budget by a
7, 1862,
vote of 251 to 36. The temporary interests of a part of the population
were in conflict with the permanent interests of the country. King
97^ THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1530
William made up his mind to side with the latter. On October 13,
he prorogued the Landtag by a decree bearing Bismarck's signature,
and thereafter governed without regard to the approval or dis-
approval of that body. From that point on one's argument would
infer the future from the past. That is characteristic of reasonings in
the experimental sciences. They seek knowledge of the future from
what is known of the past. One uses that method when one in-
quires whether, under certain circumstances, one may expect that a
policy that has been used in times past and then had certain conse-
1529
*
A
similar analysis might be made for most manifestations of social activity.
Such analysis gives us some inkling as to the forces that are at work in determining
the social equilibrium.
1531 "UNIVERSALITY" AND "NECESSITY" 977
was once believed that one's life could be prolonged by a child-
sacrifice, as
though lifewere a fluid that might be piped, as it were,
from one person to another. On the same theory, a man of sober
years was able to imagine that he could prolong his life by sleeping
beside a young woman. So resemblances oftentimes imaginary are
transformed into metaphysical entities and serve to explain facts.
In general the function of such entities is to
give a semblance of
logic to combination residues (Class I).
1531. The metaphysical concept
may be taken for granted; and
we then get derivations that are very close in type to those based
on accords of sentiments ( 1469) and may be indistinguishable
from them. A
striking example would be the case of the meta-
physicist whorefutes logico-experimental science with principles
which that science denies, and insists at all costs on finding the
absolute in reasonings which he is over and again told are irremedi-
sibly have been so obtuse as not to grasp the fact that experimental
science does not have, does not seek, and does not want "necessary"
regard them, all that remains is: (i) Experimental facts; and (2)
pseudo-experimental principles. Those two categories merge into
a homogeneous mass in which, for example, experimental remedies
and magical remedies figure side by side. Here too there are idio-
syncrasies such as fetishisms and other beliefs of that kind. Large
numbers, in fact very large numbers, of people, in times both past
and present have been and still are able to adopt such ideas, which
are hardly to be called doctrines.
1534. Wehave already seen that evolution does not follow a
single line and that consequently we would be losing touch with
realities if we imagined that a given people started in the state Be,
then went on to the state Bb, and finally reached the state Ba
( 1536). But to get at the real situation, we are free to start with
that hypothesis, correcting it as we progress in order to get closer
to the facts. Let us suppose then, and strictly by way of hypothesis,
that a given people develops successively through the three states
Be, Bb, Ba. From what has been said above it follows that the sum
of non-logical actions in the state Be, along with the rudimentary
Figure 17
is
lilt
a very crude device. In reality
11
the classes that have to be taken
into account are more numerous than that. To
give graphic form
to the above, let A, B, C, D . .
(Figure 17) stand for different
.
strata in a
given population. A certain evolution carries the stratum
A to a position m. This change influences B, quite apart from the
general effect of the historical evolution, and brings the stratum
B to the position n. But the resistance of B also has its effect on
A, so that the point m
is determined not
by the general direction
of the evolution only, but also by the resistance of B. The same
considerations apply, if we assume several strata A, B, C in- . . .
interests, and
and of the logico-experimental sciences. All
so on,
the same, it is well to keep that error in mind, for it is very com-
theological state of a later group less general and more backward, or to the positive
state ofan earlier group less complex and more advanced. That apparent confusion
[He has just said himself that it is not apparent but real.] may indeed occasion in
people who have not clearly grasped the principle {Read: "who do not accept
Comtc's chatter at face value/'], an embarrassing hesitation as to the true philo-
984 THE MIND AND SOCIETY J
537
17, in determining the state of a
society made up of several strata
A, B, C . . . Comte tries to substitute the line mx for the real line
responds with the use that he makes of the term in the course of his
1
writings. According to the definition, "positive" philosophy would
correspond to our state A above, and the development would be of
sophical character of the periods corresponding. But to anticipate or dispel it en-
tirely, it is sufficient here to distinguish, in general terms, the intellectual group by
which the real speculative stage of a given period ought more especially to be
judged." And there we go galloping out of the experimental field! Never mind
minor imperfections, such as his calling the "hesitation" "embarrassing" why so
embarrassing, after all? and his allusions to a "philosophical character that is true"
and a "speculative stage" that is "real" how arc they to be distinguished from
others that are "false" or "unreal"? The more important point is that Comte takes
for granted the thing that has to be proved: namely, that there is but one specula-
tive stage at a given period of history. Several such stages exist simultaneously and
it is hard to see why one should be called more "real" (veritable) than another.
1536
2
Op. cit., Vol. V, p. 27 (italics ours) : "Now all essential considerations have
worked together of their own accord in this connexion to indicate with utter clear-
ness [So saith the prophet, and that is the end of the matter.] the more special and
complicated order of fundamental concepts in other words the body of moral and
social ideas, as always being the one that is to constitute the main basis for such a
decision, in view of their intrinsic importance, which is necessarily very great not
only in the mental systems of almost all [ordinary] men [But that was the very
thing that had to be proved.], but with philosophers themselves, as a result of their
rational location at the extremity of the true encyclopaedic hierarchy, as outlined at
the beginning of this treatise."
1
T 537 Qp- cit., Vol. I, Preface p. xiii and p. 3 (italics his) "I use the term phi- :
[That, really, would be the experimental method.] In the positive stage, the human
mind comes to recognize the impossibility of obtaining absolute concepts. It aban-
X
537 COMTE'S MENTAL EVOLUTION 985
the pattern Be, Bb, Ba, A. But very shortly Comte's "positive" philos-
dons the quest for the origin and destiny of the universe and for knowledge of the
inner causes of phenomena, and tries merely to discover by the use of reasoning
and observation combined their actual laws, in other words, their invariable rela-
tions of succession and likeness." And that again would be a definition of the logico-
Cf., for example, Cours, Vol. VI, p. 858 (italics ours) : "A sound appreciation of
our nature, in which vicious and wrongful inclinations necessarily predominate at
the outset [Who is to decide which inclinations are "vicious" and "wrongful"?
Comte's own inclinations, of course!], will make commonplace and unanimous the
obligation [Where does it come from? From whom does it emanate? Certainly it is
not an experimental relation.] to exercise over our various inclinations a wise and
orderly control that will be calculated to stimulate them and keep them within their
respective channels. Finally, the fundamental conception, at once scientific and
moral [The word "moral" is here suddenly appended to an inquiry that was adver-
tised at the beginning as strictly scientific.], of the true general situation [What on
earth can that be?] as the spontaneous leader of real economy, will always emphati-
cally stress the necessity of constantly developing by judicious exercise of those noble
attributes, no less of the heart than of the mind, that place us at the head of all
living creation." All that patter may be anything one chooses to call it but it is
certainly not a search for experimental uniformities.
2
1537 Op. Vol. VI, pp. 286-87: "This first scientific exercise of the abstract
cit. t
sense of evidence, of the nature of proof and harmony, however limited in scope
i.e.,
at first, was enough to provoke an important philosophical reaction, which, for the
986 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1537
moment favourable to metaphysical speculations only, was none the less a remote
predecessor of the inevitable advent of a positive philosophy by making sure of the
early elimination of a theology then preponderant." In that Comte is evidently
thinking of Newton and Newton's successors, forgetting all about the era of reli-
gious scepticism towards the end of the Roman Republic. The remarks that Cicero
made in his De natura deorum, or Lucretius in the De rertim natura, by no means
originated in mathematical research, yet they were aimed at polytheism and all
religion. Sextus Empiricus lumps mathematicians and polytheists together in one
simultaneous attack. Those, however, are mere errors of fact we can overlook
them. But where on earth did Comte discover that the "advent" of positive philos-
ophy was "inevitable"? If that is not a mere tautology, a way of saying that what
has happened had to happen mere determinism, in other words it indicates that
Comte is subordinating his facts to certain dogmas. He adds: "In that, the ancient
unity of our mental system, which down to that time had been uniformly theologi-
cal, was irrevocably broken up." Again we may disregard the error of fact. But
from what "coordination of facts** can Comte be inferring that such a break in the
old uniformity was "irrevocable"? Lucretius was also of that opinion and gave
Epicurus credit for the destruction of religion. And yet religion came to life again
(assuming as a very lame hypothesis that it had ever died) and again prospered.
Why should Comte be a better prophet than Lucretius? Then too the distinction
that Comte tries to draw between a theological faith and a positive faith is alto-
tions!], though they are products of that universal aptitude for trust [Authority.
Comte wants to replace the Pope's with his own. That is all there is to that.] with-
out which no society could subsist." And that is all very well; but only in the sense
that the non-logical impulses in which authority originates are useful and indispen-
sable to a society: it in no way follows that they will produce theories that square
with the facts. Comte's "positivistic" faith may be more or less useful to society
than what he calls a theological faith that question remains open. But both types
of faith lie outside the logico-experimental domain.
1541 DERIVATIONS III-: SUPERNATURAL ENTITIES 987
1538. We have lingered at some length on Comte's case because
it illustrates a serious error that in our time especially is
general
the assumption that the personification derivations are much farther
removed from experimental reality than metaphysical derivations,
the difference between them being simply a matter of form. Says
Homer, Iliad, I, v. 5 and passim: "So was the will of Zeus accom-
plished." Say the moderns: "Thus were the requirements of Prog-
ress met." The two states of mind are the same. Whether
"Prog-
ress," "Solidarity," "a Better Humanity," and so on are, or are not,
equally well. The principle that God acts as a man of good sense
serves to show that the Bible is "true," but just as well to show that
1
it Needless to add that from the experimental standpoint
is false.
2
neither the one proof nor the other has the slightest validity. Even
l
1542 The numberless "scientific" objections that are raised against religion are
of that type. The only conclusion they can justify is that the content of the Bible
and experimental reality are entirely separate things. Lefranc, Lcs conflits dc la sci-
ence ct de la Bible, pp. 143-44 quote the book simply in view of the date of its
publication, 1906): "If God called forth from nothingness those species which are
alive and in full activity today with their present organs which have remained
essentially unchanged, the Creation must have been overwhelming and complete at
the very outset. [What creation is nobody knows, but Lefranc knows what it must
have been like.] Dixit et facta suntl Dens crcauit omnia simull It is inconceivable
[But so many many things are inconceivable!] that the Almighty should have
begun with timid efforts at first [How can Lefranc be sure they were necessarily
timid efforts and not applications of far-sighted design? Was he there personally to
see?], first making simple outlines, very unassuming in aspect and structure, and
many as six hundred thousand different types, to keep to the animal kingdom alone.
That childish conception carries its own refutation within itself.'*
2
1542 During a session of the City Council of Milan, Dec. 31, 1912, a Socialist
councilman made a fierce attack on the teaching of Christian doctrine in the schools,
on the ground that it contained "absurd assertions belied by science." Among such
he quoted the statement that the light came first and the Sun afterwards, he appar-
ently having certain knowledge that the Sun came first and the light afterwards;
whence it would follow that the Sun must have been created before all the other
stars. That may in fact have been the case. But who told him so? However, suppose
we assume that by "Sun" he meant all the stars, all luminous bodies. It would in-
deed seem natural that there should be first luminous bodies and then light, but,
154^ THE DIVINE WILL 989
from the merely logical standpoint, quite aside from any experience,
the idea of an omniscient God cannot be reconciled with the idea
that a human being can pass judgment on His work. An ignorant
man is absolutely incapable of understanding what a scientist does
in his laboratory, nor are a large number of such individuals any
better equipped than one alone to pass such a judgment. That shows
the fatuousness of the man of
knowledge little in presuming to
judge the work of anyone whose knowledge far surpasses his
( 1995 the
*). It is indispensable premise in all such judgments on
personifications that the personification should be mentally, as well
as in other respects, fashioned in the image of the person who
creates it.
truth to tell, we know absolutely nothing about the matter. We do not know what
"bodies" are nor what "light" is. Much less do we know in what relation, chrono-
logical or otherwise, those entities may have stood "in the beginning.'* Christian
"science" gives one solution, Socialist "science," apparently, another. Logico-experi-
mental science knows nothing of either.
CHAPTER X
traits. In
may be conveniently placed as
this class logical sophistries
regards their purely formal element, so far, that is, as they serve to
satisfy
the need of logical development that human beings feel (resi-
dues I-e). nearly always incidental and does not
But that element is
ferent things: but people do not notice that and applaud the argu-
ment ( 1607). If X
is "Nature,"
"Right Reason," "the Good," or
something else of that sort, one may be almost certain, not to say
certain, that the argument is of the verbal type. Example: "One
lives well according to Nature. Nature recognizes no private prop-
erty.
Therefore one lives well without private property." In the first
(things that are "natural") and there again the person following
;
the lead of his sentiments will admit that private property is not a
992 THE MIND AND SOCIETY X
547
product of Nature, that Nature does not recognize it. Put the two
propositions together and it
logically follows that "one lives well
without private property"; and if this proposition chances to har-
monize with the sentiments of the person at whom the argument is
directed, he will regard it as sound from every point of view. And
who hears it, including his desire for a logical tinting for some
derivation or other ( 972, 1602).
1547. In concrete cases the Class IV derivations that we are here
dividing into subvarieties are used together, and often also in com-
bination with other derivations. Only by abstraction can we isolate
the simple derivations of which the concrete derivation is com-
pounded. That point must never be forgotten.
1548. The subgenera in Class IV ( 1419) show derivations of two
forms: in the first, procedure is from the thing to the term, in the
second, from the term to the thing, real or imaginary as the thing
may be. In concrete cases the two forms often mingle: after going
from the thing to the term, one goes back from the term to some-
thing else. There are plenty of arguments that amount, substantially,
to nothing more than that. As we saw in 108, one may slip from
the logico-experimental field both by using terms that correspond to
entities not belonging in that field and by using indefinite terms
1548
x
We encountered many verbal derivations in Chapter V. In 658 we illus-
trated the procedure from the thing to the name and from the name to the thing,
and showed, in the paragraphs following, how errors divergences, that is, between
certain derivations and arose in that way. Theories that infer the nature
reality
of a thing from the etymology of its name ( 686 f.) are in fact verbal derivations
where procedure is from the name to the thing; and that direct etymological process
also has its reverse (691). Everything said on that subject in Chapter V must be
variety, going from the thing to the name. He imagines that any
word which exists must have something real corresponding to it:
"Nature [When that lady comes dancing on the scene, the attend-
ance of a fallacy be taken for granted.] has given us no knowl-
may
edge of the limits of things." So then, there is in fact a thing cor-
responding to the term "long"; but Madame Nature has not deigned
to reveal to us the limits or boundaries of "long"; so we, poor devils,
cannot tell it from "short." But what if, instead of things, there were
nothing but sentiments
corresponding to such terms? In that case,
Dame Nature would be free of all blame, and the fault would lie
1550
*
On
the sorites see Ulpian, in Digesta, lib. L, tit. 16, sec. 177 (Dc vcrborum
significatione) (Corpus iuris civilis, Vol. I, p. 969; Scott, Vol. XI, p. 284): "The
994 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY J
55 r
Those philosophers who failed to find the error in this fal-
1551.
their habits of metaphysical thinking, and they
lacy were misled by
could not recognize a particular error without admitting thereby
that all their reasonings were fallacious. As a matter of fact the
error in the sorites lies in the use of terms that do indeed arouse
indefinite sentiments but otherwise correspond to nothing real.
There is
nothing objective corresponding to the terms "much" or
"large" or "small," "heavy" or "light," and so on. But the
"little,"
evidentlyfalse.'* Familiar the passage in Horace, Epistulac, II, i, vv. 45-49, where
he shows by that method that no dividing line can be drawn between "ancient"
and ''modern,'* and that a horse's tail can be all plucked out one hair at a time,
stillremaining a tail. The Pseudo-Acron remarks: "The syllogisms of Chrysippus
are pseudomcnes and sorites'* [missing in Paris, 1519]. As for the Sceptics and the
"method of rest" see Sextus Empiricus, Pyrrhonianae institutioncs, II, 22, 253
(125) (Opera, Vol. I, p. 203): "Therefore whenever an argument is being worked
out before us we shall suspend our assent to each and every proposition; and then
when the is complete we shall set against it anything we see fit. For, in
argument
fact, if thedogmatists of Chrysippus are to teach that when an argument by the
heap (sorites) is being worked out, one must hold one's tongue while the argument
is in progress and refrain from assenting so as not to be led into an absurdum, it
is much more advantageous for us who are Sceptics and are always on the watch
for absurdities not to allow ourselves to be entangled in the lines of a reasoning,
but to suspend our assent to each and every step until the whole argument has been
set before us."For Carneades, see Sextus Empiricus, Contradictioncs, IX, Adversus
physicos, II, De diis, 190 (Opera, Vol. II, p. 611).
I55 2 DERIVATIONS IV-/3: VERBAL PROOFS 995
exactly what you mean by Value.' Tell us how and why it should
have one cause. Then we will answer, not before." To be sure, in
ordinary parlance the term "value," like the term "heap," has an
obvious meaning; but unfortunately the two meanings are equally
indefinite, and that fact eliminates any possibility
of using them in
1
scientific thinking.
*
1551 Pareto, Systemes socialities, Vol. I, pp. 338-40.
1552 In the Italo-Turkish war of 1912, Arabs who brought information from
*
the Turco-Arab camp to the Italians were called "informers"; those who carried
information from the Italian camp to the Turks and Arabs, "spies.** Bentham,
Tactique des assemblies legislatives, Vol. II, pp. 178, 163-66, 175: "The word 'per-
secution' does not appear in the dictionary of persecutors. All they know is 'zeal'
for religion.When the Abbe Terray defaulted on public creditors he called it a
Reservation' (retenue). [In Italy a reduction of 4 per cent in the 5 per cent interest
on the public debt was euphcmized as a "tax on personal property."] In the
nomenclature of moral beings there are terms that present the object pure and
simple without adjoining any sentiment of approval or disapproval. Such would be
'desire,' 'inclination,' 'habit.' I call them 'neutral' terms. There are others that add
a general idea of approbation to the main idea: 'honour,' 'piety.' Others supple-
ment the main idea with an habitual idea of disapprobation: 'libertinage,' 'avarice,'
'luxury.' ... In referring to the conduct, the inclinations, the motives of a given
996 THE MIND AND SOCIETY J
55 2
ple who do not agree with him. If a person wants freedom in the
sense of removing restraints from thought, he should be in favour
of allowing uncramped discussion both for and against Catholicism.
Our free-thinkers, instead, consent to attacks on Christianity, on
Catholicism, but deny the privilege of defence. They insist on pro-
is he an object of indifference to you? Then
individual, you use the neutral term.
Do you wish to win him the favour of your auditors? Then you resort to the
term that incidentally implies approbation. Will you have him despised or hated?
You use the term that implies reproach. What does a man mean when he talks of
'good order'? Merely an arrangement of things to which he gives his approval
and of which he declares himself a partisan." But how comes it that while so many
writers all the way from Aristotle to Bentham have been sign-boarding the error
in such sophistries, they continue to be so lavishly used? Simply because their force
lies not in the argument, which, to tell the truth, is childish, but in the sentiments
1552
8
I am not inquiring here whether that programme is, or is not, beneficial
to society. I am merely saying that to proceed in that fashion is to distort the
word "free" from its usual acceptation and give it an approximately opposite mean-
ing. The National Congress of Free Thought, meeting in Paris in October, 1911,
voted a resolution that read: "Faithful to the international ideal of progress and
justice[That is a faith. It may be a good one. Other faiths may be bad. But it is
none the less a faith and has nothing to do with free thought.], this Congress of
Free Thinkers urges all associations of free-thinkers to make constant demand for
the application in toto of the international conventions signed at The Hague.
[What have those conventions got to do with free thought? "free" thought A
should be at liberty to favour or oppose them as it saw fit.] Free-thought associa-
tions should urge Republicans elected to the government of the Republic to take
the initiative in negotiations looking to the conclusion of new agreements for the
limitation of military and naval budgets and the assurance of disarmament." A
very pretty pair of handcuffs locked on in the name of freedom! Anyone whose
thought is "free" has to be in favour of disarmament; and if a man believes that
disarmament is dangerous for his country his thought is "enslaved"! Those are
absurdities that require no refutation; yet there are people who fall under their
spell. And how can that be? Simply because the meanings of the words have been
changed, so that they function, not through their common meanings, but through
the sentiments to which they appeal. The words "free-thought" set in motion
a body of sentiments connected with a thought that is shackled to a humanitarian,
anti-Catholic religion, and they therefore serve as labels for the dogmas of that
religion.
l
1553 1912 the Patriarch of Venice, following a doctrine of the Church
In
Fathers, vigorously censured women who dressed in a manner that he thought
immodest and suggestive, warned them that he would not admit them to the
baptismal font with their children nor to communion, and actually withheld the
latter rite from a lady who presented herself in a gown that he considered too
low-cut. Newspapers time compared him to Senator Berenger. But the two
at the
cases are entirely differentand belong to categories that must not be confused.
For the parallel it would be necessary for the government to compel women to
attend the religious functions over which the Patriarch of Venice presides. But
that was not the case. Those functions were attended only by people who chose
to attend them, and the Patriarch had not the least power over anyone electing to
disregard him; whereas the man Berenger imprisons and fines people who disre-
gard him and confiscates newspapers and books. In short, to say "If you want me
to do A, you must do B" is one thing. To say "Whether you want to or not, I
998 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY J
553
anny, and the same term is used both when submission to papal
though the two cases are radically different. In like manner, one
often hears accusations of oppression against people who are trying
to expel some individual member from a society of theirs. They are
said to be "excommunicating" him, whether the excommunication
involves penalties enforced by a public authority or has no other
effect than expulsion from some private group. Yet those things also
are altogether different. In France, excommunication in the Middle
Ages and excommunication today are things that have the same
name but nothing else in common. Today the non-Catholic laughs
at being excommunicated and has no fears of
being prosecuted by
the government. But there are many persons who would like to
invert the roles and who demand in the name of "freedom" that the
government interfere to force their society upon those who will have
none of it. That is
changing the sense of terms Keeping to
entirely.
meanings, a "free" state of things is a state in
literal which a person
chooses the company he will keep at pleasure, without forcing his
upon others or having others force theirs upon him. And if one is
going to call "free" a state of things in which a distasteful or repug-
nant company is forced upon one, why then, if one is to avoid mis-
understandings, one had better find some other word to designate
a state of things where one is not compelled to accept unwanted
2
company.
compel you to do B" is quite another. Sentiment docs not bother with any such
analysis and views the matter synthetically. The anti-Clerical censures the "intoler-
ance'* of the Patriarch of Venice and applauds Bercnger; and that is all a deriva-
tion, which means simply that the anti-Clerical dislikes the Patriarch and admires
the Specialist in Purity.
2
1553 In Germany a Protestant pastor, Mr. Jatho, who professes a Christianity
all his own, preached a series of sermons on Goethe. They scandalized good Chris-
tians, and the consistory of the Rhineland and the High Council of the German
Evangelical Church interfered. Journal de Geneve, Feb. 23, 1911: "The Consistory
has begged Mr. Jatho to declare that his sermons had been incorrectly reported
and to pledge his word that he will deliver no more of that kind. The pastor
has refused on both scores. He asserts he is the victim of anonymous charges and
takes his stand behind the indelicacy of that procedure to avoid making any con-
cessions. As a result charges have been lodged against him before the High Coun-
cil of the Evangelical Cliurch. ... A coincidence, unfortunately, complicates the
case still further. All Protestants have felt in duty bound to take a vigorous stand
against the anti-Modernist oath. Mr. Jatho and his press have not missed the
chance to say that an anti-Modernist oath was being demanded of him, and they
1554 DERIVATIONS IV-/3: VERBAL PROOFS 999
1554. The fate that has befallen the term "freedom" is, in truth,
comical enough. In many cases nowadays the word means the exact
opposite of what it meant fifty years ago; but the sentiments that
it stirs are the same in other words, it
designates a state of things
of which the average auditor approves. If Smith is
interfering with
Jones, Jones calls "freedom" to escape from
it the interference. But
ifJones in his calls it "freedom" to
turn gets control of Smith, he
tighten the ropes. In both cases the term "freedom" has the pleas-
antest associations for Jones. Half a century ago, in England, the
"Liberal party" was the party that sought to reduce as far as pos-
sible such restrictions as to some extent deprived the individual of
tried to get the evangelical press to shower the Cologne preacher with the same
inordinate praises it has been bestowing on the handful of priests who have balked
at the anti-Modernist oath. Needless to say, the Protestant papers have side-stepped
the issue, seeking and finding distinctions." He who seeks finds, and always finds
as many distinctions as he happens to need.
l
1554 La Fontaine, "Lc savctier ct Ic financier" (Fables, VIII, 2) the poor
cobbler speaking:
". . . le mal est quc ton jours
et sans cela nos gains seraicnt assez honnetes
Ic mal cst qttc dans Van s'cntrcmclent dcs jours
qu'il fautchomcr. On nous ruine en fetes:
une fait tort a I'autre, et monsieur le cure
I'
issue, and people still remember the fiery pamphlets that Courier
2
wrote on the subject. As late as 1856 dread of
seeing the Sunday
holiday become a matter of law prompted the Senate of the
Empire,
ordinarily a tame and submissive body, to resistance "strong feel-
3
ings" will move even a lamb to rebellion. According to Ollivier,
Senator Lavalette "proposed that the oath taken
by the Empress-
Regent, in
conformity with the senatus-consultum of 1813, should
be re-enforced with an oath
'guaranteeing respect for the provisions
of the Concordat,
including the organic law and freedom of wor-
ship.' The blow was aimed directly at the Empress, who was sus-
is an
infringement on the "liberty" of people who prefer not to work
on those days, whence one can argue logically that Sunday idleness
isenforced by law in the name of freedom. Some liberal who has
read Hegel will even add that in so "the state is free-
5
doing creating
dom." The term "freedom" as used in that derivation has three
law must be added those enforced by violence on strike-breakers, and those con-
nected with political strikes, and strikes of "protest,"
solidarity, and so on. The
difference lies in the fact that in our day a person is constrained to act
contrarily
to his own will in the name of "freedom," the term so acquiring a meaning
directly opposite to its
primitive meaning.
2
Petition a la Chambre des deputes pour les
1554 villageois que Von empeche dc
danser ((Euvres completes, p. 84): "Gentlemen, those who are so bitter against
working on Sundays want high salaries, vote increases in the budget, and put in-
digent taxpayers in jail. expect us to pay more and to work less each year."
They
8
1554 L'Empire liberal, Vol. IV, p. 11.
4
J 554 [Pareto wrote "derivation" a lapsus linguae. A. L.]
6
1554 The argument
reduces to an absurdum on one's noting that it applies to
every case where conflicts arise in the exercise of freedom of action by numbers
of persons. A law might be passed to compel violin-teachers to give lessons free
because for them to accept fees would be an "infringement on the liberties" of
1555 "FREEDOM" 1001
nay opposite, things by a single term? Nothing more nor less than
a desire to exploit the agreeable sentiments that the term suggests
the same reason that prompted the Roman Empire to go on calling
itself a
republic. And then, too, though in a very secondary way, a
people who want to learn the violin but cannot afford to pay. It is therefore a
duty of the Ncver-Sufficiently-Praised State to "create" said ''freedom" of violin-
study. In the same way, if a lady refuses to requite a suitor, she is depriving him
of free action in loving her, is, in other words, infringing on his "freedom" of
action. The law therefore should "create freedom" in sex by at once coming to the
rescue and compelling the lady to be merciful to anyone who desires her. But,
it will be objected, such "liberties" are not as respectable as the freedom of persons
not to work on the Lord's day and who ought to be working if others are to work.
And the objection is sound enough; but to take that ground forces us to inquire
whether, with a view to certain definite ends, it is desirable, or whether for one
reason or other we are inclined, to favour the one or the other of these respective
freedoms to do or refrain from doing; and that would at once take us entirely
outside the field where it is possible to speak of "infringements on freedom" or
"creations of freedom."
IO02 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1556
certain sense of decency in our politicians. Burning today the idols
logical reasoning.
Instead of saying simply, A B, one says, A X; =
and it is then assumed implicitly by accord of sentiments, or stated
explicitly,
that X=
B; and so it results that B. From the logical A
standpoint the detour is no whit better than the short cut (783);
but it is effective from the standpoint of sentiments as satisfying the
1
hankering for pseudo-logical expatiation.
*
1555 Among the many amazing travesties of the term "liberalism" one of the
most striking is an equation brought into play by the Italian Premier Salandra,
some years ago. Outlining his policy before the Chamber of Deputies on Apr. 6,
1914, he said: "To my mind liberalism in Italy means patriotism [Applause]."
The item should be added to some future dictionary of synonyms! But perhaps
the Italian Premier meant simply that "liberal and patriotic** was a phrase used to
designate a certain group of politicians. In that case he was, alas, not far from
the truth. The phrase is very truly a euphemism that the party of our "speculators'*
( 2235) in Italy is pleased to take as its name.
*
1556 The Pythagorean tradition seems to have set up as its ethical rule a
striving to be like the gods (Themistius, Orations, XV, 192; Dindorf, p. 236).
Hierocles located perfection in that likeness: Commentarius in Aureum carmen,
vv. 63-66: [The Carmen reads (Lowe
translation): "These [the mystic rules of
nature] if to know thou
happily attain, soon shalt thou perfect be. . . ." Hierocles
paraphrases merely: "Mortals are kin to God, in that nature reveals everything to
them." A. L.] Stobaeus, Eglogae physicae et ethicae, II, 7 (Heeren, Vol. II, p.
66), quotes a saying of Pythagoras: ""ETTOV 0e>": "Follow thou God.** If the god
in question were the god of the multitude, the norm alluded to would be adding
something to the simple assertion of a precept: it would, that is, be saying that the
1556 DERIVATIONS IV-y : VERBAL PROOFS 1
003
To belong the many sophistries in which the middle
this variety
term broken up into two meanings, and those other equally nu-
is
questions. But if one does ask for a definition of the ,4's, an answer,
more or less verbose, involved, inexplicit, is made, to the effect, sub-
stantially, that the A's are those who hold the opinion B, A in that
1556
2
We have given many examples of arguments of that type, e.g., 592-93.
l
1557 In Bourgeois, Essai d'une philosophic de la solidarite, Preface, p. vi.
2
1557 Croiset continues (Ibid., Preface pp. vi-viii) :"The solidarity of which
our moralists and politicians are now
talking so glibly is a very different thing,
or at least a much more complex thing. [They admit that now, the sly foxes, but
for a long time they tried to keep up the confusion. Now that that game is failing
to work, they are changing the tune for the same old song:] When one speaks, as
M. Leon Bourgeois speaks, of the social debt of individuals, it is not a question of
a common debt to an outsider, but of a reciprocal obligation among associates,
which is an altogether different thing. [Yes, but for a time the estimable champions
of solidarity tried to make out that they were the same thing.] When the example
of biological solidarity is pointed to, that is far from meaning that individuals in
society are subject, like the cells in a living organism, to a sort of external natural
fatality which they can do nothing but recognize. [But in that case, why all the
patter about "universal solidarity" the solidarity of animals with plants and
plants with minerals?] The concept of solidarity is in reality envisaged as a prin-
ciple of conduct, moral conduct, as a means of stimulating in individuals an
aspiration to a higher justice [Just how is the height of this or that justice to be
1558 "SOLIDARITY" IN FRANCE 1005
for payment of the common debt, half the hand on one arm ought
and half the hand on the other arm. Yet only one of
to be cut off
the two arms pays the common debt. So the two arms are not in a
us a scientific theory.
1558. An example of the indirect use of the IV-y derivation would
be the precept "Thou shalt not kill." It
established by giving a
is
measured in feet and inches?] and as a rule that is calculated to facilitate their
reaching it. [How many things in just one word! Solidarity! Magical term indeed!
And still M. Croiset has left out something. Solidarity also stands for a desire on
the part of certain politicians to get a following, and for the verbal sops that are
handed out to the mob by democratic metaphysicists. Croiset rightly concludes:]
It is therefore evident that the word 'solidarity* has taken on a wholly new mean-
ing in that connexion, and that in spite of the identity in words moral solidarity
is something profoundly different from biological or juridical solidarity" which,
in their turn, as we have just seen, arc also different things.
3
1557 Croiset, loc. cit., p. x: "The word 'solidarity/ taken over from biology,
fitted in with that vague but deep-seated yearning [for oneness
marvellously
of all individuals in some whole]. The word 'altruism* was out of the question.
It was too great a barbarism ever to have made its way into ordinary parlance.
[There was another reason: the word "altruism" could never have led anyone to
believe that the Moon was made of green cheese, that, in other words, "solidarity"
was a scientific theory.] The term 'solidarity' was furthermore rather vague, as
being taken over from a field where it had an exact meaning to another field
where, in fact, the problem was to acclimatize it. So people were free gradually to
bring under it all those still hazy ideas which older words, more definite in
meaning as a result of long usage, were not so well fitted to express."
IOO6 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY J
559
eral, members of one's own community. But
or at least the blood of
lo, the case arises in which one has to say "Thou shalt kill!" To be
rid of the contradiction the term "kill" is not restricted in mean-
not by war," and that they call "peace under law." In 1911 Italy de-
clared war on Turkey without in the least concerning herself with
arbitration or with the international Court at The Hague. Pacifists
abroad stood loyal to their formula and condemned the Italian Gov-
ernment; but a number of Italian pacifists stood by their govern-
ment, because in going to war it had vindicated "Italy's good right."
goes without saying that if some other country, X, had been
It in
"assassins" and that were no "just" wars, unless, perhaps, wars in self-
there
defence. Then one fine day they change their allegiance and ask us to admire
other conquerors as heroes, and applaud other wars of conquest as "just," without
telling us how conquerors and wars that are to be condemned are to be distin-
guished from those which are to be applauded. Instead of enlightening those who
disagree with them, they abuse them. Before burning her heretics, the Holy
Catholic Church at least taught them the catechism! The Italian "war-pacifists"
were so indignant at their sometime comrades, the "peace-pacifists," that had
they been able they would have challenged them to mortal combat. And they
took that position, they said, in defence of their country's honour. But was not
"the country's honour" the very cause of many of the wars they had previously
1561 DERIVATIONS IV-yl VERBAL PROOFS IOO7
formula would seem, therefore, to be "International disputes must
:
XIV, pp. 558-59: "Faced with the choice between a war of doubtful outcome
and a dishonourable peace, bcllum anccps an pax inhonesta, we were forced to
pronounce for war ncc dubitatum de hello. 'For peoples as for individuals there
arc circumstances where the voice of honour must speak louder than the voice
of prudence' (Letter of Cavour to Arese, Feb. 28, 1860: Lettere edite cd incdite,
Vol. Ill, pp. 220-23.) Governments fall not only from defeat on the battle-field.
Dishonour also destroys them. ... A military disaster can be repaired. Dis- . . .
be right? To answer with the national anthem or by abuse of one's critics may
be a good way to rouse emotions; but it is not in the least logical, nor in the
remotest degree rational.
1
1560
-
This is not the place to solve the problem of utility that is involved in this
special case. Itis sufficient for our purposes here that the two solutions mentioned
should in fact be possible. Farther along ( 1704 f.) we shall see just what residues
underlay the above derivations, and one aspect of utility we shall discuss in
Chapter XII.
I008 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1562
bly of Finland would have granted to that country had it not been
solidarity)."
1564. All the Christian sects have their martyrs, and each has
had
considered its own martyrs the only "true" ones. St. Augustine de-
*
1562 In his early day, Cicero, Acadcmica, II, 46, 142, notes several meanings in
which the term "true" was used. From his time to ours the list has constantly been
lengthening: "Pythagoras is of one view, that the opinion of each individual is
truth to him; the Cyrenians of another, that there is no criterion of judgment apart
from inner intuition (permotiones intimas); and Epicurus of still another, for he
located all judgment in the senses, in our perceptions (notitiis) of things and in
pleasure (voluptate). Plato, however, held that the whole criterion of truth, and
the truth itself, have nothing to do with opinions and feelings (adductam misprint
for abductam), but are prerogatives of thought and of the mind."
1564 "TRUE FREEDOM," "RIGHT REASON" 1009
*
clares flatly: "Heretics, furthermore, all suffer [Le., martyrdom]
in behalf of error and not of the truth, for they lie against Christ
Himself. Whatever things the impious and the heathen suffer they
2
all suffer in behalf of falsehood." It
goes without saying that
"truth" is what St. Augustine believes in, and "error," any other
belief.
Bayle clearly perceived the fallacy in a reasoning of the type
of St. Augustine's that was designed to show that the orthodox were
3
right and the heretics wrong in persecuting dissenters. That fallacy,
centuries and centuries old as it is, is at all times fresh and retains
the full vigour and vitality of youth. It did yeoman's service for the
Christians in persecuting the pagans, for the Catholics in persecut-
ing the Protestants, and vice versa, for the various Protestant sects
in persecuting one another, for all Christians in persecuting free-
and "error" have as many meanings as there are parties; and only
in virtue of a IV-/2 derivation are they preferred to their equivalents:
"What I believe" and "What I do not believe."
persons who do
not subscribe to their party's platform; and the practice is in-
dispensable to them, as it is to anyone who is trying to build up a party. How-
ever, certain members of the Socialist party insist on barring Catholic priests from
teaching in the schools because they are not "free" to think as they choose, but are
obliged to follow the teachings of the Church. That "obligation" on the part of
the Catholic priest is identical with the Socialist's "obligation." Roth have to sub-
scribe to the dogmas of the group to which they belong under pain of expulsion
from it. It follows that if such an "obligation" precludes efficient teaching, it is
desirable, for the sake of efficient teaching, that both should be denied the right
to teach. If it is no such obstacle, it is desirable that both should be allowed to
teach. Sentiment, however, draws the distinction. Those who like priests and dis-
like Socialists say that priests ought to be allowed to teach and Socialists be barred.
That more or less is what happens in Germany. Those who dislike priests and
like Socialists say that priests should be barred and Socialists accepted. And that
is what is going on in France. Ingenuous souls, simpletons, and idiots are then
fed with the notion that it is all being done out of love for the "ethical State," or
Madame Liberty.
1567 DERIVATIONS IV-yt VERBAL PROOFS IOII
required to make them square with the faith. The science of me-
chanics from Aristotle to Laplace, natural history from Pliny to
Cuvier, Roman from Livy to Mommsen, Greek history from
history
Herodotus to Grote, Curtius, and others, have progressed from this
last extreme to the first; and the term "truth" has constantly
2
changed in meaning all
along the line (776f.).
x
1567 a person has a religious or metaphysical faith, he says that the "truth"
If
which is found at that extreme is "superior to," "higher than," the truth
to be
located at the other extreme. It is a logical consequence of the Hegelian's belief
that his religion, his metaphysics, his "science" (i9f.)> are "superior" to ex-
perience. Materialists invert the relation, but their "experience" is itself just a form
of religion. Really they are comparing two "truths" both located at our second
extreme.
2
1567 one among hosts of examples: Merle d'Aubignc, Histoire de la
Just
Reformation, Vol. I, p. i: "A weakened world (a) was tottering on its foundations
when Christianity appeared (). The national religions that had satisfied the
fathers had ceased to satisfy the children (r). The gods of all nations had
. . .
been transported to Rome and had lost their oracles there (d) as the peoples had
their freedom (c). Soon the narrow conceptions of nationality fell with their
. . .
gods. The peoples blended one into another (/). In Europe, Asia, Africa there was
now but one empire (g). The human race (/;) began to be conscious of its uni-
versality, its unity." If one fix one's attention on historical realities, the following
remarks will at once suggest themselves: a. What does D'Aubigne mean by "the
world"? He seems vaguely to mean the Roman world, the Mediterranean area,
but then again he seems to be thinking of the whole globe. When he says "a
weakened world" he is probably thinking of the Roman world, for it hardly seems
IOI2 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1568
1568. As we have already seen ( 645), in repeating a story a per-
son uses language somewhat different from what he heard, and he
thinks that he is reporting the "truth," in the sense that the lan-
guage he uses makes the same impression upon him as the language
he heard. The precise words uttered in a long conversation cannot
possibly be remembered. What sticks in the memory is the impres-
sion one had of it, and that impression is what one tries to
reproduce
in setting out to repeat the conversation. If one has done that suc-
cessfully one feels in all good faith that one has "spoken the truth."
In practice, before courts of justice, such approximate
reproduction
is
usually adequate for ordinary purposes. If it seems insufficient in
possible that he could have been thinking of China, Japan, Germany, and the
many other countries, "weakened"? At the time when Christianity ap-
b. Why
peared the Roman Empire was
very strong and prosperous. It was rather after
the triumph of Christianity that the Empire "weakened." Many pagan
Emperors
dictated peace to the barbarians at the point of the sword. Many Christian Em-
perors bought peace with gold. c. D'Aubigne forgets that if Christianity was quite
willing not to be a national religion, it ended by being one. Islamism, instead, is
essentially even in our day; and of Islamism far better than of
non-national
Christianity might one say that it appeared in a "weakened" (Roman) world.
d. The Delphic oracle was very famous in
antiquity. Did it really p?ss out of ex-
istence because its god had been transported to Rome? Where can
D'Aubigne
have found evidence of any such transfer? e. D'Aubigne is trying for a literary
effect by balancing the oracles of the gods against the
liberty of the peoples.
Historical realities have quite gone out of his mind. /. What peoples? He must be
thinking of the peoples who were conquered and made subject by the Romans,
forgetting all about the Barbarians, the Chinese, Japanese, Hindus, Africans,
Americans mere bagatelles, they! g. Here D'Aubigne is surely naming the
. . .
whole by the part. He could not have been unaware that the Roman Empire was
very far from extending over all Europe, all Asia, all Africa. //. But if the preceding
strictureis sound, how can it now occur to him to think of
mentioning the "hu-
man race"? If our assumption was unsound, if D'Aubigne really meant all
Europe, all Asia, all Africa never mind about America and Oceania he can
then, it is "human race"; but just as truly he
true, allude in all strictness to the
will be talking nonsense. person Ashares who
D'Aubigne's faith does not notice
such obvious departures from reality in reading his
history, any more than a
lover notices the freckles on his sweetheart's face. Of such a lover Lucretius in his
time wrote, De rcrtim natura, IV, vv. 1160-72:
("Is she black? She is blond as honey! Is she unclean, uncouth? She is
pleasantly
negligee! Has she green eyes? She is Minerva! Is she stiff and wooden? She is a
gazelle! A puny dwarf, she is one of the Graces and what wit! ... But were I
157 THE MODERNISTS AND THE BIBLE 1013
some respect, the court can ask the witness to make himself more
clear.
ing the orations that they allege were delivered by one character or
another in their story. Even Polybius, who is otherwise so conscien-
1
tious, follows that practice. He repeats verbatim the oration which
Cornelius Scipio delivered before his army on the eve of the battle on
the Ticinus, III, 64, 3-11 (Paton, Vol. II, pp. 155-57). Now it is
altogether certain that Polybius could not have known the contents
of that speech, word for word. It cannot be an accurate reproduction
of the incident, but a mere formulation of the impression left with
whatever.
1570. This extreme is
by the impressions that Jean
illustrated
1
Rcville describes, in connexion with the problem of the Fourth
to give the whole list of such things, the task would be long indeed.") [Lucretius
is mimicking the Greek affectations of love-making in the Roman Mayfair of his
nibal marched into Italy with his army. That is a historical fact.
But who can say just how much "eternal truth" it contains? Such
talk is arrant nonsense.
1571. After alluding to prevailing doubts as to the historical real-
*
Flood, M. Loisy adds "The story of the Creation
ity of the biblical
:
is true, even
though it contains no history and is framed in a cos-
mogony that is no longer accepted today. knows but that in Who
the chapters following there may be stories which are also true in
their way, though they do not contain all the materially exact his-
2
torical elements which we would like to find in them ( 774) ?"
Evidently in passage the word "true" has, for the writer, a
all this
different meaning from the one it has when we say, "It is 'true' that
Garibaldi landed in Sicily in 1860." But until he tells us the precise
sense he chooses to give to the word, we can neither accept nor
*
1571 Etudes sur la religion chaldeo-assyrienne, Vol. IV, pp. 152-53.
2
1571 There is a similar derivation in another work by Loisy, Etudes bibliques,
pp. 131-32: "One cannot
say, however, that the Bible contains errors in astronomy.
That would be at once unjust and naive. Before we could have a right to charge
the Bible with an error of that sort, an inspired author would have to make it
apparent, in some passage or other, that he is trying to force this or that concep-
tion of the universe upon his reader as a certain truth. [Another kind of truth!
How many many kinds there are!] But none of the sacred writers ever betrayed
any intention of giving lessons in astronomy." Loisy does not care to have the
unfavourable sentiments associated with the word "error" come into play where
the Bible is concerned. He calls in a derivation, in order to confuse "objective
error" with "subjective error" and bring those two different things under a single
name. Had he chosen to express himself clearly he might have said: "The fact
that the Bible contains assertions which do not correspond to the facts (objective
errors) docs not justify the conclusion that the writer was trying to make anyone
believe that they corresponded to the facts, or even that he thought they did him-
self (subjective error)." But that concedes the presence of the objective error, a fact,
after all, which Loisy does not care to deny. He is however unwilling to use the
word "error." Loisy's position, which as a matter of fact is the position of many
exponents of the "higher criticism," has not, to tell the truth, any great prob-
ability; but it cannot, strictly speaking, be disputed. Suppose a naturalist is dis-
cussing preparations for dinner with his wife and says, "For fish, instead of smelt,
I suggest we have lobster." The statement would contain an objective error: a
lobster is not a fish. There is no subjective error, however, because the naturalist
knows very well that a lobster is not a fish and he also knows very well that he
would look ridiculous to his wife if he were to say, pedant-fashion, "For fish, in-
stead of smelt, a fish, I suggest we have a crustacean a lobster." All the same,
even granting that, the fact still remains that his first statement contained an
objective error.
IOl6 THE MIND AND SOCIETY
ally" ? If the word "true" is taken in the sense of "accord with the
facts," how
can a story be "historical" and not "materially exact" ? It
might be historical as a whole and not be exact in parts, but that is
not what Loisy seems to mean. Had he meant that he would not
have spoken of "stories that are true in their way." Julius Caesar was
or was not a dictator. In the first case, Caesar's dictatorship is a his-
torical fact; in the second case it is not. In the first case, it is accurate
to say that he was a dictator; in the second it is not. One cannot im-
agine what the following proposition could mean: "To say that
Caesar was not a dictator is a story true in its way, even though it
does not contain the materially exact historical elements which we
would like to find in it." And indeed it is hard to guess just what
Loisy was trying to say. He may have meant that there are stories in
the Bible which do not correspond to historical, experimental, real-
ity,
but which do correspond to certain things lying outside the
f
8
1571 Rousselot, Etudes sur la philosophic dans le moycn age, Vol. II, pp. 14-15:
"At the time when Christianity appeared, sentiment had been stifled or vitiated in
the peoples. Then came Christianity with all its blessings, to warm hearts
. . .
and strike a note from the religious chord before which the other two [intelligence
and will] fell silent. But truth residing only in a reality that is complete [An un-
intelligibleproposition.], the time came
intelligence when
will, after ex- and
piating, so to speak, their shortcomings by a long submission, again demanded
the right to occupy the place that belonged to them. [So then: because the "true"
can reside only in a "reality" that is "complete," intellect and will ask back a
certain place that belongs to them.] So, among thinking people, first Nominalism
arose, as a first manifestation of independent intelligence we know what our
judgment is then Realism as a higher and worthier, but no less ex-
to be of it;
versial
pamphlets, local conferences, sermons, letters, the bishops did
all in their
power to set forth the truth and get it before the Donatist
public." Even Monsignor Duchesne the "truth" in question is,
for
evidently, different from the "truth" which St. Augustine and other
Holy Fathers "set forth and got before the public" when they denied
the existence of antipodes. To avoid misapprehensions, Monsignor
Duchesne might, in place of "truth," have used the phrase: "What
Catholics believe to be the truth." But that wording would have
defeated his purpose of creating a confusion between "subjective
truth," a truth recognized by certain individuals only, and "objec-
tive truth," which is tested by its accord with the facts, and so nurs-
are the very ones that are being used in France today to justify per-
secutions of Monsignor Duchesne's coreligionists. Monsignor Du-
chesne begins by rebuking the Donatists for their hostility to the
Catholics. So the French free-thinkers rebuke the Catholics for hos-
tility
to themselves and the Republic. In Africa a Catholic bishop
of Bagai was mishandled by Donatists. In France Dreyfus is said
to have been abused by Catholics. Says Monsignor Duchesne, Vol.
Ill, p. 130: "Their backs to the wall, the Catholic episcopate [The
French republican government.] recollected that there were laws
l
1572 Histoire ancienne dc I'Eglise, Vol. Ill, pp. 130 f.
10 1 8 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY J
574
against instigators of schism [Against religious congregations.], and
that, at bottom, the whole Donatist Church [The majority of the
politics,
one might have said in France had Catholics not been "in-
triguing monks" (moines ligueurs), Waldeck-Rousseau actually
said.]; but considering the temper of the Donatists and the extrav-
among them were aware of the ineptitude of their schism [Of Papal
infallibility,
one might say, for France.] and were waiting only for
a pretext for breaking loose from it. Many were Donatists by habit,
desirable and practicable to do for the France of our time what the
1575 DERIVATIONS IV-y: VERBAL PROOFS IOIQ
Old Regime so well achieved for the France of old. One king, one
faith!Such the watchword, then! And it was a tower of strength
to our monarchical governments. Our task is to find for ourselves a
similar watchword that will
correspond to the requirements of the
present age." Monsignor Duchesne, Vol. Ill, p. 127, mentions a cer-
tain popular
song that "Catholic children sang about the streets, so
popularizing the cause of unity." In twentieth-century France, La
Lantcrne and other anti-Clerical newspapers played just that role.
Under Louis XIV, in the Cevennes district, the
Royal Dragoons also
exerted themselves actively in behalf of
religious unity.
1575. There are so many kinds of truth in this world that there
may well be one to fit the relationship that obtains between Mon-
signor Duchesne's narrative and the facts as related by St. Augus-
tine, along with the comments that the Saint makes on them. But
truth, that I have said as well of all Donatists as of all heretics who
are Christians by sacrament yet depart from Christ's truth or from
1575 ^Epistolac, XCIII, 1-2 (Ad Vicentium) (Opera, Vol. II, pp. 322-23; Worlds,
Vol. VI, p. 397).
2
1575 Ibid., 2, 5 (Worlds, p. 399): "Putas neminem debcre cogi ad iustitiam!'
1575 *lbid. t 3, 10 (Opera, loc. tit., p. 326; Worlds, p. 403): ". ut coercitionc
. .
p. 329; \Vor\s, p. 409) that the important question not whether one is, or is not,
is
constrained, but whether the constraint is toward good or toward evil: ". sed
. .
qtiale sit illud quo utrum bonum an malum." It is the same old story: I set
cogttttr
out to force a person to do what I like. What I like I call "good," what he likes
"bad"; and then I tell him that he has no right to complain since I am forcing him
into what is good," Epistolae, CLXXIII, CLXXXV (Opera, Vol. II,
pp. 753-57;
Wor^s, Vol. XIII, pp. 346-53; Opera, Vol. II, pp. 792-815; Worlds, Vol. Ill, pp. 479-
520). Delightfully, the Saint adds (after a number of theological considerations on
baptism), LXXXIX, 6 (Opera, Vol. II, p. 312; Works, Vol. VI, p. 379): "And yet,
though such a luminous truth [A pretty name that the Saint has found for his own
patter.] strikes the ears and hearts of men, such a whirlpool of evil habit has en-
gulfed them that they prefer to resist all reasons and authorities rather than defer
to them. They two ways, now raving in their fury, now sulking in in-
resist in
action (saeviendo aut pigresccndo)" That too is perfectly clear! And then we are
given to understand that the Catholics were on the defensive! It takes courage to
pretend that a man who is "sulking in inaction" (pigrescendo) is attacking
someone!
5
1575 Commentaire philosophique
, Pt. Ill, Preface: "So let us glance at the two
Tetters' of this Father Augustine] which the Archbishop of Paris has had
[St.
printed in a special pamphlet in a new French translation. The pamphlet is . . .
pp. 490-91) "If however they choose to kill themselves to prevent the deliverance
:
[from error] of those who have a right to be delivered ." [Pareto renders: "to . .
prevent us from persecuting the others.'* A. L.] And he concludes, "What there-
fore shall be the stand (quid agit) of brotherly love as between fearing the tem-
porary fires of the stake for the few or sending all into the eternal fires of Hell?"
("Quid agit ergo f rater na dilcctio: utrum dum pattcis transitorios igncs metuit
caminorum, dimittit omnes aetcrnis ignibus gehennarum.") Those few words
state the whole program of the Inquisition. Cf. Contra Gattdentium, I, 24 f. (Opera,
1576 ^Epistolae, CLXXXV, 9, 35-36 (Opera, Vol. II, pp. 808-09; Worlds, Vol.
Ill, p. 508) "They reproach us with being greedy for their property and confis-
:
cating it. ... But the Christian Emperors have commanded by their religious
laws thatall property held in the name of churches of the Donatist sect should go
over to the Catholic Church with the churches themselves." So in our day in
France the property of the religious congregations "went over" to the govern-
ment and also it seems, in great part, to the liquidators, and to the politicians who
were their accomplices. Another passage in St. Augustine contains an indirect ad-
mission of such spoliations (Ibid.,loc. cit., 9, 41; Opera, pp. 810-11; Worlds, pp.
"But those who are wrongfully withholding the property of others do not know
this." The
Saint, replying, does not dispute the fact of the possession, but merely
insists that the Donatists arc not "the righteous" (justf) to Scripture alludes: whom
"It is a question," he says, "of righteousness (justitia), not of money." And that
may well be, but meantime the Catholics were pocketing the cash, and the Dona-
tists, seems, should have been satisfied, for it is written: "The righteous shall
it
spoil the ungodly" [Wisdom of Solomon, 10:20: 'Laborcs impiorum justi cdent'\\
and because the Catholics were inspired not by any design of greed but by zeal in
repressing error: //; talibus quippe omnibus jactis non rapina concupiscitur sed
error evertititr. And, besides, the Catholics seized the properties of the heretics
with every intention of restoring them the moment the heretics were converted.
1022 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY J
577
their properties back, and pretends not to understand what the quar-
rel is about when he objects that greed for the possessions of the
Donatists is inconsistent with a desire to convert them; for the
Just to enable you freely to buy and sell while daring to divide what
2
the sold Christ had bought?" And so the Saint
goes on piling up
antitheses that are based on double
meanings of words and other
cavillings. These wretched and inept arguments have been admired
by many people; and that, as we have so often said and repeated in
3
similar cases, shows the great
power that sentiments have. At bot-
tom St.
Augustine's argument comes down to this: "You hold a
belief that we consider erroneous; therefore we are justified in doing
anything to bring you over from your belief, which we think bad,
to our belief, which we think
good. And you have no cause for
complaint, since you can escape your plight by adopting our view."
But in that form the argument has far less persuasive force than the
form used by St. Augustine, where "truth" and "error," "good" and
"bad," are palmed of? not as subjective but as objective entities.
1577. Of
course a person
sharing St. Augustine's faith cannot
grant that the terms in question are subjective. But if he will have
them objective at all costs, he might still admit, without derogating
2
1576 Epistolae, XCIII, 5, 19 (Opera, Vol. II, p. 331; Worlds, Vol. VI, p. 411):
"Ita sane huic provision! contradicere debut ne res
quas dicitis vcstras perderetis et
sccuri Christum proscriberetis? ut iure Romano testamenta condcrctis et iure divino
patnbus conditum Testamentum ubi scripttim cst: 'In semine tuo bencdicentnr
omnes gentes' [Gen. 26:4] calttmniosis criminationibus rtimperetis? ut in
emptioni-
bus et vcnditionibus liberos contractus haberctis ct vobis dividere Christies emit
quod
venditus auderetis?"
8
1576 [Parcto says, "and that shows the fatuousness of derivations" apparently a
lapsus linguae. A. L.]
1578 DERIVATIONS IV-yl VERBAL PROOFS IO23
one whit from his faith, that their objectivity is something different
from the objectivity of a chemical or physical experiment. That ad-
mission would be enough to eliminate all conflict with experimental
science, which concerns itself strictly with facts of this latter type.
1578. At other times the confusion between the many kinds of
truth arises without any preconceived design on a writer's part to
take advantage of it merely as a reflection of a similar confusion
little
importance. But unless one would chatter to no purpose, the
name, whatever it be, must be different from the name one uses for
the miracles of the various religions, the legends of folk-lore, proph-
ecies and portents, and stories of the type of Aladdin's marvellous
lamp. Some of these stories may have, if one will, a "higher" truth
than experimental truth that is not the question. What is impor-
tant is that that truth, however superior it may be, should have a
name to distinguish it from our modest, inferior, commonplace, "ex-
8
perimental truth."
8
1578 There are many other "truths," and very pretty ones. Writing of Tolstoy
in the Corriere della sera, Nov. 21, 1910, Antonio Fogazzaro, the novelist, says:
"He created truth and never seemed to care about creating beauty. He seemed
almost to disdain Art as something inferior, as something human and not divine.
But of the whole Truth he was the voice, as it were, and the flame, not only of
the truth that the artist pantingly pursues, but also of that moral truth which glows
resplendent in the soul that it has permeated. The True and the Good were one
with Tolstoy. Not everything, to be sure, that seemed Good and True to him
seems Good and True to me, or to numberless others who feel the passion of the
Good and the True." Fogazzaro prints the word "true" sometimes with a capital,
sometimes with a small letter. Whether there be a difference, and just what, in the
two cases is not very clear. Dame Truth has a voice and a flame. That seems to be
very consoling to Fogazzaro. To us it is merely obscure. There is a certain "moral
truth which glows resplendent in the soul that it has permeated." That is under-
1579 PROPHECY AND FULFILMENT 1025
*
1579. The Abbe de
Broglie exemplifies very fairly a subjective
conception of prophecies. Abraham Kuenen had shown that cer-
tain prophecies in the Bible do not accord with the facts. Father de
prophecy. He assumes that the prophetic texts have only one mean-
ing, that the meaning has to be clear, that it has to be the meaning
which the prophets and their contemporaries gave to it. He does not
recognize any fulfilment unless events conform to the meaning so
established." Such, in fact, is the
meaning used in the objective
reasonings of historical criticism and of logico-experimental science
2
in general. The Abbe de Broglie meets Kuenen with subjective con-
siderations that may perfectly well be accepted so long as they are
kept distinct from those of the logico-experimental type. Such a dis-
tinction is essential unless we are to talk to no purpose. Says he:
"The true conception of prophecy is quite different." And as usual
the term "true" leads to an argument in a circle. That would not
be the case instead of saying the "true conception," the Abbe had
if,
standable. Everybody finds resplendent a truth with which he has been "per-
meated." The trouble is, not everyone is permeated. And what does it mean to
"create truth"? Truth ordinarily is discovered, asserted, proclaimed. Fairy-stories
and old wives' tales are "created" and very easily. It might be objected that such
criticisms miss the point in Fogazzaro's article in that they approach from a
logico-experimental point of view a paragraph designed exclusively to act upon
sentiment. And that would be true. Our criticisms aim at nothing else than at dem-
onstrating the sentimental value of the passage. Writings of that kind are ridicu-
lous from the logico-experimental standpoint. They may be very effective as ap-
fulfilled; and his arguments are neither better nor worse than other
4
disquisitions of the kind (62if.). But as everybody
knows and
1579 Guillaume de Jumiege, Histoire des Normands, p. 313. A mysterious in-
3
dividual asked whether Count Rollon's line is to endure very long: "lie refused
is
to make any answer and began merely to draw something like lines in the ashes
on the hearth with a little stick which he held in his hand. His host then insisting
very obstinately on getting him to say what was to happen after the seventh gen-
eration, he began with the same wooden stick to erase the lines he had drawn in
the ashes. Whence it was inferred that after the seventh generation the duchy
would be destroyed, or at least would have to undergo great trials and tribulations,
the which in fact we have seen to be fulfilled in large part, those of us who have
survived King Henry, who was, as we can show, the seventh in descent in that
line." Paulin Paris, Les romans de la Table ronde, Vol. II, pp. 56-57 (The magician
"
Merlin declares) Henceforward I shall not speak before the people or at court
:
save in obscure words, nor will they know what I mean until they see it come
"
to pass.' Merlin, says Paris, "kept his word to the letter, and all soothsayers before
and after him have followed that same policy." That, in fact, was an excellent
precaution on Merlin's part, and it may be recommended in full confidence to all
our estimable prophets and fortune-tellers.
4 La
1579 concordance des propheties de Nostradamus avec I'histoire, pp. ii5f.
One "verification" chosen at random, Centurie III, Quatrin 91:
"L'arbre qu'avoit par long temps mort seiche
dans une nuit vicndra a revcrdir:
chron. Roi malade: Prince pied attache:
tf
craint d'ennemis fera voiles bondir.
("The had long since dried up and died will leaf out again in the course
tree that
of a night. Chron.: King sick; Prince tied at the foot; fear of foes will set sails
a-bounding.") "Explanation: Historians are quite in agreement as to the veracity
of the matter of this prophecy, but not as to the day or the month of its ful-
filment. Favyn reports [Histoire de Navarre, p. 868] that the day after St.
. . .
1579 DERIVATIONS IV-y: VERBAL PROOFS 1027
as theproverb says, hindsight is better than foresight del senno di
poi son piene Ic fosse! Even when the divergence between the
prophecy and the fact is altogether patent, the Abbe de Broglie
makes one more attempt at reconciliation and ends by saying that
Bartholomew, Aug. 25, 1572, an old tree known as 'the Hawthorne* which had
long since dried up and died was found to be entirely green the morning after
the night of Sunday-Monday. . .That proves today the truth of the first two
.
verses. . However, Jean le Gaulois claims that that did not take place till Sep-
. .
tember of that same year, 1572. ... But whether the miracle occurred the day
after St. Bartholomew or a week or more later is of no importance today. It is
enough for us that Nostradamus had predicted it. [As for the two following lines:]
There arc also signs of the veracity of the predictions of Nostradamus, inasmuch as
Charles IX, some time after the occurrence of the miracle in question, fell sick . . .
of a chronic ailment, a sort of quartan fever. As for 'the Prince tied at the foot/
that meant that M. the Due d'Anjou would, as he actually did and also about that
same time, tie himself to the foot of the walls of La Rochelle. The last verse . . .
meant that in fear of the enemies of France the King would fit out a great naval
force." See also Nicoullaud,Nostradamus ct ses prophcties.
In his Bickerstaff Papers Swift delightfully satirizes such mongers of prophecy.
He pretends in person of Bickerstaff to make a number of prophecies, one among
others foretelling the death on a certain day of Partridge, the almanac writer, and
the Cardinal de Noailles. He assumes that the fulfilment of the prophecy has been
disputed and replies: "With my utmost endeavours I have not been able to trace
above two objections ever made against the truth of my last year's prophecies. The
firstwas of a Frenchman, who was pleased to publish to the world 'that the Cardi-
nal de Noailles was still alive notwithstanding the pretended prophecy of Monsieur
nology about the hour of his death, I shall only prove that Mr. Partridge is not alive.'*
Arguments follow parodying the arguments used on such occasions, among others
this one: "Secondly, Death is defined by all philosophers a separation of the soul
and body. Now it is certain that the poor woman who has best reason to know, has
gone about for some time to every alley in the neighbourhood and sworn to the
gossips that her husband had neither life nor soul in him. Therefore, if an unin-
formed carcass walks still about and is pleased to call itself Partridge, Mr. Bicker-
staff does not think himself any way answerable for that." As to the precise mo-
ment of Partridge's death: "Several of my friends assured me I computed to
. . .
utility,
where the idea is to arouse, provoke, foment certain senti-
Pyrrhus would have had sense enough to know that the ambiguity in the line 'you
the Romans can defeat' promised no better for him than for the Romans."
Op. at., pp. 121-24: "Kuenen notes a fact still stranger. When the New
5
1579
Testament writers need to use an Old Testament text in a sense contrary to the
natural meaning of the terms, they are not afraid to alter it, suppressing sentences,
clauses,and words that determined the original meaning. [The Abbe mentions a
case where St. Paul certainly altered a biblical text.] This passage is extremely
strange and perplexing. St. Paul seems to declare that Moses said something that
he obviously did not one looks attentively into the matter, the
say. Nevertheless, as
difficulty lessens. .
[And very captious exegesis proves that St. Paul is, at bot-
. a .
tom, right. All the same, the good Abbe is not easy in his conscience:] In spite of
these interpolations one difficulty still remains. St. Paul's way of quoting the Old
Testament is certainly free to a degree, and it is apparent that he is giving a lesson
grammatical commentary but a false text.] Solutions for such difficulties may be
sought. However, if they seem to us inadequate, we can still fall back on a resort
that the Pope himself has suggested to us: suspense of judgment: cunctandum a
sententia. One may wonder, indeed, whether such procedure is not the wisest when
we are faced with texts like the one just mentioned."
1580 METHODS AND PURPOSES OF HISTORY IO29
ments such as patriotism,
loyalty to this or that political system,
enthusiasm for some noble and useful enterprise, the sense of hon-
esty, and so on. Such purposes are envisaged in compositions that
stand midway between scientific history and historical romance. It
is characteristic of them that
they manage to colour their facts in
1
the proper direction and, as occasion requires, suppress them. One
must however manage to diverge from experimental reality with-
out being caught telling lies; and that task is frequently made easy
by the fact that before the author deceives his readers he deceives
himself: he sees reality in the colours in which he paints it.
There is another ambiguity in the question, "How ought history
to be written?" The term "ought" may refer to the purpose itself,
or to the means that are to be used in attaining it. The question may
mean: i. Which of the purposes mentioned "ought" one, must one,
is it better to, select? 2. The
purpose decided upon, what means
"ought" one, must one, better to, use in
is it
attaining it? The first
2
of these two propositions, like all others of its tribe, is elliptical: the
in view of which history "ought" to be written in
special purpose
this or that manner is not stated. One may ask: What course had
historians better follow with a view to promoting the material,
political,
or other prosperity of a country, social class, political sys-
tem, and so on? Or: How and when is it advisable to use the dif-
ferent sorts of history ? Is it better to use just one or all of them in
different proportions, according to different social classes or the
1
Inpcrface to his Geschichte dcs deutsch-jranzosischen Krieges von
a
-
1580
/ #70-77, p. xi (English, Vol. I, p. viii), Marshal von Moltke states his own views
as to his purposes in writing: "The things that are published in a military history
that has been achieved. But loyalty and love of country require one not to damage
the respect with which the victories of one's arms have clothed this or that individual
person." That is excellent. It makes his purpose clear: he is to describe facts, but
may be involved in his narrative. [The
taking into account the social effects that
preface in question however, by Major von Moltke, the Marshal's son, and the
is,
Germany. Let our young men temper their steel in the fire of faith With such arms !
we can dash forward, full of confidence in the divine power." The Berliner Tage-
blatt observed in comment: "The Emperor says that Prussia lost her faith soon after
the death of Frederick II and was One cannot help
for that reason defeated in 1806.
The criticism sound from the standpoint of experimental history, but not as re-
is
gards stimulating sentiments in a country, which was the sole purpose the Emperor
had in view. From the experimental standpoint the Emperor's address is so wild
that when he speaks of "the hand of God" one can only think of Fucini's verse on
the aurora borealis: "That? That was the finger of the Omnipotent!" [Poesie,
. . .
30, p. 64.] But what weight will experimental truth have in the balance on the day
when the German warriors go marching forth to death? When, furthermore, some
people think they are using experimental truth, they are really doing nothing more
than exploiting another religion; and religion for religion, the religion of the Ger-
man Emperor seems better under the circumstances than many others in that it
fortified, instead of depressing, the sentiments required by men who were destined
to die on a field of battle. Consider, now, the devotees of the "Dreyfusard" religion
1582 DERIVATIONS IV-/! VERBAL PROOFS 103!
'teaching,' 'history'?"
problem when so stated has but one solution,
1582. Since the
many people imagine that it also has but one solution when con-
sidered from the objective standpoint; and if they chance indeed to
be in some doubt, they are not likely to discover the various objec-
tive solutions. A writer who is
producing a more or less adulterated
noted, when
a person is thinking scientifically he distinguishes, he
separates, things
that persons unaccustomed to such thinking con-
*
1583 Along that line we enter a practical field quite different from the one in
which we are interested here.
*
1584 Cicero, Academica, II, what one's
43, 132, notes the importance of defining
"highest good" is to be, "because one's bound up with the
whole scheme of life is
definition one gives of the highest good: those who dissent from it, dissent from
one's scheme of life." Now indeed we are in for it, if we have to discover what the
"scheme of life" is! It was a good two thousand years ago that Cicero was voicing
such doubts, and they have not yet been dispelled. Will they be in another two
thousand years? Meantime people have got to live, and live they do without bother-
ing their heads too much over the "highest good," which remains a pretty play-
thing for the metaphysicists.
1587 THE PROBLEM OF THE "HIGHEST GOOD" 1033
side. He himself, in his own mind,
almost never sees things in just
that way. generally the case with sentiments, where
First of all, as is
quite different matter, "This is the highest good," and then produce
a flock of derivations to prove it.
1586. The
derivation will be partly justified by the fact that in
addition to the subjective phenomenon just noted, there are objective
future pain." One may say: "To many people, in general, the
momentary pleasure may bring serious pain through loss of the
esteem and consideration (in general) of the other individuals in
the community." But it would be a mistake to draw any particular
conclusion from that general proposition to say, for instance: "For
John Doe the present pleasure may bring serious pain through loss
of the esteem and consideration of Messrs. M, N,P. ." In.
point of
.
fact it may well be the case that John Doe cares not a fig for such
esteem and consideration in general, or for the esteem and consid-
eration of Messrs. M, N, P in particular.
1588. Effects upon communities are often more or less
vaguely
designated by such terms as the "prosperity" economic, military,
political, and so on, of a nation; or the "welfare" from the stand-
humanity.
1590. All that comes out in the
derivations, whereby, starting with
sentiments present in the individual, with certain residues, that is,
one ends by showing that he "ought" to act in a manner considered
good by the author of the derivation it never diverges very widely
from the manner accepted by the society in which the author lives.
Ordinarily the point of departure and the point of arrival are
known in advance. The derivation follows some path, any path, that
will bring the two points together.
1591. The
derivation that exploits the phrase "highest good," or
groups of sentiments from which the start is made and all that is
possible of the results that it is purposed to achieve. One of the
derivations most frequently used, in fact, starts with the sentiments
of egoism to arrive at altruistic conduct as its goal.
1592. Something similar has happened in the case of political
was humorously suggested as a fitting epitaph for the tomb of Sardanapalus (licen-
tious king of Assyria): "What I ate and drank and enjoyed in gay lust, that do I
possess. All else of other good things have I lost." Cicero comments, quoting
many
Aristotle: "What
would you suggest for the tomb of an ox, let alone a king!"
else
Extant also is a rejoinder by Crates of Thebes, loc. cit., 326: "What I learned and
thought and enjoyed in the companionship of the Venerable Muses, that do I pos-
sess. All else of many other good things has vanished in smoke." In a dispute with
Archytas, Polyarchus remarks, Athenaeus, Deipnosophistac, XII, 64, 545, that to his
mind the doctrine of Archytas strays far indeed from Nature: "For Nature, so far
as she can make herself known to us, enjoins us to pursue pleasure, and that, she
in the sense of vmav "to overcome": "What, therefore, Aristippus says is that over-
1*
ing Zeus in lecherous mood and "saying that he was more possessed by passion
(VTTO iiuOvfiiac) [for Juno] than he had been at any time since they first united
behind the backs of their beloved parents" (Iliad, XIV, vv. 294-96). So Aristippus
was not "possessed" in that way by his passion for Lais. Lactantius Firmianus,
Divinae institutioncs, III, 15, 15 (Opera, Vol. I, p. 223; Fletcher, Vol. I, p. 173),
quotes the remark of Aristippus, but altogether failing to understand it. [This stric-
ture seems undeserved. Lactantius understands but embroiders. A. L.] Cicero,
Epistnlae ad fawiliares, Paeto, IX, 26, 2: "Listen to the rest. Cytheris [mistress of
Mark Antony] had the place [at dinner] next beyond Eutrapelus. I can hear you
thinking: 'The great Cicero was a guest at such a dinner?' ... I never suspected,
I assure you, that she was to be there and yet, Aristippus the Socratist never batted
an eyelash when he was taunted with a passion for Lais! 'I am possessed not by her
but of her!' he said (the thing sounds better in Greek)." Diogenes Lacrtius, loc. cit.,
69 (Hicks, p. 199) "Once as he [Aristippus] was entering a courtesan's house, a
:
young man in his company evinced some shame; and he remarked: 'The shame is
"
not in going into such a place, but in being unable to go out.' Persius, Satnrae,
V, v. 173, also calls that man free who can leave a courtesan's house in full posses-
sion of himself (Ramsay: "entire and heart-whole") :
8
1595 loc. cit., 93 (Hicks, pp. 221-23). That however is in-
Diogenes Lacrtius,
consistent with what Aristippus is said, Ibid., 68 (Hicks, p. 199), to have replied to
a question as to what philosophers were good for: "If all laws were abolished, we
would still live as we do now." However, we are not interested here in what Aris-
tippus really thought, but merely in certain derivations: whether they be his or of
someone else is of little moment.
*
1596 Cicero, De finibus bonorum et malorum, I, 12, 40.
1038 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1596
it with another also indefinite and obscure. The "pleasure" that
figures in the formula mentioned
is not the
ordinary pleasure which
everybody knows, but another that has still to be defined. Cicero,
DC finibus bonorum ct turns the point to jest:
malorum, II, 3, 6,
"Then, said he, laughing: 'A fine idea, that the very man who says
that pleasure is the goal of all our hopes, the last, ultimate Good,
"
should not know what it is!' And he goes on to say, Ibid., II, 3, 8,
that the terms voluptas in Latin and n^ovrt in Greek are perfectly
2
"Hos ego asotos bcne quidem vivere ant beate nunquam dixerim"
1596
3
1596 "Ex quo cfficitur non ut voluptas non sit voluptas, sed ut voluptas non sit
summum bonum."
1596
4
There are five parts to Cicero's argument: i. A philological question, II,
4, 13: fj6ovf} should be rendered in Latin as voluptas: "By that term all Latins the
world over mean two things, and to wit: a feeling of joy in the spirit, and a pleas-
urable excitation of body." On that point Cicero seems to be right: f}6ovfi in Greek
and voluptas in Latin seem in fact to have just those meanings. 2. question as A
to Epicurus's manner of expressing himself, II, 5, 15. Epicurus uses the term tffiovJt
in a sense different from the meanings stated: "Whence it comes about not that
we do not sense the term in usual force (non ut nos non intdligamus quae vis
its
sit istius verbi)> but that he speaks in a manner of his own, ignoring ours (sed ut
1598 DERIVATIONS IV-yi VERBAL PROOFS 1039
1597. We
have the proposition, A B, and we want A to be
equal to C. There are two ways of going about it. Either we may
respect the first statement and alter the meaning B, so that it be-
comes equivalent to C; or we may negate the statement and re-
place it with A
=
C. This situation is general and accounts for
large
numbers of derivations.
1598. The derivation tends to in length because, along with
grow
"pleasure," it is better to take residues of group-persistence into ac-
count ("justice," "honesty," and so on) and residues of personal
integrity ("honour," "self-respect" .)
either with reference to the
. .
ille suo more loquatur, nostrum negligat)." And there again Cicero is right, but
much too right for his own thesis. The fault of Epicurus is the fault of all meta-
physicists, Cicero not excepted; for he too suo more loquitur, nostrum negligit, if
by "our way" we mean the way of anyone who disagrees with him. 3. A question
as to the relations of sentiments aroused in certain persons by certain terms. The
sentiments suggested respectively by the terms "pleasure" and "highest good" do
not accord in the case of Cicero his own testimony is adequate proof of that. Nor
do they accord in the cases of certain other persons, as may be verified by observa-
tion. On that point too, then, Cicero is right. 4. A question as to the relations be-
tween sentiments or between things in the minds of all men. Not explicitly, but
implicitly after the manner of many many metaphysicists, Cicero leaps over from
the contingent to the absolute. For the same reason that Cicero's own testimony is
sufficient to show that the terms "pleasure" and "highest good" do not make the
same impression on him, the testimony of a person who disagrees with him has to
suffice as evidence that the two terms do make an identical impression upon that
person. And just as observation shows that many people agree with Cicero, observa-
tion also shows that many people think otherwise. Cicero therefore is in error in
ascribing a universal, absolute value to a proposition that has a particular, contin-
gent value only. 5. A
sophistical argument to eliminate dissenters, and so again to
get the contingent back to the absolute. Here too Cicero's reasoning is packed with
unstated assumptions, as is common with metaphysicists. It is intimated that there
and "highest good," things that are of common
really are things called "pleasure"
knowledge; and if some empty-headed individual chooses to deny their existence,
we need no more take account of his chatter than of the ravings of some lunatic
to whom it might occur to deny the existence of Carthage. In other words, Cicero
intimates the universality of his proposition by raising the question as to what
"people say." "People" means "everybody," and when everybody says the same
thing, the thing must be as everybody says it is as when everybody says that the
Sun gives heat. As many incidental considerations as rhetoric can furnish are then
brought in. So there Cicero is wrong, but neither more wrong nor less wrong than
any other metaphysicist.
1040 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1599
ideals one would attain. This process also yields theories in large
1
numbers.
1599. In his De finibus bonorum
malorum, II, 3, 8, Cicero
et
takes up the view of Hieronymus of Rhodes that the highest good
was freedom from all pain. He censures Epicurus, II, 6, 18, for not
his mind; for, says he, Epicurus
making up ought either to accept
the term "pleasure" in its ordinary sense the sense of Aristippus,
Cicero calls it or else take the term in the sense of absence of pain,
or else combine the two things and two ends or purposes. II,
so get
1598
*
We need not deal with them here in detail since our present aim is
merely
to get a better understanding of the character of such derivations.
1602 "NATURE" 1041
its own sake.
St.
Augustine has his fun with all such verbal drool and
firmly and flatly
sets
up a supreme good of his own, eternal life; and
1
a supreme evil, eternal death. And there we are at the other extreme
in such derivations.
1601. The
nucleus of sentiments corresponding to the different
terms are all so vague that oftentimes not even the person who uses
them knows just what meaning he is trying to convey. 1 In his daily
life the human being encounters many things that are inimical to
De civitatc Dei, XIX, I, 4f.: "Si ergo quaeratur a nobis quid civitas Dei
1600 l
Vol. VIII, p. 229), St. Thomas says: ". for the supreme good of man lies in the
. .
cleaving of the soul unto God (in hoc quod anima Deo inhaercat)"
x
1602 In the Retractationes,
I, 10, 3 (Opera, Vol. I, p. 600), St. Augustine cau-
tions that hisdictum about there being no natural evil "nullum esse malum natu-
rale" might be misunderstood by the Pelagians. He used the term "natural" as
referring to that nature which was created without sin the nature that is "truly
and properly'* the nature of man: "ipsa enim vere ac proprie natura hominis did-
tur." By analogy, says he, we also use the term as designating man's nature at birth.
1042 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1603
him, either doing him harm or causing mere annoyance through
certain circumstances which he considers artificial. Such the
depre-
dations of highwaymen, the wiles of thieves, the tyrannical acts of
the rich and powerful, and so on. If all such circumstances are
eliminated, we are left with a nucleus that we will call "natural,"
as opposed to the "artificial" things we have discarded; and it must
necessarily be good, nay, perfect, since we have thrown out every-
thing that was bad in ( 1546). That, in fact, is the reasoning of
it
all
metaphysicists or theologians, of the followers of the Physiocrats,
of Rousseau and other dreamers of that do not
type. They say:
"Here is a state that we call 'natural.' From observations by such and
such scientists who have seen and examined it, it is known to
present such and such traits." What they do is to start with a present
state, eliminate from it everything they dislike, and then foist the
term "natural" on what is left. Rousseau, indeed, who is still ad-
mired, not to say worshipped, by many people, candidly confesses
his indifference to the facts
(821); and even more indifferent to
them was that Holy Father who praised the beautiful order which
God had bestowed on Nature and gravely assures us that in Nature
2
all little animals make their societies in
peace and concord. He had
never seen spiders eating flies, nor birds
eating spiders, nor had he
8
read Virgil's description of bees
swarming to battle! But then
again, nothing is more diverting than the manner of thinking of
those who deride "Catholic superstition" but
pay reverent homage to
the superstitions of the Rousseaueans.
1
1603. De Remusat enumerates at least four senses in which
2
1602 St. Clement the Roman, Epistulae ad Corinthios, I, 20, 10 (Gebhardt-
Harnack, p. 39) Td re i^d^cora
: rtiv
tyuv rdf awsfabaEis avruv kv dpfjvy K.OL
ofiovoip troi-
ovvrat.
8
1602 Gc orgies, IV, vv. 67-70:
("But when they rush forth to battle (for discord and noisy tumult often arise from
there being two kings) one can sense straightway and even from afar the
temper
of the swarm and its quivering eagerness for combat.")
1
1603 (Euvres de Ciceron, Vol. IV, p. 411 (Lecler, Vol. 27, pp. 95-96).
1604 DERIVATIONS IV-yl VERBAL PROOFS 1043
Cicero uses the word "Nature" in his essay on Laws? i. general A
meaning: Nature as the sum total of the facts of the universe. 2. A
particular meaning: Nature as the constitution of each individual
being. 3. Another meaning, which Remusat explains as "a personal,
individual sense that is never more than
implicitly defined,
and
transpires only from a knowledge of his doctrine [A fine expedient
for starting arguments!] The nature of a being is that which makes
:
9 9
'Natura largita est, docentc natura, I, 8, 25-26; 'eadem natura , I, 9,
9
26; 'natura jactos, a natura dati, natura data I, 12, 33." What a
treasure-store such a term must be for derivations the reader may
easily imagine.
It means everything and nothing!
1604. With Aristotle, Dame Nature changes altogether in aspect.
The Stagirite begins by noting,
Naturalis Auscultatio, II, i, i (Wick-
1
stead, Vol. I, p. 107), that natural beings have within themselves a
1603
2
We can touch on them here but briefly, but the reader would do well to
look at them in the original.
1603
3
[Remusat's reference is erroneous. There is no such phrase in De Ic gibus,
that 'nature* iscombination and dissolution; in other words, birth and destruction."
8 "A/lAov 6e rp6nov 7} fiop^j nal TO eMof TO Kara rov %6yov. It is not
1604 easy to divine
what all that means. At bottom there seems to be a dispute as to whether "nature"
is matter or form, and the apparent conclusion is, I, i, 15, that it is form: 'II npa
fj-of)^ <pvois. However, we are shordy thereafter advised that"form" and "nature"
have two senses, since privation is a sort of form. All of which is mere prattle. St.
Thomas, Sttmma theologiac, I a II
ae
, qu. 31, art. 7 (Opera, Vol. VI, p. 221), tries
to clarify the Master: answer by saying that a thing is called 'natural' which
"I
is according to nature, as he
[Aristotle] says, Physica, II, 4-5. In man, however,
nature may be taken in two ways: in the one sense, inasmuch as intellect, reason
(mtellectus et ratio), is the outstanding trait in man, since by it he is given his place
in species. From that standpoint, those human pleasures may be called 'natural*
which apply what is proper to a man according to reason. So delight in the con-
to
templation of truth and in acts of virtue is natural to man. [What a pity our crim-
so!] In man considered as partaking of reason, nature may
inals do not find things
be taken, in another sense, as that which is common to man and other things, and
especially as that which is not subordinate to reason." Nature, therefore, means
white and black. But that is not the end of it: of the two species of pleasures, some
are natural in one sense, but not natural in another: "As regards both these
pleas-
ures some are unnatural, simply speaking, but natural (conn aturales) in certain
relations (Secundum utrasque autem delectationes contingit aliquas esse innaturales
and reality."
An excellent example of verbal derivation an endless
the Apostle says [Ephes. 5: 6] that 'by nature we are children of wrath,* that is to
say, by conception and nativity, whence we derive sin. 2. In the sense of matter
and form. So man is said to be made up of two partial natures. 3. In the sense
of the essence of the thing. So we say that the angelic nature or essence is superior
to human nature. 4. In physic, nature is taken for the intrinsic principle of move-
ment and rest in the things about us." It does not occur to these good souls that
to give the same name to things so vastly different is an excellent device for never
being understood.
4
1604 Physique d'Aristote, Vol. I, Preface, p. iv.
5
1604 Earlier in his Preface, p. iii, Saint-Hilaire had said: 'The theory of mo-
tion is so truly the necessary antecedent to physics that when Newton is laying the
mathematical foundations of natural philosophy toward the end of the seventeenth
century, his immortal book is nothing more or less than a theory of motion. ([In a
note:] He says so himself in the preface to the first edition of the Principia.) In his
Principles of Philosophy Descartes had also placed the study of motion at the head
of the Science of Nature. So, two thousand years before Descartes and Newton,
Aristotle had proceeded exactly as they proceeded, and if his work is to be fairly
appraised, will be recognized as of the same family
it and in more than one respect
to have nothing to fear from the comparison." We may let that pass as regards
Descartes. As for Newton, the difference between his Principia and Aristotle's
Physica is the difference between day and night. It is true, alas, that here and there
in the Principia a little metaphysics creeps in it is like the barren rock that holds
the experimental gold, and metaphysicists, of course, grasp at the rock and leave
the gold. Says Newton in his Preface: "Since the manual arts are primarily con-
cerned with the moving of bodies, Geometry is commonly applied to mass and
Mechanics to motion. In that sense rational Mechanics will be the science, accurately
stated and demonstrated, of the movements resulting from certain forces, and of the
1046 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1605
1605. From the way in which the group of sentiments correspond-
ing to such expressions as "purpose of life," "highest good/' "right
reason," "nature," has been built up, it is readily understandable
that such terms may be equated with one another, since they repre-
the Stoics could say that the "purpose of life," the "highest good,"
was to live according to "nature." Just what that "nature" is nobody
knows, and better so; for it is the various indefinite meanings that
are associated with the term that win acquiescence for the Stoic
maxim and others of the kind. In fact, according to Stobaeus,
Eglogae physicae et cthicae, II, 7 (Heeren, Vol. II, pp. 132-35),
Zeno began with a language even more indefinite, holding that the
purpose of life was to live harmoniously; and that, Stobaeus adds,
"means living according to one plan and harmoniously. But those
who came him, by way of improvement, explained it as mean-
after
.* Cleanthes was the first
ing living in harmony with nature.' . .
... to bring in nature, and he ruled that the purpose was to live
in harmony with nature." And going on equating terms correspond-
ing to this or that sentiment, the Stoics came to assert that the goal
was "happiness"; and "happiness" was "to live according to virtue,
sociality and
altruism, and by no means to forget right reason. All
those pretty things we can cram into the concept of "nature" and
forces required for certain movements." Of such things Aristotle talks not at all,
but of matters quite different.
*
1605 Td tie rAof 6 filv Zfyvw ovrug a7r6cjK.e y rb 6fiohoyovfj,ivG)$ rjv f Tovro < earl rccitf eva
'/,6yov Kal GV[i.(j>(
)vov C^v. 01 <5 fiera rovrov t TrpnofiiapOpovvres, oirwf ^l(f>pov f o^oTioyovpiv-
t
ug r?7 <j>voet, $fjv. The word b^oyov^tv^ properly means "suitably," "harmoniously,"
"concordantly," "conformably," and is therefore somewhat vague unless the thing
with which the harmony or suitableness prevails is specified. Zeno's meaning would
accordingly be: to live suitably, harmoniously, and so on; and one might even say
perhaps, temperately, moderately.
1607 DERIVATIONS IV-y: VERBAL PROOFS 1047
all
existing things. And that same law is the virtue of the happy
man and the happiness of life when, that is, all is done in a harmony
of the individual temperament with the will of the ruler of all
things. And
therefore Diogenes expressly declares that the ideal of
life is
right thinking in the choice of what is according to nature,
x
and Archidamus, living in fulfilment of all duties." That is a good
example of the verbal derivation. Words are heaped on words, till
one gets a hotchpotch containing a little of everything.
1607. These reasonings are of the following type. One sets out to
prove that A
=
B. One begins by demonstrating that A X, be- =
cause the sentiments associated with A and are in accord. Mean- X
while pains are taken to select an X
so indefinite that while the
sentiments associated with it are in accord with the sentiments asso-
ciated with A, they also accord with the sentiments associated with B.
In that way an equation is established between X and B. But since
it has already been granted that A =
X, it follows that A B =
the thesis that was to be demonstrated. This reasoning follows the
lines of the one we examined in 480 f., where the equation A=B
was proved by the elimination ofa non-experimental entity, X. As in
other cases, the introduction of a vague term imperfectly corre-
Vol. II, p. 59), imagines that the "nature" of the Stoics is none other than God:
*
Therefore the Stoics opined that the purpose of life was to live according to nature,
"
very properly using the term 'nature* for 'God.*
1048 THE MIND AND SOCIETY l6o8
constituting one single person, as having the same will; and the
proposition means for that matter giving a special twist to the term
"error" judge of what, to him, is agreeable or
that a person is sole
exist. It is asserted, without proof of any kind, that the general will,
X, expressed by the sum of particular wills when the citizens in
is
decision of the citizens, B, when the vote is held apart from intrigue
and pressure of private interests. This game is all to the liking of
Rousseau's admirers, and they go on playing at it. Still again X
is modified, and once the
opinion of the majority (?) of the electors,
it now becomes the
opinion of the majority of those elected. Such the
evolution of one of the sublimest dogmas of the democratic re-
*
ligion!
*
1608 In the Contrat social, II, i, after showing how the social contract is drawn,
Rousseau adds: "The first and most important consequence of the principles above
established is that the general will can alone direct the forces of the State according
to the purposes for which it was established, the common weal." can that be? How
II, 4: "If the State or City is just a moral person deriving its life from the union of
its members, and the most important of its concerns is its own preservation, it
if
needs a universal power of compulsion to move and arrange each part in the man-
ner most advantageous to the whole. Just as Nature gives each individual absolute
power over all his members, so the social pact gives the body politic absolute power
over all its members, and it is that power directed by the general will which bears
... the name of sovereignty. . . .
Why else is the general will
always right, why
else do all invariably wish for the welfare of each individual among them, unless it
be that there is no one who does not take the words 'each individual' to himself
and does not think of himself in voting for all?" The general proposition, X = A,
1609 ROUSSEAU'S "GENERAL WILL" 1049
1609. This argument is
accepted by many people, not because of
its intrinsic logico-experimental value, which is zero, nor for
any
lack of intelligence on the part of those who assent to it some of
them are very intelligent indeed. To what, then, is the success of
is now established: the general will, X, in other words, is always right, A. Follow-
ing a method customary among metaphysicists and very dear to them, Rousseau
attributes a characteristic to the general will before explaining at all definitely what
that entity is. Now we proceed, II, 3, to modify X: "It follows from what has just
been said that the general will is always right and always tends to the public wel-
fare; but it does not follow that the deliberations of the people always have the
same rectitude. A man always wants what is good for him, but he does not always
know what it is. The people is never corrupted but is often deceived, and then only
does it in appearances seek what [The modification in the meaning of "error."
is evil.
We shall return to the point presently.] There is often a great difference between
the will of all [One of the forms of X.] and the general will [Another form of X.] :
The latter envisages only the common interest; the other envisages private interest
and is only a sum of particular wills [Watch the juggler's ball it is slipping from
one box to the other!]: but strip those same wills of the more and the less that
cancel each other [For them to do that, the less would have to be equal to the
more, otherwise there would be a remainder; but the divine Rousseau cares not a
fig for such petty details.] [Pareto seems to misunderstand Rousseau's passage, which
means not that the less cancels the more, but that a larger or smaller number of
particular wills cancel each other: the French reads: "Otez de ces memes volontcs
Ics plus et les moins qui s'entrcdetruisent." To amend Pareto's stricture one might
say against Rousseau that when a certain number of particular wills cancel each
other, the dark horse wins; but the dark horse may represent a particular interest.
A. L.] and the general will is left as the sum of the differences. [Now the ball has
It will soon be doing something cleverer still: a real state, B, is going to be described
for the purpose of equating it with one of the indefinite abstractions, X, just prof-
fered.] When after sufficient enlightening the people deliberates, if the citizens have
had no intercommunication [How can they be enlightened if there is no intercom-
munication? It must be an internal spontaneous sort of enlightenment!], the great
number of little differences [Who told Rousseau that they were "little"?] will
always yield the general will [i.e., X.], and the decision will always be a good one.
[Even when the people votes to burn a witch?] But when there is electioneering
by partial associations at the expense of the great association, the will of each clique
becomes general as regards its members, particular as regards the State. Finally, . . .
when one such association is so large that it overbalances all the others, one gets as
a result not a sum of little differences but one single difference. Then no general
will is possible, and the view that triumphs is a particular view.'* A person knows
what he likes or dislikes, but he may err through ignorance. Provision is made for
eliminating this difficulty by asking that the people be not deceived and that they
be adequately enlightened. The deception on that basis is always an intrusion from
without. If the citizens were not deceived, they would always judge righdy; but
the majority err because they are unable to discern the truth. However, in order to
understand, they need only to be "enlightened." Rousseau's City contains no people
who cannot understand. It being thus demonstrated: (i) that the general will is
1050 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY l6lO
from protective tariffs and other measures, and politicians who win
power, honours and wealth through popular suffrage judge theories
of whatever kind not by their intrinsic soundness but by their
capacity for winning the votes on which said schemers and poli-
ticians depend. Is it
any fault of theirs if voters dote on absurdities ?
large or small, in which they live; and they readily pass from admira-
tion of Bossuet to admiration of Voltaire, Rousseau, Tolstoy, or any-
one else who happens to achieve fame or reputation. 6. Other persons,
who judge theories much as an untrained amateur judges music,
consider this theory good simply because it stimulates their senti-
ments agreeably. Other causes might be identified by considering
the many classifications that might be made on the basis of the
Absurd as this fantastic reason was, it none the less enabled him to
god's activity. It has been said though far from proved that the
activity so designated
was an evil one. In Hesiod, the $ai[iove<; have
an intermediate status between gods and men, but they are all benefi-
cent. As time went on, this intermediate character admitted of a
distinctionbetween good demons and bad demons. Milords the
philosophers would have their say, and their ethical sensibilities be-
ing outraged that popular religion should ascribe both good and
evil conduct to the
gods, they thought they could be rid of the em-
*
1610 Fleury, Histoirc ecclesiastique, Vol. XIV, pp. 619-20; and see Labbe, Vol.
XII, pp. 1659-60.
IO52 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1613
*
barrassment by foisting the wicked conduct upon the "demons."
The derivation in this case is
something like the one that dis-
are told in the myths and sung in the hymns are things that happened not to gods
but to demons; and they are told to show the virtue and power of the latter. Where-
fore Aeschylus should not have said [Sttpplices, v. 222]: 'Chaste Apollo, god exiled
from heaven/ nor Sophocles through Admetus \_Fragmenta, 65, 2; Musgrave, Vol.
"
II, p. 275] 'My cock [husband] hath led him [the god] to the mill.' The text of
:
this last inPlutarch is certainly corrupt Admetus cannot be the speaker, but, at the
most, Alcestis, his wife. [So Pareto. Goodwin renders: "My cock by crowing led him
to the mill." Grotius, quoted by Musgrave: "Meus se sponte pullus ad molam salsam
tulit."A. L.]
*
1613 Grote, History of Greece, Vol. I, pp. 426-27: "This distinction between gods
and daemons appeared to save in a great degree both the truth of the old legends
and the dignity of the gods: it obviated the necessity of pronouncing either that the
gods were unworthy, or the legends untrue. Yet although devised for the purpose
of satisfying a more scrupulous religious sensibility, it was found inconvenient after-
wards, when assailants arose against paganism generally. For while it abandoned as
indefensible a large portion of what had once been genuine faith, it still retained
the same word daemons with an entirely altered signification. The Christian writers
in their controversies found ample warrant among the earlier pagan authors for
treating all the gods as daemons and not less ample warrant among the later pa-
gans for denouncing the daemons generally as evil beings."
1615 ARGUMENT BY METAPHOR 1053
to Plato's authority to show that the spirits which animated the
2
statues of the gods were demons. Lactantius Firmianus also thinks
that the gods of the pagans are demons, and turning to the heathen,
he bids them, "if they refuse to believe us, to believe their Homer,
who classes the great Zeus among the demons, as indeed others of
their poets and philosophers do who use the terms demons and
gods in the same manner, the first being the true name and the
3 4
latter false." Tatian makes Zeus king of the demons. He may be
right,
for of Zeus or demons alike we know nothing and experi-
mental science is without means of any sort for determining whether
Tatian uttering truth or rubbish.
is
1613
8
instittttioncs , IV, DC vera sapicntia, 27, 15 (Opera, Vol. I, p. 387;
Divinae
Fletcher, Vol. I, p. 281): "Si nobis credendum cssc non putant, credant Homero qtd
summum ilium lovem dacmonibus aggregavit, sed et aliis poctis ac philosophis qui
cosdcm modo daemones modo dcos nuncupant, quorum alterum verum, alterum
falsum est."
4
1613 Oratio adversus Graecos, 8 (Migne, p. 823; English, p. 12): Ka* p/n ye ol
analogy between the search for justice and the reading of a script.
Is not a
piece of writing more readily deciphered when it is written
in big letters? Let us look, therefore, for something in which
on in that tone through the whole book. In the Phaedo, 71, Plato
gives a celebrated demonstration of the immortality of
the soul:
"Socrates. Tell me, as regards life and death would you not say that
life is the contrary of death ? Cebes. Certainly. Socrates. And that the
one is born of the other ? Cebes. Yes. Socrates. What, then, is born of
the living ? Cebes. The dead man. Socrates. And of the dead ? Cebes.
One has to agree the living. Socrates. Of the dead, then, Cebes, O
are born the living, and all that has life. Cebes. So it would seem.
Socrates. So then our souls [after death] are in Hades? Cebes. I
1
1617 (Opera, Vol. I, p. 463) "Exserendus est nunc uterque gladius in passione
:
Domini, Christo denuo patientc ubi ct altera vice passus est. Per quern antem nisi
per vos? Pctri uterque est: alter sno nutit alter sua manti quoties nccesse est evagi-
nandtts. Et quidem de quo minus videbatur de ipso ad Petrum dictum est: 'Con-
verte gladium tuum in vaginam! Ergo suns crat et ille sed non sua manu utique
educendus." Says Fleury, Histoire ecclesiastique, Vol. XIV, p. 581: "This allegory
of the two swords, which was to become so famous in course of time, had already
been stressed in a work of GeofTrey, Abbot of Vcndome. St. Bernard carries it much
further here." In another address to Pope Eugene, De consideration, IV, 3, 7, St.
Bernard exhorts him to use the material sword: "Why should you be trying again
to usurp a sword which of yore you were bidden to return to its sheath? Those who
deny that it is yours seem to me to pay insufficient heed to the Lord's words. For
He said: Tut up thy swordinto the sheath' [John 18:11]. The sword, therefore,
was yours, drawn, mayhap, at your bidding though not by your hand. Other-
to be
wise, if that same sword also in no sense belonged to you, when the Apostles said
'Here are two swords/ He would not have answered 'It is enough/ but 'It is too
many.' Therefore, both the spiritual and material swords belong to the Church, the
latter to be drawn on behalf of the Church, the former by the Church, the former
by the hand of the priest, the latter by the soldier at, of course, the beck of the
angels. Did not the soul prevail over matter, the Church over lay
society, and
the priesthood over the Empire, as the Sun over the
Moon and gold over lead?" 8 These two metaphors the comparison
of the papal power to spirit and lay powers to matter; and the com-
parison of papal power to the Sun and lay powers to the Moon, were
widely used. St. Ives resorts to the
in his letter to Henry, King
first
4
of England, and it is
upheld by the Saint of Aquino.
1618. Another metaphor considers the Church pictured as a man
as wedded to the State pictured as a woman. 1 Nor should we forget
2
1617 Fleury, Op. cit., Vol. XIV, p. 76.
3
1617 d'Allcmagnc, Vol. Ill, p. 321.
Jules Zeller, Histoire
4
1617 Epistolac, CVI (Ad Hcnricum
Angliae regem) (Opera, Vol. II, p. 125):
"Just as the senses of the body (sensus animalis) should be subject to reason, so
earthly power should be subject to ecclesiastical rule, and unless the earthly power
is ruled and inspired by ecclesiastical discipline, it would be no better than the body
apart from rule by the soul." In the De rcgimine principum, III, 10 (Opuscula, 20;
Opera, 1570 ed., Vol. XVII, p. 177, 2B-C), St. Thomas contradicts those who hold
that the words of Jesus which gave Peter authority to bind and to loose applied only
to the spiritual domain: "For if it be said that they refer to the spiritual power
alone, that cannot be, because the corporeal and the temporal depend on the spiritual
and the internal as the activities of the body on the powers of the soul."
1618 1
Phillips, Du droit ecclesiastique, Vol. II, pp. 473-75: "The position of
Church and State has of late been likened to the union of the man and the woman
in marriage. The comparison certainly suggests a number of perfectly sound reflec-
tions . . . though one must be careful not to get things upside down as would be
the case if, on the mistaken analogy of the [gender of the] words, the Church were
to be taken as the feminine element and the State as the masculine. Matters have
way round." The creation of woman corresponds to the cre-
to stand just the other
ation of the temporal order. The divine order "appears at first only in the back-
ground and as it were asleep. [A very pretty metaphor.] The temporal order is
drawn forth from it during its slumber. The human race awakens in the new Adam
and the divine order salutes the temporal as flesh of its flesh, bone of its bone.
Thenceforward, both of them, united one to the other as the bride to the husband,
are to reign together over the world." But what a power in the metaphor! In its
name, O ye heretics, shall ye be burned, or at least imprisoned! Phillips couches a
history of the relations between Church and State in the same figures: first the
Church asks the hand of
the State in marriage: "It is, after a fashion, the period of
courtship." In a second period, Church and State have married and are living in
perfect bliss: "There may be, as in marriage, some occasional misunderstanding
but, the two spouses sincerely intending to abide together in Jesus Christ, such dif-
ficulties are soon smoothed out. Finally the temporal power draws apart from the
1619 ARGUMENT BY ALLEGORY 1057
that other,which used the name of St. Peter to prove that the
Church and the Papacy were founded on the authority of Jesus and
2
which has been the occasion for spilling no end of ink.
1619. Various peoples have books that are sacred or greatly
revered, such as Homer among the Greeks, the Koran among the
1
Moslems, the Bible among Jews and Christians. The book may be
taken literally ; but sooner or later someone tries to find out whether
2
it
may not have some meaning other than the literal. That may be
faith of the Church and the obedience it owes the Church in divine matters." That
is the third phase, the separation stage. Three situations arise: "i. The wife [i.e.,
the State] becomes entirely freed of dependence on her husband [the Church],
severing the conjugal knot of her own accord. 2. She breaks up the marriage and
hurries into a second union, exalting her new husband to domestic authority and
oppressing her legitimate spouse with his help. 3. She refuses to recognize the abso-
lute authority of the one who has detached her from her husband, but she remains
cool to this latter, or indeed, if she does become reconciled to him, demands recog-
nition of the other on the same footing." A
clear case of polyandry.
2
1618 Op. cit., Vol. I, pp. 53-55: "That utterance, 'Thou art Peter,' made
Phillips,
Simon the foundation of the Church, the rock that supplied the keystone for the
divine edifice.'* Unfortunately, the metaphor has given rise to endless dispute: "How
many differing interpretations have been given for the words Petrus and Petra, which
were used in the Greek translation to render the word Cephas, the only one that ap-
pears in the Syriac original as well as in Persian, Armenian, and Coptic translations!
The difference arises from the fact that in Greek the word Trerpa, of feminine gender,
could not be applied to a man. The translator therefore was forced by the genius
of his language to change the physiognomy of the word in order to adapt it to the
use he was obliged to make of it: whence Tr^r/aoc, twice repeated, instead of irirpa.
That explanation, so plausible in itself, has been accepted by the bitterest adversaries
of the primacy of St. Peter. What inference can therefore be drawn from a purely
syllabic, a purely external, difference? Can one say, to carry it into the very mean-
ing of the terms, that nirpa means a great rock, while Tr^rpof suggests the image
of a pebble? That interpretation, which some recent lexicographers have adopted,
is ... devoid of any basis. We
will grant it, nevertheless, if one insists, but on one
condition that cannot be disputed us: namely, that if nirpos means a pebble, that
little pebble becomes, through the transmutation thrust upon it by Jesus in changing
with a view to seeing whether and how one could get back from them to the facts
in which they originate. Here we are considering them chiefly as means of arriving
at certain desired conclusions.
2
1619Berg, Principes du droit musulman, pp. 3-4: "The Koran or 'the Book'
(al-Kitab), is the supreme, the fundamental law for the Mussulmans. . . . The
fundamental principles of law have had to be deduced by jurists from the relatively
few decisions rendered in the Koran. Such decisions all bear on special cases, and
they would often lead to absurd consequences if the rigorous implications were not
evaded by the hair-splitting that casuistry can marshal [Derivations], One could
all
hardly imagine the strange embarrassments in which one would find oneself if one
1058 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1 620
kept to the letter of the Koran instead of to the spirit of the particular passage. . . .
The Koran is not only a book inspired by Allah. It is the book eternal, increate
like Allah himself, and only one copy of which was revealed to the Prophet. ([In a
note:] Allah Himself is supposed to be speaking in the Koran.) Whence the conclu-
sion that not only the substance but the form of the Koran is sacred and infallible
and that all criticism is That doctrine has, to be sure, long since found
forbidden.
its adversaries in Islam (the Mu'tazilites, for instance); but it is still generally
itself
interpretations,
certain doctrines, may have.
1
interpretation may An
be absurd from the experimental standpoint or from the standpoint
of formal logic, and be (or not be) beneficial to society. That has to
be decided in each particular case.
1622. Allegory is often resorted to because of an impulse human
beings feel to embellish the stories they tell, even when they have
no definite purpose in doing so. There are writers who cannot tell
a story without dotting it
spontaneously, and perhaps unconsciously,
with allegories. But
more often the allegory is used to attain some
purpose, to reconcile theories with theories, theories with facts, and
so on.
1623. Striking the case of St. Augustine, who begins with allegory
and ends with meanings, whereas ordinarily procedure is in
literal
the opposite direction. The Saint needed allegory in his fight with
the Manicheans, and used it, coming to the sense which he called
1
"literal" in another connexion. We. must not allow ourselves to
be deceived by that term, however. St.
Augustine regards a figura-
tive meaning also as "literal," and that serves his purpose
quite as
well as allegory in getting any meaning he chooses out of Holy
Writ. When, in the De Genesi ad litteram, II, 13, 27 (Optra, Vol.
Ill, p.245), the pious Doctor says that "light" means the "spiritual
creature"; when he says, IV, 9, 16, that the Lord's rest on the seventh
books against the Manicheans, I was dealing with the words of Scripture according
to their allegorical signification and did not dare to expound such great secrets
of natural things according to the letter." And Ibid., II, 24 (Opera, Vol. I, p. 640):
"I have called these books \De Genesi\ 'On Genesis, according to the Letter* not,
that is, according to the allegorical meanings, but according to the actual happen-
1624
l
Sermones (Opera, Vol. V) XCVlll (Dc verbis Evangclii Lucac VH t et de
tribtts mortals qtios Dominus suscitavii), III, 3; IV, 4.
1625 ST. AUGUSTINE AND ALLEGORY Io6l
2
manner. In such a case the logical nexus that he establishes between
the fact and the allegory is not easily determined. But the difficulty
where, that is, the author of story and allegory may himself have
been satisfied with a vague nexus.
1625. From
the allegory that is intentional and
clearly taken as
unreal e.g., the allegory used by a poet we go on by impercep-
tible degrees to the allegory that a writer uses
unwittingly and
which blends with reality in his mind. That is often observable
when language is to express some vigorous sentiment
called upon
that gives form and animation to epithet, image, and allegory; and
1
legends also not seldom originate in just that way. This is one of
1624
2
No end of examples might be mentioned. In the Violier des histoires
romaines, fiction, and facts that the writer regards as historical, appear side by side,
and he gives allegorical interpretations of both: L' exposition moralle sur le propos.
According to St. Augustine, he says, Chap. 22, p. 74, the heart from the corpse of
some Roman Emperor or other could not be consumed on the pyre because the
Emperor had been poisoned: "Then the people took the heart out of the fire and
bathed it with theriaque [Venetian treacle] In that way the poison was driven out
.
and when the heart was returned to the fire, it burned at once." For the writer
that is historical fact. And he continues: "Moral explanation of the above: Morally
speaking, the hearts of sinners that have been poisoned by mortal sin cannot be
kindled and enlightened (esprins et illumines) by the fire of the Holy Spirit save
by that theriaque which is penitence."
d'histoire, pp. 128-32, Du style revolution-
*
1625 Rocquain, Notes et fragments
naire (In question, the writings of revolutionary leaders of 1789): "In the qualifiers
which he ordinarily adds to the terms he uses he gives them a letter, a sign, that
brings them before the mind in a more striking manner. Is it a question of duty?
It is 'sacred.' Of selfishness? It is 'blind.' Of treachery? It is 'black.' Of patriotism?
It is 'burning.' ... As a result of the same tendency, the strongest words are in-
variably chosen to express any given state of mind. . . After that it is only a step
.
to giving life to words, or better, to the ideas they translate. That step is forever
being taken in the writings of those days. In using the expressions 'body politic' or
'body social,' which the Revolution borrowed from the period just preceding, there
is no stopping at the cold designations which those terms taken together make. The
social body lives. It has arteries and veins through which a blood now vigorous,
now impure circulates. . . . Ideas are not merely endowed with life. They are per-
sonified. Abstract terms, of such frequent use in those times, as I have noted, terms
such as 'justice,' 'liberty,' 'reason,' and others of the same sort, stand for living
beings that speak, move their eyes, act. .
Personality is ascribed not only to ab-
. .
stractions of that kind which were, so to speak, the divine emblems of the Revolu-
tion. At that time, when France was prey to foreign wars as well as to civil dis-
cord, 'country' is a favourite theme in public utterances and appears with all the
traits of a living being. ... understandable, also, that under pressure of the
It is
IO62 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1626
the many cases in which, as we have seen, terms are vague because
the limits of the sentiments with which they are associated are also
from its
allegorical character any more than the objective character
of a personification is
distinguished from its
subjective character
( 1070 f.). hard to say whether the ancient Greeks took the
It is
prevailing passions the Revolution should personify the things it hates as well as
the things it likes. 'There stands Fanaticism!* cries the Committee of Public Safety
of refractory priests whom it is accusing of trying to arouse public opinion. "There
she stands, watching, waiting for her credulous victims, the palm of martyrdom in
her hand.' Fanaticism, Federalism, and other objects of revolutionary hatred ordi-
and such 'monsters' live in 'lairs' into which the Revolu-
narily figure as 'monsters';
tion, like a modern Hercules, makes its way to fell and capture them. ... As a re-
sult of their propensity to vivify, to personify, ideas, the writings of those times
offer not so much pictures as living pictures."
1
1626 Here is an example, pp. 8-n: "It being forbidden us ever to aspire to abso-
lute notions, we can set up the relative conception of external bodies by endowing
each of them with the faculties of sense and action, provided we deprive them of
thought, so that their volition is always blind. [So, on pretext of our ignorance of
the absolute, we treat fiction and reality on the same plane.] Confined to the Great
Being, assisted by his worthy servants and their free auxiliaries, intelligence, spurred
by sentiment, guides activity in such a way as gradually to modify a fatality, all of
whose agents tend constantly to the good, without being able to know its conditions.
Itcould never be proved that a given body does not sense the impressions that it
undergoes and does not will the actions which it performs; though it shows itself
devoid of capacity to modify its conduct according to circumstances, which is the
1627 DERIVATIONS IV-5 : VERBAL PROOFS 1063
AT (636), that leads from certain facts, A, to a theory, (Figure T
18). Suppose some centuries hence knowledge of that path
has been
lost, and that all that is left is a certain theory which asserts
that
the Earth wisely prepared the conditions required for the existence
of a certain Great Being. In that case, interpreters of the myth will
come forward. A few of them will set out
merely to discover A and very probably go
wrong and get something quite different
from A. Many, many others will start out
from said worshipful theory, T, but with
the idea of arriving at certain conclusions,
C,
ter to get there,
11
which they want
they will
to reach;
-11
and the bet-
11
invent all manner
__
Figure 18
Since, by chance or otherwise, that work had found its way into the
prove that it is not reality! One cannot prove that Zeus does not exist therefore
Zeus exists! What are the "sensations" that a body receives from "impressions"
upon it? What is its "will"? What its "conduct"? No one can prove that the sea
docs not "sense the impression" of a ship, or that the sea does not "will" the things
that it docs to the ship, simply because no one can prove the incomprehensible and
the absurd. Once started along that path, Comte goes galloping ahead, writing less
poetically but not less mythologically than Hesiod: "Forced to be continually sub-
ject to the fundamental laws of planetary life [What in the world can such a "life"
be?], the Earth, when she was intelligent [That, probably, was in the days when
animals could talk.], was able to develop its physico-chemical activity in such a way
as to perfect the astronomical order by changing its principal coefficients. Our planet
was so enabled to make its orbit less eccentric and thereby more habitable, by man-
aging to execute a long series of explosions such as have produced the comets (ac-
cording to the most credible hypothesis). Prudently repeated, those same shocks,
seconded by vegetative mobility [Another wonderful thing but again, what is it?],
also succeeded in making the inclination of the terrestrial axis more congenial to
the future requirements of the Great Being." And Comte runs on chattering in the
same tone page after page.
1064 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1627
1
such devices. Such proofs come down to us in abundance from
every period of history. Gautier classifies them as follows: "i. Polit-
ical allegory.This theory has never had any great number of ad-
herents. It is represented by a series of individual hypotheses that
look to the history of Israel for the key to the Song. ... 2. The-
ocratic allegory. Interpreters who have taken this point of view
have had, like the preceding, the merit of not overstepping the
boundaries of the old dispensation. According to them the Song of
of the Bride and Groom of Christ, the divine leader, and His
Church. ... Mystical allegory. With this mode of interpretation
4.
we quit the domain of history ... to enter the inner sphere of the
relations of the soul to God. ... It is not surprising to find it
obvious text, but in considering and interpreting the events described as symbols of
higher truths. Hugo Grotius was not the first to try that method. He had been . . .
preters, the love of Jehovah for Israel; the older Christian commentators almost
unanimously, the love of Christ for His Church." St. Augustine says in his Specu-
lum de Cantico Canticorum (Opera, Vol. Ill, p. 925): "And we come finally to the
book of Solomon called the Song of Songs. But what abridgment could we make
of here, since every line of it glorifies in figurative language, and foretells with
it
sing of human love. But, they add, it is no less permissible and even
enjoined upon us to ascribe a spiritual, religious, meaning to the
poem. presence in the Bible proves that that is the will of God.
Its
they are wondering whether some religious or at least moral tendency cannot be
detected in the canticle if it be interpreted as a drama. Glorification of true love,
opposition to sensuous passions and vulgar enjoyments, the superiority of monogamy
over polygamy, the eulogy of marriage, constancy in love, conjugal fidelity, the
triumph of a sincere and profound sentiment over the allurements of wealth and
royal pomp there is the list of themes that have seemed worthy of being cele-
brated and which have been designated as the inspirations of the poet of the canti-
cle." Gautier favours the view that the canticle is a collection of nuptial songs. That
view is supported by one consideration of great weight: the fact that it is obtained
by the comparative method ( 547-48), explaining the past by customs observable
in our day. However, it is still doubtful whether the origin and character of that
literary fragment have really been hit upon, and fortunately humanity can live on
without having the doubt dispelled.
IO66 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1627
were therefore in a mood to accept a system that was more or less
sceptical but paid
all due
respect to established beliefs, which did
away with the supernatural but spared the sublime which fol-
lowed, in a word, that middle course on which so many people are
satisfied to remain. Humanitarians are never energetic enough to
in the old theology. From that point of view it might be said that
hope of an eternal life.*' Crocodile's tears, more or less! Renan is so sensitive in such
matters that farther along, p. 43, he does not even venture to quote the Bible!
"Sulem, or Sunem, was a village of the tribe of Lssachar, home of a certain woman,
Abishag the Shunamite, whose adventures, as recounted in I Kings 1:3 and 2:17 f.,
are not without their points of resemblance to the ones that make up the scheme
of our poem. We read, in fact, in the first of the passages mentioned, that the
servants of David, in circumstances too greatly at variance with our notions of
propriety to be stated here, sent out a call for the fairest maiden in all the tribes of
Israel." We are certainly in a bad case if historians are to mention only such circum-
stances as do not diverge too widely from our present-day morality! Renan is hiding
something that everyone knows. The translators of the King James Version were
not as squeamish as the fashionable Parisian. They translate, I Kings 1:2: "Where-
fore his [David's] servants said unto him: Let there be sought for my lord the
king a young virgin: and let her stand before the king, and let her cherish him,
and let her lie in thy bosom, that my lord the king may get heat." Sometimes Renan
goes to even greater extremes: Sorel, Le systeme historique dc Renan, Vol. I, p. 48:
"Some years ago, M. Pascal, professor at Catania, called attention to a curious ex-
ample of Renan's far-fetched translations (Carlo Pascal, Uincendio di Roma e i
primi cristiani, p. 30)." It was a question of a series of double meanings that Renan
insisted on seeing in the sign domus transitoria, which keeps appearing on certain
bring, Op. tit., pp. 606-07: "The Book of Ruth was not divined
true purport of the
till very recently in our own time. ...and meaning have been missed
Its intent
says Piepenbring, "is in reality a very precious pendant to the reform of Esdras. It
shows that the Jewish world as a whole did not allow itself to be carried away
by the intolerant exclusive spirit of that scribe. We learn in that way that
. . .
mixed marriages which had been fought bitterly and in the mass by Esdras and
his associates were justified not only from the standpoint of passion and interest but
from the standpoint of justice and equity. At bottom, the author of the Book of
Ruth placed the spiritual ties of religion above ties of blood, ascribing more im-
portance to truly pious conduct than to flawless genealogy, and anticipating the
doctrine of the Gospels that it is not necessary to be descended from Abraham in
order to be a true believer.*' It cannot have been altogether by chance that such a
1629 THE SONG OF SOLOMON 1069
1629. Sometimes, and
especially in olden times, the derivation be-
comes truly fantastic, as witness St. Bernard's long commentary on
the of Songs. In the fanciful manufacture of
allegories over-
it
Song
all bounds. I select a few at random. There is the line:
steps
*
"My
mother's children fought against me." First, the Bride that is to
2
persecuted. How can
say,
the Church exclaims that she has been
that be? Nothing simpler! "Annas,
Caiaphas, and Judas Iscariot
were children of the Synagogue, and the Church, which was also a
child of the Synagogue, they
cruelly beset at the time of her birth,
crucifying her founder, Jesus. And so the Lord accomplished
through them at that time what he had foretold of yore through
the prophet, saying: 'Ishall smite the
shepherd and disperse his
sheep.' ... Of these, then, and of other such people who are known
to have resisted the Church
ye may consider that the Bride saith:
" 8
'My mother's children fought against me.'
Ecclesiastes and Ecclesiasticus have also exercised the commenta-
tors not a little. The latter was classed
by the Protestants among the
Apocrypha, but Ecclesiastes has held its
place among the books of
4
the biblical canon.
Epicurean maxims certainly abound in Eccle-
meaning should have been discovered in a humanitarian and democratic age such
as our own. Gauticr, Introduction a I'Ancien Testament,
p. 152, says with much good
sense: 'To discover the provocation and
purpose of the Book of Ruth, there is no
need of resorting to ingenious and far-fetched conjectures. One has
only to think
of the fondness of Orientals for dramatic, striking stories that stir the emotions
and are handed down from one generation to another." But that would be some-
thing far too simple for an inveterate interpreter.
x
1629 1:5: "Filii matris mcae pugnavcrunt contra me."
Following the Vulgate,
King James Version, "My
1:6: mother's children were angry with me."
2
1629 In Cantica sermoncs, 28, 13 (Opera, Vol. IV, p. 928): "Adiiciens
siquidem
'Fihi matris mcae pugnaverunt contra me/ persccutioncm
passam se esse aperte
significat."
3
1629 Op. cit., 29, i: "Annas ct Caiphas et ludas Iscarioth filii synagogue
juerunt et hi contra Ecclesiam acque synagogue filiam in ipso exortu ipsius acerbis-
sirne piignavcrunt, suspcndentes in
ligno collectorem ipsius lesum. lam tune siqui-
dem Dens implevit per eos quod olim praesignaverat per Prophetam f dicens: 'Percu-
tiam pastorernt et dispergentur ovcs! DC his ergo et aliis qui de ilia gcnte
. . .
Christiana nomini contradixisse sciuntur, puta dictum a sponsa: Filii matris mcae
"
pugnaverunt contra me.'
4
1629 As regards Ecclesiasticus, one may read in an essay, "Les livres apo~
cryphes de I'Ancien Testament," which accompanies La sagesse de Jesus fils de Sirach,
published by the Biblical Society of Paris, pp. 391-92: "The son of Sirach is not
innocent of selfishness. The precepts of wisdom that abound in his book a betray
too absorbing concern with personal interest. Even love of pleasure finds some echo
IO7O TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1630
siastes, but the commentators twist them by ingenious interpreta-
tions into religious precepts. St. Jerome uses two methods in chief.
On the one hand he assumes without trace of proof that the author
is not
speaking for himself when he recommends conviviality at
5
table. Then again he distorts to a spiritual significance what is ob-
viously said in a material sense. So the reference to eating and
drink-
ing must be taken spiritually, and when the author speaks of em-
bracing a woman, he must be understood as meaning the embrace
of wisdom. On that basis Ovid's Art of Love could be turned into
6
a moral and religious tract.
in his heart and he expresses himself in many places like a disciple of Epicurus. . . .
However, such blemishes should not be exaggerated. On the whole the book is
packed with good sense, uprightness, charity, piety."
6
1629 Commentarius in Ecclesiasten, 9:7 (Opera, Vol. Ill, p. 1082): "Go thy way,
eat thy bread with joy, and drinf^ thy wine with a merry heart. Such, he says, the
talk of some people Epicurus, Aristippus, the Cyrenians, and other such cattle
among the philosophers (ceteri pecudes philosophorum). But after pondering the
matter diligently I find, not, as some falsely conclude, that all things are gov-
erned by chance and that a capricious fortune is at play in human affairs, but
that all things happen by judgment of God."
Q
1629 Ibid. f 8:15 (Opera, Vol. Ill, p. 1079): "Then I commended mirth, because
a man hath no better thing under the sun than to eat and to drinl^ and to be
merry. That we have interpreted more fully above, and now strictly we say that
he prefers to the troubles of the world the pleasure of eating and drinking, fleeting
and soon ended as such pleasure may be. ... But this interpretation, taking the
text as it is written, would prove that they that mourn and do hunger and thirst
are the wretched ones, while Our Lord in the Gospel [Matt. 5:4, 6] calls them
blessed. Let us therefore take the food and drink spiritually. For [Matt., . . .
Chapter 9; Eccl. 3:11-13] the Lord's flesh [i.e., communion] is the true food and
His blood the true drink." Loc. cit. p. 8 (Eccl. 3:1, 5) (Opera, Vol. Ill, p. 1036):
f
"To everything there is a season a time to embrace, and a time to refrain from
. . .
'Defraud ye not one another except it be with consent for a time.' [Then comes an
even stranger explanation:] Or else, that there was a time for embracing when
the precept [Gen. 1:28] 'Be fruitful and multiply and replenish the earth* was in
force. And after that, when that had been done, came a time to refrain from
embracing. If, however [This is the best of all!], we choose to rise to loftier alti-
tudes, we see Wisdom embracing those who love her .
clutching them with her
. .
clearly enough and but ill conceal their eagerness to win honours
2
and favours of her. But said blessed Democracy already has cor-
*
1630 [Buonaiuti], // pro gramma dei Modernisti: risposta aU'Enciclica di Pio
X, 'Pascendi Dominici gregis,' p. 121 (Tyrrell, pp. 124-25): "As we have already
said, in full accord with contemporary psychology Modernists sharply distinguish
between science and faith. The mental processes that lead to science and those
which lead to faith seem to them wholly foreign to each other, and independent."
Excellent! But why such a great fuss, then, on the part of the Modernists, to recon-
cile science and faith? And one of their most revered leaders, M. Loisy, asks flatly,
L'Evangilc ct I'Eglise, Preface, p. xxxiii: "Can conscience very long keep a God un-
known to science, and will science forever respect a God of whom it has no
knowledge?"
2
1630 The same Programma, pp. 123-24 (Tyrrell, pp. 127-29), says of the
Church (and Clericalism) "What popularity can petty and
:
decrepit oligarchies of
aristocrats give the Church, when
exchange for a little pomp they force upon
in
her customs and procedures that are openly at war with the trend of the modern
world? We understand that, and we speak our mind frankly: We arc tired of
seeing the Church reduced to a mere bureaucracy, jealous of powers she still retains
and eager to regain powers she has lost. The Church should feel a longing to
. . .
embrace those currents of unwittingly religious feeling which are fostering the
rise of democracy. She should find a way to merge with democracy, in order to
give it a chance to succeed through the beneficent influence of her restraints and
the stimulus of her moral leadership, which alone can impart lessons in abnega-
tion and unselfishness. The Church should honestly recognize that in democracy
a loftier expression of her own Catholicity is being formulated. And then democ-
racy, in its turn, will come to feel the attraction of the Church as embodying the
continuity of that Christian message in which democracy itself has its remote but
none the less genuine origins." And one is tempted to add: "And then democracy,
in its turn, will bounteously recompense deserters from the Catholic Church."
However, once upon a time there were priests in France who in a similar frame
of mind made common cause with the Third Estate to organize the National
Assembly and so contributed to bringing on the Revolution. But they were sadly
disappointed. Some of those good souls did not even collect Judas's thirty pieces
of silver, but had to find their sole recompense in exile, prison, and the guillotine.
1072 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1630
railed the goddess Science for her Pantheon. What is to be done in
that case? Nothing simpler! What on earth else were allegory and
ity
of which has not undergone any transfiguration. But it belongs
to faith not as a natural death, but as a voluntary death, as the out-
4
standing symbol of redemption." Hidden in a fog so thick, M.
if one understands science
Loisy's idea is hard to capture "Likewise, :
may even say governed, by the influence of faith." That is all a rid-
dle! If "scientific labour" inspired and governed by faith, how
is
can the science which is the product of that work help being subor-
dinate to faith? If you "inspire and govern" a workman, it would
seem that what he produces would be subordinate to you. Epithets
of course are, as usual, on hand to facilitate changes in the mean-
ings of words and lift them from Earth to the clouds. Loisy's
"science in itself" must be at the very least an own cousin, if not a
born sister, of "right reason." Another beautiful unknown is "scien-
tific work in so far as it emanates from a moral being." It would
3
1630 Loisy, Autour d'un petit livre, pp. 93-95: "This Christ, to be sure, is not a
metaphysical abstraction, for he is alive in the soul of the Evangelist. But this alto-
gether spiritual and mystical Christ of faith is an undying Christ independent of
the limitations of time and earthly existence. John's narratives are not a his- . . .
tory but a mystical contemplation of the Gospel. His harangues are theological
meditations on the mystery of salvation. The Christian Church allegorized . . .
the Old Testament. It did not refrain from allegorizing the Gospel narratives. . . .
One must not find it surprising, therefore, that critical exegesis should discover
allegories inthe Fourth Gospel. Was not allegory, in the eyes of Philo of
. . .
Alexandria, the key to the Old Testament, the natural form of divine revelation?
And is not the influence of Philoism on John beyond dispute?"
4
1630 Loisy, Simples reflexions sur . . .
VEncy clique "Pascendi Dominici gregis/'
pp. 170-71.
1631 THE MODERNISTS AND PIUS X 1073
seem that the scientific achievement of formulating a mathematical
dominici gregis, p. 379: "So much for the Modernist considered as a philoso-
. . .
holy of holies, who docs not frequent the sidewalks in those precincts. The Mod-
ernist, therefore, is a believer, encyclical goes on to show how the Modernist
and the
sets the believer over against the "philosopher'*:] The believer, on the contrary, holds
as an unquestionable certainty that the divine reality really exists in itself and in
no way depends upon the person who believes it. If we should go on to ask on
what the believer's conviction is based, the Modernists reply: On individual ex-
perience. But if, in so saying, they part company with the rationalists, they fall
into the opinion of the Protestants and the pseudo-mystics." It is in that, according
to M. Loisy, that the encyclical seems to err. That is not the view of the Modern-
ists, he says. But what their view actually is we cannot know unless Loisy ex-
more intelligibly, clarifying the fog that enwraps a "science
presses himself a little
work in so far as it emanates from a moral being," and
in itself," a "scientific
many other obscurities of the kind. The encyclical further declares that science
must be subordinate to faith. And since that statement is perfectly clear, perfectly
clear also can be the answer of anyone who has resolved to keep to the field of
logico-expcrimental science, and declares that he is in no way concerned with
what faith, be it Catholic, Protestant, Moslem, Humanitarian, Democratic, or any
other whatsoever, may try to prescribe for him in that field. Though from that
it would by no means follow that under certain circumstances it may not be useful
were called in, among others a very pretty metaphor about a debt
that is forever being paid but which is forever being reincurred so
sounds like a childish
that it is
always there ( 1503). It all
jest, yet
as the argument is offered in all seriousness. Involved in the
it is,
1631 ^Essai d'une philosophic de la solidarite, pp. 65, 77: "It must be positively
understood that man cannot acquit himself once and for all, for the future as
well as for the past. He must keep acquitting himself endlessly. Day by day he
conn acts a new debt that day by day he must pay. The individual must acquit
himself at each moment, and so at each moment he reachieves his freedom." An
individual, referred to in the text as X, was seized with panic lest, should his
"debtors" clear their obligations, he should not be able to get anything more
out of them a situation that would in fact be defeating the practical pur-
poses of "solidarity"! Said Monsieur X: "From the moral point of view, does not
the notion of the acquittal of social debt lead, or possibly lead, to selfishness?
When I have paid my debt, I am free. But am I not free also as regards human
kindness, brotherly love? And would not that persuasion induce a certain dryness
of heart?" Have no fear, good souls! The debts of your debtors are of a nature
so marvellous that if they paid them in as many millions as there are grains of
sand on the sea-shore they could never be free of them. M. Leon Bourgeois answers
in fact: "That might be the case if the acquittal were a sweeping one covering
everything for all time. [The reader will note the absence of any specification of
amounts large or small.] But I have covered that point: A
man is never completely
freed. By the very fact that he goes on living, he acquires a new debt, a feeling
that he owes something to his fellows, that they are his creditors, for ever laying
hold on him!" Lucky for us that that blessed debt does not follow us after death,
so that we are still allowed to think of the Grim Reaper as a Liberator! Meantime,
supposing the debtor refuses to pay and tells Her Holiness Democracy to go West
along with her prophets? Simple enough! Force is then called in! But in that
case, why not resort to force in the first place without so much beating about the
bush? Perhaps because chicanery is easier to use than force?
1633 DERIVATIONS IV-5: VERBAL PROOFS 1 075
of being poisonous. The
viper likes to live in dry places. That is a
characteristic, Q, which is apparent enough in the viper but which
is not so
clearly apparent in Quintilla. But in view of Quintilla's
resemblance to the viper, assumed that she must also affect
it is
the arid and loathe dampness and water, C. Then Tertullian re-
woman a viper, she acts like a viper.]; for as a rule vipers, asps, and striped snakes
is
(reguli serpentes) prefer arid waterless places. [A more effective manner of state-
ment than by mentioning just the viper. In virtue of the incidental sentiments
aroused, to yoke the asp and other snakes with the viper leaves the impression
that the snake of heresy belongs with it just as well.] But we are little fishes. [In
virtue of baptism. In his DC resurrectionc carnis, 52 (Opera, Vol. Ill, p. 251; English,
Vol. II, p. n), Tertullian says: "There is one sort of flesh the flesh of fowls of
the air, and that is the flesh of the Martyrs who aspire to loftier heights. Then there
is the flesh of fishes who are nourished by the water of baptism."] were bornWe
in water [Spiritually, that is, the water making us Christians.] following our'I#0{>c,
the Lord Jesus Christ, and we are saved only as we remain in the water. [A new
metaphor: "to remain in the water" means to remain in the state of grace con-
ferred by baptism.] That monster of a woman [Quintilla] therefore, who would
have no right to teach even if she taught the truth (cut nee integre quidem docendi
ius erai), knew it would be a fine way to destroy little fishes to take them out of
the water." The logical inference from the argument by metaphor.
x
1633 Returning to the same subject, Ibid., 5, he cautions that the lustral waters
of the heathen do not have the saving powers of Christian baptismal water
1076 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1634
water is considered worthy of regenerating the Christian, and he
answers with analogies involving residues of our I-/3 type (similar-
ity, oppositeness).
Then we get combinations of IV-5 (analogy) and
III-a (accords of sentiment) derivations. First of all, says Tertullian,
the origin of water has to be taken into account (Opera, Vol. IV,
that the holy angel of God doth apply water to the salvation of men,
( 1292). The appeal to authority, therefore, serves merely to show that, in general,
water can do wonderful things. In particular, of course, not all waters have that
efficacy.
1638 ANATOLE FRANCE ON CRIME 1077
since the angel of evil, as is his profane habit, turneth the same ele-
ments to the hurt of man." The IV-5 derivation is itself re-enforced
with another of the IV-/3 type (accessory sentiments) that involves
residues of our I-/3 type (unusual occurrences).
1635. The compound
derivation type, which is so naively manifest
in Tertullian's argument, figures in a manner now more, now less
dissembled in huge numbers of reasonings: one finds, that is, a IV-5
derivation (metaphor, analogy), re-enforced by IV'-(3 derivations
(accessory sentiments) that bring into play a great variety of resi-
dues and especially residues of Class I (combinations).
1636. Allegories and metaphors can be met with other allegories
and metaphors. Frequently enough an unscientific argument will
be victoriously refuted by an argument equally unscientific. What,
from the logico-experimental standpoint, may be a mere war of
words may, from the standpoint of doctrinal propaganda, be tre-
mendously effective in view of the sentiments that are called into
play.
1637. Opponents of the death-penalty have a commonplace based
on a metaphor. They say that the infliction of the death-penalty is
'legal murder," and that "Society" so meets one murder with an-
other.
1638. People go even farther in that direction. Anatole France
says that the only way that has been found to punish thieves and
murderers is to imitate them and that, at bottom, justice serves
them and I am pained to see that the courts have found nothing better as a pun-
ishment for thieves and murderers than to imitate them. [A IV-y derivation terms
with varying meanings.] For, really now, Tourncbroche, my boy, what is a fine
or an execution except a theft or a murder carried out with ceremonious pre-
meditation? Do you not see that, for all of the airs it puts on, our system of justice
amounts only to the shameful thing of avenging a wrong by a wrong, one wretched
act by another, and serves only to double, out of love of symmetry and balance, the
number of crimes and felonies?" Anatole France assumes that he is answering a
charge that he is "taking the part of thieves and murderers" and in that
assump-
tion we already get the beginning of the derivation. It is of little importance to the
public just whose side M. France and his humanitarian friends desire to stand;
on
but of great importance that thieves and murderers should not be allowed to
it is
run the streets in deference to the kind-heartedness of M. France and his friends.
Going on, France makes a prison warden his spokesman and has that character
1078 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1638
family of four children, and even to build a little house of his own on a micro-
scopic plot at the end of the alley. The oldest of the children, Marcelle, has just
reached her fifteenth birthday. She is in every respect the 'little mama* that is so
frequently to be met with in poor and numerous families. Up at dawn, she makes
breakfast for 'her babies,' then takes neatly dressed to day-school. Then
them all
she goes to a shop where she works day, coming home at night to get supper
all
for the family. Yesterday evening at seven o'clock, the 'litde mama* went out to
the end of the alley to draw water from the fountain there. A
gang of young
men stopped some yards away from the group formed by Marcelle and the 'big
mothers.* 'Ready now!' cried one of the gangsters. It was a signal. A
number of
shots rang out one after the other. The 'little mama* gave a cry and sank to the
pavement. A bullet had struck her in the middle of the forehead. The gangsters
had merely used her as a target for revolver practice! The people of the neigh-
bourhood came running. Marcelle was picked up from a pool of blood, while
someone ran for Dr. Perraudeau. . The physician declared the child seriously
. .
injured and sent her to the Bichat hospital, where she was admitted." According
to the theory of Anatole France, the "unfortunate" party in this case would be
not the girl who was shot but her assailants. To the little girl people need not give a
thought; much less should any measures be taken to prevent the recurrence of such
incidents: only the footpad should have the benefit of "society's" tender solicitude.
1638 DERIVATIONS IV-5: VERBAL PROOFS 1079
names to the things that people have so far called now a "theft"
and now a "fine," now a "murder" and now a "legal execution."
However, it at we are to understand each other,
once develops that if
trying to kill your son. You therefore will not care whether you
kill
your son or the bandit." He, we may be sure, would answer:
"The name is of no consequence to me! I am going to kill the bandit
and save my son!" Names are of no consequence to human society
either. Among the thing-problems that are here involved, two, in
agreeable names are given to people or things if the intent is to favour them, dis-
if the intent is to oppose them. At the present time in France, a
agreeable names
defence counsel never breathes the word "crime" in connexion with a client. As
Mme. Miropolska said in a lecture, Ltberte, Feb. 19, 1913: "There are words that a
along that path, allegories, metaphors, symbols, are grafted upon it,
8
1638 See Henri Robert, La defense de Lady Macbeth and L' affaire Lafarge.
Sorel,Independance, Oct. 10, 1912, p. 38: "The books that have been written to
prove the innocence or guilt of Dreyfus fail altogether to satisfy people of any
great amount of critical insight. That is readily comprehensible. The writers of
such books work very much after the manner of certain scholars who go delving
into the archives to review condemnations of the distant past. Everybody is now
agreed such enterprises. [Too benevolent a judgment on our
as to the fatuousness of
times.] Legal experts [Not all! Not all!] righdy hold that, in matters of crime,
intelligently conducted debates held shortly after the fact arc alone likely to
yield sound verdicts. The historian, however, does not stand entirely disarmed in
the presence of old cases. He may determine in the light of the science of institu-
tions whether procedure has been in accord with the spirit of the law. In case of a
*
1639 s.v. Tanaquil, Bayle quotes a passage from
In his Dictionnaire historiqne,
Pliny, JJistoria naturdis, VIII, 74 (Bostock-Rilcy, Vol. II, p. 336) "Marcus Varro
:
relates as an eyewitness that in his day in the Temple of Sancus one could still see
wool on the distaff and spindle of Tanaquil, also called Gaia Cecilia, and in the
Temple of Fortune, a waved royal robe which she had made and which Scrvius
Tullius had worn. Hence the custom that when a young woman is married, she
carries in her wedding-march a dressed distaff and a loaded spindle. Tanaquil
invented the art of making the straight tunic such as is worn by young men and
newly married girls along with the plain white toga." Bayle also calls attention to
a passage in Plutarch, Quaestiones Romanae, 30 (Goodwin, Vol. II, p. 221), where a
second answer is suggested for the question: "When a bride is introduced [to her
home] why sheisexpected to say: 'Where thou art Gains, there shall I be Gaia'?"
Says Plutarch: "Is it perhaps because Gaia Cecilia, wife to one of the sons of
Tarquinius, was a matron beautiful and pure? A bronze statue to that matron was
erected in the temple of Santus [The name is variously spelled.]; and there, also,
once upon a time, were treasured her sandals and her spindles, the former as a
symbol of her domestic virtues, the latter of her industriousncss." After a digression
upon other matters, Bayle continues: "A Frenchman writing in the sixteenth cen-
tury [Fr. Tillier, of Tours, Philogame, on I' ami dcs noces, Paris, 1578, p. 120]
comes out with a statement that he would have found it impossible to prove. The
Tarquins,' says he, 'had had a statue erected in their palace, with nothing but a
pair of house-slippers, a distaff, and a spindle.
That was to encourage successors
of their family to imitate their assiduous meticulousncss in frugality (en mesnageant)
and in keeping to their home.' Such the fate of Pliny's account of the statue of
Tanaquil! Everyone takes it upon himself to alter some detail or other in a story
he tells. So facts are distorted and rapidly degenerate in the hands of those who
quote them."
IO82 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 164!
that is to say, on drawing more or less
logical derivations from it.
So it comes about that from the same T one writer will arrive at
certain things. A, which are altogether imaginary; and another, at
still different things, B, likewise imaginary; and still other writers
standing critics and the 'Gotthelf question' had become a subject of passionate
discussion in the newspapers. Now in the last number of Heimat und Frcmde,
M. Loosli explains that the idea of his practical joke came to him in the course
of a conversation with a friend on the Bacon-Shakespeare controversy. M. Loosli
had remarked to his companion on the ease with which the genuineness of the
literary work of any writer could be disputed fifty years after his death. All one
had to do was to put out some absurd statement with an air of authority. The
1643 DERIVATIONS IV-<$: VERBAL PROOFS 1083
1642. If A is anterior in time to B,
many literary historians will
regard B out of hand as an imitation of A. have seen cases We
(733f.) where the absolute falseness of such an inference is
physics, much more symbolism, than they contain. Now the author
world of literary pontiffs could then be relied on to grasp at it and discuss it with
allthe seriousness imaginable. His companion remaining unconvinced, M. Loosli
made a bet that he could prove it and at the height of the season sent to the
magazine in Berne the article that set all the Swiss press agog. Before publishing
his article,however, he took the precaution to deposit with a notary a sealed en-
velope containing the following statement: 'Bumplitz, Jan. 4, 1913: I have this
day drawn up, under title of "Jeremias Gotthelf A Literary Riddle," an outline
that I intend to publish and in which I show that the real author of the works of
Jeremias Gotthelf was not Albert Bitzius, but his contemporary and friend, J. U.
Geissbiihler. This I have done with the idea of demonstrating by a practical example
how easy it is hypotheses in the field of philology and for the
to devise ridiculous
pleasure of having a laugh at the expense of the scholars who will attack my
article. I desire to give a lesson to philologists, because in my judgment they are
betraying art and poetry. I am this day depositing thisexplanation with the notary
Gfeller at Bumplitz and I shall publish it when the time comes. This I do to
avoid any misunderstanding of my conduct and to protect the memory of Albert
Bitzius from overzealous philologists. C. A. Loosli/ That document was sup-
plemented by another: 'I, the undersigned, certify that the document herewith
has been lying under seal in my office from Jan. 4, 1913, to the present time.
Bumplitz, Feb. 15, 1913. Office of Public Notary Gfeller, Luthi, public notary.'
The theory put forward by one of the victims of the jest that M. Loosli had gone off
at half-cock and then tried to save his face by pretending that he had been joking
has therefore to be discarded. In his new article the jester, M. Loosli, rubs it in:
'My article/ he writes, 'contained as many absurdities as words. It cannot bear
examination and be taken seriously by any sensible person. Anyone at all wide-
awake should have seen at once that it was a hoax. In spite of all that, I have
before me articles with judgments like these: "A very plausible hypothesis"
(Frankfurter Zeitung); "Bitzius the man may not be affected by M. Loosli's declara-
tions, but Bitzius the poet will surely be, for just as Homer was not the man
." (National Zeitung). M. Loosli continues: The Nachrichten of Zurich
9
who . .
and the Bund naturally devoted full-fledged articles to my "revelations" and the
question was discussed at length by the Swiss press generally, and even abroad.
The public had its hankerings for a sensation satisfied, and the name of Gotthelf,
which is ordinarily of as much public concern as a dill-pickle, is today in every
mouth. As I had foreseen, the national vanity was pricked and a most impressive
group of Gotthelf specialists have been given an opportunity to display their
"
learning in this battle with a ghost/
1084 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1644
of the Fourth Gospel may well be narrating in a way of his own
facts of which he had the same knowledge as the other three evan-
that is, be working from fact to
gelists (he may, theory). But it may
just as well be that he got his facts at second hand and is giving his
own metaphysical interpretation of them (that he is working from
theory to fact). Nor is it by any means impossible that he is work-
1
ing in both those ways at the same time.
1644. St. Paul in his
day alludes to a certain "deceitful learning"
(Ephes. 5:6 ["vain words"]), which may have been something along
the lines of what was subsequently known as Gnosticism,
something
like theembellishments in the Fourth Gospel. We are not inquiring
here as to whether there may have been some direct connexion be-
tween Gnosticism and the Fourth Gospel or whether the two things
arose independently from the general human need of ratiocination,
of giving a metaphysical elaboration to history or legend; or
whether, finally, they arose in some other manner. Here we are
looking at them as mere facts; and we note that they show a cer-
tain gradation, the maximum metaphysical development appearing
1
in the Gnosis.
The terms "Gnosis," "Gnosticism," are not very
1645. definite.
selves, nor of adding one chapter more to the many that have already been written
on this subject. I am viewing the case in a very restricted aspect, as an example of
derivations.
x
1644 Buonaiuti, Lo gnosticismo, p. 124: "Gnosticism is a gigantic manifestation
of a morbidly exhilarated religious psychology. [That is to say, it shows on a larger
scale mental processes that are observable in many other manifestations of re-
phenomenon deriving its substance from a thousand sources and protruding its
insidious tentacles upon a thousand different temperaments."
*
1645 Our knowledge of Gnostic doctrine is derived almost exclusively from
what its Christian adversaries say of it; but, from the little that is to be gathered
from other sources, it seems that on the whole the Christians gave a fairly accurate
picture of it. That at least seems to be indicated by Gnostic fragments recently re-
covered. We are in no sense interested here in the difficult, and for the present
1645 GNOSTICISM 1085
of the species. In it one notes broad traces of procedure from the
word to the thing. Words become persons, and the person retains
a sex corresponding to the grammatical gender of the word. These
entities of differing sex once created,
they are made to copulate and
give birth to new entities, which are not distinguishable from the
words that serve as their names. Then the legend grows more and
more elaborate. The entities have all the characteristics of the words,
and live and act according to those traits. Numbers have their role
in the legend. Whether deriving it from the
Pythagoreans or other-
wise, the Valentinians have a notion that there is
something real
by the word. But that need not distress us. Very probably the Gnos-
2
tics did not know themselves.
partly unsolvable, problems that arise in connexion with Gnosticism and the
Gnostics. Weare not writing the history of the doctrine. We
are merely looking
for examples of derivations. Amelineau, Les traites gnostiqucs d' Oxford, p. 39: "The
vagaries that are now accessible in the documents published by Amelineau. For
example, p. 9: "What is the issue in this second treatise? In the first place, it is a
question of the initiation that Jesus gives to His disciples in order to perfect their
possession of the Gnosis, of the 'passwords' which He imparts to them, to enable
them to traverse one world after another and finally to reach the last where the
Father of Fatherhood, the God of Truth, abides. The word 'mystery' must
all
The word Logos must be taken here as referring not to the Aeon-Logos, but to the
passwords, the great and mysterious passwords that the Word gives to the Gnostics
that they may reach the abode of the God of Truth after making their way
through all the aeons, without, meantime, suffering in any respect from the con-
duct of their inhabitants. The title of this second treatise is nothing more than one
of those plays on words which were so dear to the Egyptians."
2 be a great, an immense, expanse of
1645 The principal meaning of al&v seems to
time eternity. We say principal, not primary; for here we are classifying things,
I086 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1646
1646. St. Irenaeus of Marseilles gives an account of the Valen-
tinian system. He wrote in Greek. Only fragments of his text are
still extant, but an old Latin translation is available. Here I shall
translate from the Greek, and since the genders of the Greek words
are lost in English and are frequently different in Italian or French,
I shall mark them as (m) or (/)
according as the Greek word is
masculine or feminine. "It is said that at a height invisible and in-
calculable there abideth a perfect pre-existing Aeon. This also . . .
[lacuna in MS.] they call First Father and Abyss (m) . [lacuna] . .
not debating origins. Hesiod, Theogonia, v. 609 (White, pp. 122-23): an' al&vofi
"From the most remote times." In the Timaeus, 3yD, Plato says that God created
the heavens "to make of them a mobile image of eternity": /cw K(vrjT6v nva aibvos . . .
Aristotle,
TToifjaai. De
coelo, I, 9, an aeon, having taken its name from its
n: "It is
ever being" [Hardie-Gaye, Vol. Ill, p. 2793: Aion: "duration, a name based upon
the fact that it is always durable, immortal and divine."] There are other abstract
meanings of the kind indicating long spaces of time, such as a century, a human
lifetime. In a chapter of the De fide orthodoxa, II, i, which he
entitles Hepi ai&vos
(De saeculo sive aevo), St. John Damascene notes those various senses (Opera,
all
"Time," is said to be a "child of Saturn" (Cronus). One may also take the passage
in the sense of "the succession of the ages born of time": "For Fate-Which-Leads-
To-The-End, and Time, the child of Cronus, bring forth many things." That is a
poetic personification, such as Claudian uses in his panegyric De consulatu Stilicho-
nis, II, vv. 424-27 (Carmina, Vol. II, p. 32) :
("Far away, unexplored of man, nay inaccessible to our minds and hardly approach-
able of the gods,is the dark and uncouth Mother of the years, the grotto of end-
less Eternity which supplies the cycles of time, calling them forth from its own
infinitebosom.") Arrian, Epicteti dissertationes,
5, 13, II, seems to take the word
"aeon" in the sense of an immortal being: Oi> -ydp ei/u aibv aAA' dvtfpwTroc: ("For
I am not an aeon, but a man"). -Tatian, Oratio adversus Graecos, 20 (Migne,
p. 851; English, p. 26), alludes to altivec in a context that does not make his exact
meaning clear, though he seems to be thinking of "worlds," "regions": "For the
sky is not infinite, O human, but finite and circumscribed; and above it are better
aeons, which suffer not change of season whereof our various diseases spring, but
have full enjoyment of a mild clime, of perpetual day, and of a light inaccessible
to men." There have been two types of translation for the word "aeons" in this
passage. Puech, for example, Recherches sur le discours de Talien, p. 134, renders
it by "worlds" and annotates: "Aeones 'centuries/ 'worlds' is one of the words
1646 DERIVATIONS IV-S: VERBAL PROOFS 1087
whom they also call Grace (/) and Silence (/). And at a certain
time it was his pleasure that said Abyss should be made manifest
as the principle of all things. This emanation (which he had been
pleased to put forth) he did place as seed in the matrix, as it were,
of his companion Silence (/). And she did receive said seed and did
conceive and gave birth to Mind
(or Reason) (m), one like and
equal unto him who had begotten him and alone encompassing the
greatness of his father. This Mind (ra) they also call the Only-Be-
gotten, fatherand principle of all things. And at the same time was
begotten Truth (/). This, then, is the primal and first-born Pythago-
rean quaternion, which they call also the root of all things: and to
sacculum, "century," may think of it as a world, a region. With the Gnostics the
Aeons become persons and regions, and they are also considered under various
aspects. In his diatribe Adversus Valentinianos, 7 (Opera, Vol. II, p. 116; English,
Vol. II, p. 128), Tertullian says of the god: "Considering him in terms of sub-
stance they call him 'perfect aeon* (Altiva r/Aen>); and in terms of person, 'first
gnostiques d'Oxford, 23 (Jesus taught His disciples that after death they would
p.
traverse the aeons): "There ... we get the numbers corresponding to each world
of seals, that is to say, the magic words which a person had to have and know in
order to enter each aeon. . . . We also learn the 'apologies' that had to be recited,
the words, that is, which had to be uttered in order to convince the Aeons that
there was no number and the seal.
trickery in one's possessing the Use of the . . .
number, the talisman, had marvellous effects. When the soul presented itself in a
given world all its Archons, all its Powers, all its denizens, in a word, came run-
ning toward it, ready to wreak all the chastisement the soul's temerity had in-
curred. But it pronounced the number, showed the talisman, recited the formula,
and straightway Archons, Powers, inhabitants, gave ground before it, taking flight
towards the West." Idem, Notice sur le papyrus gnostique de Bruce, pp. 194-95
"
(Jesus says to his disciples) 'I will now give you the
:
"apology" for all these
places of which I have given you the mysteries [passwords] and the baptisms. . . .
When you have left the body and perform these mysteries for all the aeons and
all those who are in them, they will retreat [before you] until you come to these
six great aeons. They will flee to the West, to the left, with all their Archons, and
"
all who are in them.' To recapitulate: the term "aeons" seems to have had three
meanings for the Gnostics: (i) a metaphysical meaning with some bearing on
eternity; (2) a meaning make an aeon a person; (3) a meaning
that tends to
that tends to make an aeon a place. But such meanings are not kept distinct. The
metaphysical trait is extended to persons and places, the persons are something like
places, and the places act like persons.
I088 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1646
wit: Abyss and then Mind (m) and Truth
(m) and Silence (/),
wl
(/). After quaternion there comes another made up of:
this first
The Word (m) and the Life (/), and Man (m) and the Church
(/). The two quaternions
added together yield an octad (6y5odg),
which, it would seem, must have been a very pretty thing. The
Word and Aeons whose names I may
the Life beget another ten
be spared from giving here; and copulating with Dame Church
l
1646 Ircnaeus, Contra haereses, I, i, i (Mignc, pp. 446-47; Kcble, pp. 3-4) :
AtyovGt yap nva dvai kv dopdrot^ Kal anarovopdoroi^ vtycjuaai rtfoiov altiva 7rpo6vra' rov-
rov J Kal [lacuna) UpoTvdropa Kal Bi'^o^ KaAovcriv vTrdp^ovra 6* avrbv a^upijrov Kal
[lacuna]
d6porov aidi6v re Kal
1 ayt'vvjjrov, iv ?jovxiaKal 7/pruia Tro/l/l?; yeytyvfvai kv airtlpoi^ altivi XP&~
VQV. ovvvTrap%eiv d'avr(f) Kal 'Evvoiav, f/v J?) Kal "Kupiv Kal 2/yr/y bvofid^ovai. Kal fvvot/Ot/vai
TTOTC afieavrov 7rpofta?itG0ai rbv "Bvtibv rovrov apxf/v T&V TTCIVTDV. Kal KaHdnep wrppua r;/v
6/u.ol6v re, law ro 7Tf)o8a?i6vTi Kal [i6vov xttpovvra TO fifyftioc rov 7raT()6c. rov 6e Not)v
Kal J
TOVTOV Kal yLovoycvf] Kafawat, Kal Trarepa Kal ap%qv rtiv TTCLVTUV. ffi'fnrpofttftfifjaOai At ai>T(j
'
"First Father and Abyss" (UpoTrdropa Kal BtrfJoV) Grabe notes: "Synesius, bishop of
Ptolemais, not only used poetical licences in his hymns but adapted almost all the
mataeology of the Valentinians to true theology singing the orthodox faith in hereti-
cal words. These two epithets, for instance, he applied to God the Father as in
Hymn II, v. 27 (Opera, p. 317; Fitzgerald, Vol. II, p. 374): 'Paternal Deep* /3v6b?
Trarp&oc (projundum patcrnum); III, v. 147 (Opera, p. 321; Fitzgerald, Vol. II, p.
377): 'Fatherless First Father* (npondTup andrup) and IV, v. 69 (Opera, p. 336;
Fitzgerald, Vol. II, p. 384): 'Beauty unsoundable' (pvOiov /ca/Uo^: immcnsa pulchri-
tudo)" It is instructive to compare this description with the one in the Bruce papyri:
Amelineau, Notice, pp. 89-92: "It [he] is the First Father of all things, the Prime
Eternal, the King of the Unattainable [those who cannot be touched], the Gulf of
All Things. ... It [he] has been given no name since it [he] is unnamable and
unthinkable. . . . The second place is called
Demiurge, Father, Logos, Source,
Mind, Man, Eternal, prop [column], the overseer, the
Infinite. It [he] is the
Father of all things, the Ennead which issued from the Father without beginning,
father and mother to itself, the one which [whom] the Pleroma girt about the
twelve abysses. The first abyss is the universal source from which all sources have
issued. The second abyss is the universal wisdom, source of all wisdoms." And so
on and on. The other abysses are: "Universal Mystery; Universal Gnosis; Universal
Purity; Silence; Universal Essence before All Essence; the Propator; the Pantopator
or Autopator, Omnipotence, the Invisible Truth." [Another truth to add to the long
list we
have already seen. A. L.]
2
1646 Amelineau, Les traites, etc., pp. 24-25, thinks he can identify three dif-
ferent pleromata in the Bruce papyri: "The word Pleroma has, I think, three very
different meanings, or at the very least two that are certain. It seems to me first
1
646 GNOSTICISM 1
089
3
story about the "passion" of Sophia (/) Wisdom. It must derive
from the Valentinians, who believed that Abyss had begotten a son
agamogenetically. It tells how Sophia "tried to emulate her father
and herself engender without a mate, that she might perform a feat
in no way inferior to her father's. She did not know that
only he
who increate, principle, root, altitude and abyss, can
is
engender
4
without a mate." Hera also was minded to emulate Zeus, who had
given birth to Athena all by himself, and without consort with any
mate she bore Hephaestus (Vulcan), who, saving the detail that one
to designate the aggregate of worlds, including our Earth; but on our Earth it is
destroyed, annihilated. I would not be too positive about this understanding of the
word 'Pleroma.' It is not categorically established. It seems however to be the one
that is implied by the texts, especially the two here in hand. In any case, it is certain
that the word 'Pleroma' designates the intermediate and upper worlds taken to-
gether, in otherwords all the intermediate aeons between our Earth and the higher
Pleroma including the aeons of the latter Pleroma itself. Finally, the term
'Pleroma' is often used as a designation for the upper world alone. That upper
world is called the 'Aeon of the Treasure,' and the Treasure, like all treasuries,
contains a number of precious articles sixty aeons, to be specific."
8
1646 [Origen ? ], Philosophumcna, VI, 2, 30: It was the last of the
Cf.
twenty-eight Aeons, "being female and called Sophia (ftrpw$ hv KOL /caAofy/evof So^fo)."
Here the explicit attribution of sex leaves no room for doubt.
4
1646 Philosophumena, VI, 2, 30. Other versions differ from this one and are to
a greater extent allegorical. Irenaeus, and Tertullian who follows him (Adversus
Valentinianos, 9-10; Opera, Vol. II, pp. 119-21), relate that Sophia desired to en-
compass her father's immensity. Unable to realize that ambition she began to
pine, and would have vanished altogether had not Limit ("0/uof [m]) come to the
rescue. Some Valentinians say that in the course of that arduous quest she bore
Cogitation (/) (or "Passion": Mvpqais [/]); others, that the offspring was Mattcr-
without-Form, a female entity (Iraeneus, Op. cit., I, 2, 2; Migne, pp. 455-58;
Keble, p. 6).
It would seem that Gnostics were still to be found as late as the nineteenth cen-
tury and that they were well acquainted with Sophia. Jules Bois, Les petitcs
religions de Paris, p. 176, puts the following words into the mouth of one Jules
"
Doinel, a Gnostic: 'Do you know,' asked the Apostle, 'why we surfer and are so
often bad? The Demiurge, not God Himself, created the world. This Demiurge, a
clumsy workman in the service of Sophia, soul of the Universe, who fell through
her noble desire to know too much, made us in his own image and it was not a
very beautiful one. But Sophia took pity on us. By her decree, one of her tears
dropping from heaven took up its abode in our human clay. Demiurge got even
by binding man to the flesh, and he will never get free of it except through knowl-
edge of his destiny, through the Gnosis."
TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1647
of his legswas shorter than the other, was an up-and-doing god.
Poor Sophia had no such luck "She produced only what she could:
29, that Valentinus got his doctrine, not from the Gospels, but from
1
Pythagoras and Plato. St. Epiphanius, for his part, fixes on the per-
sonifications and declares, Panarium ad versus
I, 3 (Opera, haereses,
Vol. p. 478),
I, that they repeat the genealogies of the pagan gods
2
as reported
by Hesiod, Stesichorus, and other poets. Those two
manners of approaching the Valentinian doctrine have each their
modicum of truth; but we must not be forgetting that all meta-
physical dreamers have a common fountain-head of inspiration, as
5
1646 Philosophumena , loc. cit.
*
1647 Tertullian, Advcrsus Valcntinianos, i (Opera, Vol. II, p. no; English,
Vol. II, p. 120), compares the Valentinian mysteries with the Eleusinian: "Eleusinia
Valentiniani jecerunt lenocinia (practised the Eleusinian whorings)."
2
1647 The Bruce papyri give comical details of personification: Amclineau, Lcs
traites, pp. 91, 97-99: "The light of his [its] eyes reaches forth from the regions of
the outer Plcroma and the Word issues from his [its] mouth. The hairs of . . .
his [its] head are equal in number to the hidden worlds. The lineaments of his
[its] countenance are the image of the aeons. The hairs of his [its] beard equal in
number the number of the outer worlds." All names become things: "There is also
another place that is called 'Abyss* and there there arc three Paternities. ... In
the second Paternity there are five trees with a table in the midst thereof, and
enthroned on the table is a Word, the Unigenitus (Monogcnes) having the twelve
countenances of the Mind (Nous) of all things, and the prayers of all creatures are
laid before him [it]. . . . And this Christ has twelve countenances. . . . Each
Paternity has three countenances." This whole passage on the "Second Place"
Buonaiuti, following Carl Schmidt [Gnostische Schrijtcn, p. 278], translates as
follows: Lo gnosticismo, p. 211: "The second place is the one called Demiurge,
Father, Logos, Source, Nous, Man, Eternal, Infinite. He is the Pillar, the Super-
visor, the Father of all things. He
he upon whose head the Aeons form a crown
is
and he doth sparkle with their rays. The lineaments of his countenance cannot be
seen in the outer worlds, which do yearn at all times to behold his face, for they
would know him, since his Word hath come unto them and they would behold
him. And
the light of his eyes doth penetrate to the innermost places of the outer
Pleroma, and the Word doth issue from his mouth, and doth reach forth above and
below in all directions. The hairs of his head are equal in number to the hidden
worlds, and the lineaments of his countenance are the reflection of the Aeons; and
the hairs of his beard are equal in number to the number of the outer worlds."
1648 DERIVATIONS IV~<5: VERBAL PROOFS I
Op I
8
do all creators of legend. It is therefore difficult to determine just
how far they are copying one another and to just what extent the
ideas they express are spontaneous and original in each (733f-)-
1648. Certainly there are many cases where direct proofs of plagia-
something in harmony with the facts, if one were to say that He-
brews, Christians, writers such as Plato, the Orphic poets, and so on,
derived their notions from a common fund of residues and deriva-
tions. That
alone enough to explain resemblances between doc-
is
beginning was Cronus, or Time, and he produced Aether and Chaos whose mar-
Cosmic Egg, a huge silver egg. From it issued a god of many
riage resulted in the
heads they were heads of animals. At once male and female he contained all
things in germ. He was called Phanes, but he also had other names: Protogonus,
Ericapaeus, Metis, Eros. At the time when the god left the Cosmic Egg, its upper
half became the firmament, its lower half the Earth."
2
1648 Aristobulus, a Hebrew philosopher quoted by Eusebius, Evangelica prae-
paratio, XIII, 12, declares that Plato evidently utilized the books of the Hebrew law.
Justin Martyr, Apologia, I, 59, 60 (Migne, pp. 415-19; Davie, pp. 45-46), mentions
doctrines that Plato got from the Bible, and in his Cohortatio ad Graecos, 14 (Migne,
pp. 267-70; missing in Davie), he decides that Orpheus, Homer, Solon, Pythagoras,
and Plato all had access to the histories of Moses by way of the Egyptians. The
Aristobulus in question was a first-rate falsifier of texts. He quotes writers as best
suits his purpose and in one case has the impudence to tamper with a verse of
IO92 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1649
1649. The Valentinians waver between abstract combinations of
elements and sexual unions. In that they are like many other systems
which try to avail themselves of the powerful residue of sex, strip-
ping the well be, of any suggestion of licentiousness.
latter, it may
In a fragment by Valentinus, which owes its preservation to its quo-
tation by St. Epiphanius, the two sexes stand combined in the Aeon,
who represented as a male-female (dopevoO^v^) but then again
is ;
leaving Calypso's island by the fourth day: "It was the fourth day, and everything
had been done by him." However, Aristobulus wants to show that the pagans
also regarded the seventh day as holy, and so blithely substitutes "Epfiopov for
Ttrparov and makes Homer say that everything had been done by the seventh
day. Eusebius, pious rascal that he was, quotes Aristobulus and pretends not to
notice the falsification [Evangdica praeparatio, XIII, 12 (Opera, Vol. Ill, pp. 1097-
98)]. But Aristobulus goes even that one better. He invents verses outright as
occasion demands, and again Eusebius quotes them without a quaver. It should not
be overlooked that those two gentlemen were great hands at harping on "morality."
*
1649 St. Epiphanius, Panarium ad versus haereses, lib. I, tomus II, Haeresis
31, 5,Ex Valentiniano libro (Opera, Vol. I, pp. 482-83) in question a male and a
female Aeon: ". and so they united in coition incorrupt, in embrace everlasting"
. .
him . .
."). The verb fiiyvvfii is the ordinary Greek term for commerce between the
sexes. A
pamphlet of Victorinus of Pettaw, entitled Ad versus omnes hacreticos,
which was once mistakenly attributed to Tertullian, declares, i (Corpus, p. 215;
Thelwall, p. 650: Tertullian, English, Vol. Ill, p. 261): "This individual [Nicolas]
says that Darkness had lusted with Light in a foul and obscene passion, and modesty
forbids me to mention the filthy loathsome things that were born of that lechery.
Then there are other obscenities. For he talks about certain Aeons that are born of
shame, about execrable and obscene mixtures and minglings, and about things even
more disgusting that come of them."
2
1649 Daremberg-Saglio, Dictionnaire , s.v. Orphici: "Not content with trans-
forming myths into symbols, the Orphics invented and adopted gods that were
altogether abstract, gods without legends and without features of individuality,
being mere metaphysical expressions of Orphic conceptions of cosmogony. Among
this number were some of their most
devoutly worshipped gods, such as the cosmic
Eros, Protogonus, Metis [Cunning], Mise [Hate], Mnemosyne, Phanes [Light].
One need only consider the etymologies of these names to be sure that they were
mere symbols without concrete substance or reality, the terms of metaphysics simply
being deified."
1650 HESIOD'S COSMOGONY 1093
Another pleasant individual is that Justinus whom we know
1650.
1
1650 "There are three increate principles of the all, two male and one female.
Of the male one is called Good. He alone is so called, for he is prescient of all
things. The other is father of all created things. He seeth not, foreseeth not (impru-
dent), knoweth not. The female foreseeth not, and she is prone to wrath, and de-
ceitful[double], in all things like unto the monster of Herodotus [Historiae, IV,
8] a maiden down to the private parts, a snake there below, as Justinus saith. And
:
the maiden is called Edcm and Israel. Such, saith Justinus, are the principles of the
All, the root and source from which
all things have come; and other than these
which Edem likewise made subject unto her the names are ." And know ye also . .
thn- the trees of the biblical Paradise are allegories of these same angels. The tree
of life is Baruch, Number Three among the paternal angels; the tree of knowledge
of good and evil is Naas, Number Three among the maternal angels. Eloim and
Edem produced all things: human beings come of the human part of Edem the
part above the groin; animals, and all the rest, come of the bestial part the part
below the groin.
2
1650 Theogonia, vv. 116-36: "And so first was Chaos, and then Earth-of-the-
Broad-Bosom, ever the firm throne of the All [An interpolation reads: "of the Im-
mortals who hold the snowy peaks of Olympus"], and Tartarus dark in the recesses
of the spacious Earth, and Eros, who is the fairest of the immortal gods, who ban-
ishes the cares [or else, "loosens the limbs"] of all gods and men. And of . . .
Chaos and Erebus was black Night born, and of Night, thereafter, were Aether and
the Days born, she having known Erebus and conceived of him. And verily the
Earth first of all bore the starry Uranus [the Sky], her equal, that he might envelop
her all about . and of embrace with Uranus did she conceive Ocean us-of-the-
. .
Deep-Whirlpools, and Cocus, Creiius, Hyperion, lapetus, Theia, Rhea, Themis, and
Mnemosyne, Phoebus-of-the-Golden-Crown, and Thetis-thc-Lovely." These verses of
Hesiod have caused a great to do among commentators and philosophers in general.
Diogenes Laertius relates, Epicurus, X, 2 (Hicks, Vol. II, pp. 529-31), that Epicurus
turned to philosophy because neither Sophists nor grammarians had succeeded in
explaining to him just what Hesiod's Chaos was. Scxtus Empiricus, Contradictiones,
X, Adverstis physicos, I, 18 (636) (Opera, Vol. II, p. 678), repeats the same anec-
dote, adding a number of details. According to Sextus Hesiod gave the name of
Chaos to the place that contains all things. Hesiod's ancient scholiast transmits sev-
eral views on the same Chaos, among them an etymology deriving the term from
XeioQai, to amass, accumulate, spread out: irapa TO ^eioBai Xdof yivero. According to
another interpretation, ascribed to Zenodotus, Hesiod's Chaos is the atmosphere
1094 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1651
able in surfeit from all times and peoples. Even a writer of the nine-
teenth century, Charles Fourier, was minded to have his own; and
if
anyone else should care to try his hand at world-building, he
8
could easily have his way by proper resort to verbal allegory.
between
1651. Verbal allegories figure largely in the controversy
the Realists and the Nominalists. As is well known, surrendering to
that mighty current which rushes down across the centuries from
remotest times to our own day, the Realists thought that abstractions
(afjp). Coming down to critics of more recent date, Guyet notes: "Xdof yver' : that
is, the sky, the air, the immensity of the atmosphere, uncircumscribed immensity,
poet: "By whom was Chaos created?" "The author of the Clementine Homilies
therefore interprets tyhero as though Hesiod had written tyevvifirj , 'Chaos was en-
"
gendered/ But that is a fatuous splitting of hairs. Quoting the passage from Hesiod,
"
he says, VI, 3: 'was made/ Evidently he means that the elements originated as
created things and had not existed from eternity as increate things. But if that had
been the meaning of the poet one would have had to devise some cause whereby he
could say that Chaos was engendered. For when one says that it was 'made' one
immediately meets the objection 'By whom?' nothing being 'made* without a
"
maker." But Robinson, pp. 356-57, is not of that opinion: "Hm-y^er': renders:
'First then Chaos was engendered,' as also below, 137, 930. So the ancients under-
stood the passage, not reading 'was,' ]uit, as does Leclerc." Robinson supports his
interpretation by various authorities and concludes: "Such the darkness in which
they grope, who, denying the cause of all things, set out to explain the origin of
the world on other hypotheses. The same question, 'By whom was it produced?'
necessarily must recur time after time until one arrives at some supreme, increate
cause."
Today we laugh at such fatuous pedantries to which experimental science has at
last put an end. But ifever the sway of such science comes to be extended over
sociology and political economy, people will laugh just as heartily at many disquisi-
tions, metaphysical, ethical, humanitarian, patriotic, and the like, which are to be
found in the literature of those subjects in our time.
3
1650 Fourier, Traitc de ['association domestique agricole, Vol.
I, pp. 521-27
(italics Fourier's) : "The planets being androgenous like the plants, they copulate
with themselves and with other planets. So the Earth, copulating with itself and
fusing its two typical aromas, the masculine coming from the North Pole and the
feminine from the South Pole, produced the cherry, a subpivotal fruit of the red
fruits and attended by five fruits in the scale, as follows: copulating with Mercury,
its principal and fifth satellite, the Earth engendered the strawberry; with Pallas, its
fourth the blacl^ currant or cassis; with Ceres, its third satellite, the thorny
satellite,
currant." Now
for the properties of such offspring: "The cherry, the subpivotal
fruit of that series (modulation} by copulation of the Earth with itself is created
of North Pole, with male aroma, and of South Pole, with female aroma. A symbol
of the tastes of childhood, the cherry is the first fruit of the pleasant season. It
1651 DERIVATIONS IV-5: VERBAL PROOFS 1095
1
and allegories
were real things. From the logico-experimental point
of view such a controversy may last indefinitely, and in fact has
ing to their private tastes will prefer now one theory, now the other,
or even some intermediate one; but once a person has made his
choice there is no way left to lock another person in the dilemma
of either accepting his theory or rejecting logico-experimental fact.
stands in the order of crops where childhood stands in the order of ages. The . . .
strawberry, given by Mercury, is the most precious of the red fruits. It pictures
childhood to us as raised to harmony in the industrial groups. The thorny cur- . . .
rant, that grows with separate berries, is a product of Ceres. It pictures the child
that repressed, held aloof from pleasures, morally harassed, educated apart from
is
others. . The black currant, the cassis, is the gift of Pallas or Aesculapius, who
. .
always modulates on the side of the bitter tastes. The plant represents poor ill-bred
children. That is why its black fruit, emblematic of poverty, is of a bitter unpleasant
savour."
I
1651 De generibus et specicbus (Ouvrages inedits, pp. 513-25)
In his essay
Abelard states a
Realist position: "Opinions differ according to the person. . . .
Some imagine that there are certain universal essences which they think are present
essentially in each single individual. . . Each individual is made up of matter and
.
form. Socrates, for instance, is made up of matter man, and of form Socraticity,
Plato of a similar matter man, but of a different form Plato-ness; and so on for
other individual men. And just as the Socraticity that formally constitutes Socrates
exists nowhere outside of Socrates, so that essence of a man which sustains the
Socraticity in Socrates exists nowhere except in Socrates, and so on for all individ-
uals. I therefore say that the species is not that essence of a man which is present
only in Socrates or in any other individual, but the whole aggregate (collectio)
brought together from other individuals of the same nature; which aggregate (col-
lectio) taken as a whole, though essentially multiple, is nevertheless called by the
authorities one species, one universal, one nature, just as a people though made up
of many individuals is said to be one."
1096 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1652
1652. But, in this connexion ( 2373), there is another problem
that belongs wholly to experimental science, the question as to
which of the two courses had better be followed if one is trying to
discover the uniformities that prevail among facts: i. Shall one
ism, lay in denying the conditions of existence to everything that exists and ascrib-
ing them exclusively to what does not exist. Guillaume de Champcaux, in our judg-
ment, did nothing less than that. According to the Nominalists universals in re
. . .
are merely the more or less general attributes of individual things: the similarity
universal in re, considered as the most general thing, is substance, or first and only
essence, which does not contain the principle of distinction within itself but takes
on individual forms as extrinsic accidents.'* What on earth is that "first and only
essence'*? A
quid simile of the "Abyss" of the Gnostics? Rousselot, 'Etudes sur la
philosophic dans le moyen age, Vol. I, pp. 253-55: "Let us briefly recall the thesis
of Nominalism. Roxellinus had said: Individuals are realities and constitute the
essence of things: the rest is only an abstraction, a play of language, a sound of the
voice, a flatus vocis. Shocked, and rightly so, at the proposition, Guillaume de
1654 THE "POEM OF CREATION" 1097
dent that they move in a world quite different from the world of
2
experimental reality.
1653. Allegories are a product of human fancy, and therefore have
a certain likeness when produced by people of the same race, of re-
lated races, and sometimes even of whatever race. The stories of the
Creation that are told by one people or another are all of a kind,
because they conceive of the Creation as something after the manner
of the procreation they have before their eyes. Spontaneously, there-
fore, and not by any reciprocal copying, they invent male and female
1654. Believers will say that such stories resemble one another be-
cause they are recording one single event, the memory of which has
been handed down in various ways. That may well be. But such a
Champeaux . . . combats that doctrine and substitutes for it one directly opposite
idea of reality must not be separated [Before deciding whether they stand united
or separate we have to know what they are.] and it is from the house-top of that
ontological principle that he proclaims the reality of universals and denies the reality
of the individual/* There are people who reason like that in the world today.
2
1652 Diogenes Lacrtius, Diogenes, VI, 53 (Hicks, Vol. II, p. 55) "Plato speak- :
ing of his 'ideas' and chancing to use the terms tablcncss and gobletness, 'I,' said
Diogenes, *O Plato, sec your table and your goblet, but your tableness and your
gobletness in no wise do And Plato: 'And rightly so; for you have the eyes
I sec.
1
that see tables and goblets; but the mind that sees tableness and gobletness, that
" 1
have you not. Both were right. Plato's followers are entitled to see what they
please. Their talk may have its use as derivation it is fatuous and sottish in every
respect of experimental science.
l
1653 Dhorme, Choix de textes religieux assyro-babyloniens, Preface, pp. x-xii:
"How and by whom was the world made? The various cosmogonies answer that
1098 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY
1655. Allegories and metaphors usually figure in the formation of
[As a matter of fact, just the other way round.] The 'Poem of Creation' ... is,
from that point of view, of the major interest. Not satisfied with running down
the genesis of heaven and earth, it goes back to the time when 'none of the gods
had been created' and displays a veritable theogony before us. The gods will issue
in successive pairs [Personification, male and female, is rarely missing.] from a
primal couple, Apsou, the ocean that surrounds our land, and Tiamat, the 'tumultu-
ous sea whose waters mingle into one.' ... If the Tocm of Creation' is steeped
in mythological and popular ideas, the 'Chaldaean Cosmogony' tells a more ab-
stract and theological story of creation. The world still comes from the sea, but we
arc not madewitnesses of the births of any gods. If the Babylonians considered their
national god, Marduk, as the author of the world and of mankind, it is quite nat-
ural that the Assyrians should have entrusted that role to Asur, their god. . . .
That other legends of the Creation must have been current is proved by the frag-
mentary 'Creation of Animate Beings,' where we see a collaboration of gods in the
formation of heaven and earth. Along with these cosmogonies of the scholarly tradi-
tion there were other hypotheses as to the origin of the world. Some of them are a
rative without metaphor; but the story now suggests an analogy:] If the conception,
1/192 of the social cycle (carrier?) , which gives 450 years, more or less, for the dura-
tion of the First Creation. [And now a passage where metaphor, analogy, narrative,
are jumbled together, Fourier apparently not in the least distinguishing between the
different things:] All creation is effected through the conjunction of a boreal fluid,
which is fluid, which is female." ([In a note:] "The star can
male, with an austral
pair: i. With itself, from the North and South poles, like plants. 2. With another
star, by emanations (versementi) from opposite poles. 3. With some intermediary
-
(the tuberose is engendered by three aromas: Earth-South, Herschel [Uranus]
North, Sun-South). A planet is a being with two souls and two sexes and procre-
ates like the animal or plant by the combination of two generative substances. The
the first foundations of the trinary dogma in its theological form, we had not as yet
come to understand how deeply that dogma had been FELT BY SAINT-SIMON in his
NEW CHRISTIANITY. Your father RODRIGUES alone kept repeating to us that that book
contained the teaching which it was given to man to receive. And we our-
loftiest
selves, when we were carried in the course of our labours to investigating the scien-
tific make-up of the trinitarian doctrine of the Christians and the ancient doctrine,
soon came to justify the problem of the Trinity in our own eyes as the most signifi-
cant that the human being could propound to himself. One of us let fall this sen-
tence, which was afterwards repeated in Eugene's letters: One who jails to under-
stand the Trinity jails to understand God. That was a real revelation as regarded
doctrine. All those who heard it, and your father RESSEGUIER in particular, found
some comprehending its full scope. It was not till then that on re-read-
difficulty in
ing the NEW CHRISTIANITY we saw that the idea of the Trinity figured on every page
in it under a thousand different forms, such as MORALITY, Dogma, Ritual, FINE ARTS,
Science, Industry. Great was our astonishment that we had been going over and
over that eternal problem of humanity so many times without noticing that it had
to be solved by us. At the same time all the sentences, all the indications, which
had made no impression upon us at the time of The Producer, now strengthened
us Eugene and me in the belief that our formula for the pantheistic trinitarian
dogma was the true formula of Saint-Simon."
1660 * Historia translations beatorum Christi martyrum Marcellini et Petri, IV,
44-45 (Opera, pp. 268-72; Wendell, pp. 57-59). Eginhard sets out for Court from the
church where the bones of the saints Marcellinus and Peter are cherished. He
reaches a certain locality on the Rhine when the following adventure befalls him:
After our supping, which had consumed a part of the night, I had retired with
my attendants to the chamber whither I was appointed to rest. But the servant who
was wont to prepare our drink hastened into the room as though he had some
strange thing to tell. I looked at him and asked: 'What wouldst thou? For thou
seemest to have something thou wouldst impart unto us.' Whereupon he: Two
1660 EGINHARD'S MIRACLE noi
metaphor but he vainly wonders what the significance of the prod-
igy may be what allegory may be inferred from it. Now suppose
we did not have Eginhard's naive confidences but knew only his
story of the bald fact. Our aim is to get from his story to what ac-
tually happened, and we argue, as M. Loisy argues regarding the
miracles in the Fourth Gospel, that the miracle as told by Eginhard
is
"unintelligible, absurd, ridiculous as fact, unless we see in it the
bold manipulation of a trickster" (774). We
shall have
plenty of
ways for discovering some "easy and simple interpretation" of the
miracle, and need only make our choice among numberless meta-
phors all
equally probable. But in such case our error would be
apparent enough; from intending to speak in metaphors,
for, far
Eginhard went looking for one and confesses that he failed to find
miracles have been wrought before our eyes, and of them would I speak unto you.'
And when had bidden him speak, he said: 'When ye rose from table and entered
I
into your chamber, I and my companions withdrew into the nether store-room,
which is under the dining-hall. We had begun to give beer to the servants who
besought us of it, when there entered a servant sent thither by some of our com-
panions and holding a flask, which he begged us to fill. The which when we had
done, he asked that we give him also of this beer to drink; and we gave him of it
in a vessel that chanced to lie empty on the cask of the beer. But as he put the ves-
sel to his mouth to drink, he cried out, amazed: "Forsooth, this is wine, and not
beer." And when he who had filled the flask, drawing the same from the tap from
which he had given the man to drink, began charging him with falsehood, the
man cried: "Take it, and taste, and then shalt thou see that I spake not falsehood
but the truth." And the man took it and tasted, and likewise vowed that the drink
had the taste of wine, not of beer. And then a third, and a fourth, and all others
who were there did each taste, and stood amazed, and so drank they all that was
in the cask; and each of them who tasted bore witness that the taste was of wine
"
and not of beer.* And then the same servant relates the second miracle a case
where a candle first falls to the floor without being touched and goes out; and then,
after an utterance of the names of Sts. Marcellinus and Peter, is relighted of its
own accord. Eginhard goes on to say: "Whereupon I bade the man who had told
me these things to retire into his own chamber. And lying on my bed to rest and
turning many thoughts in my mind, marvelling, I began to speculate as to what
this transmutation of beer into wine, that is to say, of an inferior liquid into a bet-
ter, could signify or portend; and why the prodigy should have occurred in that
way and in that place, that is to say, in a house of the King rather than in the man-
sion where the holy bodies of those blessed Martyrs lay, who through the power
of Christ had worked those miracles. But though however long and diligently I
pondered, it was not given me to solve the problem of a certainty, still I had and
shall always have it for a fact that that Supreme Power whereof it is held that these
and other like miracles come, never doth anything, nor permitteth anything to hap-
pen, without cause in those creatures which, I doubt not, abide under his providence
and government."
IIO2 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY l66l
system some would follow today, inverting that relation and assum-
ing that a writer cannot have believed in the reality of facts which
happen be susceptible of allegorical interpretation.
also to
1663. With so obvious an example before our eyes, how can we
assertwithout trace of direct proof that the author of the Fourth
Gospel followed a procedure wholly different from St. Cyprian's
and distinguished what the Saint combines ? So long as we have no
evidence on the point and follow the mere probabilities, these will
the Holy Spirit came in the form of a dove. The dove is a simple,
joyous bird, not bitter with gall, not cruel in its bites, not savage in
1
its
clawings." Either words have lost all meaning and the texts we
have are valueless, or else we are constrained to admit that St. Cyp-
rian believes that theHoly Spirit actually assumed the form of a
dove; and the things he adds to his description serve to show the
considerations prompting the transformation but not in any way to
cast doubt upon it (loc. at.): "loving human dwellings, knowing
the association of one home when they have young, bringing them
;
forth together, and when they fly abroad, flying side by side." (Wal-
2
lis.)
1665. Derivations with metaphors are frequently for the benefit
of educated people, but often also they serve half-educated people
to harmonize faith with logico-experimental science. Anything in a
story or theory that seems impossible to accept from the experi-
mental standpoint is at once set down as metaphor. The difference
between faith and this semi-scepticism lies in the fact that faith be-
lieves in the historical truth of the story and adds the metaphor:
what actually happens is a "sign" that teaches us something. Semi-
scepticism does not believe in the historical reality of the story. It
does not add metaphor to fact, but substitutes it for fact the meta-
in columba vcnit Spiritus sanctus. Simplex animal et laetum est, non jelle amarum,
non morsibus saevum, non unguium laceratione violentum."
St. Augustine, however, says, De symbolo, Sermo ad catcchumenos X, 20
2
1664 ,
(Opera, Vol. VI, p. 649): "So the Spirit appeared in a dove but was not a dove."
So one eats one's cake and has it too! It was, and yet it was not, a dove! The next
step is to go farther still and see a mere allegory in the dove.
1
104 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1667
arise in connexion with theories. There we dealt with the first of
those problems (relations of a theory to experimental fact) and in
this present chapter we deal with the second (means of arriving at
It now remains for us
pre-established conclusions, persuasiveness).
to consider the two problems together, epitomizing the observations
that may be made on each of them separately. Suppose we take con-
crete cases as types: i. A story that is
purely mythological, such as
the story of Aphrodite and Ares in the eighth book of the Odyssey,
vv. 266-366. 2. Some wholly allegorical fable, where animals are
made to talk the fable of the wolf and the lamb, let us say. 3. The
Valentinian Gnosis (1645^). 4. Fourier's theory of creations
8
(i65O , 1656 *). 5. Comte's theory of the Earth and the Great
Being ( 1626'). 6. The theory of the Realists ( 1651). 7. The the-
ory of "solidarity."
1667. As regards the first
problem, as regards their relations to
fact, all those types stand on a par: their logico-experimental value
is
exactly zero. They in no way correspond to experimental facts. As
regards the second problem, as regards the methods by which im-
plications are drawn from them, and their persuasive force, we may
distinguish: (a) the structure of the derivation; () the manner
of its acceptance.
1668. a. Structure of the derivation. The
seven types noted have
one common characteristic: the arbitrary use of certain non-experi-
mental entities. Tertullian, seeing the mote in his
neighbour's eye,
challenges the Valentinians to prove their statements as to their
"Abyss," and takes no stock in what they say: "As though they
could ever prove its existence, if they define it as we know that it
has to be defined!" Bravo! As if
figments of the human fancy could
ever be proved to exist! To prove the existence of their Abyss, of
Hesiod's Chaos, of gods and goddesses, of copulations of planets, of
Fourier's sentient Earth, of universals, of talking animals, is some-
in Fourier one does not readily see just how and just why the Earth
copulates with herself and with Pallas. The North Pole and the
South Pole are both cold. It is not self-evident therefore why the
fluid of the North Pole should be male and that of the South Pole
female. But keeping to the terms "North" and "South" in them-
selves, we do understand that the warm South may somehow sug-
may take on. In Hesiod's theogony there is less, though still a great
deal, of the arbitrary. One can see that sentiment will readily grant
that Chaos, and even Love, existed before anything else. That the
Earth should have produced the Sky, or the Sky the Earth, and
that Earth and Sky should unite to produce many other things
that too is sentimentally intelligible. But why Coeus, Crei'us, Hy-
and unnamable, nor are the names "Abyss" or "First Father" in-
appropriate to such an entity. All such words are chosen for the
simple reason that they arouse sentiments that accord with a feeling
we have we know nothing of the principle of the all. The story
that
of Sophia's striving to know her father's face awakens in us a sense
of the yearning men feel to know what is beyond experience. We
understand by analogy that tears go with humid matter, laughter
with light, and so on ( 670). The analogies with Pythagorean per-
fections in numbers or with the numerical values of letters, super-
ficial and arbitrary as they are, still awaken some response in human
emotions. In Comte's mythology the status of the arbitrary element
is not
greatly different from its status in Gnostic theory, but it is
not so conspicuously obtruded. And very much the same may be
said of the theory of "solidarity." The object, in two words, is to
ing back and forth from the ones to the others and then round
again, without ever finding a place where they can stop. When they
have endowed one of their entities with sex, they would seem to
have personified it; but then back they go from personification to
abstraction, changing the Aeon into a male-female "principle"
(Irenaeus, Contra haereses, I, i, i). However they do not stick to the
abstraction. Soon again they begin talking of a generative process
that is
by the deposit of something like seed in something
effected
like a matrix, and of entities that fertilize, conceive and bring forth
1
young. Then they try to shed the material connotations by talking
x
1670 The Greek text and the translation of Irenaeus, Contra haereses, I, i, i,
are given in 1646. The ancient Latin translator understands the passage thus:
"Prolationem hanc praemittt volunt et earn deposuisse quasi in vulva eius quae cum
co erat Sige [i.e., Silence]. Hanc autem suscepisse semen hoc et pracgnantem factam
[How could an abstraction ever get with child? All the terms here in question
apply to human women.] generasse Nun." Tertullian, Adversus Valentinianos f 7
(Opera, Vol. II, p. 116; English, Vol. II, p. 129), reads: "Hoc vice seminis in Sigae
suae veluti genitalibus vtdvae locis collocat. Suscipit ilia statim et praegnans efficitur
et parit" The Valentinians do not seem to have been all of the same opinion: Phi-
losophumena, VI, 2, 29: "Many differences are to be noted among them. Some, in
1672 DERIVATIONS IV-5 I VERBAL PROOFS IIO7
of a coition that is
"incorrupt" ( 1649). But as regards creation they
also dispense with the sexual union: "They say that humid sub-
stances were born of the tears of Achamoth, luminous substances
of his smile, solid substances of his gloom, and the mobile of his
fear." In short theywaver between literal meanings and metaphor,
between personifications and allegory, without ever fixing once and
for all on any definite attitude.
1671. Metaphor, as is well known, easily leads to personification,
and many many examples of such developments are available. The
personifications in Comte's mythology are very like the personifica-
tions of the Gnostics, with the difference that Comte begins by
saying that his are fictions, but then proceeds to forget that and
talks of them as though they were actual persons. Personification
amounts to nothing in the theory of solidarity; nor does it play any
part in the theory of the Realists. But that is true only as regards
forms, not as regards substance. After all, the Abyss of the Valen-
tinians and the universal essence of the Realists are the same actor
in different costumes. All things proceed from the one as they do
from the other, and such origin is conceived either by resort to a
greater degree of personification, as in generation by the Aeons, or
by dispensing with personification, as in Abelard's "accidents of the
universal essence." One may add, ifone chooses, Hesiod's Chaos or
any other entity of the sort; for, whether all things proceed from an
Abyss, from universals, from a Chaos, or from some other such
entity, the
same sentiments are satisfied and one gets theories that
various persons will accept according to their individual preferences.
1672. Transformation of metaphors not into persons as just
fectly explains the identification of the maleach with God Himself. . There are
. .
passages, nevertheless, where God and His maleach are contradistinguished as two
IIO8 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1673
traces of are detectable in Fourier's mythology. In the Valentinian
it
Gnosis, as we have
just seen, metaphors are mixed and mingled
with
them. Comte, for his part, first tries to keep them distinct, then
combines them, and ends in personification pure and simple. Meta-
phorical entities reign sovereign in the theory of solidarity
and
among the Realists.
Merging of metaphor and reality is the rule with persons
1673.
who reason on sentiment. In the case of metaphysical and theological
dreamers things, symbols, metaphors, allegories, all make one jum-
ble in themind. It is out of the question to reason in earnest with
people who use terms so vague, so nebulous, that not even they
know what they mean. Here, for instance, is M. Leon Bourgeois,
who expatiates, mouth agape, on the notions implicit in his concept
of interdependence, as "filling the moral idea with a new content."
That string of words means exactly nothing: M. Bourgeois's moral
idea is filled with a new content in the same way that Sige was
fertilized by the Abyss of the Gnostics. Had he lived in the day of
the Valentinians M. Bourgeois might perhaps have personified his
1
metaphors.
1674. All these types of verbal derivations with metaphors are of
common use in metaphysics oftentimes they predominate over
everything else and in the metaphysical parts of theologies, where,
however, they are generally incidental. word awakens certain A
different persons, and on one occasion the identification and distinction stand side
by side in the same passage. An angel of Jehovah, also called a Man of God, appears
to Samson's parents (Judges 13:3, 6f.). He is definitely distinguished from Jehovah
(13:8 f.; i6:i8f.); yet after his disappearance, Manoah says to his wife (13:22):
'We we have seen God/ Theologians have been to great
shall surely die, because
divergent conclusions.'* And how otherwise, when they go looking for a single
objective thing where all there is is a multiplicity of subjective things? Dugas-
Montbel, in his Observations sur I'lliade, Vol. I, pp. 145-46 (Iliad, III, v. 105), notes
"
of an expression used by Homer: 'Fetch the might of Priam hither' means 'Fetch
Priam hither.' In thesame way Homer says 'might of Hercules' for 'Hercules.' The
term isfrequent in Homer, and many other poets have imitated it from him. .
. .
The Latins have similar locutions, using, that is, a distinctive trait of the person for
the person himself. Thence doubtless have come such locutions in our modern
. . .
"
languages as 'his Majesty,' 'his Eminence,' 'his Grace,' 'his Highness.'
*
1673 Essai d'une philosophic dc la solidaritc, p. 38: "We change nothing, I
again insist, in and right; but to follow an ex-
those general principles of morality
pression that I have kept and which admirably expresses what we have in mind,
1676 VOGUE OF DERIVATIONS 1 1
09
sentiments; it is transformed into a thing; and, thereupon, one
readily believes that the sentiments so awakened are produced by
that thing. Poetry, literature, eloquence, even ordinary conversa-
the concepts that we have derived from our recognition of the interdependence that
prevails among men fill as M. Darlu says fill the moral idea with a content alto-
gether new." So then the general principles of morality are in no way changed,
but the moral idea is nevertheless filled with an entirely new content! If it is new,
one would expect it to show some change, as compared with the old; and if there
has been no change, how on earth can it be new? The brain that can make head
or tail of that isa brain indeed. Bourgeois further explains: "There is something in
these facts that clarifies and broadens old conceptions of right, duty, justice." So
then, it was not true that nothing had been changed! The change would lie in that
very "broadening"!
11 10 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1677
into
specially stirred in other words, Class II residues are brought
play. The sixth type and, in more general terms, metaphysical
ally they survived but for very brief periods of time and won
rela-
tively few adherents. Religions that have endured for long periods
of time and enjoyed large followings must have realized their pur-
passed upon them in their relations to reality, and that not only as
point of its accord with experience and declare that any other way
of regarding it is That theory shocks the
absurd, fatuous, harmful.
sentiments of many people and furthermore does not square with
the facts, which clearly demonstrate that doctrines (derivations)
that transcend experience are expressions of sentiments, and that
these in turn play an important part in determining the social
made until the exposition of theories just given had been completed. Nor shall we
have exhausted the subject when we have made them. It will still remain for us to
study various concomitant fluctuations in the vogue of derivations and in other social
phenomena. To that we shall come in Chapter XII ( 2329 f.).
11 12 THE MIND AND SOCIETY l68l
specifically,
from the close of the eighteenth to the beginning of the
twentieth century, one witnesses a wave of Voltairean scepticism,
and then Rousseau's humanitarianism as a sequel to it; then a re-
ligion of Revolution, and then a return to Christianity; then scep-
ticism once more Positivism; and finally, in our time, the first
society, how
comesf it that it can return to fashion every so often
in the plain good sense of a Lucian, a Montaigne, a Bayle, a Vol-
taire? How comes itthat the progress which cannot be discerned
in social opinions is
indisputably real in the natural sciences ?
1682. If one is disposed ta keep strictly to the facts, an error will
be apparent in both views, in that they both reduce to one unit
things that have to be kept distinct. The accord of a doctrine, or
theory, with fact is one thing; and the social importance of that
doctrine, or theory, quite another. The former may amount to zero,
the latter be very great; but the social significance does not prove
the scientific accord, just as the scientific accord does not prove the
social significance. A
theory may not correspond to objective fact,
may indeed be altogether fantastic from that standpoint, and yet
meantime correspond to subjective facts of great moment to society
( 843). A person aware of the social importance of a mythology will
have that mythology real. A person who denies the truth of a
mythology will deny its social value. But the facts clearly show
also
that mythologies have no reality and at the same time have the great-
est social importance. Feelings are so strong on this point that people
are persuaded that the day of the mythologies is definitely over, that
myths are but ghostly memories of a past for ever dead, and so
1681 l
We shall study them in their general traits hereafter ( 2329 f.).
1683 VOGUE OF DERIVATIONS 11 13
vast in numbers which
deliberately shut their eyes to facts truly
show that mythologies are still alive and flourishing. So also there
are who believe that the achievements of logico-experimental
people
science in the course of these many centuries amount to nothing,
and that to know realities we can again go back to the dreams of a
Plato revamped by a Hegel.
1683. The fluctuations observable in social opinions result theo-
retically (234of.)
from a clash of two opposing forces: the cor-
respondence of the derivations with realityon the one hand, and
their social utility on the other. If the two things cogged together
perfectly,
a continuous movement
ultimately leading to the absolute
predominance of the resultant of the two forces would not be im-
possible;
but since, instead of working in harmony, they are dis-
cordant, antagonistic, and since both a complete desertion of reality
and a complete disregard of social utilities remain if not impossible,
at least difficult, it necessarily follows that in regard to social mat-
ters theory oscillates like a pendulum, now swinging in one direc-
tion, now in the other. That is not the case with the natural sciences,
because the theories of mathematics, chemistry, astronomy, and so
on, have in our day at least a scant, if any, bearing on social ques-
tions ; and so the pendulum swings farther and farther in the direc-
tion of logico-experimental science, without encountering any force,
or at least any appreciable force ( 617), tending to push it back in
the direction of metaphysical, theological, or like derivations. Such
forces have manifested themselves in certain instances in times past,
as in ancient Athenian prosecutions for impiety or in the case of
part, in the
matter because such forces did not correspond to
sentiments with which men could not dispense short of serious
1
alterations in the social equilibrium.
*
1683 There are
still traces of such forces, nevertheless,
owing to the fact that
individuals who
devote themselves to the natural sciences live in the same world as
other men and cannot altogether escape being influenced by the various oscillations
that disturb it. So at the present time a counter-offensive by metaphysics is observ-
able in the theories of mechanics. Examine, for instance, Lemeray, Le principe de
relativite, pp. 98, 31. The author has been examining a hypothetical case where two
observers, both in motion, exchange signals by carrier pigeon and adds: "Now the
11 14 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1684
1684. Some reader may perhaps have regarded my exposition of
Gnosticism just above as quite superfluous and have asked: What
has such nonsense got to do with sociology ? Such nonsense enters the
field of
sociology because it
expresses sentiments that are still
power-
fully active in present-day society. Even disregarding such mani-
festations as the theories of Saint-Simon, Fourier, Comte, or humani-
we can any day, in England and the United States,
tarian Socialism,
observe the appearance and prosperous growth of Christian sects
which, from the experimental standpoint, are no less absurd than
Gnosticism; and to such Anglo-Saxon phenomena we must add the
neo-Buddhism, the Theosophy, the Spiritualism, the Occultism, that
have been winning converts all over Europe. Anyone desirous of
convincing himself that moderns are no whit less adroit than the
ancients in peddling balderdash as sublime truth need read, among
the hosts of books available, only a volume by Sinnett on Esoteric
Buddhism}'
conclusion we have just reached as regards the pigeons the principle refuses to ac-
cept in the case of light. [And of course we can only bow the knee to the will of
Monsieur Principe.] In fact, the two relations (i) give us T and T 2 as functions
of T and v: we might decide, that is, which of the two observers was at rest vis-a-vis
of space a proposition that has no meaning [Exactly what used to be said of
not a few propositions that are now commonplaces.], just as in the case of the
pigeons, the relations (i) show which of the observers is at rest vis-a-vis of the
Earth." This argument starts on a par with many other metaphysical reasonings
for a few examples see
492-506 except that it has been decorated with mathe-
matical embellishments. But mathematics cannot themselves confer reality upon a
hypothesis that is devoid of any! Among the implications of the "principle of rela-
tivity"one notes "that different observers of one system [one of two systems in
motion] on seeing one same observer from the other system go by, will note that
he goes less rapidly than they; and one observer, seeing the different observers of
the other go by in succession, will note that they age more rapidly than he." The
system where one ages less rapidly will be in danger of overcrowding by women
they will flock to it as to a bargain-counter. Once one goes excursioning outside the
experimental world, it is certain enough that one can prove anything one chooses.
Since my aim in these volumes is not to preach, but merely to look for the uni-
formities that prevail among social facts, I may without harm, and in fact I must,
keep the pendulum altogether swung in the direction in which it swings in the
natural sciences ( 86,1403).
1
1684 Pp. 47-48: "By what prophetic instinct Shakespeare pitched upon 7 as the
number which best suited his fantastic classification of the ages of man a question
is
with which we need not be much concerned, but certain it is that he could not have
made a more felicitous choice. In periods of seven the evolution of the races of man
may be traced, and the actual number of the objective worlds that constitute our
system, and of which the Earth is one is seven also. Remember, the occult scientists
1685 DERIVATIONS IV-$l VERBAL PROOFS 1 1
15
1685. in the habit of holding with the hare and
Renan was always
running with the hounds. After describing the nonsense of the
Gnostics and telling the touching story of Sophia's passion, he some-
what inadequately states a notion that has its element of truth when
he praises such portions of those ancient fancies as tended to exhila-
rate certain sentiments. He would have been much closer to the
factshad he expressed himself subjectively instead of objectively, and
said that the sentiments which were satisfied by Hesiod's Theogony
and other such productions, as well as by the Gnostic myths which
he, Renan, describes, are still active in many people of our day and
know this as a fact, just as the physical scientists know for a fact that the spectrum
consists of seven colours, and the musical scale of seven tones. There are seven king-
doms of Nature not three, as modern science has imperfectly classified them. . . .
Seven rounds have to be accomplished before the destinies of our system arc worked
out. The round that is at present going on is the fourth. ... An individual unit,
on arriving on a planet for the first time, has to work through seven races on that
planet before he passes on to the next, and each of those races occupies the Earth for
a long time." How many fine things such good people know! But there sit the neo-
1
Hegelians, telling us that "there is no thought that is error" ( 1686 ). So the
"thought" of these Buddhists cannot be error; and if anyone should dispute that
and give a preference to neo-Hcgelian thought, who on earth would there be to
settle the quarrel ?
*
1685 p. 175: "There is surely an element of greatness
Renan, L'cglise chrctienne,
in these strange myths. [Instead of making an objective assertion of that sort Renan
should have said: "There are people who find something great in such myths, and
that fact should be taken into account even by people who consider them fatuous
absurdities."] When one is dealing with the infinite, with things that can be seen
but through a glass darkly, with things that cannot be said in words without falsi-
fying them [A detour designed to give the impression that he is returning to the
experimentalfield while carefully keeping outside of it.], pathos even has its charm.
[For some people, not for others.] One enjoys it as one enjoys an unhealthy poem,
of which one disapproves as taste, but which one cannot but find stirring. [That
may be true of Renan and of people like him. It was not true of Lucian nor of
people like Lucian. The usual error of representing what is subjective as objective.]
The history of the world conceived as the agitation of an embryo aspiring to life,
painfully attaining to consciousness, disturbing everything by its contortions, its very
travail serving as the cause of its progress and tending to the full realization of
vague yearnings for the ideal that would be a fair picture of the story we tell at
IIl6 THE MIND AND SOCIETY l686
1686. IV-s: Vague, indefinite terms corresponding to nothing
concrete. This isthe extreme limit in verbal derivation, and it ends
1
as a mere jingle of words. Among such derivations a few are for
the consumption of the ignorant, who halt in stupefaction before
the strangeness of the terms, and imagine that they must conceal
2
some profound mystery. Most, however, are for the use of meta-
physicists, who feed on them day in and day out and end by imag-
ining that they stand for real things. The torrent of such verbiage
rushes tumultuously down across the ages from a remote antiquity
to our own day. Sometimes it swells, overflows, floods everything;
then again it shrinks to the confines of itsnormal bed; but it per-
sists at any rate, and
shows that it
that must satisfy some human
3
need, as do songs, poetry, romance. Every age has its fads as to
"superare" (to overpass) and its derivatives "super atari" (those who
"
overpass) and superamento" (the act of overpassing) are being
times to express our views on the development of the infinite." Who is "we"?
Surely not everybody! There are plenty of people who care not a fig about the "de-
velopment of the infinite"; many others who do not know what that jabberwock
may be, and still others who laugh aloud at mere mention of its name.
x
1686 Voce, Jan. 28, 1914 (Fazio-Allmayer is analyzing Gentile's Riforma della
dialettica hegeliana): "Gentile's philosophy is a living philosophy, it is an ethical
vision of the world. He has therefore felt no need of elucidating the import of this
identity of history and philosophy. The philosophy that is identical with history is
the philosophy which is life, and that life is the ethical life, and the ethical life is
the realization of liberty, and liberty is the assertion of the real as self-consciousness.
The fundamental new
history is that thought is act, in other words,
thesis of this
concrcteness, and that therefore there is no thought which is error and no nature
which is not thought. Thought-act, the actuality of thought, actual idealism, have
now become terms that everyone thinks he readily understands [No, no, no! There
are plenty of peoplewho are sure they understand not a syllable in such jumbles of
words.], but which, alas, go wandering meaningless about the philosophical world
of today. The ease with which some people think they have disposed of them is a
sign of that."
1686 2 There is a story, truth or fiction as it may be, that one day the French
"spiritual." They
stand in antithesis to various words in a bad
sense: "dead," "static" (and "stasis"), "mechanical," from which last,
physical derivations comes into clear prominence. Allmayer knows what the con-
clusion of the proof is to be. All that is looking for is the proof. Just how he
he
knows that his proposition is so sound neither Hegel nor any other philosopher
if
has ever been able to prove it is not so clear. May it not, perchance, be a matter of
faith?
1686 4 Cf. Natoli, Voce, Dec. 19, 1912: "Few writers have, within such a brief
time since the publication of a book, aroused to any extent comparable with Croce,
along with admiration, a vague feeling of discontent, a vague, almost abstract,
"
yearning for 'overpassing.' In Croce's defence against his "overpassers," one might
aptly quote a remark he made in the Vocc some time ago such a remark as he
only could make on this matter of "overpassing": "These fine terms, 'overpass,'
'overpassing,' and so on, have as much meaning as the words 'funicoli, junicola' in
the Neapolitan song only the Neapolitan song is less tiresome and more intelli-
gible."
1686 5
PI a ton in Independance, February, 1913 (pp. 85-86): "How warmly
M. Sabatier glows at the spectacle of history! Overflowing with satisfaction, full of
himself, he cries, L'orientation religieuse de la France actuelle, pp. 153, 156, 159:
'We have introduced the concept of Life into history, and that simple introduction
of Life into History socializes history in all directions, makes it over into a philos-
ophy, a religion, an ethical system [And also a thing devoid of meaning.], a foun-
dation of foundations for individual political education.* Or again: 'We are par-
takers of the Truth, of the Life, of the Revelation. The Church had talked to
. , .
IIl8 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY l686
that,you will also be clever enough to squeeze some sense out of the
following lines from Swinburne's "Nephelidia":
Surely no spirit
or sense of a soul that was soft to the
spirit
and soul of our senses
Sweetens the stress of surprising suspicion that sobs in the
that
Aristophanes, Ranae, vv. 1195-1242, says in ridicule of Euripides
after almost any one of his verses one may add, by way of con-
clusion: "He lost his bottle." In just that way any word that has
us of tradition and of its value in religious instruction. To us life reveals its power
in all spheres,and showing us what we are, suggests to us all what we ought and
1
arc able to become. Well, let M. Sabaticr glow and gloat we have nothing to say
on that point. That is an aesthetic matter. But let him try to 'make history over
into a philosophy, a religion, an ethical system/ and it becomes an altogether dif-
ferent matter. That and no other is the question at issue between him and the
Papacy. What is the position of the Papacy, except that history needs a philosophy,
a religion, an ethical system in order to be an 'acceptable history/ a history worthy
of man and humanity?" Logico-experimental science is entirely neutral in that dis-
a third kind, and it is the only kind in which experimental science can take any
interest: it is the kind of history that purposes solely to describe the facts and to
discover the uniformities that prevail among them. Pray note that in so saying, we
are distinguishing, not comparing. We are not in the least saying that this third
iswelcome to join our company. Anyone not sharing it had better seek other com-
pany and we will have two watch-fires. In M. Sabaticr's text the word "life" is
written sometimes with a capital sometimes with a small initial. The things those
two forms stand for are probably different; but just what the difference is, I could
not say; and one may wonder whether the writer who used them would be able to
do so either. I would guess, merely, that the "Life" which is honoured with a capi-
tal initial must be something better than the "life" which is not so decorated. There
may be the same difference between M. Sabatier's "History" and his "history." As
for "Truth," she is an old acquaintance of ours, and we have encountered her fre-
quently in these pages. She is a creature who has nothing whatever to do with ex-
perimental truth; but she is of a nature so lofty that her beauty transcends all things.
l686 DERIVATIONS IV-Ft VERBAL PROOFS .TI2I
"typize" as well! [The passage from Swinburne, above, was ingeniously found by
Mr. Bongiorno. Pareto had used a nonsense rhyme that has been current for a
generation in Italy, and which seems to emanate from some comic weekly:
"Come nave che esce dal porto
navigando con passo scozzesc,
c lo stcsso che prendere tin morto
per pagarlo alia fine del mcse."
M. Boven, Traite, pp. 1108-09, substituted the pleading of the two lords before
Pantagruel, Rabelais, (Euvres, Paris, 1854, pp. 110-13. A. L.]
CHAPTER XI
nary empiricism deals with- the two problems at one time, either
failing to distinguish themor distinguishing them inadequately
gible. A. L.]
2
1688 [The "manifestation" would really be a "derivative" ( 868), and why
Pareto discards that term, which is quite his own, for an obscurer "manifestation"
must remain a mystery. C/. 1826. A. L.]
1 122 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1689
we are using it here. Take, for instance, "natural law," or the "law
of nations." In the minds of vast numbers of persons the concepts
of certain relationships between human beings are welcomed as
agreeable, whereas the concepts of certain other relationships are
rejected as disagreeable. Concepts of the former type do not differ
very widely from certain other concepts that are commonly desig-
nated by the adjectives "good," "honest," "just," whereas they con-
flict with the
concepts designated by the opposite adjectives, "bad,"
"dishonest," "unjust." Now
there is nothing wrong in designating
that first group of concepts, vague as
they are, by the expression
"natural law," nor in describing the situation by the statement that
the concept of natural law "exists in the minds of men." But from
that point people go on to conclude that the thing called natural
law must necessarily exist, and that the only question is to discover
what and define accurately. If we were to meet that
it is it view
with the theory that "subjective existence" docs not necessarily
imply "objective existence," we should be involving ourselves in a
metaphysical argument the sort of thing we are trying to avoid.
Our answer quite another.
is It is, in the main, that in the statements
dent that the Powers in question were able to do what they pleased
with the "law of nations." But they could not have done what they
pleased with reactions in chemistry. With all their armies and navies
they could not have kept sodium chloride in solution from precipitat-
ing a solution of silver nitrate.
From the practical standpoint, therefore, there is an essential dif-
ference between the two cases in question. The "existence" of sodium
chloride and other chemical bodies is one thing, the "existence" of
"natural law," the "law of nations," or other entities of the kind is
quite another thing. And likewise different in the two cases are the
logical inferences that may be drawn from them. In chemistry I
name is given. A
practical test can be made of that, and it will be
seen to succeed. Moreover one may draw the inference from that fact
that in arguing with certain persons in the intent of persuading
them, it would be well to take account of the fact that that concept
is
present in their minds. And there too the practical test turns out
well. That is why the powerful, instead of saying simply that they
want a thing, go to the trouble of devising sophistries to show that
they "have a right" to it: they imitate the wolfs palaver with the
lamb. The proposition that natural law "exists" in the minds of men
is therefore of the same character as the assertion that the
concept
of sodium chloride "exists" in the minds of certain men, except that
the latter statement is
something much more definite. Likewise
similar the proposition that a thing called sodium chloride "exists."
is
l
1689 An official communique issued by the Russian Government to justify its
veto of the Montenegrin occupation of Scutari was couched in the following lan-
guage: "Furthermore the population of Scutari is in the majority Albanian and that
city is the see of a Catholic bishopric. It must, in this connexion, also not be over-
looked that the Montenegrins have never been able to assimilate several thousands
of Catholic or Mussulman Albanians who have settled on the frontiers of Monte-
negro." Substitute Russia for Montenegro, and Poland for Albania in the argument.
Its validity will of course not be altered. Russia is Orthodox, Poland is Catholic,
that the propositions directly contrary to those three are in accord with the facts,
namely: (i) that the concept of natural law "exists" (i.e., is present), though in a
very indefinite way, in the minds of certain men; (2) that that concept (or rather,
the fact that that concept is present in the minds of certain men) plays a part in
determining the form of society; (3) that in many cases, the fact that such a con-
cept has been present in the minds of certain men has been beneficial to society. Let
us add one more: (4) that the belief that natural law "exists" (or the belief that
the concept of "natural law" can play in an argument the part that is played by
concepts such as sodium chloride) has frequently proved beneficial to society,
though such belief is in complete disaccord with the facts.
3
1689 Mctaphysicists and literary economists have hit on a very pretty derivation
to meet objections of this type. They say that economic, moral, and social "laws"
differ from "natural laws" in that they have exceptions, while the latter do not.
Suppose we disregard the consideration that a "law" that has exceptions, that is to
may have its exceptions, he can always meet every fact that is adduced against him
with the excuse that it is an "exception," and he will never be caught in the wrong.
And that is exactly what literary economists, moralists, and mctaphysicists do: They
proclaim "laws" and then do what they please with them, taking advantage of in-
dcfinitencss in terms, exceptions, and other subterfuges of the kind, to bend their
laws to their every wish and whim.
Unfortunately for their thesis they are altogether too right if they follow that
path: a law of that kind has no significance, and knowledge of it is not of the
slightest use. A
person might say that it rains only on even days in the calendar
and then meet facts to the contrary by saying that rains on odd days are exceptions.
Another might assert that it rains only on odd days, and meet objections in the
same way. Reasoning in that fashion, both would be right, and neither "law" would
teach one a single thing. To make it helpful, there has to be some obstacle, a re-
striction of some sort on the free manipulation of the "law." One might assert
that the facts against the "law" are much less numerous than the facts in favour
of it. The "law" has to be stated in language definite enough to be interpreted by
persons other than the author of it. The conditions considered necessary for the
verification of the "law" have to be at least suggested. And so on and so forth.
1 1 26 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1690
termine what actually happens. We regard them merely as mani-
4
festations of sentiments.
1690. Returning to the matter of our modes of expression, we
must further note that since sentiments are manifested by residues
we shall often, for the sake of brevity, use x the word "residues" as
VIII, as belonging to that group of things which can be used in determining what
actually happens. For the same reason, in Chapters IX and X we studied the dis-
guises under which such sentiments are hidden from view. And in doing that we
were following the procedure of the scientist who first determines the composition
of a chemical body, and then the form in which it crystallizes.
1690 PROPERTIES OF RESIDUES AND DERIVATIONS 1
127
some, and altogether pedantic to be for ever talking with such
prolixity.
That is why we replace the proposition just stated with its
shorter original form: "Residues are among the elements that de-
1
termine the social equilibrium."
Derivations also manifest sentiments. Directly, they manifest the
sentiments that correspond to the residues in which they origi-
nate. Indirectly they manifest sentiments through the residues that
serve for purposes of derivation. But to speak of derivations in place
of the residues they manifest, as is done in ordinary parlance, might
lead to serious misapprehensions, and we shall refrain from doing
so in all cases where any doubt as to the
meaning of a statement is
possible.
The subject being very important, it will not come amiss to offer
some further elucidation. We observe, for example, a number of
cases in which a hen defends her chicks, and we epitomize our
observation of past facts, our forecast of future facts, and our guess
at a uniformity, by
saying that "the hen defends her chicks," that
present in the hen is a sentiment that prompts her to defend her
chicks, that that defence is the consequence of a given psychic state.
So we observe a number of cases in which certain individuals sacri-
fice their lives for their countries and we epitomize our observation
;
of the past fact, our forecast of future fact, and our conception of a
things which we associate with the facts that are observable when
1690
2
Between the statements D and the conduct A there may be a direct rela-
tion, DA. the only relation envisaged by people who reduce all social
That, in fact, is
phenomena to logical conduct. But the actual relation, as a rule, is different: that is
to say, both statements and conduct have a common origin, O. Such common origin,
which is generally unknown, may be called a "sentiment/* a "psychic state," or
something but to give an un-
else of the sort;
known thing a name does not in the least
increase our knowledge of it.
One might further assume that D stands for
residues and A for derivations, and repeat the
above: Residues and derivations have a com-
mon origin, O, unknown. To get at the resi-
dues we establish, theoretically, a relation AD;
and then, to get the derivations from the resi-
get farther and farther away from it: i. Observable side by side are
and expressions of approval or praise
acts of self-sacrifice for country
for such acts. Such expressions have an element in common. We call
it a residue. 2. Human
beings sacrifice themselves for country and
have a sentiment, manifested by residues, which spurs them to such
conduct. The divergence from reality lies in the term "sentiment,"
which has an element of vagueness. Then again, the uniformity is
stated without limitations, whereas some limitation is essential.
dues, D, and of the derivations, or conduct, A; but in by far the greater number of
cases, we know very much what the philologist knows: that is to say, only the deri-
vations, or conduct, A, whence, theoretically, we infer the residues, D, and then re-
deduce from the residues, D, the derivations and conduct, A, considering, in other
words, the relations AD and DA, though the actual relations remain OA and OD.
Many many investigations in sociology are like philological speculations as to the
"origins" of languages. They aim at discovering the "origins" of social phenomena,
and so have been of little use to science.
Our aim in these volumes is to constitute a science of sociology by stopping at
residues just as the philologist stops at roots, the chemist at elements (simple
fice themselves. ... In that we get very very far from reality,
the term "because" that appears in it. The term "sentiments," "resi-
dues," and so on, are convenient makeshifts in sociology, just as
the term "force" has proved convenient in mechanics. They may be
used without untoward results if the realities to which they corre-
phenomena (2329). A
Figure 22
that is vir-
phenomenoi^
tually constant is not represented by a straight line, mn (Figure 22),
but by an undulating curve, svt. A phenomenon of increasing in-
*
1691 The difficulty lies in the ambiguity of the term "strong." It may apply to
the intensity of a residue in an individual as compared with the intensity of other
residues in the same individual, or as compared with the intensity of the same resi-
due in other individuals.
However, we cannot go too far in this direction, for we lack as yet a the-
*
1692
ory for the division of society into classes. Here, therefore, we can merely broach
1132 THE MIND AND SOCIETY
Figure 23
ing at historical societies as facts, without any concern, for the pres-
ent, with origins. Observable in such historical societies are phe-
nomena that vary little in substance, but widely in forms. As the
various religions succeed one another in history, their forms may
be as different as one please, but after all they are all expressions of
religious sentiments that vary but slightly. The same may
be said
of the various forms of government, each of which explicitly or im-
differing from the code that the God of the Israelites proclaimed for
His people, or the code that the Christians received from their God ;
1695
x
We
have already given many examples. Here is another that may serve as
typical of a very very large class. The derivations it uses serve, in general, for other
cases without end.
The use of absinth had been prohibited in Switzerland, and Swiss temperance
fanatics were vexed because the courts were not showing themselves very severe in
dealing with violations. A newspaper wrote in that connexion: "Under a system of
absolute monarchy, the will of a single individual is forced upon a whole nation.
That single will may offend the sentiment of a people. It may flout legitimate tra-
ditions and customs. It may be in arrears or in advance of the
period in which it is
manifested. When a divergence of views arises between a monarch and his people,
it becomes difficult to enforce the law. Quite otherwise the situation in a
republic.
There the people is the sovereign. Its rulers are not forced upon it it chooses them
itself. And under the system of direct
democracy, a system such as ours, the citizens
themselves determine the constitutional principles on which the country is to be
governed. The constitution cannot be amended without the assent of the majority
of the voters, who are always consulted in such a matter. The laws themselves,
which are worked out by legislative bodies after public discussion and within con-
stitutional limits, become obligatory only when the people has approved them for-
of initiative in legislation. So all the legal provisions that govern the conditions of
social life are passed through the sieve of public discussion. Only those measures
acquire force of law which correspond to the will of the people at the moment of
their proposal. All antiquated conceptions are thrust aside, premature reforms are
postponed. General obedience is required only of those laws and constitutional prin-
ciples which have found favour with the majority of voters."
A number of points deserve comment here. i. The careless attitude, as usual, of
religions towards facts. Let us accept for the moment the comparison that is set up
between the bad laws that presumably are peculiar to absolute monarchies, and the
excellent laws that certainly, according to this editor, arc peculiar to democracies.
From that it would follow that Roman law as exemplified in the imperial Institutes
should be greatly inferior to Athenian law. But is that really the case? 2. The fal-
lacy, verywidely resorted to, whereby "the people" is confused with a "majority of
the people" and what is even worse with a "majority of the voters." As a matter
of fact the prohibition of absinth was not voted by the majority of the Swiss people,
but by a majority of the small fraction of that people which participated in the
voting. How in the world that number, which was much smaller than the majority
of the people, becomes equivalent to "the people," is a mystery that may well
stand on a par with the mystery of the Holy Trinity. And how in the world
the will of that small number becomes equivalent to the "will" of "the whole
people" is another mystery, less mysterious, to be sure, than the one just mentioned,
but fairly mysterious at that. It may be said that citizens who did not vote were
wrong in not doing so, and that may well be; but it is not the point in question
here. They may be as much at fault as one please; there may be excellent legal
reasons why their preferences should not be taken into consideration; but all that
1
134 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1695
ages to the temples of Aesculapius in order to regain their health.
They were succeeded in the Middle Ages by devout Christians who
prayed to their saints for health and visited shrines and relics. Now-
adays they would recognize descendants in the throngs that flock
to Lourdes, in the devotees of "Christian Science," or even in those
humbler souls who fatten the purses of medical have quacks. We
no accurate statistics to show the exact numbers of such persons and
therefore whether and to what extent their relative
proportion to
population has changed. Certain it is that the proportion has been
and remains a very considerable one, that it has never been and is
does not change a minority of a "people" into a majority, nor reveal what the will
of those who were guilty of not voting actually was, great though their crime may
have been in not doing so. 3. The derivation which assumes that a person belonging
to a community can be oppressed only by an absolute sovereign, never by a majority
of which he is not a
part. The justification for such a distinction is to be found only
in a "divine right of the majority," or
something of the sort. If an individual is
absolutely averse to doing a certain thing, and disregarding the sentiments of rever-
ence in deference to which he subordinates his will to the will of others what
difference can it make to him whether the thing is required of him by a Roman
regularities it refers to the majority, often a very slim majority, of those voting.
4. Thederivation that a person who is forced to act in accord with the will of a
majority even granting that it is the majority that makes the laws acts according
to his own will as the will of the people of whom he is a
part. Take a group of
twenty-one persons. Eleven of them decide to eat the other ten (something of the
sort has actuallyhappened in cases of shipwreck). Shall we say that such a decision
"corresponds to the will of the people," that the people is avro^oppoe self-eating
and that each of the persons eaten will have to say as much before being put to
death, and agree that the "will of the people" is his will? 5. Observable not only
in the case mentioned, but in numberless others, is a theory similar to the Catholic
theory of contrition and attrition ( 1459). ^ is n t enough that the citizen submit
to the will of the majority through fear of the punishments the latter may visit upon,
him; he must also pay worship to its divine will.
As
usual, to avoid misunderstandings, let us caution that all the above has noth-
ing whatever to do with the essentially different question as to whether it may not
be better for a community that the public should be given to understand that such
divine rights exist, and that it be convinced of their existence.
1696 PROPERTIES OF RESIDUES 1
135
not now small. If one may guess that it has decreased in our day as
1696. And to such things still others of the same brand have to
be added. In the temples of Aesculapius treatment was not ex-
clusively a matter of supernatural forces or, if one will, of sugges-
tion ; was often, in parts at least, material and therefore genuinely
it
they a perpetual threat to us, sometimes overwhelming us: their very existence is a
riddle to our reason and an insult to our faith. How can the evil that reigns in the
world under those three forms go back to the Creation? How reconcile it with a
supremely good and powerful God? All the suggestions that have been put forward
to solve that agonizing problem are more indicative of the embarrassment of the
thinkers than satisfying to the intelligence. And now comes Mrs. Eddy and cuts
the Gordian knot with one slash of the sword. Those formidable foes are mere
phantoms. To see them vanish like fog one has only to tear the terrifying mask
from their features and say to each one of them: 'You do not exist/ [A long
theological divagation follows. We need not dwell on it. Let us see what hap-
pens in the real world, pp. 26-27:] The cures of Christian Science are to be counted
by hundreds, thousands, tens of thousands. . Their genuineness is vouched for
. .
by all the guarantees that can reasonably be asked for. [Equally numerous and well
established were ghost phenomena and the feats of witchcraft and magic.] . . .
That is why they meet neither raillery nor incredulousness in Anglo-Saxon coun-
tries. Ever since the third century of our era Christianity has been neglecting its
rights and its duty as regards disease. It is time we were coming to our senses.
That is why on the cover of Science and Health there is a crown hung over a cross
with an inscription written about it: 'Heal the sick, raise the dead, cleanse the leper,
cast out devils.' Mrs. Eddy took that surprising command of the Saviour in earnest
and now rewarded for her trust. Like the Master she is curing 'all
sees herself
sorts of diseases and infirmities/ and her pupils have learned to do likewise." But
she never "mastered well that art" as regards herself. She died! Medice, cura te
tpsum! Some of her disciples, either more stupid or more logical than others, said
that she could not be dead, since that would have been inconsistent with her doc-
trine, which denies the reality of death. They therefore looked for her resurrection.
Needless to say, they are still looking. William James, in a spirit of professional
jealousy perhaps, did not take kindly to Mrs. Eddy. M. Byse talks back to him,
p. 35: "The celebrated psychologist, I am sorry to say, treats this vast and subtle
subject very superficially." Perhaps in fear of the Latin's sense of ridicule, M. Byse
does not go into details as to the manner in which diseases are cured. We
are there-
1136 THE MIND AND SOCIETY l6p6
term of comparison, one might conclude that there has been retro-
gression rather than advance as regards any increase in the scientific
1
element. In the miracles at Lourdes, and in the practices of Christian
Science, there is no trace of medical treatment. Of it, indeed, Chris-
fore obliged to depend on other sources. A correspondent of the Resto del Carlino,
Vol. XXV, No. 330, met devotees of the new science in Berlin. They were people
who were swallowing rigmaroles of the following order: "You say that a tumour
gives you great pain. The tumour is merely a sign of your belief in
pains as caused
by inflammations and swellings, and that belief you call a tumour." Mrs. Eddy, one
may conclude, was a consummate Hegelian, but only as regards diseases, not as
regards money. "Imagine that you are not ill, but be sure to pay in money that
is not imaginary." Mayor, Mary Bafer Eddy, ct la Science chretienne, pp. 123-28,
224-29: "The treatment that is designed to destroy the false belief of the patient
must therefore be purely mental, and partly silent, and it may even be given at a
distance. .Cases have been mentioned where patients have been cured without
. .
even suspecting that they were under treatment. The practitioner mentions dis-
. . .
ease only to deny it, his one purpose being to provoke a realization of its un-
reality. Tumours, ulcers, inflammations, boils, deformed joints, pains of all sorts, are
nothing but depressing images born of the Spirit of Death and to be dissipated by
the Divine Spirit. . . . \Quoting from Mrs. Eddy:~\ 'Summoned for a case of child-
birth, in other words, the birth of a divine idea, the practitioner will try to banish
all preoccupation with material things, that everything may take its course in a nat-
ural manner. Born of the Spirit, born of God, the child cannot cause its mother
. . .
"
pain.' Mrs. Eddy gives her ideas gratis. Now let us see what she takes in return:
"All such books are sold at prices which may seem high in view of the fact that
publication costs have been reduced to a minimum. . . . Book-reviewers [Who were
not at favourable.] have now changed their tune and are showing themselves
first
full of deference for the Mother of the Scientists, who on her side knows how to
appreciate the favours that are done her. . . . The net profits from the sale of the
book that was 'offered to the hungry* [That is what Mrs. Eddy calls her dupes.]
may be estimated at present at about $2,000,000. The author's royalties have
amounted to $1,000,000, the Church's share to $800,000. One may doubt whether
any writer ever earned greater royalties than the Prophetess of idealistic asceticism."
Mrs. Eddy was shrewder or luckier than the run of faith-curers, who also heal all
sorts of diseases. She was certainly luckier than poor Cagliostro and other adven-
turers of that kind. Centuries and centuries have passed since Lucian wrote his
Pseudomantis or False Prophet; but the book is contemporary history of ours, as
true now as ever, in spite of the fact that devotees of the god Progress would
to be seen again on a steel plaque that is fitted to a staff and is held aloft by an
attendant a sort of beadle. The attendants all wear uniforms that are black
throughout, long afternoon-coats that are severely buttoned to the chin. They wear
tall hats, of half-length, with flat brims very much the sort of hat that Alexandre
Duval designed, but minus the suggestion of chic. This forenoon there was a large
audience for the dedication of the Church, all the more since 'Mother' was to work
cures.An old woman, held up by two friends, made her way to a row of seats
appointed for patients in front of the pulpit. Every step she took cost her an effort
and a groan, but her eyes shone with a feverish brilliancy. She walked with
shoulders bent, and was finally settled in a chair. An attendant strikes a gong
three times, some distance apart, as at elevation in the mass. A door opens and
'Mother' appears. She is an old lady neatly dressed in black. Her widow's weeds
are pinned to her bonnet. She walks up the steps to the pulpit, her hands folded.
There she stiffens in an ecstatic pose, then slowly raises her arms and draws them
apart. Her lips mutter incomprehensible words. Then she brings her hands to-
them first to the right, then to the left, then throws herself flat on
gether, darts
the platform, face down. That is the whole show. Resuming her normal self,
'Mother' walks down the stairs and leaves the auditorium, followed by 'Father,'
who has stood motionless near the pulpit in an inspired attitude during this whole
'consultation.' 'Mother's' destination is a wooden shack behind the church, some-
thing like the tool-houses where city gardeners keep their tools. The aged patient
musters all her will and rises; but her exhilaration has vanished suddenly. She
leaves as she came, supported by her two friends. A young woman takes her
1138 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1697
1697. It is further to be noted that the treatments practised in
the temples of Aesculapius are not completely represented in modern
times by the miracles at Lourdes, the treatments of Christian Science,
and other phenomena of the kind. To such are still to be added the
practices of those medical quacks whom Daudet happily
many
dubbed "deathers" ("morticoles"). In their regard the credulity of
the ancients has its
perfect counterpart in the credulity of
the
moderns. At no time in history have quacks flourished more abun-
dantly on the money of simpletons than they do today; and in many
countries the law protects such priests of the goddess "Science"
just
as
religiously as it protected priests of the pagan gods of old
sometimes even more gather in droves in those clinics
so. Believers
and sanitoria which are the temples of the modern quack. Some
of them get well, if Mother Nature chances to look upon them
with kindly eye; but all of them contribute to the collection-box
place. She is carrying in her arms a little girl, four or five years old and frightfully
thin. All the life in the child seems to have gathered in her eyes. Her arms and legs
hang listlessly from her body. As she doubles over her mother's left arm she seems
as cloth. Indifferent to everything that is going on around her,
limp as a piece of
she keeps her eyes fixed on the ceiling. The young mother's dismay transpires
through the waxy pallor of her features. She keeps wiping her forehead with her
handkerchief to remove the great drops of sweat that stand out like glass beads.
The same ceremony is repeated: three strokes on the gong, a second appearance
of the old lady, the same scene over again without a single variation it is the
prescription for every case. Then the mother carries her child out again, the same
rag of a girl she had been before. Not a trace of comment in the congregation.
The audience has looked on at
all that in a sort of stupor, a sense of acute distress
checking any thrust of irony. People have gathered in groups on the sidewalks
outside. I hear a fat man with rum on his breath remark to an attendant, 'Why
not, if a person has faith?' Then, locking arms with the other, he adds: 'Come
"
on, copain! Let's have another glass. It will brace us up.'
Every now and then something happens to show the fatuousness of such beliefs.
In 1913 the actress Nuscha Butze-Becrman died in Berlin. Corricre dclla sera,
Dec. 13: "Nuscha had been suffering from diabetes since the previous summer.
She had been under the care of a physician and had followed the prescribed treat-
ment; but later she fell into the hands of a Gcsundbeterin, in other words, one of
those female faith-curers who treat diseases by prayer. The actress neglected her
medical regime and placed her whole reliance on the virtues of will-power and
prayer. She grew steadily worse and a few days ago she was too weak to get to
the theatre. Her practitioner, however, told her that she must not allow herself to
lose heart; that she must always remember that mind knows not pain. She need
simply say a prayer and go to her performance. The actress went, but half-way
through her act collapsed, and never recovered consciousness."
1697 INTENSITIES AND VARIATIONS 1 1
39
among whom, let us not fail to count the pharmacists who sell their
drugs at 1000 per cent profit; and the inventors of those patent
medicines which shoot across the sky of publicity like meteors,
cure every conceivable disease for more or less extensive, and often
very brief, periods of time, and then are gone; not without leav-
ing huge fortunes in the pockets of certain traders on public cre-
dulity who exploit the poor in spirit under the kindly eye of the
legislator. And there isno argument, no fact, however obvious,
however striking, that can avail to open the eyes of the fools who
1
are thus fleeced.
Confessors were accused in days of old of extorting legacies from
the dying under threat of eternal punishment. Today our "deathers"
dies, then fleece his heirs by presenting exorbitant bills for services
Lent, and they collected fees for procuring dispensations from such
1697
2
The tale of Boccaccio, Decameron, I, 6, "in the which an honest man
confounds the wicked hypocrisy of the monks with a witticism" may be applied,
mutatis mutandis, to the hypocrisy of our humanitarian "deathers." The Academy
of Medicine in Paris has asked for a law forbidding pharmacists to fill a doctor's
prescription more than once. The silly rascals who support such measures say that
their aim to safe-guard "hygiene." Really their aim is to safe-guard the pocket-
is
books of the "dcathers," who in that way will get their fee for a new consultation
oppose those among their colleagues who are disposed to force such uncertainties
upon unwilling citizens. That is the case because worship of the god State is re-
quired not only of believers but of sceptics as well.
1
698 THEOSOPHY II4I
changed their forms and are still alive under new guises. From the
Middle Ages on to our time, the influence of magic on human
societies has lessened, even if we reckon in the count its
legacies to
4
1697 In countries where prohibitionist legislation is rife, the "deathers" derive
large incomes from prescriptions for alcoholic beverages, which they pretend are
to be used for medicinal purposes only. That is one of the reasons why so many
doctors are prohibitionists. Cf. Felice Ferrero, in the Corricre della sera, June 2, 1913
(the United States in question) "Tectotalism is so persistent and aggressive, and
:
the bad repute into which it has succeeded in throwing King Alcohol is now so
people who drink feel somehow called upon to explain and almost to offer excuses
when they arc screwing up their courage to perpetrate the dastardly act. Save for the
sacred precincts of the clubs, where things are done behind friendly walls that no
one would dare do in light of day, there is not one man in a thousand who has
the courage to say frankly with Anacreon: 'Let my friends cease annoying me. They
are free to do what they will. As for me, I drink.' There are those who drink 'by
doctor's orders.' There are those who 'do not refuse a glass' for the sake of 'good
fellowship.' There are those who drink 'a sip now and then.' Apparently there is
no one who drinks for the most obvious reason of all the pleasure of taking a
drink." [The late Felice Fcrrcro lived for many years in Middletown, Conn. This
description of the "American" attitude towards drinking, which denizens of the
metropolitan and urban areas of the United States in 1935 may find na'ivc, is very
accurate, so far as my own memory serves, for what one might call the "provincial"
America of twenty years ago. A. L.]
1142 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1699
organization. It is
significant that simple combinations foreign to
scientific experience are far from having disappeared from modern
social life; in fact, they persist in great numbers, thriving in pros-
perous exuberance. Since simple combinations, in great part at least,
are based on 1-5 residues (need for combining residues), it is safe
goes to the goal of our desire, our will. That detachment takes place unconsciously
in everybody; only, some individuals do not suspect any such thing and
consequently
conserve no memory of it, whereas others do remember and regard as a dream the
scenes, the activities, the journeys they knew in the astral body; for man lives on
the astral plane as well as on the physical plane. ..." "Sensitives," advanced me-
diums, psychometrists, occultists,' says Ernest Bosc, Dictionnaire d'orientaUsrne,
d'occultismc ct de psychologic, Vol. I, p. 336, 'can detach their astral, their aetheric,
double from the physical body even while awake, and
adepts or initiates of Occult-
ism who are very advanced are even able with the of the aetheric fluid to ma-
help
terialize the psychic is from the sthulic to
[physique, misprint] body (move that
the astral plane) and appear to friends, acquaintances, strangers, far from their
"
bodies.' Suppose we append a bit of explanation for those who do not know what
the planes in question arc: "Sthtda or Sthule: matter: the Sthulic
plane is the
Physical Plane. The cosmos is made up of seven planes, each divided into
. . .
times, but for the most part they have occupied territory formerly
held by the combinations of trial-and-error empiricism, magic,
mative Plane, whence man gets his astral body. The Kamaloka, or place of passions
and desires, is located on the Astral Plane. To it man repairs, after death. It cor-
responds to the Purgatory of the Catholics." Side by side with these new forms of
old vagaries a few of the old forms here and there themselves survive. Periodically
in the newspapers one read accounts of witches, sorcerers, and other such
may
persons. I select at random from
the Corriere delta sera, Aug. 31, 1913: "Mysterious
Rain of Stones Halted by Sacrifice of Two Cats: At Termo d'Arcola, near La
Spezia, a strange thing recently occurred that has given those innocent ruralites a
great deal to talk about. ... On July 21 last, a certain Irma Dal Padulo, eleven,
while walking home from school noticed that a rain of stones was falling about
her on the deserted country road. The stones had the peculiarity of being very
hot. ... On the following morning, however, the rain began again the moment
the girl rosefrom her bed, and in spite of the vigilance of her parents and neighbors
it lasted almost the whole clay. Wherever the
girl went stones began falling about
her, without however hitting her, and they were always hot. The thing kept up for
several days. Numbers of persons went to the village to witness it,
among them
Signor Luigi Parioli, city councillor of Vezzano Ligurc, two women, and one of
Irma's brothers. [It all reads like a story from the Malleus maleficarum, save that,
with the passing of the years, the Devil has retired, relinquishing his role to spirits.]
Someone suggested [Some Clerical, no doubt.] that the girl be treated with an
exorcism by the village priest; but the exorcism was without result. [How hath the
Devil fallen!] The family could not imagine what saint to turn to next, when a
fellow-townsman [Probably an anti-Clerical certainly a man with a sense of
up-to-clateness.] suggested that a spiritualist seance be held in the Dal Padulo home.
The suggestion was taken, and it seems that the table, speaking in the tiptological
code, ordered that two cats be killed and buried in a certain place. That was
done and the rains ceased forthwith.'*
1
144 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1
70 1
pose, for instance, we consider Class II (group-persistences). The
II-/? variety in that class (relations of living and dead) has by no
means disappeared. Indeed it was through observation of present-
day phenomena that we were able (Chapter VI) to strip it clear
which in former times had hidden it from view.
of the derivations
But there can be no doubt that it figures much less extensively in
our times than in a remote era, when
worship of the dead was
virtually the only cult our Graeco-Latin ancestors knew; or in the
Middle Ages, when the chief concern of the living seems to have
been to endow masses for the dead. We may confidently assert, there-
fore, that the importance of residues of our II-/3 variety has greatly
diminished in the course of the centuries.
1701. But that
falling-off has been balanced, to some extent at
least, by intensifications on the part of other varieties in the same
class, so that the class as a whole has not greatly changed. The gods
of Graeco-Latin polytheism came little by little to the terri-
occupy
tory left vacant by a waning worship of the dead ;
and they in their
turn were displaced by the divinities and saints of
Christianity. In
the sixteenth century the Reformation
waged bitter war on the cult
practised in the Roman Church
of relics, and especially on the rites
for the mitigation of punishments after death. Yet, at bottom, the
Reformation merely replaced the old group-persistences with new
ones. Life at Geneva under Calvin was much less free, much more
extensively governed by ultra-experimental considerations, than life
in Rome ever had been under the rule of the
Popes; and taken all
in all, Protestantism was much more narrow-minded, much more
positivistic
humanitarianism receded a little. Socialistic
religious
sentiment lost
ground, as did also, and to a greater extent indeed,
x
1702 For many such people Christ has been stripped of all divine attributes and
is to be applauded only as a Socialist or humanitarian teacher. Not a few go
farther still. In November, 1912, while the Balkan War was raging and Christians
under Turkish rule were trying to rid themselves of Mussulman oppression, an
internationalist Socialist congress convened at Basel to pass furious resolutions de-
nouncing that war. One of the most influential orators there was Jaurcs. He had
already published a number of articles in defence of Turkey. All the same, the
Parochial Council of Basel put the cathedral of that city at the disposal of the
congress, in other words, of people who were defending the Crescent against the
Cross. To be sure, middle-class cowardice, which prompts many individuals to
kotow to the Socialists and become their adulators, had something to do with
such action; but it cannot be taken as the only cause, especially if one consider
the approval of the action of the Catholics that was voiced in many quarters. A
correspondent of the Journal de Geneve wrote from Basel, Nov. 27, 1912: "What
will distinguish the Socialist convention at Basel will be, not so much the lip-service
to humaneness that is paid in its resolutions, as the fact of its gathering in the
and trustful gesture on the part of our religious and political
cathedral, that noble
community towards partisans of peace. . . . That gesture symbolized the city's
attachment not to the revolutionary International but to international peace and
social peace among the classes in the various countries." Now the people who met
in the Basel Cathedral were champions of the "class struggle," which was one of
their dogmas, yet aiding and abetting them is represented as a symbol of "attach-
ment to social peace"! Of the many absurd derivations that we have had occasion
to note in course of these volumes, this certainly is not the least ridiculous. The
Armenian Christians, endured the massacres of Abdul Hamid and then
who first
the massacres of the "Young Turks," might have found the Turkish peace that
was preached from a still-Christian Cathedral at Basel but little different from
what Galgacus (Tacitus, Agricola, 30) said of the Roman peace: "Ubi solitudinem
jaciunt, pacem appellant"!
2
1702 In view of the scant variability of classes of residues taken as a whole,
such a thing might have been foreseen. Cf. my Systemcs, Vol. II, p. 419: "It may
well prove that in certain countries the Nationalists, the Imperialists, and the
Agrarians will be the only parties capable of resisting Socialism, and vice versa.
The choice in that case would be confined to those parties."
1146 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY *73
3
systems emerged from their eclipse, and even magic and astrology
4
again made room for themselves.
1703. The differences in intensityobservable in the increasing
Seeds of Love and Sympathy about One and Win Happiness for Oneself and
Others. Psychic Bureau, 98 rue Blanche, Paris, ist edition, 25,000 copies." Then,
pp. 2-7: "The means that we would reveal to our readers for winning love and
happiness are obtained from magic Perfumes and astrological Stones. . . . The
chief magical perfumes are seven in number. Each of them corresponds to an
essential heavenly body . . the Sun, the heliotrope; the Moon, the iris; Mercury,
.
sweet broom . . . Our readers, men and women, already know how important it
to them. [A reasoning that would seem for all the world to ape Bergson's line of
as the above, but experimentally it stands on a par with it.] . . . What we have
said of perfumes also applies to precious stones. Of all earthly substances none have
party. During the past year only 12,000 new members were enrolled, a ridiculous
figure relatively. Hitherto the number has always exceeded 130,000. Another very
interesting fact: Of the 12,000 new members this year 10,000 are women, a cir-
cumstance that will fill feminists with a very legitimate pride but which gives the
party leaders little cheer, since, in electoral terms at least, they find in this year's
enrolment only two thousand persons who can be accounted as usable material.
In many districts more than a hundred membership has actually decreased, and
the slump affects all parts of Germany but especially Prussia.
"Socialist leaders are trying to find some comforting explanation for this very
alarming development. They say that it may be due to the hard times which
have been afflicting Germany this year. That argument, however, shows not a few
wrinkles. The history of the Socialist party indicates, to the exact contrary, that
during hard times in the past Socialist gains have stood in direct ratio to the
distress and discontent. They also say that 'the party's propaganda in the press
has been neglected.' But another section of the same report shows that expenses
for agitation have been considerably higher this year than in previous years. As
regards the Socialist newspapers, one notes a development that is in perfect harmony
with the slump in new enrolments: subscriptions have fallen off perceptibly. The
Vorwarts alone has lost 8,400 subscribers in the past nine months, and lesser papers
asmany as 5,000. Another circumstance completes the picture of decline in the
German Socialist party: the number of votes it has polled at elections has fallen
off, whereas past years have shown steady increases (up to the fabulous figure of
4,000,000 including sympathizers, of course; for the party has fewer than 1,000,000
actual members). In the thirteen local elections held this year the Socialists have
1148 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1704
cial
religions have been made at the expense of one or more of the
others; but in that country the gains went to Socialism, the losses,
to nationalism and liberalism. Since the
present trend in England,
in one of its
aspects, nationalism, is in a direction counter to the
general trend on the Continent, one may surmise that it will not
hold very long. The transformation of Japan in the course of the
nineteenth century is a most interesting case. There derivations
had, with one single exception, many fewer votes than in past years; and they
were defeated in almost every case. Of course, to infer from all this that the German
Socialist party is falling to pieces would be a gross mistake; but we may assert in
all confidence that having attained its peak in the elections of 1911, Socialist power
is now on
a declining curve. To justify the party's vote in favour of appropriations
for increased armaments, Socialist leaders say that 'had they thrown their
weight
to the Opposition, the Government's bills would have been in danger of defeat,
and that would have meant an immediate dissolution of the Reichstag.' So the
Socialists were against any dissolution of the Reichstag!
They did not care to
enter a general election on a platform that, logically, should have been altogether
in their favour: a billion fornew military expenditures! There could be no clearer
demonstration of the present exhilaration of German national sentiments, and of
the predicament of a Socialist party, which feels that not even under circumstances
so exceptionally favourable could it maintain, in a new struggle, the position that it
won at the last elections through a combination of circumstances which will never
return." [Of this last, really,we cannot be sure. It will all depend on future devel-
opments.]
2
La Mazeliere, Le Japon, Vol. V,
1703 pp. 7-10: "In that country where, for a
moment, everything seemed to be going to pieces, one single institution held its
ground, its enhanced by the collapse of everything else. That was the mon-
prestige
archy, strengthened now by hatred of the foreigner, by revolutionary passions that
had identified the monarchical cause with democratic reforms, by the mystical
character which the Restoration had assumed. There were thirty millions of human
beings who had no religion left and wanted one. So they began worshipping their
Emperor. ... So love of the Emperor was intensified by all other loves, worship
of the Emperor by all other religious aspirations. ... In the turmoil of hatreds
and schisms that had resulted from the strife of civil war, the Imperial cult became
the one focus of union for all Japanese. Officers of foreign armies who saw
. . .
Nogi's soldiers advance to the storming of Port Arthur, or Oku's men at Liao-
Yang, all use the same expression: it was fanaticism." La Mazeliere wrote these
lines in 1910. Two years later, on the death of the Mikado, General Nogi committed
hara-kiri, adding further confirmation to La Mazeliere's picture.
1704 NATIONALISM IN ITALY 1 1
49
for history shows movements of far greater scope and violence but
because it time under our very eyes and we
took place in our own
are therefore better able to sound its character. are not inter- We
ested just here in the role political and financial interests may have
ballot showed 9 'nays,' though, as proved by the official minutes of the session,
22 Deputies who had voted against the bill on roll-call were present. The names
of the 9 who voted 'nay' are of course not known; but it is clear enough that 13
of those who had at first been opposed changed their attitudes and voted for the
bill when they were in a position to cast a secret ballot and were safe from any
group control embarrassing to the free exercise of conscience. This incident
. . .
is unprecedented, unique, and must be taken as the index of a state of mind that is
extraordinarily significant. Evidently those thirteen Deputies did not have the
against the bill and they sacrificed their convictions to appearances. In the secrecy
of the ballot they could be sincere, and then and then only were they sincere [Who
can say that? They might very well have refrained from voting. The truth is they
were spinning like weather-vanes, not knowing where they were at.], dropping
the masks that they had been craftily wearing. But what a humiliation in a courage
so secret!What a confession of weakness in such an act of sincerity!" But after
the elections of 1913 came as usual from the masses a wave of faith; and the
newly elected Deputies showed themselves violent defenders of their party.
*
1705 Among those to be mentioned on the roll of honour as standing faithful
to their professed doctrines and refusing to let themselves be swept away like
chafT in the wind of war enthusiasm, were Deputy Napoleone Colajanni, Edoardo
Giretti, a lawyer, and Professor Arcangelo Ghisleri.
Shortly afterwards, in 1912, the Italian pacifists petitioned the Minister of Public
Instruction "to request teachers in the public schools to give talks on February 22
[the day when the conclusion of peace with Turkey was to be celebrated] showing
how love of peace can and ought to go hand in hand with love of country"
(Corriere dclla sera, Feb. 3, 1912). The minister was well aware of the absurdity
of setting out to glorify a war in the name of peace! He may also have been de-
terred by a sense of the insult he would have been offering to freedom of thought
on the part of Italian school-teachers by requesting them in an official order to
address their pupils in a manner so fraught with bad faith. At any rate he replied
1708 PROPERTIES OF RESIDUES
been opened for her by other countries and very possibly she could
;
not have refrained from doing as she did without serious disadvan-
tage to herself. If that simple truth had been stated, it would have
described the actual causes of what was happening. But the Italian
pacifists saw fit to resort to derivations calculated to satisfy senti-
ments corresponding to Class II residues.
1708. To Sentiments of justice. In the ultimatum sent to
wit: i.
[The spirits of the Romans were enlightened by the same smile as they went about
conquering the Mediterranean world. So was the spirit of Napoleon I as his armies
overran Europe.] But surely, sir, it cannot escape a man of your acuteness that a
public demonstration in favour of peace made at this time would, in spite of any
reservations that might be attached to it, lend itself to distorted and embarrassing
interpretations. . .
[So the Minister dismantles the Professor's derivation.
. But he
has one of his own:] The Romans closed the temple of Janus only when the enemy
had been defeated. So shall we
celebrate the festival of peace once more [Here
perhaps the Minister is somewhat ironical. He too reminds one of the phrase of
Tacitus ( 1702*)] when the blood of our soldiers, the flower of the youth of
Italy, shall have won for our country the recognition of her good right and the
respect of the whole world; and it will be a sincere festival, one deeply felt by all."
Substantially, stripped of its rhetorical frills and furbelows, the Minister's idea was
that there would be plenty of time to glorify peace when war had brought home
all the bacon it was expected to deliver a very sound notion, for that matter.
But it is as old as the world and has been held by very warlike peoples; so that
it was really quite superfluous to fish up a high-sounding theory of pacifism just
1152 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1708
try.
If this be granted, it would be difficult indeed to find one person
in the who is not a pacifist; for, after all, where find
whole world
the dolt to say "I am for war because I believe it will be disastrous
:
pacifists
and non-pacifists is not as to whether a man ought to do
what is beneficial or what is detrimental to his country. The ques-
tion is whether war is at all times harmful, save when
waged in
self-defence, as non-Italian pacifists aver, and as Italian pacifists also
averred before the war of conquest in Tripoli supervened: or
whether wars, even wars of conquest, may not sometimes be bene-
the adversaries of pacifism contend. Similarly there is a real
ficial, as
issue between pacifists and non-pacifists as to whether the rules of
"law" are adequate for settling international quarrels, as the pacifists
assert, or whether, as non-pacifists claim, war is sometimes indis-
say that in the war between Turkey and the Balkan and Hellenic
peoples Holy Progress, and Civilization, Holiest of Holies, were on
the side of Turkey. Finally, if Turkey had to be considered a non-
*
1710 In 1912 the Italian Government withheld its exequatur from Monsignor
Caron, who had been appointed Archbishop of Genoa by the Pope. There seems
to have been quite a story behind the incident. It was hinted that Monsignor Caron
had had a finger in the removal from Genoa of Father Semcria, a clergyman tainted
to some slight extent with Modernism and who had a powerful following among
many ladies highly placed in Genoese society. However, on all that we have no
documents and therefore cannot go into it. We can consider the reasons which a
minister in the then government, Signer Finocchiaro-Aprile, put forward before
the Chamber in its session of Feb. 10, 1913, in justification of the refusal of the
exequatur. He alluded to certain newspapers which were favouring the restoration
of the temporal power, and charged Monsignor Caron without producing any
great proof with aiding and abetting that campaign. And he concluded: "In deal-
ing with circumstances such as those confronting us today, what must prevail over
everything and everybody is a supreme consideration of state interests whereby no
civic recognition can be accorded to anyone who, in a vague hope of restorations
that are impossible, fails to render to the State the homage that is its due." Now in
that we have the statement of a general principle. Had it come from a Prussian
Minister of State there would be nothing to say to it, for in Prussia the Government
does exclude from state offices, including university professorships, all persons who
"fail to render to the State the homage that is its due." But no Italian
politician
can climb as high as a ministerial portfolio and not know that the Italian Gov-
ernment regularly awards appointments to Socialists who declare publicly and re-
peatedly that they are determined to destroy the bourgeois State and that they
1156 THE MIND AND SOCIETY
1711. With
reference to the greater or lesser degree of resistance
offered by the various forms of religious sentiment to the wave of
Nationalism that began to sweep Italy in 1911, it is to be noted that
not a few Socialists remained loyal to their doctrine of opposition to
bourgeois wars. So again almost all the Mazzinian Republicans
stood
firm against what they regarded as a monarchical enterprise. Mean-
time, Italian pacifists turned belligerent in great numbers, while the
humanitarians and the Tolstoyans crawled into their shells and ut-
tered not a sound. That therefore is the order in which those beliefs
political and class "parades" and what the Latins call "manifesta-
tions." Protestants do not go
to mass as Catholics do, but they go to
the prayer-meetings of their several sects (which are often as noisy
as "revivals"), and they join free-thinkers in
swelling audiences at
spiritualistic meetings. English and American Protestants sing
hymns at the
top of their lungs. Many of them break away from
Christian worship; but their old religious fervour merely turns to
"social," humanitarian, patriotic, or nationalist enthusiasms, and of
nourish not "vague hopes of restorations that are impossible" but positive hopes of
downright destruction. The Minister was not telling the exact truth, therefore, in
asserting that his conduct was determined by the general principle he stated. He is
mindful of his principle only when he finds it politically convenient, and forgets it
thing, and it makes him look like the exception that proves the
rule. Careful thinkers who are convinced in their heart of hearts of
the ineptitude of the new
religion dissemble such atheism, just as
their predecessors dissembled unbelief in the
days when it was a
crime to doubt the "truths" of the Christian religion. They speak
of "abuses" in democracy just as people of former times
spoke of
"abuses" in the clergy. They thrash the saddle,
1
knowing well that
thropes," but "the People" has no "rrfisodemes." There is no one bold enough
to display hatred, or antipathy, or repugnance, or even mere indifference, to it. And
all that seems so obvious, so natural, that no one ever
gives a thought to it. Indeed
to mention it seems as useless as to say that a human
being walks on two legs.
1158 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY I
7I3
forms. In times past sentiments of subordination found their expres-
sion in the submissiveness of the lower classes to the higher; today
"The masses need something to worship. The adoration . . . the militants have
for their leaders generally remains a latent thing. It betrays itself in barely percepti-
ble ways, such as the respectful tone in which the leader's name is mentioned. . . .
In 1864 the inhabitants of the Rhine district welcomed Lassalle like a god. . . .
(1892), men and women had an almost supernatural faith in their leaders. Mixing
together in their simple-mindedness the social question and their religious habits,
they often carried crucifixes in their parades side by side with the red flag and
placards inscribed with maxims from Marx. ... In Holland, when Domcla Nieu-
wenhuis, a Deputy, left the prison where he had been confined, he received from
the people, as he himself relates, honours such as no sovereign had ever received.
. . Such attitudes in the masses are observable not only in so called backward coun-
.
tries. . All the proof we need is the idolatry with which the Marxist prophet,
. .
France. Even
manufacturing districts in England the masses at this late day
in the
are still welcoming their leaders with enthusiasms that remind one of the times of
Lassalle. Worship of leaders endures after they have died. The greater among them
are frankly sanctified. Karl Marx himself has not escaped that sort of Socialist
. . .
canonization, and the fanatical zeal with which certain Marxians are still defend-
ing him is something very like the idolizing of Lassalle in a day long past."
Maurice Spronck, Liberte, Nov. 17, 1912. (In France school-teachers were re-
belling against the politicians: the snake had bitten the fakir. Of a session of the
Chamber during which the crisis was under discussion, Spronck writes) : "In the
eloquent but slightly vague address of M. Paul-Boncour one point stands out as
strikingly sound, and we gladly take upon our own shoulders all that the speaker
said as to those responsible for the present unrest in the schools. 'These groups of
teachers/ he declared, 'arose not only with the full knowledge of those in power
but with their full approbation, and not so long ago the annual celebrations they
held were held under the auspices of the men most highly placed under re-
publican rule.' Nothing could hit the nail more squarely on the head. Not only
did high government officials tolerate, not only did they encourage, the develop-
ment of the old-fashioned plodding schoolmaster into a political courtier, but they
did so in terms that in a measure, one must admit, extenuate the worst aberrations,
the most absurd irregularities, in these poor souls who now have to be brought back
to good sense and discipline. No sovereign of the farthermost regions of ancient
Asia was ever courted, flattered, cajoled, boot-licked, as were those unfortunate
1713 PROPERTIES OF RESIDUES 1 159
say nothing of offering open resistance. All of which does not mean
that "the People" of today is not duped, deceived, and exploited by
its leaders as much
Athenian Demos was exploited by syco-
as the
gime is maintained. The fact is well known, and one may find the 3
proofs of it in any number of publications of one sort or another.
young men, who, to the still greater damage of their mental health, had chosen
the honourable profession of instructing the young only to see permanently prostrate
in obeisance before them politicians and would-be politicians in uncountable num-
bers. To make sure of their services at election time, government officials have
literally crawled at their feet. Observe, moreover, that that atmosphere still con-
tinues about the school-teacher, andthat at this very moment when there are signs of
a reaction against an intolerable state of affairs, we are being offered a law that,
under false pretences of protecting a secular school-system, is making a sort of
sacerdotal caste of our teachers, sacrosanct and untouchable." During that same
Deputy reproached the Government for not continuing to blarney
session a Socialist
the school-teachers.M. Compere Morel: "So long as the teachers served the Radical
party, you buried them in flowers. Now that they are deserting you, you are treat-
ing them as enemies [Hisses. Applause] ." In Italy the Government buys the votes
of a number of Socialist Deputies by according pecuniary favours to certain Socialist
cooperatives. A
socialist Deputy in Rome owes his seat to the votes of employees
of the Royal House. Journal des Goncourt, Vol. VIII, p. 22 (Feb. 28, 1889): "I note
in this evening's Temps a sentence addressed to working-men by President Carnot: 'I
thank you from the bottom of my heart for the welcome you have just given me,
my dear friends you are my friends since you are working-men/ [As every-
for
courtiers, say the same things to "the People," which has succeeded the King; and
one may say with Courier: "Chamber, Senate, and Press repeat: 'Master, all is
yours,' which is the politician's way of saying 'All is ours'; for politicians give
all to the People the way courtiers gave all to the princes of yore, and the way
those convictions aspirations which would divide it into parties, and so, on a
and
basis, at the very most, of divisions that are nominal more than anything else, it
lives on in a state of political anaemia. Such being the situation, such the atmos-
phere in political and social life, since some centre must nevertheless be found, it is
sought, naturally, and found in the constituted authority, in the Government, which
exists inevitably and which, in virtue of its control over a whole concatenation
. . .
bers of the Camorra were excused from compliance with the requirements of the
'special surveillance' [probation] to which they had been sentenced. Others received
licences for carrying fire-arms or business licences; still others were placed on parole
from prison or even pardoned outright. Such the soldiers who fought a battle that
was ostensibly being staged in defence of civilized institutions. ... In this un-
confessable enterprise, criminals joined forces with the infantry and cavalry, and
the latter bivouacked about the streets and squares of the city, charging suspicious
voters with galloping horses. ... A
'State Camorra' is certainly something quite
iscertainly an amazing one." Marvasi concludes, p. 283: "I confess that purpose my
has been to call attention to the situation now prevailing in the country in its
bearing on the capitalist system and the political system that are sapping the coun-
try's vitality." In that Marvasi is confusing two things that are entirely distinct:
(i) A description of fact, which seems to be, in great part at least, accurate and
sound; (2) the cause of those facts, which he locates in the "capitalist system."
This latter is an assertion unsupported by scientific proof and it can find its place
only in a Socialist theology.
Facts without number serve to show that for many people in the governing
classes politics is
simply the art of looking out for the interests of certain voters and
the representatives they elect. In them Class I residues are absolutely dominant,
while Class II residues tend to be weak. Many Deputies call themselves anti-
Clericals yet get themselves elected by Clerical votes. Here is an incident that is
1713 MODERN FORMS OF SERVILITY Il6l
venerit" "A city ripe for the destruction and up for sale, if only
it
Bishop to keep a closer eye on the conduct of his Deputy and the scolding has
caused quite a flurry among the Clericals. With that we need not concern our-
selves. What does interest us is the case of the Deputy from Y, for it is just an-
other of those daily incidents to which the political deportment of a number of
pecially legislative, acts corresponding, and you do not find them, unless a fine
chance to do a little anti-Clericalism comes along by refusing Monsignor Caron an
exequatur and so doing a favour to the great majority of Genoese (and Italian)
Catholics! The president of the Catholic Voters' Union has, therefore, it would
seem, made a move towards introducing a little sincerity and honesty into our
electoral morals, and for that our best praise. But we do not believe that he will
at all succeed. This system of double-dealing comes in altogether too handy for
both the Deputies and the Clericals for the Deputies because it assures them
votes; for the Clericals because it assures them that they will be let alone."
For such general situations everybody tries to find particular causes, and finds
one that suits his sentiments. At the present time [1913] in France, many people are
attributing this same evil to the system of electing Deputies by plurality votes; and
they contend that proportional representation would be an effective remedy. Noting
that the Chamber of Deputies never succeeds in approving the budget on time,
Bcrthoulat writes, Libertc, Feb. 18, 1913: "What an arraignment this Chamber of
the plurality ballot (petit scrutin) has made of itself! So, in eight months' time, it
has not been able to patch together a bad budget! We are thinking of appropria-
1 1 62 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY I
7I3
4
could find a buyer." Now and then a "scandal" occurs such as the
tions, the taxation aspect of the subject not having been even broached as yet, for
statesmanship with our district Deputies begins and ends with asking for greater
and greater expenditures to fatten their followings with. All the same,
. . .
what is the essential and abiding justification for the parliament's existence? Is it not
the same which had, in their time, an intermittent
as for the old States General,
mandate protect the taxpayer from the demands of the Crown for money?
to
fief has to have something to feed to his troop of retainers. So they all, one by
one, interminably, have been asking for the floor to be sure of having their share
in the scramble for five billions and a half."
Ciccotti's pamphlet on his experiences at Vicaria ought to be transcribed in its
entirety here, so packed is it with data of the greatest interest to experimental
sociology. Unfortunately we shall have to confine ourselves to the following quota-
tions. Pp. 58-60: "But these increasingly frequent ministerial crises serve to turn
up the man who is shrewdest, most energetic, and most accomplished in applying
the inexhaustible resources of the Government to his own advantage; who gets the
greatest hold on the press by making the wisest use of secret funds; who shows him-
self most adaptable, pliable, and skilful in organizing that chain of patronage
which runs from minister to Deputy and from Deputy to election district; who
tabulates, documents, and files away within reach the 'records' of friends and
enemies alike, so that he may be able to control them and even blackmail them as
occasion arises; who makes friends with people who have connexions at Court;
and who so succeeds in showing himself able, omnipotent, indispensable, and in
creating for himself a title to virtually absolute rule, which, in the form of a more
or less disguised dictatorship, endures for years now under his own name and now
under the names of his figure-heads. Meantime such portion of this interplay
. . .
1713 *Libcrte, Feb. 16, 1913: "Deputy Colly, who never minces words, remarked
yesterday to his colleagues in the Chamber: 'Oh, we have not a very good reputa-
tion in the country at large. But when voters in my district tell me that the parliament
is rotten and the Deputies so many and drunkards, I answer: "If the
roisterers
Deputies are good-for-nothings, the reason is that the voters who elect them are no
" '
whit better." As we have noted often already, such literary phrases, which put a
situation in a nutshell, have the merit of presenting a vivid picture, though the
picture is not altogether exact, overstepping the literal truth now more, now less.
1713 INTENSITIES AND VARIATIONS 1163
tion. Then
shortly the troubled waters return to their customary
calm; and since forces that are constant prevail in the end over
forces that are temporary, the politicians return to their wonted
ways and not infrequently a politician who has been severely dam-
aged by an investigation again is able to become a cabinet minister,
5
and even Premier of a country; and meantime the so-called life-
saving operations that are involved in such things increase the power
of those who hold the whip-hand.
In general, opposition parties are the ones to impute misdeeds to
individuals who are in power, and they believe that in so doing
of combination and makeshift as can and must be exposed to light of clay; that
visibleform which these intrigues, these veerings and tackings, have to assume if
they are to get results and be widened in scope, and all along dissembled; the
manners in which conflicting interests have to compromise, clash, and make up
under the public eye all such things transpire from the debates in the parliament,
from the speeches that are made on that floor. The spoken word is the means of
winning public favour [In more general terms, the derivation is a means of stirring
sentiments.], of attracting, or it may be of diverting, public attention; and, to an
even greater extent, it is a means of simulating and dissimulating, of attacking
and defending. And all that goes on in the realization or semi-realization on the
part of everyone that it is, after all, mere ceremony, mere stage-play. The Deputies
will all tell you, if you ask them, that a speech is not going to change a situation
[They recognize practically the truths that we have been expounding in these
volumes theoretically.^ that it will not shift one vote, not amount in a word to a
tinker's dam. And yet the speaking goes on, in real earnest sometimes. [Derivations
have been used since the beginning of the world.] An ingenuous soul may at times
even have some illusion as to the immediate effects of a speech he has made, while
men of passionate faith cherish the illusion, or comfort themselves with the thought,
that everything comes to an end in the form in which it manifests itself, but that
nothing in the end is lost. . Most parliamentary orators, however, feel more or
. .
less consciously that whenever they make a speech before the Chamber they are
mere actors reciting their parts on a stage." At his trial before the French
Chamber on one occasion on a charge of extorting money from the Panama Com-
pany for political purposes, Rouvier, it will be remembered, retorted: "If I had
not done what I did, not a man of you would be here!" Well known the fact that
the big banks of France are forced to contribute to the election funds of the party
in power, and that some of them also give money to an opposition party that
seems to have a chance of soon assuming power. The funds they use for such
purposes are kept secret, so that the banks will always be in a position to make a
denial if a newspaper, as sometimes happens, gets hold of the facts.
5
1713 See, for example, Palamenghi-Crispi, Giovanni Giolitti. In France Rouvier
became a minister again after the Panama affair. In England Lloyd George re-
tained his post in the cabinet after an investigation of stock speculations which he
had made and denied that he had made, so that he was placed in the position of
having to admit that he had told an untruth.
1164 THE MIND AND SOCIETY I
7I4
to drive such men from office. Friends of the victims issue denials,
look about for extenuating circumstances, or, with greater success,
find ways of "hushing everything up." Individuals who know the
ins and outs of the government admit the wrongdoing when they
are speaking as man to man with their friends; but they add that
such things do not make it any the less to the public interest that
6
their friends should be kept in power. Needless to say, when an
condemning or approving the facts alluded to from the standpoint of social utility.
All that we have proved is that the arguments which are used to disguise such
facts are, as a rule, derivations.
*
1714 Not a few election districts in Southern Italy are veritable fiefs and some-
thing of the sort is observable in France. Gazette de Lausanne, Nov. 22, 1912 (article
by F. C.) 'The trial that has
:
just taken place before the Yonne Criminal Sessions
throws a distressing light on political morals in the French departments. ... In
the little district capital of Courson-les-Carrieres, two lists of candidates were com-
peting at the last municipal elections, one headed by the retiring mayor, M. Bou-
quet, Councillor-General, the other by M. Jobier, Sr., conservator of mortgages in
Paris. The day before elections, M. Jobier went to a little hamlet in the district to
hold a meeting. On his way back to his home he passed a number of gangs of ruf-
fians of more or less threatening demeanour. Chancing to step aside from his com-
pany for a moment, he was struck from behind with a cudgel that stretched him
on the ground in a serious condition. His son rushed to his side, found him in a
pool of blood, and started in pursuit of the ruffians, discharging in their direction
a revolver he was carrying on his person. The bullet hit a bakery-worker, one Sali-
got, killing him instantly. The Yonne jury acquitted young Jobier, who, however,
had spent several months in prison awaiting trial. . . Everywhere the same situ-
.
ation seems to prevail. In the Municipal Council yesterday a member on the Right
raised the issue of the poor-relief budget in connexion with the conduct of the poor-
children's physician for the Commune of Etang-sur-Arroux (a good name for a
1714 MODERN FEUDALISM 1165
feudalism the lords called their vassals together to
wage a war, and
if
they won, they paid them in booty. In our
day, politicians and
labour leaders operate in the very same
way. They marshal their
gangs at election time ( 2265) to browbeat their opponents and so
procure the advantages that go to the winning side. In the old days
vassals refusing to follow their lords to war were
punished, just as
the crumiri in Italy, the yellows (black sheep,
blacklegs) in Eng-
land, the foxes (renards) in France, the "scabs" in the United States,
are punished today for
refusing to march in industrial wars. The
feelings that are aroused in loyal "militants" today by the "treason"
of these people who refuse to be organized are exactly the feelings
that people in the Middle Ages felt for the
"felony" of a vassal. The
privileges that the nobles enjoyed in those old days have their coun-
terparts in the immunities as regards the courts and the tax-collector
which are at present enjoyed by Deputies to the parliament and in
backwoods' constituency). The doctor had exerted pressure on voters by threat-
ening to withdraw from them the children in his charge if they voted the wrong
way. The charge was so strongly substantiated that the Council of the Prefec-
ture felt obliged to quash the election, though it is not much inclined to take
such measures. Naturally when M. Billard brought the matter up on the floor, the
members on the Left began crying 'slander,' but, unluckily for them, a Socialist
who chanced to be a native of the district in question rose from his bench and de-
clared that the facts were exactly as charged. M. Mesureur had to back down, beat
about the bush, beg that such an exception not be taken as the rule, give his
word of honour that the bureau's physicians in the majority were meticulously loyal
to their professional obligations. But that is not so. The placing of homeless chil-
dren is a well-known device for influencing elections. It is cynically practised and
oftentimes admitted. The Department of Public Charities, under the presidency of
one of the outstanding Freemasons of the day, has become a mere vote-factory. . . .
Returning to the case of young Jobier the boy did what he did at one of those
moments when there is no weighing of pros and contras, when one listens to in-
stinct in its most spontaneous and praiseworthy impulses. In similar circumstances
I am sure that anyone would have done what he did. But that is not the
question:
the drama has its lessons. The court trial showed that at Courson-les-Carrieres politi-
cal passions had been whetted to a paroxysm. It was shown that members of the
Councillor-General's party had been singing songs in which the elder Jobier was
referred to as 'Cholera,' and that not a few had gone so far as to say, 'We've got
to kill the Jobiers.' On the other hand, the prosecution described the chief of the
Jobier dynasty as a 'tough old bird,' a tyrannical old man in whom ambition stopped
at nothing. Why, in any event, were all those people fighting so
bitterly? For ideas?
By no means They all held the same ideas. They were Radical-Socialists on both
1
sides. Indeed the onewho stood farthest to the Left was a conservator (of mort-
gages, at least!). They were fighting for the possession of power, for the possession
of the town hall! An unpleasant job, the town hall! Agreed! But in a social
system
1 1 66 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY I
7I5
smaller but by no means inconsiderable measure by such of their
2
constituents as are on the side of the party in power.
1715. In olden times the requirement of
uniformity asserted itself
in certain regards; nowadays it asserts itself in certain other regards,
but the requirement is still there. Requirement of uniformity as re-
From the 6,ooo-lire level there is an abrupt drop to 4,000 and under, and then on
down to a minimum of 1,000 lire.'* Engineers and architects: "They are few in
number, and only one of them has any considerable income (25,000 lire)." num- A
ber of the Deputies mentioned in the list are well-known men; and it is a matter
of common knowledge that their professions yield them larger incomes than the
amounts declared, twice as much, three times as much, perhaps five times as much.
The same applies to members of the Italian Senate. How comes it that members of
the parliament can get such false returns accepted by the tax authorities? A writer in
the same paper (Oct. 12, 1913) explains the mystery: "In connexion with our ad-
vance notice on the results of the interesting investigation which the Riforma sociale
will publish in its forthcoming issue, Signer Antonio Corvini, president of the Direct
1715 PROPERTIES OF RESIDUES 1167
and hours during which a man may work. The ancient Roman was
required to respect official worship, but he could drink as
he pleased.
Today not a few countries have abandoned official worship (or at
least lay no upon it) but forbid the use of alcoholic beverages.
stress
any sense of tenderness or any reverential fears as regards Deputies and Senators. If,
therefore, the low tax-assessments of many such gentlemen are to be deplored, the
blame must be placed on other procedures and other persons. The public should
know, in fact, that if the Commissioner fixes a definite sum as an acceptable income
for a person, that person has the right to appeal to one or more higher commissions,
which are the final, and not always the dispassionate and disinterested judges in the
controversy. Unfortunately, in Italy such local and provincial Appeal Commissions
are direct creations of local party organizations, these in their turn being creatures
of the Deputy or Senator, who thus obtains, without any angelic benevolence on
the part of the tax commission, anything he wishes, or anything he believes to be
fair to himself. There is one defect that is common to the whole administrative
paying personal property taxes on returns that were evidently lower than their
actual incomes. His remarks attracted harsh retorts and criticisms altogether irrele-
vant to the matter in hand; but no one dared deny or even question the truth of
the charges.
x
1715 In Italy, in 1910, the Knight Commander Calabrese, Deputy Crown's
Attorney and chairman of a subcommittee for the drafting of a bill relative to con-
trol of the press, proposed requiring that bonds of from 500 to 10,000 lire should
public peace, good morals, and civic and domestic virtue." Such commissions were
to serve their decisions by constable on editors and managing editors of newspapers,
who would be required to print them in the next following issue of their paper
under penalty of a fine of 200 lire. Commendatore Calabrese even played school-
master to the proposed commissions as to manner of procedure and wrote: "Instead
of striving to exert a calming influence upon the public, instead of acting as a mod-
erator, the present-day newspaper capitalizes and whets public excitabilides. It seems
to me to give excessive relief to anything that is dramatic, passionate, or romantic,
stressing criminal trials and murders, even if they take place in the backwoods of
China or Patagonia." It might be objected that one swallow does not make a spring-
time, and that the whims and fancies that chance to flit through one eccentric mind
should not be taken too seriously. But these pleasant contrivances of Calabrese
prompted the Corriere d* Italia to make a reportorial investigation, and many per-
sons of prominence were found to sympathize with Calabrese's general feeling,
though differing with him as to means. So the swallows were not just one, but a
whole flock. Said Senator Filomusi-Guelfi, a professor of the philosophy of law:
"My work as a philosopher and jurist is based upon the fundamental concept that
law has its basis in morality; and it therefore seems logical that any attack made
upon morality should be dealt with by law. And since the press in our day is miss-
ing no occasion or pretext for violating the norms of morality, the conduct of the
press ought also to be subjected to some new and more effective sanction. For us
Italians censorship has an odious past, an unpleasant tradition. It reminds us of old
errors, old oppressions, old and outlandish intolerances. It recalls Spain to our minds
and the era of Spanish influence. In a word, its efficacy is always an open question.
In my opinion, therefore, what we need is not a censorship. We need to think up
more energetic laws, measures that will provide for exemplary sentences and punish-
ments for the more characteristic violations of the rules and laws that safe-guard
morality. In my opinion the law should adopt a frankly punitive attitude, which,
from the very nature of the juridical factor, would prove to be spontaneously pre-
ventive."
In June, 1914, a Republican newspaper in Ancona published an article that seems
to have been held offensive to the memory of Victor Emmanuel II, who, to tell the
truth, now belongs to history. Had the article been taken for what it was, a political
utterance, the newspaper could not have been confiscated; and had the authorities
chosen to prosecute, they would have had to bring the case before Criminal Sessions,
where, in all probability, the paper would have been acquitted. By a clever sleight-
of-hand, the Government chose to view the article as an "offence against decency,"
at the very least changing what was secondary into what was primary. In so doing,
it was
able to suppress the paper, have it convicted by government judges, and, in
addition, behind closed doors. It is interesting that when, under identical circum-
stances in France in the days of the Restoration, Courier was accused of "offending
public morals" by publishing a pamphlet that was obviously political, the Govern-
ment did not dare conduct his trial behind closed doors.
1715 DUMAS'S "CAMILLE" 1169
cence of prosecutions of that type. The criticisms that are being
made in France of literary productions styled "immoral" recall,
though in a much less marked degree, the attacks that were made
on the Camillc (La dame aux camelias) of Alexandre Dumas the
2
younger. In England a bishop rises to criticize the songs of Gaby
2
1715 The censorship made three reports advising prohibition of the production
of the play,which was finally allowed by Minister Morny. La censure sous Napoleon
III. La dame aux camelias, Vol. I, p. 10: "This summary, though very incomplete
in the twin respect of the incidents and the scandalous details that enliven the plot,
will none the less suffice to show how very shocking this play is from the standpoint
of public decency and morality. It is a picture in which the choice of characters and
the baldness of the colouring overstep the most liberal limits of what can be toler-
ated on the stage."
Yet nowadays the play is produced everywhere without being found in the least
shocking. The history of La dame aux camelias is an interesting example of the
utter fatuousness of the effortsgovernments sometimes put forth to influence morals
by attacking derivations ( 1833). Hallays-Dabot, La censure dramatique et le the-
atre, p. 15: "Camille was long under the ban. A revolution was required to get it on
the stage. The coup d'etat of December 2 and the advent of M. de Morny to the min-
istry determined its fate. By our time [1871] the public has grown familiar with
spectacles of an equivocal world that has invaded and one might almost say ab-
sorbed the stage in the course of the past eighteen years. But twenty years ago
. , .
vice had a less brazen, more homelike demeanour, manifesting to a certain extent
its shame for its degradation. The numberless reclamations of lost women in the
now republican, according to the party in power." And p. 220: "Under the Empire
[Napoleon I], the censorship was supported by the public in efforts to purify its
stage morals. A
strange reaction had occurred. For more than ten years past the
theatres in Paris had been showing every conceivable debauch of the imagination,
all conceivable shamelcssness. Now lassitude, disgust, had laid hold on audiences,
and they rapidly slipped down the opposite incline till they had now reached an
intolerant prudery. [The case of our virtuists today.] The better-educated kept all
their admiration for great tragic sorrows. The masses would listen only to heavy
sobbing melodrama. People no longer cared to laugh. And it is curious to see how
uneasy the censorship grew at this prudery in the theatre public."
Dumas's play has been the bete noire of no end of writers who are labouring
under the illusion that morality can be enforced by suppressing this or that deriva-
tion. Vicl Castel, Memoires stir le rcgne de Napoleon 111, Vol. II, pp. 34-36, Wednes-
day, Feb. ii [1852]: "Last evening I attended the production of a play of Alex-
andre Dumas the younger, ai. the Vaudeville. Our theatres are subject to a censor-
ship that is established for the purpose of obliging them to respect decency, good
morals, and public respectability. [In his memoirs, Viel Castel describes the "good
morals" of his time as extraordinarily bad.] The play in question, La dame aux
II7O TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY I
7I5
Deslys, and
would have them kept from the public. These, at bot-
tom, are all expressions of one same sentiment: an inclination on
the part of certain individuals to force their own "morality" upon
others. Among such are many hypocrites, but also many persons
who are acting in all faith. The state of mind of these latter
good
seems to be as follows: They have within them a number of group-
persistences,
which are so active and powerful as entirely to control
their minds. That is what we call "faith." The objects of such faiths
In 1913 the French Academy refused to participate in the observance of die bi-
centenary of Diderot. Perhaps we ought to thank the Academy for not resolving
that his works should be burned and people put into prison for daring to prefer
them to the insipidities of not a few Academicians one might mention.
3
1715 It is a curious fact that when their own faiths are not concerned
practical
men sometimes perceive these truths quite clearly. Bismarck, Gedanl^cn und Erin-
nerungcn, p. 499 (Butler, Vol. II, p. 169): "In politics as in the religious sphere,
the conservative can meet the liberal, the royalist the republican, the believer the
unbeliever, only with one theme that has been bandied about with all the countless
1
716 INTENSITIES AND VARIATIONS 1 171
variations of eloquence [That utterly simple remark contains the germ of our whole
theory of residues and derivations.] 'My political convictions are sound, yours are
:
false,' 'My belief is pleasing in God's sight, your unbelief leads to damnation.' It is
understandable, therefore, that religious wars should arise from differences of reli-
gious opinions and that party struggles in politics, even if they are not settled by
civilwar, should at least result in the suppression of those limits which the decency
and well-mannered people maintain in the social life that is foreign
self-respect of
to politics."Bismarck was thinking particularly of politics, but his remark applies
to the domains of religion, morality, and so on, just as well. And he concludes very
truly: "But the moment a man can say to his conscience or to his group that he is
acting in the interest of his party [In the general form, "of his own faith."], any
infamy is winked at as permissible or at least excusable."
l
1716 Examine almost any catalogue of books and pamphlets of our day, and
one will find any number devoted to ways and means of helping criminals, or effect-
ing their moral reform, or to proposals of new measures in their favour, such as
pardon laws, indeterminate sentences, probation, non-registration of sentences in
judicial records, and so on. But look for books or pamphlets devoted to saving
honest men from murderers, thieves, and other criminals and one will find but
1172 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1716
the "rights of society" as against the individual when it is a question
of fleecing their neighbours of their possessions, and the "right of
the individual" as against society when it is a question of safe-guard-
ing the criminal one of the many cases where contradictory deriva-
tions be seen in use by the same individual at the same time.
may
We must not, however, stop at derivations. have to go on to We
look for the sentiments that they veil. In this case they are evident
tain his purpose in two ways: i. He can have the law award him
possession of the object, and for that purpose it is better for him to
appeal to the rights of the majority as against the minority, a notion
2
that he states as a right of "society" as against the "individual." 2.
persons claim that it is proper to rob people who are very rich and possess great
fortunes though they have never worked. . Those who say that are wrong. Un-
. .
doubtedly it is NOT JUST that one should be rich without working. Neither is it just
that those who workshould be poor, and everybody should wish there should be a
change in that. But for a change to come, it is sufficient to elect Deputies and Sena-
tors who are friends of the working-men who are poor. Such Deputies will then
make laws so that each person will be more or less rich according to the way he
works. Meantime the rich must not be robbed."
Note that the reason given for refraining from theft is merely one of expediency:
1716 "INDIVIDUAL" AND "SOCIETY" 1173
He can appropriate the thing directly.
But in that case, John Doe
no longer member of the more populous class of society, but of
is a
the least populous. The democratic derivation cannot therefore be
used as it was before. One may use the term "poor" as equivalent to
the term "society," but however great the sottishness and stupidity
that wins acceptance for certain derivations, the term "society" can-
not possibly be equated with our estimable criminal class. Another
derivation has therefore to be devised for the purpose; and it is
8
let
society go to smash, but let no innocent man be harmed." If
it is better not to lay hands directly, just now, on what in a short time will be ob-
tained through the law. The opinion expressed in this manual of Bayet's is impor-
tant because the book is in general use in elementary schools in France and because
a law has been proposed that punishes anyone venturing to condemn the instruction
furnished in the lay schools too openly by imprisonment for from six to thirty days
and by a fine of from 16 to 300 francs. Commenting on this law, which was
. . .
est expression of feeling. The moral sense implies, however, a profound respect, and
a great love, for society. But what respect, I ask you, what love, could this woman
have for society? What did society ever do for her? When
the moral sense is miss-
ing, the responsibility nearly always lies with society, as a biological consequence, I
mean. She is also subject to hysteria, to hysteria in that broad sense, as Professor
P has told you, which makes her unstable, changeable, in all her ideas, there
being no organization of them; and her mental products are the result of that very
disorganization.' [Suppose we agree that "the responsibility lies with society" every
time some criminal is found wanting in a moral sense. But is "society'* also respon-
x
sibleevery time an alienist is found wanting in a scientific sense ( 1766 ) ? Even
the testimony of the expert for the prosecution had so little to do with medical sci-
ence that he earned a reprimand from the presiding judge. Said he:] 'I should have
preferred not to appear in this case, but since I could not get excused, I am forced
to open my remarks by drawing a picture that will bring out the moral physiog-
nomy of this wretched woman and set the environment in which she grew up in
its true light. You have heard how she was cared for as a child
by a certain woman
named Giordano, who took her into her home and played the part of step-mother
in her life. The Giordano woman had none of the tenderness of a mother, and the
poor child in her charge was frequently obliged to go without food, endure all
sorts of ill treatment, and listen to the degrading insult that she was
nothing but
4
1716 Similar things are also observable in other countries. As above noted
( 1638), many people go looking about for historic convicts to "rehabilitate," with
the idea of attracting attention to themselves and so winning fame and profit. Of
the attempted "rehabilitation" of the Lafarge woman, Maurice Spronck writes in
Liberte, Feb. 5, 1913: "In Mussulman countries there are monks, the 'howling' or
'spinning' dervishes, whose main occupation consists of whirling, on certain occa-
sions, round and round and faster and faster like a top, shouting meantime at the
top of their lungs, Allah ou! Allah out Sooner or later, those who practise this
noisy rotative gymnastic fall into a pious trance where they see the gardens and
cool springs of Mohammed's Paradise and houris waiting on the faithful.
Anybody
can see that after a person has spun and shouted long enough, he ought to be able
to see almost anything he chooses. In the same
way, when people have shivered and
shouted long enough over some criminal case they know nothing in particular
about, they are very likely to enter a state of beatitude where all sorts of hallucina-
tions are possible. Justice and Truth descend from the clouds,
Light sets itself in
motion. This is the lay form of ecstasy, the only kind of ecstasy becoming to scien-
tific minds
emancipated from all outworn superstitions. The only question of any
importance now is to decide whether Mme. Lafarge makes a good subject for the
cultivation of ecstatic crises. We, personally, are not so sure. In the first
place she
has been dead quite some time. The few pictures we have of her show her gowned
in a fashion long out of date. Besides, it is hard to unchain
any very profound pas-
sions of a political or religious character in connexion with her adventures. Most
line. You are to state the facts on which you base your findings.' Professor P : 'But
the facts have been stated in the evidence. I am concerned to get a complete picture
of the defendant before the Court.' The Court: 'But that is permissible only on the
basis of sworn testimony.' Professor P :
'Very well, I will say nothing of her early
help and guidance along the pathway of life. So she found herself alone in the
world, and that first day, she appealed to a girl friend to help her get to France
to look for an uncle, her mother's brother. But that favour she could not obtain.
Instead she went to Turin, where she found work as a maid. But she was not fitted
for such work .' The Court: 'But who told
. .
you all that?' Professor P : 'Mile.
Farneris herself.' The Court: 'Well?' Professor P (continuing): 'Her mistress was
a quick-tempered woman. One day she threw a candlestick at her. Mile. Farneris
fled the house, and she met a man on the staircase.' The Court: 'But you cannot say
such things! How
can you possibly continue in that fashion?'"
In any event, we still have not been shown why people who, be it through fault
of "society/* happen to be "wanting in a moral sense" should be allowed freely to
walk the streets, killing anybody they please, and so saddling on one unlucky indi-
vidual the task of paying for a "fault" that is common to all the members of "soci-
ety." If our humanitarians would but grant that these estimable individuals who
are lacking in a moral sense as a result of "society's shortcomings" should be made
number of priests, which one of our literary reviews has just published. What can
one expect to do with a woman who is not even a victim of the Jesuits? Careful
study of her case might have attracted the attention of specialists in the history of
manners or in psychology. That was already a distressingly small group. As it is,
the 'review' of her case, worked up in public meetings, will attract only a few
'intellectuals' from among the Anarchists a slender phalanx, and all the slenderer
since said 'intellectuals/ really, are finding in the ordinary course of our daily life
far more exciting occasions for exercising their wits and coddling their tempera-
ments. At this very moment
number of them are founding an association to estab-
a
lish the right of any make his abode a place of refuge for a murderer or
citizen to
burglar the moment he makes profession of Anarchistic faith. In days like these,
with that perfect security in the streets with which the emasculation of crime-
repression has blessed us, no more timely measure could indeed be imagined. The
protectors and friends of our more formidable cut-throats certainly ought to be
assured that they have the protection of the law and that the police are not to be
allowed to molest them. One such philanthropist at least is at present seated in the
pen in Criminal Sessions on a charge of complicity after the fact in a murder. Obvi-
ously the jury finds him guilty, it will be a much more timely task to rehabilitate
if
that pleasant character than to go bothering about Mme. Lafarge and the exact
always unmitigated evils; and if she saw and heard what came of it all, she must
have understood that if once upon a time the converted sinner was with some reason
preferred to the spotless soul, nowadays, thanks to this new religion of the god
Progress, conversion is no longer necessary. In fact, the Giornalc d'ltalia reports
the sequel of the story in the following terms: "Naples, May 30. Our readers will
remember the language in which the President of the Assizes exhorted Mile. Villes-
preux, immediately after her acquittal, to take up a life of work that would redeem
her. They will also remember how a committee of society ladies interested them-
selves in procuring her admittance to a shelter that looks after women released from
prison. That day Mile. Villespreux excused herself with a few words of thanks, ex-
plaining that she had to go back to the prison for her clothes. But on leaving the
prison again, she refused to accompany the representatives of the shelter and went
away alone. Nothing more was heard of her that day; but the next it was learned
that she had gone back to the via Chiaia, next door to the house where Ettore
Turdo was killed and in the very house of the man who had testified at the trial
that Yvonne was a good girl and that she stopped with him whenever she returned
to Naples from her trips to music-halls in other cities. That was the house she went
to after being acquitted of a crime and after, as she said, thirty-eight months of
mourning for poor Turdo. But after all, why should all that be wrong, or rather,
why should such a thing be taken in an unfavourable sense? Mile. Farneris still has
time to devote herself to work and to begin her life of redemption, starting perhaps
from the very house where she should have closed her life of shame. However, we
should be failing in a duty were we to refrain from reporting this last phase of her
melodrama, just as during the trial we reported everything that tended to favour
her acquittal. The news, we might add, has occasioned great surprise about town."
Those who were surprised must have been either very great humanitarians or very
great fools. Or maybe both.
1716 "INDIVIDUAL" AND "SOCIETY" 1177
very considerable proportions are sentiments of individual integrity.
As regards the second, there may be, in the case of this or that poli-
tician, some idea of winning the favour of certain criminals of ex-
days later, more dead than alive, by some Spanish fisherman who set him ashore
near Valencia. Pavier lived from then on by stealing. He soon reached the frontier,
made his way across France carefully steering clear of Saint-Denis, and stopped at
Lille in June, 1912. There he was arrested for stealing food and was given six days
in jail, though nothing was discovered as to his record. Thereafter Pavicr settled at
Villers-Saint-Paul, near Creil, getting a job in a factory located near the railway line
that runs from Creil to Compiegne and working there three months. It was at Vil-
lers that Some days ago he makes a point of his influential con-
he was arrested.
nexions Pavicr wrote to a Deputy to ask whether the parliament had not passed
an amnesty bill covering offences such as his. The Deputy very politely answered
that no amnesty had been voted and ended his letter with urgent advice that his
correspondent should be extra careful if he did not wish to be found out. The
Deputy's letter fell into the hands of the police and that was the way Pavier was
discovered."
Liberte, Apr. 6, 1912, "Marne Rioters Pardoned." The article is too long to be
transcribed entire, though that would be valuable as showing the general features of
such cases, which are to be observed not only in France but in Italy and other coun-
tries. We suppress proper names. One of the chief mistakes people make in such
matters blame some specific individual for things that are consequences of the
is to
way in which society is organized. The person in question here was a cabinet min-
ister. "After he had kept an eye on the progress of the judiciary investigation and
narrowed the circle of penal severity to a number of heads that had been lifted too
conspicuously against the background of fire that had consumed mansions and wine-
cellars, it still devolved upon him to rescue the last soldiers of the riot who had
been condemned in the courts of the Marnc and in the Assizes at Douai. Now that
has been attended to. Not one breaker of hogsheads, not one plunderer is left in
the jails of the Republic. Senator X
has paid his debt of political gratitude to the
rioters. judiciary investigation of these disturbances and crimes was a calvary
The
of anguish. Taking things in their order: the complaint was filed with the guardian
of seals at the time, M. Perrier May 20, 1911. The papers did not reach the prose-
1178 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1716
volved, and if the derivation is used, it obviously must correspond
to the sentiments of a large number of individuals. Such sentiments
are mainly sentiments of personal integrity, which, it is felt, must
not be offended even in the case of a criminal. Never in any period
of history have criminals been allowed to be insolent to their judges
as they are in our time. There are trials in criminal courts today
where the roles of the presiding judge who
questions and the de-
6
fendant who answers seem to be inverted. This view of the matter
till a week or ten days later, since the order of the investigating judge
cutor's office
was not handed up till June 3. What state were they in when they reached Rheims?
The Government had prevented several important documents from coming into the
hands of the investigating judge during the inquest. Did it not make sure as to
anything tending to show political responsibilities in the affair? In any event, de-
spite the manoeuvres of M. Valle and the governmental pressure, which echoed to
the very doors of the inquest, some dozens of the rioters were remanded to the
Assizes or tried before lower criminal courts. Seven were convicted at Douai and
sentenced to terms varying from four years down to a month. The Appellate Divi-
sion, for its part, affirmed thirteen sentences imposed by the lower courts, raising
seven of them from ten to eighteen months. And what are we to say of the
. . .
acts that brought their authors before the bar of justice? The reviewing orders of
the Court of Assizes and the indictments and complaints against the rioters tell the
story. The first was accused of deliberately setting fire to the Gallois house and of
pillaging in the Bissinger house. He was seen on the roof of the former 'tearing up
and throwing lighted grape-vines inside the building/ Fire broke out at once
tiles
and the house was burned to the ground. The second was accused of pillaging in
the houses. . . . 'Red flag in hand, he led the rioters to the doors of the houses,'
and they were broken in. The third worked for two hours at the safe in the Bis-
singer house before he finally succeeded in getting into it with the help of a
pickax. Then he burned deeds, account-books, and all business papers. The fourth
lent a hand in the sacking of the Bissinger house. The fifth led the sacking of the
Ayala and Deutz houses, breaking down a picket-fence to get into those places. . . .
The pardons were dated February 9. On February 15, acts of sabotage at Pommery,
on the twenty-first, twenty-second and twenty-fifth, further sabotage at Hautvilliers,
Cumieres, and other places."
Such the currency in which politicians pay their constituents, exactly as brigand
chieftains used to pay their confederates.
1716
6
We will say nothing of certain cases, such as that of Mme. Steinheil, where
the defendant enjoys political "influence" or the protection of persons highly placed.
They have no bearing on the point here at issue. But in other cases, where no such
patronage or "influence" figures, defendants may be seen "talking down'* to judges
on the bench. Just one example from the record of the trial of the Bonnot-Garmer
"gang," Paris, February, 1913: "Q. The Court: You were being persecuted in your
home town because of your ideas? A. \Callemin, alias Raymond La Science}: You
said this was not a political case. Yet you do nothing but talk politics Anarchism.
Q. You mean I am inconsistent. Well, what do I care? I choose to conduct my ex-
amination of you the way I please. A. Well, I will not answer then, whenever /
please that's all. Q. That is your look-out. [In fact Callemin lets a number of
1718 INTENSITIES AND VARIATIONS 1 1 79
is further confirmed by the extraordinary repugnance people of our
time feel for corporal punishments, which are
falling into disuse
for the sole reason that they are insulting to "human dignity/' be-
integrity.
To conclude, then: Considering substance rather than the deriva-
tions that disguise it, it would seem that in our day Class resi- V
dues (personal integrity) have rather augmented than diminished
in intensity as compared with the residues of our Class IV (so-
ciality),
1717. The residues of our Class VI
(sex) are probably among the
least variable of residues. There are
changes in the veilings that dis-
guise them, and changes also in the amount of hypocrisy they pro-
voke; but np appreciable changes are apparent as regards substance
(1379*.)-
17J8. For a given society, therefore, we may establish the follow-
(i) Classes of residues; (2) the genera in such classes; (3) deriva-
tions. A
graph (Figure 24) may make the relations between classes
and genera clearer. The movement in time of a class of residues
increase, is
represented by AB; and the same movement in the gen-
era, some of which are increasing, others diminishing, by ab, xy.
The variation represented by AB
is much less wide than the varia-
questions pass without an answer. Then come other questions, which he answers
with his usual insolence. The Court questions the veracity of one such answer, and
Callcmin flics into a fury.] The Court: I am doing my duty. Callemin: But not
fairly. Someone wrote somewhere: 'I call a cat a cat and Rollet a rascal!' You are
acting, you are, in the complctest bad faith. The Court: Your insults do not affect
me." In olden days steps would have been taken immediately to halt such behaviour
towards a court. At a certain point in the examination of another defendant, the
attorney for the defence also took a hand at berating the same unlucky judge: "The
court-room is in a hubbub to a purport that is not quite clear. Presiding justice
Cominaud decides to stop it: The Court: I cannot allow demonstrations against these
defendants. Maitre de Moro-Giafferi: They are demonstrating against yon. This is
an audience of admirable generosity [sic,not "imbecility*'!]. The Court: I cannot
allow demonstrations either for me or for or against you." Truth compels me to
add that Judge Cominaud was not even jailed for contempt.
Il8o THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1718
some of the genera, ab, xy.
tions in On the whole, there is a certain
Figure 24
compare the position r with the position s, to get the general trend
of the residue, one would conclude that the sentiment was
growing
in intensity, whereas the line xy shows that, on the
average and in
general, there is a diminishing intensity. And similarly if one were
position v one would register an
to compare the position s with the
development is
susceptible of measurement and we have observa-
tions
extending over long periods of time, it is
fairly easy to
elimi-
nate such difficulties.
By interpolation one may determine the line,
xy, about which the intensity is fluctuating and so discover its mean
2
general direction. This is much more difficult when accurate meas-
*
1718 Cf. Pareto, Manuale, VII, 47.
2
1718 One is sometimes able to push the inquiry further and separate the various
elements in a situation. Many phenomena involve variations in different entities.
For example, if the concrete development is represented (Figure 25) by mnpqrstv,
one observes: (i) That that line fluctuates about the undulatory line MNPQ; (2)
that the latter in turn fluctuates about the line AB. In other words there are fluctu-
1719 UNDULATORY MOVEMENT IN HISTORY Il8l
that the simple curves that are successively obtained do not approach the real curve
in a uniform manner: the precision begins first by rapidly augmenting; then there
is a
period of slow augmentation, then another of rapid augmentation, and so on.
These periods of slow augmentation in precision divide off the great groups of sinu-
ositiesmentioned in other words, they separate the group of more and more par-
ticular influences that are influencing the phenomenon. [An example is given
population in England and the article concludes:] It is seen that the indices of
precision increase rapidly as far as the index 3; A
after that, much more slowly.
One finds, therefore, in the case in hand, that population is influenced by a first
group of forces that give the phenomenon the form indicated by the first four terms
"
of formula 2. The
other terms represent 'perturbations,' irregularities.' We shall
meet other examples in the pages following ( 2213 f.).
1 1 82 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 171 pa
apparent: one may get anything one chooses out of them ( 1558 f., 1797 f.). As
an example of such paradoxes, one might mention Fournier's, Le vieux-neuf: His-
toire ancicnne des inventions et decouvertes moderncs:
By far-fetched comparisons,
and remote and often imaginary analogies, Fournier shows, p. i, that "there is
nothing new what has been forgotten." For one of the many literary fancies,
save
enjoy the poems of Homer and the elegies, tragedies, and comedies
of the Greeks and Latins if we did not find them expressing senti-
ments that, in great part at least, we share? Aeschylus, Sophocles,
Euripides, Aristophanes, Plautus, Terence, Virgil, Horace, and other
writers of Graeco-Latin antiquity are they foreigners whom we no
long before him and, in fact, ever since human beings had been
3
able to distinguish between clay and limestone.
2
17193 Dugas-Montbel, Observations sitr I'lliade, Vol. I, pp. 70-71 (Iliad, II, v.
38): "The Latin poet [Virgil] almost always swings into the movement of the
Homeric phrase, that being the expression of the soul which never changes. The
manners, customs, habits of men are for ever being modified by civilization, but
passions do not vary with the centuries: the voice of the heart is the same in all
ages. So it is with all the poets. When Racine imitates Homer, it is the rhythm of
the phrase he catches, steeped as his poetry is in the manners of his own age and
in the ideas of a vastly different society. [The critic mentions imitations of Iliad, V,
116-17 by Virgil and Roilcau; then, Vol. I, p. 230:] Neither Virgil nor Boileau men-
tions 'the thighs of the sheepand the goats covered with thick fat* they share the
ideas of their own times. But they follow Homer in everything touching expressions
of the soul. That is the real imitation, the only one that genius can permit itself.
[And on Iliad, VI, v. 303 (Vol. I, p. 296) :] If the imitators of Homer differ from
him as regards details of manners, customs, and usages, they insist on following
him with happy fidelity in everything touching the expression of sentiment. This
cannot vary, the human heart remaining at bottom for ever the same."
17193
3
There are Utopians who set up a certain "human nature'* as the founda-
tion for their studies of society, and to uphold one reform or another that is sug-
The or not
1720. fact that classes of residues change but slightly
at all in a given society over a given period of time does not mean
1
that they may not differ very widely in different societies.
1721. The differences between Sparta, Athens, Rome r England,
and France that we noted in Chapter II were nothing but differ-
ences in intensities of Class I and Class II residues; and it is inter-
being aware of as much, that there is a constant element in social phenomena solid
Now we can say that the maintenance of such relations is a group-persistence; and
such phenomena we examined at length in Chapter VI. In 174 we spoke of a force
X uniting sensations P t Q, R. Now we can say that that force is a force that
. . .
keeps the groups from disintegrating, that its measure is the measure of the inten-
sity of the group-persistence. The force Y ( 174) that prompts innovations corre-
sponds to Class I residues (combinations).
1726 INTERDEPENDENCE VS. CAUSE AND EFFECT 1185
far as possible, resorting, for that
purpose, to opportune modifica-
tions in derivations, so as to
justify, be it fallaciously,
the use of the
same names for different things." That is the rule, one might add,
uted nor are they of equal intensities in the various strata of a given
age. The neophobia and superstition of the lower classes has often
been remarked, and it is a well-known fact of history that they were
the last to abandon faith in the religion, which derived its very
name, paganism ("ruralism"), from them., The residues of widest
diffusion and greatest intensity in the uneducated are referable to
Classes II and III (activity), whereas the opposite is often the case
with the residues of our Class V
(individual integrity).
1724. Dividing society into two strata, calling one the "lower"
and the other the "higher," brings us one step closer to the con-
crete than we were in thinking of society as a homogeneous unit,
pations of
human beings. Such too have been familiar from most
ancient times; but almost always those who have utilized them have
confused two very different things: (i) The simple fact of a dif-
1724
*
In order not to stray too far afield from the matter here in hand, we must
postpone that inquiry till later on, 2025 f.
1 1 86 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1727
rustica, proemium: "Our farmers furnish very strong men and
brave soldiers, men who earn their bread in manners most honour-
able and above reproach; and they who till the soil do not cherish
*
evil thoughts." And an indirect way of saying that residues
that is
ples. Hippocrates
deals with such influences at length in his treatise
On Airs, Waters, and Places. The correlations he sets up between
human character-traits and living-conditions are probably mistaken;
but they none the less
recognize differences in temperaments as in-
dependent of will, of thought, and of level of enlightenment. The
differing temperaments of Europeans and Asiatics he explains by
differences in soil and climate supplemented by differences in insti-
tutions; and not satisfied with generic differences, he goes into the
precluding that in a minor way derivations also may have had their
influence.
1731. The mentioned were attempts to explain social
theories just
ing it. So persons who deal with entities of that sort make interpola-
tions ( 1694) without
knowing it. But it is always better to pro-
ceed in full knowledge of what one is about. We had better look
more closely therefore at the second method for determining trends
in certain phenomena. The method is to determine curves to
rep-
interpolate those curves, and finally
resent the phenomena, then to
2
determine the relations between the average movements ( 1718 ).
But in all that we must guard against a new error into which one
may easily fall. This second method must not result in our neglect-
ing the first, for both may be made to contribute to the sum of our
analyzes the horizontal movement under the influence of the heavenly bodies of the
molecules contained in it, and then observes that it has to involve an alternate rising
and falling of level. But he considers the question in a much loftier perspective in
getting at the analytical theory of the phenomenon. Ignoring the molecular move-
ment, Newton looks for the momentary picture of equilibrium that the water-mass
would assume under the influence of the attractive force of one heavenly body, and
determines the shape and dimensions of its surface an ellipsoid with the long axis
constantly pointing towards the star. As a consequence of the Earth's movement,
the distortion makes the round of the Earth in twenty-four hours, the level rising
and falling at each point twice a day. But the hypothesis on which Newton's theory
rests is not consistent with the rapidity of the movement. [That has been a reason
not for rejecting mathematical theories of tides, but for perfecting them.] The
water-molecules, drawn at every moment to a new position of equilbrium, evidently
tend to overpass it and develop fluctuations determined by the laws of dynamics.
The problem of the tides therefore requires assistance from the theory of the move-
ment of liquids on which Laplace's analysis rests. [So in mathematical economics
there was a move from Cournot's theories to present-day theories, and so there will
be from present to future theories.] Book IV of the Celestial Mechanics is entirely
devoted to a theoretical and practical examination of the oscillations of the sea, and
we may say that the pure theory has suffered no appreciable modifications since it
was established on its foundations by the great analyst; but the general solution of
that difficult problem still remains to be discovered. Despite all the efforts of mathe-
maticians, theory has so far proved unable not only to adapt itself to the infinite
variety of conditions on the Earth but even to approach the question otherwise than
in the very simple situation of a spheroid entirely covered with water. But if we
envisage practical aspects of the matter, the analysis has been extraordinarily pro-
ductive. The general principle of a correspondence between periodic forces and
marine movements that it brought to light [In mathematical economics, the prin-
ciple of mutual dependence that we are here extending to sociological phenomena.]
served as point of departure for the study of the tides at Brest, to which the fourth
and almost all the thirteenth book of the Celestial Mechanics arc devoted. On the
same principle Sir William Thomson in England based his method of harmonic
analysis, a theory that is as remarkable for its simplicity as for its inflexible logic
and which seems destined to serve as crown for the whole edifice of the empirical
study of tides, as offering a more effective instrument of investigation for resolving
the complex movement of the sea into its elements."
1732 THEORY OF INTERDEPENDENCE
working out an abstract formula for tides, Traite de mccanique celeste, II, Bk. IV,
216, 241, Laplace remarks in connexion with one of its corollaries: "Now we shall
shortly be seeing that this result is contrary to observed facts, and however far the
formula above is extended, it docs not succeed in satisfying all observed phenomena.
Irregularities in the depths of the ocean, its manner of distribution over the Earth,
the location and slope of its shores, their relation to neighbouring coasts, the resist-
ance that the waters meet, all such causes, which cannot be reduced to measurement,
modify the oscillation of the great fluid mass. We can therefore merely analyze the
generalphenomena that ought to result from the attractions of Sun and Moon and
draw from observation the data indispensable for completing the theory of the ebb
and flow of the sea in each seaport. . [Then, after stating his formulae:] Now
. .
let us compare these formulae with observations. Early in the last century and at
the initiative of the Academy of Sciences a large number of observations of the ebb
and flow of the tide were conducted
in our harbours. They were continued each
tory, they make up by their number and in view of the height and regularity of the
tides in that harbour the most complete and useful collection that we have of that
kind. It is with the Brest observations, therefore, that our formulae will be com-
1731
8
Protectionist derivations lend themselves much better than the scientific
theories of political economy to the defence of the protectionist system. There are
excellent subjective reasons why a person deriving or hoping to derive some direct
or indirect advantage from protective tariffs should give his preference to deriva-
tions. But no such reasons exist for the person who is merely trying, in an objective
those facts upon residues, but of all factors, including residues, upon
each other reciprocally ( 2203 f.).
There are various ways of envisaging interdependent phenomena.
Suppose we classify them: i. Relations of cause and effect, only,
may be considered, and interdependence wholly disregarded. 2. In-
phenomena are not distinguished from secondary, the procedure is i, and results
are almost always vitiated by serious errors. If, however, in deference to the achieve-
ments of mathematical economics, 2b, considerations of cause and effect are used,
but with due account taken of interdependencies by studying actions and reactions
and by distinguishing between principal and secondary phenomena, the procedure is
2a and results may closely approximate realities.
1732 METHOD 2tfl CORRECTED CAUSE AND EFFECT
2
them, at least in their general form. So as regards the economic and
social sciences, the ib method remains as an ideal goal that is almost
3
never attained in the concrete. Shall we say,
on that account, that
it is useless? No, because from it we derive, if nothing more, two
It
gives us a picture of a situation, which we
i.
great advantages,
could get in no other way. The surface of the Earth does not, to be
sure, have the shape of a geometric sphere; and yet to picture the
Earth in that way does help to give some notion of what the Earth
2
1732 See Pareto, Manuale, Chap. Ill, 217-18. Not a few economists have made
the mistake of imagining that the theories of pure economics could directly control
the concrete phenomenon. Walras thought he could reform society on that basis
[Elements d 'economic politiquc pure, Preface, p. xv, and pp. 277-80] On that point .
see Bovcn,Lcs applications mathcmatiqnes a I' economic politiquc, p. 112 and passim.
3
1732 Pareto, Manuale, Chap. Ill, 228: "The chief advantage derived from the
theories of pure economics lies in their providing a synthetic conception of the eco-
nomic equilibrium, and at the present time there arc no other means of attaining
that end. But the phenomenon envisaged by pure economics diverges, now little,
now much, from the concrete phenomenon, and it is for applied economics to study
those divergences. It would be futile and not very intelligent to pretend to regulate
concrete phenomena according to the theories of pure economics. [Very very . . .
often the theories of sociology will be found in the same boat.] The conditions that
we have found for the economic equilibrium give us a general conception of that
equilibrium.... To discover what the economic equilibrium was, we tried to see
just what forces it. We must further caution that the identification of
determined
those forces isno sense designed to supply a numerical calculation of prices.
in
Suppose we are placed in the situation most favourable for such a calculation: sup-
pose we have overcome all our difficulties as to knowledge of the data involved in
the problem. Such assumptions would be absurd and still they would not be
. . .
adequate for making a solution of the problem practically possible. ... If all those
equations [in the equilibrium] were really known, still the only means humanly
available for solving them would be to watch the practical solutions provided by
the market in terms of certain quantities at certain prices." As I have elsewhere
shown (in my article, "Economic mathematique'' in the Encyclopedic dcs sciences
l
mathcmatiqnes) [and see above, 87 ] y only an infinitude of index-functions could
show how the economic equilibrium is actually determined. The selection one makes
from among them is a question of expediency merely. In particular, the purpose of
our selection of lines of indifference is not at all to find some practical measurement
of ophelimity; but merely to bring into relation with the conditions of the equilib-
rium and with prices certain quantities that may theoretically be assumed to be
measurable. Similar reservations arc pertinent in the case of sociology. The purpose
of that science is not to reveal the future in detail. It is not "carrying on" for the
Delphic Oracle nor is it competing for business with prophets, sibyls, soothsayers,
trance-mediums or fortune-tellers. Its object is to determine in their general form
the uniformities that have obtained in the past and those which are likely to prevail
in the future, and at the same time to describe the general characteristics of all such
uniformities and their mutual relations.
11
94 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY X
73 2
is like. 2. It
sign-boards the path we have to follow if we are to
avoid the pitfalls of method i and so approximate realities. Even a
beacon we shall never reach may serve to indicate a course. By anal-
ogy we can carry over the results achieved by mathematical eco-
nomics into sociology and so equip ourselves with concepts that we
could get in no other way and which we can proceed to verify on
ogy, and pure economics is a small part of economics. Pure economics, therefore,
cannot of itself give rules for dealing with a concrete situation, nor can it alto-
gether give the feel of that situation."
6
1732 With them we shall deal more amply farther along, 2091 f.
1734 SOCIAL CLASSES 1 1
95
are not deciding whether it is living in a certain class that produces
certain residues in individuals, or whether it is the presence of those
residues in those individuals that drives them into that class, or,
7
better yet, whether the two not be there simultaneously.
effects
may
For the present we are to confine ourselves to
describing such uni-
formities as are discernible in the distribution of residues in the vari-
ous social classes.
1733. Data in abundance are available on that point They are not
very exact, often coming forward under literary or metaphysical
guises. From them, nevertheless, we are able to infer with reason-
able probability that for the various strata in society the scale of in-
1732
7
To all that we shall come in tlic next chapter.
1196 THE MIND AND SOCIETY J
735
further error of mistaking changes in the personnel of a class for
is
open, a further change results from changes in the composition of
the class; and this second change depends, in its turn, upon the
acquire till further along ( 2329 f.). Let us devote our main atten-
tion therefore to the relationships a, c, d.
1736. a. Influence of residues on residues. Itwill help, first of all,
to distinguish residues a, b, c . . .
corresponding to a given group
Figure 26
ing to one same group P go fairly well together they are not too
discordant, not too openly contradictory. On the other hand such
any bearing they may have on individual utility or the utility of society.
It was with a view to showing that that we began this study with an
2
in-
1735
vestigation of non-logical conduct.
1738 INFLUENCE OF RESIDUES ON RESIDUES 1197
Since all we know of such residues we know through derivations,
we shall likewise find derivations that are not too discordant and
derivations which frankly disaccord. Still other discordant deriva-
tions arise through the importance of influencing various sorts of
individuals who are equipped with various other sorts of residues
( 1716).
1737. Discordant residuesand their derivations^ Contradictory
derivations expressing residues that are also
contradictory are often-
times observable in one same person, who either fails to notice the
contradiction or tries to remove it
by resort to more or less trans-
1
parent sophistries. Of that we have given many proofs, but further
elucidation will not come ^miss in view of the importance of having
the fact clearly appreciated. Let us take a number of groups of resi-
if
they fit in with his sentiments or, if one will, with the residues
corresponding to his sentiments. That is sufficient for the majority
of human beings. Some small few feel a need for logic, for pseudo-
scientific ratiocination, which impels them to refined disquisitions
at
large such effects are often gradual and not very considerable,
since, as we have seen, a class of residues as a whole varies slowly
and but In a single individual it may be far stronger and
slightly.
more rapid. That would be the case with the
Hindu converts to Christianity whom we
mentioned farther back ( 1416) as losing
the morality of their old religion without
longed to b, c . . .
So, finally, a group, b, may increase because
,
1744
1
That was a common error of governments in olden times, and in a day
quite recent it was observable in France as a special trait of the policies of the
Restoration and the Second Empire. Two further errors usually go with it: (i) A
belief that the religious sentiment may be awakened in people who do not have it,
and intensified in people who have it, by using force upon dissidents and punishing
them; and (2) a tendency to identify the religious sentiment in general with the
religious sentiment attached to a given faith in particular. So governments wear
themselves out in efforts to force a religion, X, upon their subjects, andif they get
festation of good morals and loyalty in a people, it is not better not to offend it
if one's aim is to encourage those manifestations ( 1753). Modern governments
endorsing the religion of Progress disdainfully reject any help from the old re-
ligion, a, in regulating civil life. But they replace it with others. Many of them are
inclined to assign the function to the sex religion, /, so repeating a common mistake
of governments of the past. It is, in fact, usual for individuals who are upright and
temperate in the various aspects of their activity to evince the same qualities in the
domain of sex; and it is not difficult to show, therefore, that, in general and on
the whole, observance of the rules of the sex religion, /, goes hand in hand with
observance of the rules of a religion, a, of decency, b, morals, c, honesty, d, and so
on. But that easily leads to the mistake of taking / as at least a contributory "cause"
of a, b, c, d. Because that error is a very very common one, we have repeat-
. . .
edly marshalled proofs to show that / is not a cause, nor even a contributory
cause, of a, b, c. That error is usually coupled with another more serious one,
. . .
which, really, follows from it: the belief that by influencing / one can influence
a, b, c till one arrives at the extreme absurdum that if sex
. . .
hypocrisy can be
enforced by law one can get a good, honest, clean-living citizenry. Nevertheless,
the countless and most striking disproofs of the doctrine that historical experience
provides do not suffice to budge the race of sex-fanatics and the plain man in gen-
eral from that utterly false notion.
1746 EFFECTS OF PROPAGANDA I2OI
in which b, c, d . . .
originate is in some respects similar to the
conduct in which a originates. If we call all such conduct "religious'*
and the complexes a, b, c, d . . .
"religions," we can then say that
to stimulate growth in one such "religion" is of scant influence upon
the other religions; but if one can procure increased intensity in
the sentiments of group-persistence, P, in which they all originate,
an effective influence will be exerted upon them all. With most
people the reasoning the direct reverse: that to stimulate a given
is
2
religion is an effective way to stimulate growth in others.
1745. But the fact that one demonstration offered for a direct in-
fluence of one residue upon other residues is fallacious in no wise
precludes the possibility of cases in which such an influence exists,
and we have to look for evidence of it directly to the facts. How-
ever, it is not easy to find. Oftentimes when we think we have
it, it is still possible to interpret it as an influence of the first type;
and we are left in doubt as to any conclusion. But there are plenty of
cases that clearly indicate the independence of the residues a, b, c
. . . the well-known fact, for instance, of brigands being devout
Catholics, and other facts of the same sort. In such cases, b, c, d
. . . seem to be in no way related to a. Confining ourselves to cer-
tain probabilities, we may
say that the direct influence, when there
is
any, arises chiefly between residues that are closely related, or at
least among residues of the same genus; seldom among residues of
might seem to be a case of direct influence; and yet one might say
that belief in silly stories is an expression of a psychic state that will
incline the person to believe in one more.
1746. c. Influence of derivations on residues. This problem is
1744
2
We shall revert to this matter farther along ( 1850!:.).
1202 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY J
747
social equilibrium. It is
just a superfluity: it satisfies
certain senti-
ments, and that is all. Briefly, but not in strict exactness, one may
say that in order to influence society, theories have to be trans-
muted into sentiments, derivations into residues. It must not how-
ever be forgotten that that holds true qnly for non-logical conduct,
not fo,r conduct of the logical variety. /
only through the sentiments which they persons who are alien
7
stir,
1747
1
Examples are legion. We
may take as typical the case of a play by Colic,
La partie dc chasse de Henry IV , which has been interpreted at one time or an-
other in directly opposite fashions according to prevailing sentiments. Hallays-Dabot,
Histoire de la censure theatrale en Prance, pp. 85-86: "One measure of severity one
is at a loss to understand unless one is keenly alive to the state of mind prevailing
toward the end of the reign of Louis XV, and the difficulties the government was
meeting. I refer to the interdiction of the Hunting-Party of Henry IV. Colic's play is
the most inoffensive thing imaginable but look a little closely at it and it be-
. . .
sweeps even people who have everything to fear from it off their feet.] Profiting by
those precedents, the Government saw in Colic's ^.lay just what the public would be
1748 HENRY IV AND THE STAGE 1 203
1748. From a logico-experimental standpoint, the only way to re-
fute an assertion, A, effectively, is
to show that it is false. When
logical conduct is involved that logic and by observations
is done by
of fact ( 1834). Not so from the standpoint of sentiments and in
many times [under the First Empire] to revive [Duval's] Edouard [en Ecosse']
[suppressed after the first performance, Feb. 17, 1802], and the Hunting-Party
of Henry IV. During the declining years of Louis XV, Henry IV was, as we have
seen, a monarchical mask for the philosophes who were plotting the overthrow of
the monarchy. Now on a stage in Paris Henry IV would have been the white
flag around which all malcontents would gather." Welschinger, La censure sous le
premier Empire, p. 226: "Napoleon kept an eye on the theatre both at short and
at long range. He wrote Fouche from Mainz, Oct. 3, 1804: 'I see they have
played the Hunting-Party of Henry IV at Nantes. What good there is in that I
"
cannot see .' and the seditious play was at once suppressed. But the Restora-
. .
tion came and the play was "formally" revived, Hallays-Dabot, Op. cit., pp. 225,
239, 291: "All the plays hitherto forbidden, the Etats de Blots, Henri IV et
d'Aubigne, plays dealing with the man from Beam, were now to be authorized.
all
It would be hard to say how many times Henry IV was put on the stage during
that period. He was to be seen somewhere every evening. From the Comedie Fran-
gaise to the Franconi, it was just one chorus of adulation, and the secret of it all
events have now revealed to us. Henry IV was the emblem of monarchy and he
had further suffered humiliation at the hands of the previous regime. . . .
[Shortly
the public tires of him:] The Etats de Bloiswas revived on May 30, 1814. Ray-
nouard's tragedy had a half-hearted success enthusiasms were already cooling.
Legislation on the press was brewing. The public was beginning to weary of the
dithyrambs which had been declaimed, sung, danced, played, mimed, on every
stage in Paris ever since April [ 1749]. . . .
[And now for Louis Philippe:] Napo-
leon now takes on the stage the place that Henry IV had occupied in 1755, 1790,
1814, and 1815. He appears simultaneously in all the theatres, and the public waxes as
excited over the Emperor's grey coat as it had of yore over the white plume of
Navarre. [Of the "Widow of Malabar" [by Scribe and Melesville], a play of
. . .
Louis XVIII's time, Hallays-Dabot remarks, Op. cit., p. 123:] That play had
always been regarded as a rather tedious portrayal of Hindu manners. No one had
recognized the Catholic clergy in those priests in Brahman garb. Now that people
are excited and on the watch for every word, every turn of expression that they
can grasp, everything becomes allusion. The clergy is aroused and M. de Beaumont
calls on the King."
1204 THE MIND AN& SOCIETY 1748
the case of non-logical conduct. Reasonings and experimental ob-
servations have very little influence on sentiments and non-logical
x
1748 Hallays-Dabot, Histoire de la censure thcatrale en France, p. 275: "To that
period [around 1827] belongs a prohibition by the censorship that is gaily re-
counted year after year in many little sheets as a model of the innate ineptitude
of the censors. It seems that in a certain vaudeville sketch there was reference to
making and the writer had put into it 'Capuchin's beard/ a sort of wild
a salad
chicory. The
censor insisted on a different recipe and pitilessly vetoed any sort
of 'monk's beard.' An amusing story! But however fastidious the cutting, I must
confess I have never found it as ridiculous as
people are pleased to suppose. One
has only to think of the battle of epigrams, puns, pin-pricks, stupid jests, that was
fought each day by Government and Opposition, that period of the Restoration
furnishing the most complete example of that sort of thing. One has only to re-
member that ten newspapers delivered broadsides every morning against the capttci-
nades of the court of Charles X that was the term then current. And then
. . .
one may wonder whether the writer in question was as innocent as was pretended
of any hostile thought when he put 'Capuchin's beard' into a salad then in vogue.
And one may wonder whether the minister who approved the cut, in itself so child-
ish, was altogether wrong in mistrusting a public that made any simple declaration
from the quai Voltaire a pretext for a noisy riot.*' So Hallays-Dabot manages to clear
the minister on the count of stupidity. But the charge of bad
strategy still stands,
for Hallays-Dabot ought also to remember what was
being said along the quai
Voltaire about the effects of such censorings. Las Cases, Memorial de Saint-Hclcne,
Vol. II, p. 107: "Speaking of the works that were censored or forbidden
by the
police under his rule, the Emperor said that having nothing to do while he was
on the island of Elba, he had amused himself by skimming some such works and
that oftentimes he could not guess the reasons of the police for prohibitions
they had ordered. Then he went on freedom or limita-
to discuss the question of
tion of the press. It was, he said, an endless
question, admitting of no half-way
measures. The great difficulty lay not in the principle itself but in
judging the
circumstances to which the principle, taken abstractly, had to be
applied. By in-
clination, the Emperor said, he was for unrestricted freedom." By no means a
unique case. Looking at things in a certain perspective, many practical men per-
ceive the fatuousness of chasing derivations, but that does not
prevent them from
following the cry when caught in the passions of the moment. Welschinger, La
censure sous le premier Empire, pp. 235-36: "It is
interesting to note that Napoleon
was as keenly concerned with the theatre as with politics. What
phase of life,
for that matter, did that universal mind not embrace, what slight detail did not
1749 SILENCE AND PUBLIC OPINION 1205
1749. To
argue about a thing with a person, in terms whether
favourable or unfavourable, may arouse in him an inclination if he
hasn't it already to interest himself in that thing; if he already has
1
the inclination, it
may whet it. It is an interesting fact that
with
have its interest for him things that would nowadays bring a smile to the lips
of our statesmen? In a letter from Potsdam, Oct. 25, 1806, he approves the can-
cellation of the ban laid on a ballet, Return of Ulysses, and asks Fouche to get a
detailed report on the performance and attend the first night himself to make
sure there was nothing wrong in it." Noble worries for an Emperor and one
of his ministers! Of verses of Marie-Joseph Chenier alluding to Tacitus \Epitre a
Voltaire, (Euvres, Vol. Ill, pp. 101-02.], Welschinger relates, p. 149: "Tacitus!
That name had a way of angering the Emperor. His public disapprobation of
Durcau de Lamalle's translation and his prohibition of the Tragedy Tiberius are
sufficient indications of his dislike for the Roman historian. [Napoleon was . . .
minded to put Chenier in prison, but Fouche dissuaded him:] 'All Paris will work
to get him out. He is not popular, but he will be pitied if he is in jail. Sire, let us
not make our enemies interesting!' [The key-verse of Chenier read: "Tacite en traits
de flamme accuse nos Sejans."} [Not even the classics were spared by the Im-
perial censorship:] 'Most surprising changes,' says Bourdienne, 'were made in
the plays of our great masters by poets hired for the purpose, and Corneille's
Heraclius was produced only in mutilated form.' The censor, Lemontey, said to a
caller one evening: 'Are you going to the Theatre Fran$ais this evening to hear
Racine revised by Lemontey?' That was not just a pleasantry. It was the exact
truth. The great poet of Louis XIV had been roughly handled by the censor no
less than any scribbler under the Empire. The Prompter's Library at the Comedie
Francaisc has a copy of Athalic that bears the most unmistakable traces of it and
enables one to imagine what cuts must have been made in other tragedies of
Racine. .
[Welschinger gives specimens of such deletions. But there is worse:
. .
the censor replaces verses of Racine with his own!] In Athalic, II, vii, the censor
deletes four verses (116-19), fearing lest an allusion to the Pretender be seen in
them; but then to tie up the passage with what follows, he suppresses the hemistich
'Que Dieit voie et nous juge' and replaces it with a hemistich of his own: ']e con-
nais votre attente,' so that Athalie can cry in the verse following 'Mais nous nous
rcverrons. Adieu! ]e sors contente. .' In Athalie,
. .
IV, in, twenty-five verses fall
under the censor's scissors; but that leaving no rhyme for the line 'Pretres saints,
c'cst a vous de prevenir sa rage' the censor follows with a line of his own: 'De
"
proclamer foas pour signal du carnage! The time Napoleon spent in keeping an
eye on the theatre, the press, and Mme. de Stael, he could certainly have better
spent on affairs of his Empire. But he had a mania that has been the mania of many
another statesman. Such men can never learn that the art of government lies not in
trying to change residues but in skilful manipulation of existing residues. If only
they would lay aside their preconceptions and condescend to take some notice of
history, they would see that in persecuting derivations in order to modify residues
governments waste enormous amounts of energy, inflict untold sufferings on their
subjects, compromise their own power, and achieve results of little account.
Speaking in L 'Empire liberal, Vol. VI, p. 346, of the acrimonious attacks
1
1749
of the clergy on Renan's Life of Jesus, Ollivier says: 'The results the bishops
achieved were not what they expected. Lcsseps once told me that the chief item in
1206 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY J
749
tinguishing the torch, they had lighted it." Charpentier, Carpentariana, pp. 337-38:
"La Mothe le Vayer having written a book that was not selling, his publisher came
to him and complained, begging him to make up for it by doing something else. He
told the mannot to worry, that he had enough influence at Court to get his book
suppressed, and that once that was done, he would sell all he cared to print. He
had the book suppressed, and things turned out as he had predicted: everyone hur-
ried to get a copy of the book, and the publisher was obliged to get out a new
edition at once in order to provide everyone with copies." Prosecution of the Chan-
sons of P. J. Beranger (Proces faits . .
(Dupin speaking for the
.), pp. 74-76
defence): 'The idea is to book of poems, and public
halt the circulation of a
curiosity is aroused to the highest pitch! The idea is to do away with certain fea-
tures that are regarded as harmful, and ephemeral as they were by nature, they
are made as eternal as the history with which they are associated! ... If there
were any doubt of that, it would be a simple matter to consult experience. It would
all prosecutions of this kind have produced results contrary to those
bear witness that
expected. M. de Lauraguais wrote to the Parlcment of Paris: 'Honour to burned
books!' He might have added: 'Profits to writers and publishers!* single detail A
will suffice to prove 1775 some satirical verses had been published against
it. In
the Chancellor, Maupeou. ... To ridicule a Chancellor, or even a mere registrar of
deeds, was a serious matter in those days. Hurt to the quick, Maupeou stormed at
the writer, threatening him with all his wrath if ever he were detected. To escape
the ministerial whirlwind the rhymster fled to England, whence he wrote to
Maupeou enclosing a new satire in verse. 'Mon seigneur,' said he, 'I have never
wanted more than a modest income of 3,000 francs. My first song which displeased
you so much has earned me a capital of 30,000 francs from the sole fact of your
displeasure. Invested at 5 per cent that gives me half my amount. Please, sir, show
the same wrath against this new satire which I send you. That will complete the
revenue. I desire and I promise you that I will write no more." Belin, The Trade in
Prohibited Booths in Paris, 7750-77^9 (Le commerce, etc.), pp. 109-10: "It was easy
to determine that to proscribe a work was to call attention to it, that the prohibi-
tion aroused curiosity and served merely to multiply surreptitious editions that
were dangerous from the inferences that were drawn from all the mystery. So a
little pamphlet entitled So Much the Better for Her, which Choiscul hesitated for
some days before condemning, sold up to 4,000 copies 'under the cloak* during the
fortnight but ceased making any noise once it was permissible to offer it
first
1749 RESIDUES AND DERIVATIONS 1
207
2
ing. In such matters when silence actually leaves the individual in
789] 'A
: censure from those gentlemen merely sells a book. The publishers ought
to pay them to burn everything they print.' Extract from the Pot pourri, Etrennes
atix gens de lettres, quoted by Metra [Correspon dance secrete politique et litteraire,
Vol. IV, p. 293] 'Burning was for a book what election to the Academy was for
:
the man of letters.' Diderot, Letter on the BooJ^ Trade (Lettre, etc., p. 66): The
severer the proscription, the higher the price of the book, the greater the eagerness
to read it, the wider its sale, the more it was read. . . . How often might not
the publisher and the author of a licenced book have said to the magistrate, had
they dared: "Please, gentlemen, a little proclamation condemning me to be tonged
and burned at the foot of your great staircase 1" When sentences against a book
were being cried, the type-setters in the printing establishments would exclaim:
" '
"Good! Another edition!" Hallays-Dabot, La censure dramatique et le theatre, p.
61 (in question Clarctic's Les gueux): "The censorship adjudged the play inoffen-
sive. It was therefore required to appear before the public as a play much talked
of in advance by part of the press but without the anticipatory sympathy that at-
tends victims of the censorship. ... It was a virtual failure." The deletion of a
number of lines in Victor Hugo's Marion de Lor me was enough to lend popularity
to others that were supposed to summarize them. I say "supposed," for the famous
verses read:
"De I' a litre Marion rien en moi est reste.
("Of the other Marion nothing me. Your love has given me a second
is left in
virginity.") Now the poet says in a note: "The author's manuscript contained four
verses that were suppressed in the stage version and which we think should be
printed here. At the odious proposal of Laffemas, Marion turns without answering
toward Didier's prison and says:
Had the lines not been censored no one probably would have remembered them.
2
1749 In a day gone by many libertines felt more deeply stirred by love-affairs
with nuns than with ordinary women, and cases might be mentioned where lovers
insisted that their lay mistresses wear monastic habits. In England in our day
certain persons are being led in a spirit of contradiction to break rules that there
is an effort to enforce by law and which would probably be respected if no pro-
hibition existed.
I2O8 THE MIND AND SOCIETY ^749
portance that serves to make him a topic of general discussion may
be the starting-point for his success. Many many lawyers, Gambetta,
for instance, owe their start towards fame and power to some
clamorous trial. To minimize the importance of an incident or a fact
3
it is somewhat less effective but still
helpful to say nothing of it,
the efficacy depending on whether or not in that way the public can
be kept from concentrating upon it, either because many people
3
1749 Many religious organizations make
a practice of saying nothing of occur-
rences that might occasion scandal. Such things are commonplace in the Christian
Church and other religions of that kind. I will give one example from the Drey-
fusard religion of certain French intellectuals. On M. Millerand's reinstatement of
Du Paty de Clam in the territorial army ( 1580 3 ), a writer in the Gazette de
Lausanne, Feb. 3, 1913, reports: "The truth is, it was all a trade, the promise to
M. Du Paty to reinstate him being given against his promise to desist from his
appeal, which was embarrassing because it rested on a charge that was true. Amid
applause from the Left, M. Jaures made a fiery protest that the deal should not
go through, that M. Du Paty was to be told: 'You can justify yourself as you see
fit!' Now let us go slowly. That there should have been no such deal is very
possible. The bargaining that was struck was nothing to boast of, but that M.
Du Paty was to be left the task of clearing himself, no, no, and again no! It
was the work of a moment to determine whether M. Du Paty had been cashiered
on the basis of a forged document, and if so and it was so he was entitled to
fair treatment. The mind refuses to admit that men who have done themselves
honour by their attitude in a tragic campaign should not have seen that it was
as intolerable that M. Du Paty should be the victim of a forged document as it was
that Captain Dreyfus should be the victim of the secret production of forged
and criminal documents." If, now, one turns to the many Dreyfusard or humani-
tarian newspapers of those days it will be seen that, in general, they maintain
scrupulous silence as to any forgery. They could have denied that the document
was a forgery; they could even have declared it genuine what is not justifiable in
defence of a faith? As a matter of fact they preferred to say nothing.
Here, in a connexion altogether different, is an instance that is typical of a large
number of cases. In the years 1912 and 1913 it was considered patriotic in Italy
tomake the state budget show surpluses that did not really exist. A number of
important newspapers abroad faithfully reported the statements issued by the Italian
ministries anent such balances and glossed them copiously with interviews by
ples of those sciences, yet not a few of whom have made counterfeit reputations
as experts. They use certain types of derivations (they are always the same) that
are well suited to their own ignorance and to brains that can swallow them. I will
specify a few such types: i. The boot^ is badly written. It is easy in any language
to find some case where the use of a word is doubtful and call it a mistake. But
even were obviously wrong, what has that to do with the logico-experimental
if it
language, does it cease to be true? No; but to refute it one has to be a mathema-
12 IO TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY
1750. Oftentimes, to refute an absurd argument, and as soundly
as one may wish, proves to be a means of accrediting it if it chances
to correspond to sentiments powerfully active at the moment
1
( 1749 ). The same is also true, of course, of reasonings that are
sound from the logico-experimental standpoint, and in general, of
attacks of all sorts and persecutions of theories, opinions, doctrines.
Whence the illusion that "truth" has some mysterious capacity for
triumphing over persecutions. That notion may accord with the facts
in the domain of pure logico-experimental science ; but it less often
tician, whereas to say that "the style is bad" one need only be a fool. 2. The boo\
contains nothing new. In its extreme implication the derivation implies an accu-
sation of plagiarism. It would be difficult to find a writer of any worth or repute
who has not been the victim of such charges. In a tale of Boccaccio, Decameron,
I, 82, Messer Erminio de' Grimaldi asks Guglielmo Borsicre to tell him of "some-
thing that has never been seen," so that he could have a picture made of it. To
which Borsiere replies: "I do not believe I could show you anything that nobody
has ever seen, unless it should be a sneeze or something of that sort; but if you
will, I willshow you something [i.e., courtesy] that I do not think you have ever
seen." Like tart retort might be made to many such critics. 3. The wor\ contains
many mistakes and pains are taken not to designate them, in hopes that people
will accept the criticism without testing it. Then again alleged errors are pointed
out; and when that they
it is shown were not errors, the rectification is ignored
in hopes that people will not hear of it or at least disregard it. That was the case
with our estimable M. Aulard, who
said nothing in reply to Cochin's drastic re-
1
joinder ( 537 ). 4. Personal attacks upon the writer, criticisms of things irrelevant
-
the world." Another, who seemed somewhat of a stranger to the subject he was
discussing, prattled about "a school" of mathematical economics that was based
on premises of "individualism" (a synonym for the Devil among such people)
and contrasted it with another school, a product of his own imagination, which
would be based on considerations of "collectivism." 6. The writer has not said
everything: he has neglected to quote certain booJ(s and state certain facts. Such
criticism would be sound if the sources and facts overlooked or neglected were
calculated to modify the writer's conclusions; it is fatuous if the conclusions stand in
accords and often frankly disaccords with the facts in the case of
logic) residues, while the very fact of restraint intensifies the eager-
ness for that satisfaction. That is especially conspicuous in matters
l
1751 Numberless examples arc available from all periods of history. Tacitus in
his day gives one, Annales, XIV, 50: Fabricius Veiento, a court favourite, had writ-
ten a satire against the Senate and the pontifices. Prosecuted by Nero, he "was con-
victed and exiled from Italy, and his books were ordered burned. Sought after
and greedily read so long as they were obtainable only with danger, they were
3
forgotten as soon as it became again permissible to own them" ( 1330 ). Hallays-
Dabot, Histoire de la censure theatrale en France, p. 265: "The Restoration Govern-
ment went so far wrong as to put an absolute ban on Voltaire. His works were
never to be named. Such a radical suppression was a nuisance. More than
. . .
that was not very shrewd. What was the result? Four years were spent in care-
it
ful watching for the marked foe, ears erect at the slightest allusion. Then one day,
in 1826, at the Odeon, an oversight allowed a valet in outlining an itinerary to
La void! . . .'
Voltaire! Voltaire's house! The two words were like a match touched to a maga-
zine. The floor leapt to its feet in an uproar and the play was interrupted by round
after round of applause."
2
1751 The first number of Rochefort's Lanternc (Paris, May 31, 1868) begins as
follows: "According to the Imperial Almanach France has 26,000,000 subjects, not
counting subjects of dissatisfaction." The witticism made a hit and was repeated
from one end of France to the other. Who
in our day would pay any particular
attention to a jest of that kind made at the expense of a French ministry? The
Lantcrne had admirers even in the monarch's entourage. ]ournal des Goncourt, Vol.
VI, p. ii (Feb. 6, 1875): "Speaking of the infatuation of all Imperial society at
Fontainebleau for Rochefort's Lanterne, Flaubert told of a jest of Feuillet's. Flau-
bert had seen everybody reading the sheet, and finally he noticed that a master
of the hounds on mounting his horse for the hunt stuffed a copy into his coat-
pocket. Somewhat irritated, he asked of Feuillct: 'Do you really consider Roche-
fort a man of talent?' The Empress's novelist looked about to right and left. Then
he answered: 'For my part, I find him very ordinary, but I should not "
care to be
heard saying so. They would think me jealous.'
1753 EFFECTS OF SILENCE AND OF PERSECUTION 12 13
pense of the other, till at an opposite extreme the indirect effect far
exceeds the direct. At the first extreme we may locate measures
bearing on small numbers of facts and not involving powerful senti-
ments, the measures, for example, that are taken against small
or moral minorities. At the opposite extreme
political, religious,
stand measures directed at large numbers of facts and involving
theory; so it came into vogue again during the first decades of die
nineteenth century. Then one by one restrictions on the free ex-
and in the end freedom comes to have but slight effects on senti-
ment. When freedom functions chiefly through deriva-
is the rule, it
tions, and we
already know, do not, on the whole, exert
they, as
any great influence. But for that very reason, it then becomes the
wiser policy to pass over a fact or a theory in silence, since that is
1
one of the cases where the direct effect far exceeds the indirect.
I
753
*
With we reach a point where examination of the ways of
the above
on which the public voices its attitude are few in number. It may have very positive
opinions but they are few. So long as those few are never shocked, one may guide
one's readers where one wills in all others."
2
1755 Bismarck was very adept in the art of using newspapers both at home
and abroad. Ollivier, L'Empirc liberal, Vol. XIV, p. 49, tries to acquit his ministry
of the charge of unskilful management of the press: "Bismarck had much the
greater influence with the press, for he could count on at least one paid writer on
every paper to follow his orders. Since we knew who some of them were, we were
in a position to use them for keeping track of the intentions of their paymaster.
[Ollivier was a naive soul. Bismarck's intentions may have been altogether differ-
1755 RESIDUES AND DERIVATIONS 1 2 15
ent from the ones he allowed his paid agents to betray.] Furthermore Bismarck had
in hand not only all the Prussian press but most of the papers in Germany and
Austria, and so, to a much greater extent than we, he had means of creating
both in France and in Europe generally any trend of opinion he pleased." Ibid.,
Vol. XII, pp. 304-05: "Bismarck's method was most ingenious. On occasion the
French Government had had some paper abroad in its pay. That had not proved
very profitable, for the fact of the paper's venality soon came to light, and no
further importance would be attached to its opinions. [Those times were different.
In our day such a thing would cast no discredit on a paper.] Bismarck did not buy
papers. He bought one writer on each important paper, the editor-in-chief whenever
possible [Nowadays nobody is bought, directly. The pressure is applied through
financiers who own stock in the corporation that
owns the paper.] or, that failing,
some ordinary reporter whom no one suspected of 'connexions.' The man so
bought was regularly conspicuous for the virulence of his patriotism [A signifi-
cant touch! That is the way of opposition papers in domestic politics.], and in
very timely ways, as best suited the purposes of Prussian policy, he would rouse or
quiet public emotions. [So again, in internal politics.] That system was much
more effective and much cheaper. I know the names of the wretches who were
so employed by German money. I had rather not divulge them." Bismarck worked
the newspapers in the same way even after 1870. Busch, Tagebuchblattcr, Vol. II,
p. 394 (English, Vol. II, pp. 95-96), Feb. 20, 1873: "It appears from a report of Ar-
nim's of the seventeenth of last month that he has engaged a certain [Rudolf] Lin-
dau, brother of the dramatist and critic, and afterwards councillor of the Embassy in
Berlin, to furnish him with detailed reports from the French press. In a despatch of
the eighth instant the ambassador states that Lindau has asked not to be deprived of
the assistance of Beckmann. . .Arnim strongly supported their request 'in the in-
.
neither Herr Lindau nor any other official at the Embassy was in a position to deal
with all the material, and to furnish full and satisfactory reports on the press, and at
the same time to write articles himself for the German, Italian, and Russian news-
papers." Bismarck rejected the device proposed, which shows simply that he preferred
some other. With his crude outspokenness Bismarck makes no secret of the money
he spent on the French press. Cf. his Gedan^en und Erinnerungen, p. 508 (Butler,
Vol. II, pp. 179-80), Arnim's prosecution in question: "At no time during his trial
did I mention the fact that certain amounts 6,000 or 7,000 thalcrs which had been
set aside to have our policy defended in the French press, he used to attack our
policy and make trouble for me in the German press." So the Prussian press, there-
fore, would seem to have been, in part at least, as venal as the French. Such con-
fessions on the part of outstanding leaders in public life are precious evidence in
that they establish facts which otherwise would remain doubtful so long as they
were known only through the gossip that is bandied about. In 1913-14, for in-
stance, it was persistently rumoured that the German Government was paying
out large sums of money for attacks by French newspapers on army legislation in
12 1 6 THE MIND AND SOCIETY J
755
will hold at the right moment, that it will not rouse every
its
tongue
it will steer its readers towards
sleeping dog, that venting their
spleen in ways less dangerous to the government than others.
Then
again, there are moments when violent agitations lay hold on a
country. At such times a spark will set off the magazine, and it is
better to be sure no opposition paper strikes it. Thirdly and this
is
exactly what powerful financial syndicates have in view, when,
like governments, they subsidize apparently hostile newspapers
there are ways of opposing certain measures, certain proposals for
legislation, which may influence sentiments quite
as favourably as
the best defence, if not more so. Fourthly, to have a subsidized
alleged diary of Emperor Frederick in question) "I myself consider the Diary
:
even more genuine than you do. [Bracketed clauses in quotations from Busch
. . .
are omitted from the published German text. A. L.] He [the Emperor Frederick]
was far from being and the father was certainly not a first-
as clever as his father,
rate politician. It is just that which proves its genuineness to me. But at first we
must treat it as doubtful. [The following (English, Vol. II, p. 435, Sept. 28,
. . .
1888) is entirely omitted in German. A. L.] On that occasion he also repeated his
:
plan of campaign with regard to the publication in the Deutsche Rundschau: 'First
assert it to be a forgery, and express indignation at such a calumny upon the noble
dead. Then, when they prove it to be genuine, refute the errors and foolish ideas
"
that it contains.'
3
1755 Busch, Tagebuchblatter (English, Vol. II, p. 471; Passage omitted from
German), quotes a letter from William I to Bismarck dated April 8, 1866, in
which the King complains of an article against the Duke of Coburg (in the
Kreuzzeitung). Bismarck replies: "I confess frankly that the main part of this
article was written at my instance, as I like every one of my colleagues while
having indeed no influence over the Kreuzzeitung to prevent their insertion of mat-
ters to which I object, have yet enough to secure the insertion of what is not
directly opposed to its own tendencies." The Siccle was one of the two republican
newspapers tolerated in France after the coup d'etat of 1851. It received patronage
and subsidies from Napoleon III. Ollivier, L'Empire liberal, Vol. IV, p. 17: "The
Siccle did not belong to a business man, but it was a going concern yielding
large profits. That compelled the editor always to be very careful when con-
ducting an opposition opposition was its reason for existence in order to
1755 INFLUENCE OF NEWSPAPERS 12 1 7
which was in no way irreconcilable with the Empire. The . . . Siecle [in 1858,
Vol. IV, p. 69] was saved only by a personal appeal by Havin to the Emperor.
. Havin [Vol. XI, p. 122] was a very wide-awake person
. . . . .
maintaining
almost friendly relations with the ministers, and posing as an anti-Clerical to escape
to seem anti-dynastic'* 4
having 1755 ).
4
X
755 I
prefer examples from the past as less likely to stir the feelings of readers
living today. Ollivier, L'Empirc liberal, Gov-
Vol. VI, pp. 212-13: "They [the
ernment's commissioners in Body] the Legislative smooth did not have such
sailing when it came to refuting charges as to stock manipulations that the 'Com-
pany of the South* was alleged to have worked on its own shares in agreement
with the Credit Mobilier. [An account of that fraudulent operation follows.]
. . .
to discover that the editor was always chosen without knowing who made the
their
choice! They know at this late day that the founder and backer was M. L ,
former chief of police and organizer of the League for the Defence of Jews. And to
think that some of them still professed to be revolutionaries! But they had to earn
I2l8 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY Z
755
festo that the Federation published on the occasion of the Balkan
War of 1912. We
are not interested here in the form in which
the sentiment was expressed, in the derivation, which was as absurd
as any other, but only in the sentiment, altogether unreasoned, in-
their bread and butter, and others just had to write from a mania for seeing their
names at the end of an article. It was a form of humbug, and one had to put up
with everything! They accepted the editorship of a certain P . Now P is
one of the big shareholders in Hiimanite! Does he still represent L and his
heirs? That question was not
raised at the last Socialist convention, yet it was the
one issue that should have been raised!" And to what advantage? If you get rid of
one, another takes his place. If that is the organization of society, there will never
be any shortage on the side of personnel! In 1913, as president of a parliamentary
commission, Jaurcs made every effort to save the plutocrat and demagogue Caillaux
from deserved rebuke for trying to influence the courts in favour of Rochette, through
his friend and crony, Monis. All parties try to use the newspapers for their own
purposes, and the papers, in turn, extort favours by threatening to attack or prom-
ising to defend now one minister, now another. If a person wants to have a news-
paper of his own, he has to face huge expenditures, and they would be net losses
were they not offset by compensations in the shape of honours pure and simple in
the case of some few (very few) politicians; of honours plus money in the case of
most politicians, most political financiers, trust magnates, political attorneys, "fixers,"
"speculators." Palamenghi-Crispi, Giovanni Giolitti, pp. 76-77: "Crispi was unique
among the politicians of his time in this respect also: Ascribing to the newspaper
the great importance that it in fact has in modern life, he always wanted to have
a paper in which he could say what he had to say. But instead of shouldering off
the expense of such a thing upon some group of business men, as so many others
have done (it would be easy to give names), he always paid the bills himself with
his own money. Only by rare exception would some friend help. So it came about
that he was often faced with debts that he was pinched to pay, and had sometimes
to resort to loans from banks, which he was always careful to settle. Everyone knows
the high cost of newspapers that are exclusively devoted to politics. The Rijorma
alone, the organ of the historic Left, which defended Liberal ideas and Liberal states-
men over a period of thirty years, absorbed about 1,200,000 lire from the fruits of
Crispins devoted [That adjective is perhaps superfluous.] labours." Giornale d' Italia,
Nov. 23, 1913: "Another nomination [for the Senate] that is being talked about
on what foundation we do not know and which would greatly please the Reform-
ists [Socialists], is the name of the Milanese banker Delia Torre, who has been and
istnagna pars financial in Socialist and democratic newspapers democratic in a
Reformist sense. Delia Torre is, in a word, the deity of 'blocist' high finance and
may some day be called a pioneer, the day that is, when high finance in Italy, hav-
6
1755 The C.G.T., as they call the Federation in France, held a congress at Paris,
Nov. 24, 1912, to declare its opposition to the war. It adopted the following resolu-
ing seen which way the wind is blowing, joins the bloc as its elder sister in France
did." Delia Torre was in fact named Senator along with two other Socialists, and
the Corriere della sera, Nov. 25, 1913, writes: "Giolitti today unlocked the doors of
the Senate to Karl Marx, who was behaving a bit too obstreperously up in the gar-
ret [Giolitti had said before the Chamber that now at last the Socialists "had
laid in the garret.*'] and disturbing the peace of mind of people
Marx away up
who thought they had adroitly kidnapped him. Three Socialists are not, after
. . .
Government, to which they owe such a debt of gratitude [And vice versa.*], or to
the bourgeoisie. Since the Senate is a legislative body, it too should have rep-
. . .
resentatives of all political tendencies, and it is therefore not a bad idea that, just
as Radicals are now quite numerous in the Senate, Socialists also should find their
place thither Socialists at least from among the favoured few who are well ac-
quainted with stairways at the Quirinal and who in practice show themselves dis-
posed to 'be reasonable.' It is a real pity that the Senate cannot be seasoned also
with a pinch or two of republic; but Republicans, fortunately, never cause any alarm
and, unfortunately, are most pig-headed about their doctrinal chastity. [And so can-
not have a newspaper, since they insist on paying for it themselves.] The Sen- . . .
ate must in fact be de-aged. Or rather, let us call a spade a spade: The Senate too
must be put to some use. That language is more exact and more faithfully describes
the reality of things. [Very true.] If in an honestly democratic spirit one should
setout in earnest to make the Senate genuinely representative of all the currents in
the nation's thought, there could be but one logical conclusion: to face the issue of
an elective Senate fairly and squarely. ... It is true that in that case there would
be a more generous sprinkling of Socialists at Palazzo Madama [the Senate build-
ing] and governmental munificence would no longer be called upon to manifest
itsselfish sympathy with extremist parties." Karly in October, 1918, the following
item appeared in the newspapers: "The great liberal organ in England, the Daily
Chronicle, has been bought by Sir Henry Dalziel and a few friends for ,300,000.
. . . The new proprietor is a wealthy newspaper man and member of Parlia-
ment for the Liberals. He is known especially as an intimate friend and loyal
supporter of Lloyd George both in Parliament and in the press. In that chiefly lies
the political significance of the purchase of the Daily Chronicle, a paper that had
seemed tolerably lukewarm toward Lloyd George of late, and was leaning rather
towards that wing of the Liberal party that recognizes Asquith as its leader. It is
announced that the policies of the paper will not be changed, but it is probable that
under its new ownership it will vigorously support Lloyd George."
7
In May, 1913, a Florentine newspaper that was discontinuing publication
1755
explained how during its thirty-three years of existence it had been sustained by
the various successive governments. Almost all the great Italian newspapers main-
tained a silence of holy chastity on the incident, which might have been of greater
interest to their readers than many insignificant items of news that they did pub-
I22O THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1756
facts in general nevertheless has faith implicit in his own news-
paper on matters in which he can have no doubt as to the part
played by the pocket-books of international finance. During the
Balkan War the news published in many papers had much less to
do with facts as they were than with the facts as coloured in the
interests of this or that "scheme" on the
part of international finance;
and yet the news they printed was accepted as news by persons who
were perfectly well aware of the resourcefulness and power of those
8
influences. Plutocratic demagogues, such as Caillaux and
Lloyd
George, are praised by newspapers of great reputation in deference to
the clink of the arguments that
Figaro found so irresistible. Many
of the small fry take the bait and that is
nothing to wonder at;
but plenty of big fish too are hooked, and that is not so
easy to under-
stand. true that the big fellows often
profess to believe
It is
many
things that they find it to their interests to believe.
posal is not an honest man (or, he is being paid to make it). There-
fore the proposal A
is detrimental to the
l
country." That of course
lish.They probably remembered most opportunely the adage: De te jabnla narratur.
The Belgian Government has published a list of the newspapers that were subsi-
dized by King Leopold to praise his administration in the
Congo or at least to say
nothing as to its crimes. Some future historian of the present plutocratic regime in
the civilized countries of the West will
get some most instructive data from that
publication.
8
1755 In Italy plenty of attention was called to the fact in the case of
newspapers
hostile to Italy; but nothing was said of the
pro-Italian papers, though their policies
were dictated by the very same forces that determined the policies of the opposition
press.
x
1756 Oftentimes the argument runs: "The person who is making the proposal
A today was opposed to it some time ago." That is supposed to prove that the pro-
posal A is not sound. Never mind the fact that a man may honestly change his mind
as circumstanceschange Bonghi used to say, in that connexion, that only an ani-
mal never changes its mind. But even if it were shown that the person proposing A
has changed not in view of any intrinsic merit in A but in hopes of
deriving some
1757 THE NEWSPAPER AND SEX 1 22 1
papers use. They never admit that there are problems of things.
They answer all
questions by abusing persons. Jugglers of pens
it easier to call names than to think
naturally find logically, and
their tactics often prove successful because the public that feeds on
such writing is an ignorant public, and forms its opinions more by
itssentiments than by its brains. But the cord breaks when the bow
is drawn too taut. In a number and slander of men
of countries abuse
in public life have ceased to be effective. They were more so in the
days when courts afforded protection against them and they were
therefor^ less common.
1757. j
A
considerable group of such derivations aims at utilizing
the sex Residues. It was a rule with few exceptions in centuries past
for members of a dominant religion to accuse dissenters of im-
morality (1341^). Ignoring the fact that such charges were
nearly always us assume that they were true. In that case
false, let
the derivationwould have a logical element, being soundly urgeable
against anyone preaching a certain morality and then deporting
himself against it. But that logical element vanishes when the
derivation turned against statesmen or heads of governments
is
( 2262). Facts clearly show that there is not the slightest connexion
between a man's sex morality and his worth as a statesman or as an
personal advantage from A, that would still be nothing against A. It would simply
be taking us back to the personality derivation mentioned above. The fact that such
derivations can have no weight in the judgment that is to be given of A is all the
truth there was in the defence Caillaux's friends made for him against the attacks
of M. Calmette in Figaro. It is undeniable that the advantages or disadvantages ac-
cruing to a given society from an income-tax levy have nothing, absolutely nothing,
to do with the domestic, moral, and even statesmanlike qualities of the individual
proposing one. But to inflict the death-penalty on a person for using those fallacious
derivations seems to be too severe a punishment; and if the practice should become
so general as to be applied by every citizen, few newspaper editors, and indeed few
writers, would be left alive.
1222 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1758
It was
long asserted, though in no way proved, that Napoleon I had
relations with his sisters. In the eyes of many people, that accusation
all
by itself was enough to condemn him as citizen, as public servant,
as head of the state. So in days gone by a charge of heresy, even
when unproved, was make a man at least suspect to
sufficient to
good Catholics.
Heresy in matters of sex holds in our day the place
held by heresy of yore in matters of Catholic doctrine.
1759* Verbal derivations are also great favourites with the news-
people. They are said, among other things, to hold meetings at night and take ad-
vantage of the darkness to mingle promiscuously. That is altogether false and has
no basis except a tale of John of Leyden, King of Munster, and the fact that a hun-
dred years or more ago there were some few who believed that in order to be saved
one had to go stark-naked Adam before the Fall, whence they were called
like
'Adamists.' ... So know, there has been nothing of the sort since, and
far as I
intelligent people in Amsterdam ridicule the absurd stories that have been spread
abroad. All the same I remember that at Paris a certain Soubeyran averred that he
had attended one such meeting at night and had had the daughter of his host who
thereafter refused him at home what she had granted him in the name of Christian
love. There is nothing surprising in the fact that there should be liars now and
then. What is more so is that an imposture should spread so easily in the credence
of a whole people, as is the case in this matter. And then there is the story of the
girl with a pig's snout, a print of whom was sold to every cobbler in Paris and
Holland. In Amsterdam she was generally supposed to live in a house on the
Keyssergraft. However, no one could ever point it out and that was enough to
show that the story was false."
1760 RESIDUES AND DERIVATIONS 1223
is enormous. It
may, therefore, be a very good idea to have several
such papers at one's disposal, and better yet if they belong to different
parties.
The powerful financial combinations of our day have come
to understand that thoroughly and, taking advantage of the im-
into the hands of the 'yellow' journalist who is at the head of the Daily
same great
Mail and a 'combine* of imperialistic protectionist newspapers. Rider Haggard is a
man of the sensational school, the school of those newspaper men in Italy who
described the agricultural marvels of Libya before the war and during the first
months of the war.'*
2
1760 Robert de Jouvenel, La republique des camarades, pp. 201-09: "The man-
ager of a newspaper is rarely a newspaper man. [That may be overstating a little.]
He is almost never a politician. He is, most often, a man interested in public con-
tracts.Pie is always a business man. [As we have often remarked, there is, in gen-
eial, an clement of truth in rhetoric of that type.] Sometimes the newspaper is his
only business, then again it is only one branch of a main business. In either case,
the newspaper business involves the turnover of a great commercial establishment.
[That is true of large countries where plutocracy is dominant.] There are papers
[in France] whose annual business amounts to more than $6,000,000. A third-class
daily represents an outlay of $300,000 a year. To handle such a budget it is not
enough to have imagination, wit, or even talent. ... In 1830 a newspaper was a
matter of four small pages the two sides of one sheet. It contained a few poorly
paid or unpaid articles, no despatches, no costly news, no illustrations. It cost 5
cents. Today most newspapers are of six, eight, ten, or twelve pages. They are illus-
trated with costly pictures. They carry articles by Academicians or other outstanding
individualities for which high prices are paid. They print columns of despatches
some of which cost several francs per word. They are sold to retailers at a fifth of
a cent per copy. How
then do they live? They live by their advertising, unless, of
course, they live by their 'deals.' A
newspaper can do without writers and reporters,
it can even do without appearing. [Jouvenel explains that paradox in a note: "There
reading a great writer, it seems evident enough that only such a man
could have the power to shape
society in that way, his way.
1763. When one reads Voltaire, it is natural
enough to conclude
that he was the artisan of the unbelief so
prominent in the people
of his time. But the matter a little more closely, we can
pondering
only wonder how it could have come about, if that is the general
rule, that the writings of Lucian, which are in no way inferior to
Voltaire's on the side of
literary quality and logical effectiveness,
failed to have an influence as great as Voltaire's, that Lucian stood
alone in his unbelief while faith and were all
superstition increasing
about him. There is no way of explaining such facts, and many
to any decision, the manager of a paper, be he an angel with wings, has to con-
sider two essential requisites: i. He must not offend those who have the news to
give out all the powers, that is, in politics or public administration. 2. He must
not offend those who have 'publicity' to give out, in other words, all the
powers
in business and finance. [Not all, to be exact: those with which the
strictly only
newspaper is when they are ser-
working.] Newspapers are called 'governmental'
are called 'independent* when
they are merely 'governmental/ An 'op-
vile. They
position paper* is a paper that is flirting with the ministry in power. Some few
organs have no connexions with the Government in any way through anybody, but
no one of course would ever make the mistake of taking them
seriously."
1764 VOLTAIRE AND LUCIAN 1225
others of the kind, except by assuming that the seed that is sown
bears fruit, or fails to bear fruit, according as it falls on congenial
or uncongenial soil. The philosophes of the eighteenth century in
France revived arguments that had already been used against Chris-
tianity by Celsus and the Emperor Julian. Why did they succeed
where their predecessors failed? Obviously because there was a
difference in the minds of the people whom
they addressed. But that
is not all. Had
Voltaire been the chief artisan of the ideas prevalent
secondary.
1764. What we have just been saying relates to the effectiveness of
certain reasonings, but it has nothing to do with the intrinsic value
of the reasonings in themselves. It is obvious that the scientific genius
of a Newton, the military skill of a Napoleon or a Moltke, the diplo-
matic talent of a Bismarck, the literary value of a Lucian or a Vol-
taire, have nothing to do with residues. But for the activity of such
men to have any notable effects, they must encounter favourable
circumstances in their respective societies through the presence of
certain residues. Had Newton lived in the Middle Ages, he might
have produced some mere work in theology. Had Voltaire lived in
the day of Lucian, he would have had no following. Had Bismarck
lived in a country controlled
by democratic or plutocratic politicians,
and had he managed to get as far as a seat in a Parliament, he would
1226 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1765
have seen a Depretis or a Giolitti preferred to him in Italy, a Rouvier
or a Caillaux in France.
1765/ Still another cause of the error of assigning too great an
where, somehow, and few the histories in our day which fail to
assume implicitly or explicitly that principles and theories serve to
1766
x
A
few centuries back almost all the derivations that were used in social or
pseudo-scientific matters were combined with considerations of Christian theology;
nowadays they are combined with considerations of humanitarian theology. The
old ones often seem absurd to us; ours will seem just as absurd to people of future
generations, when some other theology has superseded the humanitarian. A few
centuries ago everything was explained by "original sin." Nowadays everything is
8
explained by "the shortcomings of society" ( 1716 ). In the future there will be
some other explanation, equally theological and, from the experimental standpoint,
equally inept.
1767 RESIDUES AND DERIVATIONS 1227
to eliminate, in appearances at least, any substantial contradiction
1
that may exist between them. Once a derivation is accepted, it
comes about that among educated persons literary men, theolo-
gians, metaphysicists, pseudo-scientists and the like there will
be
some who insist on drawing logical inferences from it. Such in-
ferences stray farther and farther afield from the residues corre-
1767
l
We have already dealt with this tendency at length, noticing the error of
many educated persons in imagining that because they themselves feel an urgent
need, apparent or real, for logic the same need is felt, and to the same extent, by
everybody. That among other reasons is why they devise "scientific'* religions, in
the belief that in so doing they are satisfying a public demand. As a matter of fact
such religions remain for the exclusive use and consumption of their few founders.
1228 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1767
to getting along together and cohabit in a sort of harmony; but the
ing, b, in
residues figure. And yet daily experience
which other
shows that many such reasonings lead to inferences that do accord
with the facts. That cannot be doubted, once we reflect that they are
the only ones that have been used in social life, and that if they led to
results which did not square with the facts, all societies would long
since have been annihilated. How then can it be that conclusions
drawn from residues should so accord with the facts?
1769. The solution of this problem is to be sought in the relation-
tion, any convenient twist, is admissible. Moses Maimonides will use the same
method in the twelfth century, upholding both the Torah and Aristotle the Torah
interpreted after the manner of the Talmudists, Aristotle after the materialist fashion
2
of Averroes 1931 ], The history of the human mind is full of such pious para-
[
doxes. What
Philo did nineteen hundred years ago, many honest minds are doing
in our day under the sway of a resolve not to abandon beliefs that are regarded as
something ancestral. [Still representing as particular a trait that is general for every
type of derivation.] The most perilous acrobatics are risked in order to reconcile
faith and reason. [In general terms, to reconcile derivations based on heterogeneous
residues.] After obstinately rejecting the results of science, people reverse positions
when the evidence is overwhelming and coolly say, 'We knew that before you did.' "
1230 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1770
elusions and experience should be certain and perfect. If the residues
were selected at random and the derivations likewise, accord would
be exceedingly rare. So then, since accord is frequent but not in-
variable, residues and derivations must occupy some middle ground
between the two extremes. It is to be noted that a residue which is
at variance with experience may be corrected by a derivation which
is at variance with logic in such a way that the conclusion is
brought
back to something like experimental That comes about be-
fact.
still more
general, as to how, namely, the forms of living beings
and
societies are determined. Such forms are not creatures of chance
problem: Social reasonings yield results that are not too greatly at
variance with realities because their residues, both those which in-
spire the derivations and those which they utilize, stand more or
less related to realities. If the basic residues do come close to realities
and derivations are moderately we
get results that, as a rule,
logical,
are not too greatly at variance with realities. If the primary residues
under just
what circumstances one must not kill, in what other
cases one may kill, and in what other cases still one must kill. The
injunction is, "Love thy neighbour as thyself"; and that too over-
steps the rule, which is
really being set up in order that the people
simple principles that overstep realities and aim at goals that lie
beyond them, sometimes far far beyond. In a word, to get back
from derivations to realities certain allowances almost always have
to be made.
The make
a good derivation out of a reasoning are
qualities that
oftentimes the opposite, therefore, of the qualities which would
make it a sound logico-experimental reasoning; and the nearer it
comes to one of those limits, the farther it
gets from the other. But
the logico-experimental reasoning is the one that corresponds to
reality,
it is clear that the
divergence existing between derivations
and reality must somehow or other have been corrected. The cor-
*
rection is obtained through the conflict and composition ( 2087 f .)
of the many derivations current in a society. The simplest, but also
the least frequent, form in which this process manifests itself is in
the case of two directly contradictory derivations, and B, where A A
oversteps reality in one direction and B in another; so that when A
and B are at work simultaneously they come closer to reality thaa
either of
singly would do. The derivation A, for in-
them taken
stance, bids people to love their neighbours as themselves, and the
derivation B enjoins the vendetta as a duty. The more complex, but
also the more frequent, form is the case where there are many der-
ivations, A, B C
f . . . that are not directly contradictory, and which,
*
1772 [A technical term, not to be taken in its ordinary senses. A. L.]
1775 APPROXIMATIVE THINKING 1233
when combined and mutually composed ( 2087 2152 f.), give a
f.,
vantages of increasing the public debt, and so on, which are all
derivations observable among all civilized
peoples.
1773. Effects upon conclusions of divergences between residues
and logico-experimental principles. Suppose we are reasoning by the
logico-experimental method. Taking certain residues, a, as our prem-
ises we reach the conclusions c. If we reasoned in the same way
cism plays, and will continue to play, for a long time to come, a very
important part in social matters: and it often corrects deficiencies
in premises ( 1769). If a person has a good topographical chart and
knows how to use accurately, he will be sure to find his way
it
from one place to another. But the road will be found just as well,
and perhaps better, by an animal guided solely by instinct, and by
a person who also follows it instinctively from having been over it
a number of times. If a person has a poor topographical chart and
reasons on it in strict logic, he will probably find his way less
readily
than persons in those extreme cases. Ancient geographers used to
*
1775 One group of derivations pretends to answer the question by restating it
4
as a problem of "rights" on the part of the individual as against 'rights'* on the
part of the "State." That solution is like explaining why water rises in a pump by
the theory that Nature abhors a vacuum that is to say, it explains facts not by
other facts, but by imaginary entities. No one can say precisely what the "State" in
question may be, much less what its "rights" are, and what the "rights" of the
"individual." The mystery and darkness increase if one inquires as to the relations
between such "rights" and various utilities. Finally, assuming that the problem of
terms is solved, no one can say how
the theoretical solution can be applied in the
concrete. The solution therefore seen to be merely the expression of a pious wish
is
on its author's part; and he might have stated it outright, without going so far
afield to dig up those very pretty but very obscure entities.
1778 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1235
1
say that the Peloponnese was shaped like the leaf of a plane-tree.
If a person starts out on that premise and reasons logically, he will
ponnese has the shape of a plane-tree leaf. Finally comes the merely
practical man, and he
is like the
ignorant person who has no map
at all but has traversed the Peloponnese from end to end. These
two sorts of persons oftentimes obtain results that are not very
will also be false (at variance with the facts). But the term "false"
often indicates a false explanation of a real fact; and in that case it
is
possible, within certain limits, to draw from such propositions con-
clusions that are true (which accord with the facts).
1778. Examples. Once upon a time to explain how a pump sucks
water it was said that "Nature abhors a vacuum." The fact was real,
the explanation false; but the explanation will lead to conclusions
that are verifiable by experience. Fill a bottle with water, press a
finger over the mouth, immerse the neck in water, and remove the
finger. What
happen? The answer is: The water will remain
will
suspended in the bottle, for if it came out, the bottle would be left
empty; and we know that that is impossible, since Nature abhors
x
1776 Commentarius in Dionysium Periegetem (Or bis descriptio, .v.
Eustathius,
157), pp. in,
245: "Ye should know that just as the Euxine is comparable to a bow,
so many other places are diversely representable by a certain similitude. So history
says that the Egyptian delta is triangular. Thus is Alexandria represented by
. . .
a chlamys [a military cloak] ; Italy by an ivy-plant; Spain by an ox's hide; the island
of Naxos by a vine-leaf; the Peloponnese by a leaf of the plane-tree; Sardinia by a
human footprint; Cyprus by a sheep's hide; Libya by a trapeze; and so other lands
the ancients pictured otherwise."
1236 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1778
a vacuum. We
perform the experiment and see that the conclusion
is in accord with the facts.
Now let us perform the same experiment with a tube of mercury
a metre long, one end of the tube being open and immersed in a
since, after all, water is "the best of the elements" and should there-
fore have greater privileges than mercury. And such a reasoning
would be quite as sound as an argument by M. Leon Bourgeois in
favour of solidarity.
To why one "ought" to be hospitable to strangers the
explain
Greeks, who were pagans, used to say that strangers came of Zeus,
and Christians quoted the Gospels, where it is written that he who
1
receiveth a stranger receiveth Christ. If one infers from such propo-
sitions that it is "useful" to show one gets
hospitality to strangers,
a proposition that might be in accord with the facts in the case of
the ancients and, though not by any means to the same degree, in
the case of the moderns. The conclusions would be something like
the conclusions we reached for the bottle full of water. If we should
1778
l
Matt. 25:35, and 38-40: "I was a stranger and yc took me in," etc.
1778 "NATURE ABHORS A VACUUM" 1237
strangers are to
be honoured as ambassadors from Zeus, according
to the Greeks, and as Christ in person according to the Christians,
we would get a conclusion that has never squared with the facts
among either Greeks or Christians.
We may therefore say, reasoning very roughly, that from the
derivations current in a given society one may get conclusions that
will be verified by experience, provided (i) We ma\e a certain
allowance in such derivations, which customarily overstep the limits
actually aimed at ( 1772) provided (2) the reasoning does not
;
graphic film, which when exposed in a given place, receives an impression of things,
of "facts." The derivations through which he voices his impressions correspond to
the developing of the film. The metaphysicist would have the film, after it has been
developed, show
things, "facts,** that were not present in the place where the film
was exposed, but which are just as "real" in fact, as some say, they are the only
"reality." The experimentalist expects the developed film to show nothing but an
image of the things, the "facts,** that were present in the place where the film was
exposed. 2. Then there is the usual difference between the metaphysical absolute
and the experimental relative. The metaphysicist thinks his intuitive operations guide
him to "absolute truth.** The scientist accepts his only as an indication of what
reality may be, an indication that it is the exclusive prerogative of experience to
confirm or refute.
To return to the analogy just suggested: After the film has been developed, the
metaphysicist thinks that it corresponds perfectly with reality. The experimentalist
knows that there are countless divergences between the two. We
will say nothing
1238 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY *779
1779. Towards the end of the nineteenth century in France the
rewards the good and punishes the wicked; and the second could
be congenial only to the fanatical ascetic who despises all earthly
of the fact that the film shows what exists in space as existing in a plane, that it
fails to show the colours of the various objects, and so on. There are other more
special differences still, as for example whether some living being may have moved,
or a leaf been stirred by the wind, while the film was exposed. By a very extraordi-
nary coincidence there happens to be a real case corresponding to the very com-
parison we instituted for mere purposes of clarity. Many people have believed that
photographs have recorded the "astral doubles" of human beings and animals. They
have shown the photographs of a human being with a spot near by, or of pheasants
with another spot, and the spot they call the "astral double" of the human being
or the pheasant. Such photographs all beginners make, when they have not yet
learned to take photographs and develop films without spots. How many such spots
have been palmed off as real things by metaphysicists and theologians!
1783 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1239
principles
from which they logically follow. In the logico-experi-
mental sciences the manifestations are in accord with the facts,
if
persons who imagine that reason and logic are the guides of human
societies; and yet those same people unwittingly accept under other
1240 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1784
forms propositions that are its equivalents. Theory, for instance, has
always been contrasted with practice by everybody everywhere, and
even the people who are pure theorists in certain matters recognize
the utility and the necessity of practice in other matters. Such
|nerely by trying
and trying again, rectifying mistakes as they went
fclong. Nowthanks to such theories, modern engineers not only
Eliminate the losses incident to the old mistakes, but erect buildings
<hat the master-masons and other artisans of past centuries could not
possibly
have built. Practice had taught physicians certain remedies
that were oftentimes better than those recommended by quacks or
alchemists. Sometimes again they were altogether worthless. Now-
adays chemical theories have eradicated not all, but a very large
1787 "THEORY AND PRACTICE" 1241
being considered as external facts purely and simply and never al-
lowed to master one's thinking. In two words: Inferences in the
practical field are the gainers from being essentially synthetic and
inspired by residues; scientific inferences, from being essentially
1242 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1788
people know how to act, but not how to explain why they act. Their
theories are almost always derivations bearing not the remotest re-
semblance to logico-experimental theories.
1790. The conflict between theory and practice sometimes takes
the form of an absolute denial of theory. certain "historical A
school," for instance, has denied not only that there are economic
theories, but even that there are laws in the economic field
( 2019 f.). If, with that start, the followers of the school had con-
fined themselves to practice, they might have carved niches for
themselves among our statesmen, instead of turning out the mere
sophists and chatterboxes they in fact proved to be. There was prob-
ably a large element of truth in the substance of their doctrines,
their error lying principally in their manner of stating it. What
they should have said was that the theories of political economy and
sociology are not as yet capable of yielding a synthesis of social phe-
nomena and giving reliable forecasts of the future in the domain of
the concrete; and that, as has been the case in other departments of
human knowledge, until
theory has made greater progress we had
better place our main reliance on practice and empiricism.
1791.But the partisans of the "historical school" were primarily
theorists. Their criticisms of the theories of political economy were
fact; whereas economic theories have at least some basis in fact and
sin only in being incomplete and unable to
yield a synthesis of con-
crete social phenomena. The theories of
political economy are
1792 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1243
religion different from the religion that they are combating. They
deny the supposedly absolute "laws" of their adversaries. But such
deities they replace with others that are just as far removed from the
sociology annoyed them. They did not feel themselves the men to
refute them, and strangers as they were to scientific method, they
could not get it through their heads that neither the old "laws," nor
"laws" of any other kind, can have any absoluteness. To remove the
obstacle that towered before them, therefore, they acted like the be-
lievers of
any new religion who destroy old altars to erect new ones,
as the Christians did when they proclaimed that the pagan gods
were but empty phantoms and that their God was the one living
1244 THE MIND AND SOCIETY *793
and true God. Nor did they fail to supplement their conviction in
faith by pseudo-reasonings designed to show that their religion was
much more rational than the old one. Such nonsense acquires and
holds prestige because it chances to accord with the sentiments and
the ignorance of the people who listen to it. That explains why "his-
torians" in the field of economics are able with little or no opposi-
tion to continue repeating, like parrots, that economic and social
laws suffer "exceptions," whereas, they say, scientific laws do not.
They do not know, they do not even suspect, that their "excep-
tions" are nothing but phenomena due to the operation of causes
alien to those which science, by its process of abstraction, chooses
to consider, and that such interposition of alien causes is as com-
monplace in chemistry, physics, geology, and all other sciences, as it
isin economics and sociology. The differences are quite other than
tion). From that point of view, political economy and sociology are
more like geology than like chemistry (97-101).
1793. Napoleon's hatred of "ideology" a striking instance of the
is
cloudy metaphysics which goes ingeniously seeking first causes and would ground
the legislation of the peoples upon them instead of adapting laws to what we know
of the human heart and to the lessons of history. Such errors could only lead to a
regime by men and they have in fact done so.
of blood, Who
cajoled the people by
thrusting upon a it
sovereignty it was unable to exercise? Whodestroyed the sacred-
ness of the laws and respect for the laws by basing them not on the sacred prin-
1794 TAINE AND THE "MATHEMATICAL METHOD*' 1245
with Napoleon's own appeal to the "sacred principles of justice."
That too belongs to pure metaphysics and in it
making
Napoleon,
unwittingly to be sure, was merely setting one "ideology" over
against another. And when he asserts that the "ideology" of the
others is the cause of the misfortunes of France, he is stating a theory
that may or may not be in accord with the facts but which in any
case remains a theory.
1794. The same thing happens with many writers. They reject
theories in words, but in the fact merely set one theory against an-
other. Taine, for instance, Ancien Regime, Bk. Ill, Chap. IV, sec. i
(Vol. II, p. 47), lays a share of the blame for the French Revolution
on the "mathematical method," by which he means the use of pure
of the Revolution, but all theories, are fashioned in just that way
with social theories, can all by itself picture the complicated phe-
nomena that we find in the concrete, and that therefore after break-
ing up phenomena into their elements by scientific analysis and
studying them in their various parts, we have to put them together
again and so get a synthesis that will yield the concrete phenome-
non. Taine has nothing of that sort in mind. He notes an error in
French thinking and tries to show that it was responsible for the
disasters of France, and going on
along that line he evolves a theory
that is as abstract, as unilateral, as "mathematical," as the theories
he is
deploring and which is false into the bargain, in that it mis-
ciples of justice,on the nature of things and the nature of civic justice, but simply
on the an assembly made up of individuals who are stranger to any knowl-
will of
practice substantially, it is an
intuitive perception that to keep close
to realities one had better reason on residues rather than on deriva-
tions comes to in still other ways. Of the same type is the
light
maxim that it is better in everything to follow the "golden mean";
or the adage that rules (derivations) should be interpreted accord-
ing to the "spirit" and not according to the letter, which, often-
times, is just another way of saying that rules ought to be inter-
reasoning one must either deny the premises or find some flaw in
the method by which the conclusions were drawn. Believers refuse
to follow the first course. They are necessarily forced, therefore, to
adopt the second. That is why some of them bluntly deny that one
can reason logically on such premises as theirs, and demand that
they be taken not "according to the letter," but "according to the
spirit"; while others, again, instead of rejecting logic take it for
and call upon casuistry to furnish a means of keeping the
their ally
of the morrow, rapacious seekers after the good things of this world, fighters. The
adaptation was made possible by derivations; but the derivations also had some
effect upon the substance of things and produced new consequences such as the
days the Roman Empire was falling. One may see from St.
when
8
Gregory of Tours ( 1379 ) how thin the Christian varnish lay over
Prankish kings and Barbarian chieftains who were adapting the
new religion to their fierce warlike natures. That indeed was the
reason why the western districts* of the Mediterranean basin were
better able to resist Asiatic invasions than the lands in the East,
where the inhabitants were by nature milder and were growing
still more so. A
people of ascetics and monks, such as would have
resulted had the derivations of the primitive Christians been literally
the old, derivations turn up in the pinch to justify the violation of the dogma. The
Catholics excogitated that most ingenious of derivations about the three contracts.
Socialists, whether because less ingenious or more modest, simply say that they can-
not refrain from borrowing money until interest on loans has been generally abol-
ished,and with that very convenient excuse handy they can go blithely on till the
day one hears in the vale of Jehosaphat
Ages; yet they should be reminded that had the sentiments which
found expression in that fashion chanced to fail, the countries of
Western Europe would have suffered the same fate as the countries
of Asia Minor and European Turkey and our philosophers, instead
;
ligious,
not sufficiently "Christian," as they say, and because it found
it, praises it, enjoys its comforts; for, as Dante says, "the contradic-
tion consenteth not" that one should accept the end without accept-
8
ing the means as well.
1800. Most of the precepts in the Gospels are poetical derivations
that express certain residues; and it has been for the very reason
that they are lacking in definiteness and are often contradictory that
they have proved acceptable to all sorts of peoples in so many dif-
ferent periods of history. In times when Class I residues predomi-
ciling certain religious and moral derivations with practical life was all to the good
of society. There were respects in which it was beneficial, respects in which it was
detrimental. We
are merely saying that the beneficial aspects were of greater weight
than the harmful.
l8oi DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 125!
1
or the lilies of the field. If that
precept were taken literally, all sav-
ing of wealth would disappear, and the civilized peoples would re-
lapse into savagery. Precepts stated in that fashion, if they are to be
taken at all
strictly,
are valid only for the
improvident and the
In every civilized* society, therefore, they have to be cor-
shiftless.
1800 * Matt. 6:19-34. There are a number of variants, but they make no essential
difference in the meaning: "Lay not up for yourselves treasures upon earth, where
moth and rust doth corrupt, and where thieves break through and steal. . . .
Therefore I say unto you: Take no thought for your life, what ye shall eat, or what
ye shall drink; nor yet for your body, what ye shall put on. Is not the life more
than meat, and the body than raiment? Behold the fowls of the air: for they sow
not, neitherdo they reap, nor gather into barns; yet your heavenly Father feedeth
them. Are ye not much better than they? And why take ye thought for raiment?
Consider the lilies of the field, how they grow; they toil not, neither do they spin.
Therefore take no thought, saying, What shall we eat? or, What shall we drink?
or, Wherewithal shall we be clothed? For after all these things do the Gentiles seek:
for your heavenly Father knowcth that ye have need of all these things. Take there-
fore no thought for the morrow: for the morrow shall take thought for the things
of itself. Sufficient unto the day is the evil thereof."
*
1801 Commentarii in Matthaeum
(6:19-34) (Opera, Vol. VII, pp. 43-46):
"i. Nc solidti sitis
quid .manducctis
. .
neque corpori vestro quid induamini:
some manuscripts add: 'or for what ye shall drink/ We are not altogether freed of
attention to the lot that nature has assigned to all beasts and animals and which is
common to man. We arc taught not to let our minds be absorbed (ne solliciti
simus) in what we eat. Since we win our bread in the sweat of our faces, we have
to labour. It is our engrossment (sollicitudo) in such things that should be mastered
(tollenda). for the reference to food and raiment, we are to take it as applying
As
to carnal food and raiment; but we should always be solicitous as to spiritual food
and raiment. 2. Is not the life more than meat and the body more than raiment?
What He means by that is that if a man has been attentive to the higher duties
(maiora) he will certainly fulfil lesser ones. 3. (6:26) Behold the jowls of the air
(Respicite volatilia caeh). The Apostle tells us that we should know no more than
is good for us. That lesson should be kept in mind in connexion with this passage;
for there are some who would go beyond what the Fathers say and, in trying to
soar aloft to the stars, sink to the depths. They say that the 'fowls of the air* are
angels of Heaven and other powers in the service of God, who are fed by God's
providence without taking any thought for themselves. If the passage means what
they say it means, how comes it that it is asked of men: 'Are ye not much better
than they?' It is better therefore to take it simply: for if the birds of the air are fed
by God's providence quite apart from worries and troubles, if they are today but
1252 THE MIND AND SOCIETY l802
torn, he would take St. Matthew's words in the sense that we should,
of course, work to earn our daily bread but in no way worry about
the future.
which figures not only in Christianity but
1802. Pure asceticism,
in many other religions, tends to shun hard work; and there have
been people in all ages who have lived in idleness as parasites on
society. That manner of living results from certain sentiments, not
from reasoning the latter comes in a posteriori to supply a logical
justification for the conduct. As regards his earning a livelihood,
Diogenes lived more or less the way a Capuchin friar lives, but the
reasons he gave for his conduct were not the ones that are put for-
ward by the friar. When, moreover, such theories have implications
that clash too violently with the requirements of individual or social
on following the words of the Gospels to the letter; and at the same
time there have been people alive to the requirements of civilized
tomorrow arc no more, if they have no immortal soul and will not live forever .
when they have ceased to be, how much more should men who have promise of
eternity be submissive to the will of God? 4. (6:28) Consider the lilies of the field:
He showed that the soul (King James Version: the life) was more than meat by the
simile of the birds. So now he shows that the body is more than raiment by the
things following. 5. (6:31) W
here j ore ta\e ye no thought, saying What shall we
eat: He grants that those whom He forbids to worry about the future should be
attentive to present things. So the Apostle said, I Thess. 2:9: '. . .
labouring night
and day because we would not be chargeable unto any of you .' The 'morrow' . .
in Scripture is to be taken as any time in the future. 6. (6:34) Sufficient unto the
day is the evil thereof: Here He uses 'evil* (malitiam) not as the contrary of virtue,
but for travail, affliction, the troubles of the world. . . . The worries of the moment
are therefore sufficient unto us. Let us refrain from thought of future things, since
it will be vain (incerta)"
*
1803 De sermone Domini in monte secundum Matthaeum, II, 17, 57 {Opera,
Vol. Ill, p. 1295; Wor^s, Vol. VIII, p. 109).
1803 "CONSIDER THE LILIES OF THE FIELD" 1253
merely proves that B has to be taken in some other sense than the
writing his treatise On the Labour of Months because there were not
a few such who were refusing to work, on the plea that in
among
that theywere obeying the Gospel. The Saint shows them that they
were wrong and involved in a contradiction, in that they themselves
3
were not following the Gospel precept to the letter. All that he
2
1803 After quoting St. Paul's exact words, the Saint adds: "To those who fail
precept of the Master when He says 'Behold the fowls of the air for they sow not,
neither do they reap nor gather into barns,' and 'Consider the lilies of the field,
how they grow. They toil not, neither do they spin.' In the passage in question the
Apostle teaches that they should work, labouring with their hands that they might
have wherewith even to give unto others (I Thess. 2:9). He often says of himself
that he wrought with his hands that he might not be chargeable to any man (II
Thess. 3:8). Of him it was written, Acts 18:3, that he joined Aquila because he
was of the same craft, that they might work together to earn a living. And in that
he seems not to have imitated the fowls of the air and the lilies of the field. [It
would seem so, in very truth. And yet not so:] It is sufficiently apparent from
these and other similar passages in Scripture that what Our Lord condemns is not
the provision a man makes for himself by human means, but rather service of God in
purport of such things [i.e., as a way of making a living] so that one aims in one's
jy
labour not at the kingdom of God, but at a comfortable living (acquisition em).
If St. Matthew really meant that, he may have had many excellent endowments,
the end that we take no thought of these necessary things. But why do they not
attend to what follows? For it is not only written that 'they sow not, neither do
they reap,' but it is further added: 'nor gather into barns.' Which barns may be
said to be either granaries or pantries. Why, then, do they wish to have hands idle
but pantries full? do they gather in
Why and save for their daily needs the things
that they receive of the work of others? Why do they grind? Why do they cook?
For verily the birds do not so.'*
4
1803 De scrmone Domini,
etc., II, 17, 58 (he. cit). [The Saint's idea, in a nut-
shell, is that are violating the precept of Jesus when they practise the monas-
monks
tic profession as a way of getting a living without work; they are not disobeying the
precept when they create and save wealth for the better service of God. A. L.J A
sermon attributed to Augustine, but which seems to be apocryphal, comes
St.
closer to the literal meaning of the Gospel text. In it the precept is taken as con-
demning greed, merely, and as a promise that God will take care to provide His
faithful with material goods. In another sermon entitled Eleemosinae efficacia:
Inanis est avarorum providentia, Sermones (Opera, Vol. V), CCCX, he writes: "Give
alms! Why do you fear? He who made you His favourite petitioner (? qui te
praerogatorem constituit) will not fail you. For His is the voice that chides untrust-
fulness in the Gospel, saying, 'Consider the fowls of the air for they sow not neither
do they reap,' nor do they have wine-cellars or pantries, yet 'your Heavenly Father
"
feedeth them.' Perhaps; but when the snow is on the ground the poor birds get
hungry, and not a few die; and such as live near human habitations are happy in-
deed to be fed on what human providence has in store.
5
1803 Anselme of Laon [Pareto attributes this work to Anselm of Canterbury.
I follow Migne. A. L.], Enarrationcs in Evangelium Matthaei, VI (6:25) (Migne,
p. 1312): "Ideo dico vobis: Ne soliciti sitis, etc. And since you cannot serve God
and mammon, be ye not solicitous [take no thought] of temporal wealth for the
sake of food and raiment. There are two kinds of solicitude, the one arising from
external circumstance, the other from the evil in man (alia est rerum alia ex vitio
hominum). Solicitude arises from external circumstance in that we cannot have
bread unless we sow, labour, and do other such things. Such solicitude the Lord
does not forbid, for He says: 'In the sweat of thy face shalt thou eat bread. [That
1803 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1255
6
thought shall one take of the morrow?" Following his usual cus-
tom, he begins by bringing out the arguments in favour of the solu-
tion that he is later to reject, and which, in the present case, is that
one should take thought for the morrow. In favour of that solution
we get: The
passage on the provident ant in Prov. 6:6: ["Go to
i.
the ant, thou sluggard: Consider her ways and be wise."] 2. Provi-
dence is an aspect of prudence, which is a virtue. 3. The passage in
John 12:6, from which it would appear
had a money- that Jesus
bag, which He entrusted to Judas ["For he had the bag and bare
what was put therein"]; and another, Acts 4:34-35, where the
Apostles are said to have kept the proceeds of the sale of the lands
that were laid at their feet. "Hence it is permissible to take thought
of the morrow. Against which stand the words of the Lord (Matt.
6:34): Take therefore no thought for the morrow/ Conclu- . . .
sion: Man should take thought for the future at proper and oppor-
7
tune times, but not except at such times." Of this invention of a
words about the fowls of the air, he adds, Homilia XXI in capitulum Matthaei VI,
VI, 3 (4) (Gaume, Vol. VII, p. sogb; Prevost, p. 1493): "What, then? There must
be no sowing, doth He say? Not that men must not sow, doth He say, but that one
should not be absorbed in the thought [of sowing] not that one should not work,
;
but that one should not degrade oneself, and torment oneself, with worldly striv-
ing."
Q a ae
1803 Summa theologiae, II II , qu. 55, art. 7 (Opera, Vol. VIII, pp. 402-03:
Utrum aliquis dcbcat esse sollicitus in futurum).
7
1803 "Conclusio. Oportet hominem tempore congruenti atquc opportune non
an tern extra illud tern pus dc juturis esse sollicitum!'
1256 THE MIND AND SOCIETY
1804
example oi the ant, the answer is "that the ant's care is proper to
the season and is therefore given us to imitate." When such a power-
ful mind as St. Thomas is found stooping to such wretched verbiage,
one is really forced to the conclusion that the enterprise of harmon-
izing the letter of the Gospel precept with the necessities of prac-
8
tical life is a
desperate one indeed.
1804. In the fourth century of the Christian era the heresy of the
Massalians (Pray-ers), also called Euchites (Praecatores, Orantes},
and Enthusiasts, broke out. The Massalians were said to have been
1
pagans originally, and that may well be; for, after all, residues of
asceticism are observable among the pagans as well as among Chris-
tians.Later on, at any rate, there were Christian heretics of the same
change them.
1806. The twelfth and thirteenth centuries witnessed a rebirth of
civilization in Italy and in France, which, as is
always the case, ex-
pressed itself in an intensification of Class I residues, which began
8
1803 [Pareto seems to overlook Ansclmc's phrase "despcrantes dc bonitatc Dei"
5
( 1803 ), which shows the ethical derivation for this Catholic view of "thought of
the morrow." A. L.]
1
1804 Epiphanius, Panariitm adversus haereses, lib. Ill, tomus II, Haeresis
St.
80, 1-2 (Opera, Vol. II, pp. 755, 758): a/Ua fi6vov "E/U^ef dvreg ("but being
. . .
41): "The Euchitae are said to believe that it is not lawful for monks to do any
work to earn their living, and so to have adopted the monk's profession in order to
be free of all work."
1807 THE POPES AND THE FRANCISCANS 1257
more vigorously to dispute the dominance of group-persistences
(Class II residues). The clergy were at that time the only intellec-
tual class in society, and they were gradually approximating lay
adopt the standpoint from which they view the situation. But there
is another
point of view as well the matter of progress in civiliza-
tion. From this latter standpoint the so-called perversion of morals
society,
which either ceases to progress or else actually retrogresses
the moment morals are "corrected" or "reformed" through any con-
siderable increase in certain Class II residues and in IV- residues
(asceticism). Not that good or bad morals in the clergy have any
direct influence on progress in civilization. They are merely an index
of the certain Class II residues, just as the rise of the mer-
power of
cury in a thermometer is not the cause of the rise in temperature
but merely an index of it. In the twelfth and thirteenth centuries a
tide of religious feeling, welling up then as it
always does from the
lower classes, arrested the progress of civilization; just as a tide
of religious feeling represented by the Protestant Reformation was
again to arrest it, though for a brief moment, later on. The medi-
aeval tidalwave left the Inquisition on the beach. The tidal wave
of the sixteenth century left the Jesuits. Both waves set back for
Pope. But if Villari had lived under the rule of that friar, neither
he nor his "vanities" would have escaped with unruffled fur. After
day, and can even count some now among votaries of the god Prog-
ress.He founded an order of friars for whom the Gospel verses
about the fowls of the air and the lilies of the field were, or were
supposed to be, a strict rule evident that such persons
of life. It is
row, there must be people to do that thinking for them. They can
be improvident only if they have a society of providents to live in
otherwise they all starve and the game is
up.
The attitudes of the various Popes towards the Franciscan
1810.
movement were determined by a variety of causes. Religious senti-
ments (Class II residues) were not altogether without effect, and
they were especially conspicuous under Celestine V. But the more
influential residues were those of Class I. The Pope had to solve a
problem that rulers are very frequently called upon to face: to find
stepped those limits, they repressed them. The Popes were willing
to use them as auxiliaries. They could not tolerate them as enemies.
They were glad to use them against heretics, and against rich and
powerful elements in the clergy who
were disposed to assert their
independence of the Holy See. Moral reform was a good weapon for
fighting such churchmen. But reform had to stop at the point
be-
yond which the Holy See itself would have been hurt. In the end
this latter conception prevailed; for, as always happens, the pre-
1260 THE MIND AND SOCIETY l8ll
1
tended return to the Gospel ended in being only a mask for heresy.
That indeed is the real reason why so many new admirers of St.
Francis have come forward in our day. They are simply enemies
of the Papacy and use praises of St. Francis as a weapon in their war.
1811. Active in them also is a residue of democratic humanitari-
the unfortunate spirit swells with pride, then by an unhappy gradation, not to say
by a headlong plunge, it moves on to contention, and from contention to schism,
from schism to heresy and from heresy to blasphemy."
x
1812 Fleury, Histoire ccdesiastique, Vol. XX, Preface, pp. xii-xiii (speaking
of the Franciscans) "It would, it seems, have been to the greater advantage of the
:
Church for bishops and Popes to have applied themselves in earnest to reforming
the secular clergy and putting it back on the footing of the first four centuries, with-
out calling on these outside troops [the Franciscans] for help, so that there would
have been but two sorts of persons sacred to God: clerics appointed to supervise the
education and conduct of the faithful and absolutely subject to the bishops, and
then monks holding entirely apart from the world and busied exclusively with pray-
ing and labouring in silence. In the thirteenth century, however, the idea of such
perfection had been forgotten, and the impressive thing was the disorder to be seen
before one's eyes: the greed of the clergy, their expensive living, their effeminate
voluptuous habits, which had also spread to the endowed monasteries.'*
2
1812 Op. cit.. t p. 428.
1814 THE POPES AND THE FRANCISCANS 1 26 1
1813.The Popes were not the only ones willing to use the reli-
gious enthusiasm of the Franciscans for their own ends. The Em-
peror Frederick II had the very same intention, and he had no re-
ligion to speak of, being, as a type, the exact opposite of Celestine
1
V. Such the substance over which a veil of derivations was
spread.
Suppose now we look at it more closely.
1814. Immediately after the death of St. Francis, and
perhaps even
earlier, contention arose in the order between those who wished to
follow the Rule or, if one will, the precept of Jesus to the letter,
and those who were disposed Rule and Gospel
to reconcile both
1
with the requirements of life in society. In course of time the order
was broken up into three branches: the "Little Friars" (Fraticdli)
and the "Spirituals" (Spirituali}, both strict observers of the Rule,
but holding different theological views; then the "Conventuals"
1
1813 Preaching a return to "evangelical poverty" was ever the favourite weapon
of the enemies of the Papacy and Frederick II also used it. Tocco, Op. cit., pp. 447-48:
"As regards the secular clergy, Frederick's language is no different from the lan-
guage of the intransigent Franciscans, as witness his letter to the King of
England, Huillard-Breholles, Historia diplomatica Frederici Secundi, Vol. Ill,
p. 50: 'The primitive Church, in the days when she was producing in such
fertility the saints who are listed in the calendar, had been founded on pov-
erty and simplicity. But at no later date could anyone establish any founda-
tion save that which had been laid and established by Our Lord. Now because
they
are wallowing in wealth, lolling in wealth, building in wealth, there is fear lest
the wall of the Church be tottering and lest when the wall has been thrown down
"
the fall of the whole ensue.' And to combat Frederick, Gregory IX favoured the
intransigent party among the Franciscans. Tocco, Op. cit., pp. 445-46: "I think it
probable that the Pope broke with the Franciscan General for political reasons.
As we have already seen, the General was equally acceptable both to Gregory
and to Frederick, and Salimbcne tells us that he often acted as mediator between
them. Perhaps in these dealings he may have shown himself more favourable to the
Imperial cause. ... In view of that Gregory surrendered to the intransigent party
and not only deposed the unlucky General, but had him expelled from the order
and solemnly excommunicated him, and worse certainly would have befallen him
had not Frederick taken him under his protection. The shrewd Emperor, lying
under a charge of heresy, found it to his advantage to have on his side a comrade
of St. Francis who a few years before had been held in high esteem by the Pope
himself."
J
1814 Somewhat later, in 1311, a similar difference is defined in a bull by
Clement V: dementis Papae V Constitutiones, lib. V, tit. XI, DC verborum sig-
nificatione, cap. i, Exivi de paradiso (Friedberg, Vol. II, p. 1193): "In view of that
a very knotty question arose among the friars as to whether they were bound by
profession of the Rule to the stricdy meagre or 'poor' use of property requisite for
sustaining life (ad arctum et tenuem sive pauperem usum rerum), some of them
believing and saying that they had made a very strict renunciation in their vow as
1262 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1815
2
(Conventual?) who interpreted the Rule somewhat liberally. Pope
Celestine V allowed another order to secede from the Friars Minor,
to be known Pope Celestine (Celestines) or Poor
as the Friars of
Hermits. This order too was uncompromising as to observance of
the Rule. That Pope was a simple soul and very devout. He did
not last long on the throne of St. Peter. On the other hand Pope
Boniface VIII, who replaced him, was a shrewd diplomat and per-
3
secuted the Poor Hermits.
1815. In a word, since it was impossible to live without property
and without providence, some subterfuge had to be found for in-
terpreting the Gospel precept and the Rule of St. Francis in such
a way that they would not jar too violently with property and provi-
dence. Derivations, as we have seen, are like rubber bands and can
be stretched to mean anything desired. It was therefore not dif-
regarded ownership of property, so that the strictest frugality and meagreness were
prescribed for them as regarded its use [i.e., quite apart from ownership]; others
holding to the contrary that they were bound by their profession to no practice of
poverty (ad nullum itsum pauper em) not expressly prescribed in the Rule, though
they were indeed bound to the moderate observance of temperance to the same
extent as other Christians and, concededly, more so."
2
1814 Tocco, Op. cit., p. 500, note: "Liber sententiarum inquisitionis Tholosanae,
p. 326: 'He said that he had heard from certain Friars Minor about the so-called
Spirituals of Narbonne and so he thought that things were in such a state that the
Friars Minor ought to be divided into three parts, namely, into the community of
the order that wishes to own barns and cellars, then the Brothers (Friars) and Little
Brothers who arc in Sicily under Fra Enrico de Ceva, and finally the friars called
Spirituals or Poor Friars and also Beguincs. And they [the friars in Narbonne] had
said that the first two divisions were destined to decline and be destroyed as not
observing the rule of the Blessed Francis, but that the third part, since it observed
"
the evangelical rule, was to endure to the end of the world.'
3
1814 Fleury, Histoire ecclesiastiqiie, Vol. XVIII, pp. 535-43: 'Those among the
Friars Minor who professed greatest zeal for strict observance did not fail to profit
by the favourable attitude of Pope Celestine towards austerity and reform. They
therefore sent two of their number to him, Fra Liberatus and Fra Pier de Macerata.
They called on the Pope . and requested that with his authorization, which no
. .
one would dare dispute, they should be allowed to live according to the purity of
their rule and the intent of St. Francis. That they readily obtained. But the Pope
further granted them permission to live together wheresoever they chose in order
to be at liberty to practise their strict observance. And he ordered that they
. . .
should no longer be called Friars Minor but Poor Hermits, and later on they came
to be called the Hermits of Pope Celestine [Celestines] So, though Celestine's in-
.
tentions were of the purest, the simplicity in which he lived his whole life, his in-
experience, and the feebleness due to age, led him into making many mistakes. . . .
Boniface began his pontificate by revoking the favours that Celestine had granted
through the abuse people had made of his simplicity."
1817 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1263
alone one device, any number of devices. The prin-
ficult to find, let
persons did the owning and the saving for them. Gregory
IX as-
signed that function to "dummies," who were outsiders. John
XXII
assigned it to
Superiors in the Order, to whom the ordinary friars
owed obedience. That he did because his enemies were using the
point of the "dummies" as a weapon against him; but
had he
chosen, he could have stuck to Gregory IX's interpretation and made
itmean whatever he pleased.
1816. The derivation contrived by Gregory IX was an ingenious
one. The Rule forbade the friars to receive money. How then were
the bare title, and the friars enjoy the use of the property. So too
other persons are prevented from appropriating the property the
friars are using. They stick to the Rule, resisting nobody who would
rob them but along comes the titular owner and does the resisting.
;
Tolstoy, in his day, got along in just that fashion. He never "re-
sisted evil," he never repelled the thief who would despoil him. But
his wife was there, resisting, repelling, and managing the property
on which her husband lived and had his being.
1817. Innocent IV, in 1245, and Nicholas
III, in 1279, gave
sounder form to the theory. Pope Nicholas says that a distinction
has to be made between ownership, possession, and usufruct (usu-
fact), that there can be no calling that bars the use of the things
necessary for subsistence. He shows at great length that, in spirit,
the Rule of St. Francis conceded such use. The Rule says that friars
plausible that it was his intent that they should have barns or cellars, since they
should hope to be able to live their lives through daily mendication."
3
1817 John XXII, Extravagantes, lib. XXII, ///. 14, De verborum significatione,
cap. i: Quorundam exigit (Friedberg, Vol. II, p. 1222) (The ordinance was pro-
claimed more than once and therefore bears various dates posterior to 1317): "By
1817 THE POPES AND THE FRANCISCANS 1265
Franciscans were not hushed. They made bold to defy the Pope's
expressed will,
and he was accordingly moved to expand his deriva-
4
tion. He revoked the bull of Nicholas III; and then, in the bull
by authority of these presents commit it to the judgment of the said ministers and
wardens to consider, determine, and rule as to how, when, where, and how often
they shall obtain and store up grain, bread, and wine for the subsistence of the
friars and as to the quality thereof and also as to whether it shall be stored and
kept in said barns and cellars. For it is to the hurt of religion if subordinates
. . .
are withdrawn from their proper obedience. Great is poverty but greater is purity
(integritas), and greatest of all is obedience if it be perfectly observed. For poverty
rules material things, purity the flesh, but obedience the mind and soul which, as it
were unbridled (cffraencs) and impatient of external control, it humbly brings
under the yoke of the will."
4
1817 In 1318, in Marseilles, four Friars Minor chose to go to the stake rather
than obey the Pope. The sentence of condemnation, quoted by Tocco, Op. cit., p.
516, says of them: "They asserted that the Most Holy Father John XXII did not
have and does not have the authority (potestatem) to make the statements, com-
mitments, and orders contained in a certain constitution or decretal beginning
Quo run dam cxigit and that they were not called upon to obey said Pope
. . .
(Domino Papae). Brought into our presence, they protested orally and in writing
that they stood by their protests and intended to stand by them till the Day of
Judgment ... to wit, that that which is against the observance and sense (intelli-
gentiam) of the Rule of the Friars Minor is consequently against the Gospel and
the faith otherwise it would not be exactly what the Gospel rule was ( ? alias non
esset penitus quod regida e v angelica) and that no mortal would be able to com-
y
They say that the following words are contained in the confirmation of the Rule
of the Order of the Friars Minor by Honorius III, Gregory IX, Innocent IV, Alex-
ander IV, and Nicholas IV, our predecessors as supreme pontiffs: This is the evan-
gelical rule of Christ and one that imitates the Apostles in that it recognizes no
1266 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1817
5
ship and usufruct in the case of things that are physically consumed.
He accordingly repudiated ownership of the property of the Friars
Minor, which they claimed was his, and handed it back to the friars
6
themselves to dispose of through their Superiors. Such great fluc-
individual or common property (nihil habet proprium vel commune) , but they
have simple usufact (usum jacti) in the things they use.' To all that
they go so far
as to add that the afore-said Supreme Pontiffs and
many general Councils have
ruled by the key of knowledge that the poverty of Christ and the
Apostles con-
sisted perfectly in an expropriation of temporal ownership of a civil or worldly
character and that their sustenance consisted of nothing but usufruct. From that
pure
they try to conclude that it has not been and is not lawful for the successors [of
those Popes] to make changes in any respect against those
premises."
6
1817 John XXII, Extravagantes, VI, 3, 14: Ad conditorcm canonum (Friedberg,
Vol. II, p. 1225). The following summary of the ordinance is
supplied by Lancelotto
in Corpus iuris canonici accadcmicum, Basel, 1783, Vol. II, p. 395 (Institutiones iuris
canonici) 'The Supreme Pontiff refutes the assertion that ownership of the property
:
coming into the possession of the Friars Minor has been held by the Roman Church,
simple usufact thereof being reserved to said friars in the constitution Exiit qui semi-
nat. He shows by many reasons that they cannot have simple usufact in anything;
and he rules that furthermore theRoman Church shall have no right or title of own-
1819.
Many among such are those who as preachers preach
all
well, but as practitioners practise badly. Words are one thing, actions
quite another. At best the more scrupulous among them try to rec-
oncile words with conduct. Often the person who admires and hails
that the Pope perceived the ineptitude of taking a natural law, or law of nations,
as the basis of legality.However, he wanted to keep a natural law all the same,
so he went looking about for a derivation suited to the purpose and, as always
happens, readily found one, making human law a corollary of divine law: "That
no property right in temporal things could have been given to man by any
human law, but only by divine law, is evident; for it is granted that no one can
give anything away unless he be the owner of it, or by the will of the owner.
There is no doubt that God is the owner of all temporal things whether by right
of creation, since He created them out of nothing, or by right of manufacture,
since He made them of His materials. It follows that no king could rule as to own-
ership of such things save by will of God." Admitting the premises, the syllogism
is perfect; and if logic had anything to do with such things, we should have to
recognize that the Pope's reasoning shows not a wrinkle: "Whence it is evident
that neither by natural primeval law if it be taken as that law that is common
to all living creatures, though such a law does not legislate (/;//;// statuat} but
merely inclines or guides living creatures in common to the doing of certain things
nor by law of nations, nor by the law of kings or emperors, was property own-
ership in temporal things introduced, but it was conferred upon our first parents
by God who was and is the owner of them."
1268 THE MIND AND SOCIETY l82O
people who would prohibit the use of alcohol, but themselves con-
sume, for their health, they say, ether, morphine, or cocaine, or
drink enough tea to contract a malady that has been named "tea-
ism." And how many others go out with their mistresses on their
by the claim that they have a right to "live their own lives."
1820. Eusebius, Evangelica praeparatio, XIV, 7 (Opera, Vol. Ill,
sibility
of our understanding anything. He was convinced forth-
with, and in his turn began professing the doctrine that we can
know nothing for certain, adducing in proof his own experience
with his pantry. One of his hearers, who knew the trick the slaves
were using, revealed it to him, whereupon the good man took meas-
ures to lock his pantry more securely. But the slaves, nothing
daunted, broke the seals and then brazenly told their master that
being certain of nothing, he could not be certain, either, that he
had put seals on the pantry. The game lasted a long time to the
damage and rage of poor Lacides; until he threw philosophy by
the board one day and said to his slaves: "Young men, in the schools
we reason in one way; but at home hereafter we are going to live in
quite another."
1821. Once one is started on the road of derivations it is
easy to
*
1819 There is nothing new under the Sun. This type of person has his coun-
terpart among the devout in all countries in all periods of history. The religious
fanatics of the past and our present-day humanitarians are of the same breed.
See,
in 1172 *, the quotations from Moliere and the Sorberiana.
1823 THE LOTTERY AND THE "ETHICAL STATE*' 1269
fact, they act very differently indeed and then resort to subtle in-
prove that women are human beings I mean, of the same species as men. That
was the subject of a little book that appeared toward the end of the last century.
... A certain Simon Gedik, Prime Minister of Brandenburg, wrote an answer
[Defensio sexus muliebris, The Hague, 1638, new ed., 1707] in all seriousness,
failing to catch the intent of the author, which was to write a violent satire against
the Socinians.' Dobeneck used the same device, but quite unavailingly, against
Luther, writing books by Luther's method, and proving by passages from Scrip-
ture that Jesus Christ was not God at all, that God had to obey the Devil and
that the Holy Virgin did not preserve her virginity." "Theophile Raynaud," Bayle
continues, "had just given [Erotemata dc mails ac bonis libris, III, 3, no. 514
(Opera, Vol. XI, p. 366)] a fine example of the pqwer of verbal trickery, showing
that if one were to follow the principles of certain censors the Apostles' Creed
would not contain an item that could pass the censorship.*'
1270 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1824
tained and continues to maintain that form of gambling. Judges
penalize gamblers in the name
of a government that derives an
1
annual income of tens of millions from the lottery. In France and
other countries horse-racing takes the place of the lottery. The Aus-
trian censors were ridiculous, but not more ridiculous than Luz-
of the 90 numbers in the urn in its own favour. In roulette the person who bets
I franc on one colour wins i franc; on 6 numbers, he wins 5 and gets back his own;
on the 'dozen' or 'column' (12 numbers), he wins u and gets back his own.
Anyone who bets i franc en plan, who bets, that is, i franc on any one number
of the 36, wins 35 and gets back his own. Anyone who desires to bet on the
bank bets on zero. The Royal Lottery pays ioj^ times the stake to the winner of
the 'simple draw.' If it operated on the same principle as roulette, it would
pay 1 8 times the stake in other words, as many more times the stake as there
are more probabilities in its favour (17+1). To the winner of the 'specified
draw' (estratto determinate) the Royal Lottery pays 525/2 times the stake, instead
of 90 (a 41.67 per cent robbery, if you please). From that point on the robbery
grows by leaps and bounds: to the winner of the ambo [two-number scries] it pays
250 times the stake, instead of 400 j4 times (a 37.58 per cent robbery); to the
winner of a terno [three-number series] it pays 4,250 times the stake, instead of
11,748 times (a 63.82 per cent robbery); to the winner of a quaterno [four-number
series] it pays 60,000 times the stake, instead of 511,038 (an 88.26 per cent robbery).
. . .
Observe, moreover, that whatever the stake may be for any ticket (terno, qua-
tcrno, cinqttina) the Royal Lottery refuses to pay the winner more than 400,000 lire;
so that the person who stakes 100 lire on a quaterno ought to receive a sum amount-
ing to 511,038 times the stake, or 51,103,800 lire; but since the winner of the quaterno
receives a sum amounting to 60,000 times the stake, a xoo-lire ticket ought to
bring him 6,000,000 lire. In point of fact, in virtue of the limitations shown above,
he receives only 400,000 lire, and the robbery, therefore, amounts to 93.33 per
cent. But that is not all. The Royal Lottery will not pay more than 6,000,000
lire to cover all the winnings from a single drawing on all the frames in the king-
1825 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1
27 1
lawful appropriations revealed by the bank investigations, and who
continue to tolerate similar "graft," are to be found honest citizens
who believe that they are faithfully following the principles of a
theoretical morality. Among the people in France who approved
of the State's Attorney-General, Bulot, when he declared that magis-
trates must bow to the "fait du prince" under penalty of dismissal,
dom; and the gains of any one drawing should amount to a sum greater than
if
6,000,000 lire, all the gains of all the tickets sold in all offices would be reduced
in corresponding proportions. In that case the robbery has no fixed percentage, but
it is greater than the percentage indicated above according to the sum above
6,000,000 that the gains may total. By this trick the state takes yearly a sum of
lire
over 90,000,000 lire from the meagre resources of the most numerous and least
pecunious portion of the Italian population." Such the "ethical state," such the "state
of right," of our moralists!
1 1
1824 For Bulot's remark see Pareto, Manuale, Chap. II, 5o "Sembat: The
:
State's Attorney has also spoken of some 'higher interest* in this case. Am I to infer
that there is a 'reason of state' to which a magistrate is required to bow? Bulot. On
time to the illusion under which people are labouring in believing that the two
things coincide. We are not passing judgment of any kind on the effects, whether
socially beneficial or otherwise, of such disaccord, nor on the effects beneficial or
otherwise of its being generally known or unknown to the public at large.
1825
1
We
shall conduct this research by considering certain groups of residues
and derivations separately ( 1687). That will give us a part of the phenomenon, but
only a part. To grasp it in its entirety we shall have to take all the elements acting
upon society and consider them as a whole. That task we reserve for our next
1272 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1826
ready answered in its general form, finding that in many cases der-
ivations (or, more
complex of derivations proper and
exactly, the
manifestations) were of secondary importance as compared with
residues, while the role of derivations proper was still less significant
and often times negligible. The production of such derivations is a
very easy matter, and if one is refuted another takes its
place forth-
with and there is no change whatever in the substantial situation.
However, that is
just a first
approximation. Secondary as the influ-
ence be and at times very feeble, the derivations proper can
may
never be absolutely without influence. To get a second approxima-
1
tion, therefore, one would have to see what that influence is.
1830. 3. What happens if one or more of the manifestations r, s, t
("Absence is to love as wind to fire: the little one it extinguishes, the great one
it rouses.")]
1837 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1275
weakens a to a greater or lesser extent, provided the suppression is
1
real and extends to the individual's inner thought.
1834. We now have the general explanation of the particular case
examined in 1748-54 above. If in the logico-experimental sciences
an assertion, A, is effectively refuted by showing that it is false
( 1748), that happens because the manifestation, r, the act of asser-
tion comes to an end, and because it has no sentiments, a, of any
The two cases are, however, radically different. In the first case the lapse indi-
cates that a change is taking place in the social equilibrium; in the second, it merely
indicates a desire on the part of public authorities to change a situation by action
that, more often than not, will prove ineffective.]
1276 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1838
words, there are cases where the weakening or elimination of one
manifestation, r, has the effect of intensifying other manifestations,
s, t. . . . That effect is very like the effect that results when one
group of residues weakened and other residues are intensified, by
is
tirpating heresy and free-thought. Had the Roman State been able
to deal with Christianity in similar fashion, it would probably have
been successful in extirpating it. It failed in that because the resi-
dues, a, that found expression in Christianity, r, were the same resi-
dues that found expression in the cult of Mithras, s; in the solar
(Osiris) cult, /; in Neo-Platonism, v; in Philo's mysticism, x; and in
pressed by them. In that sense, one may say, roughly, that the in-
l
1838 a, 1838-41; /?, 1842-49; y, 1850-59; 8, 1860-62.
1
84 1 EDUCATION 1
277
dividuals who harboured the sentiments corresponding to the group
1
a have disappeared.
1840. A similar situation arises
when, instead of disappearing, in-
dividuals harbouring the sentiments a come on the scene. That is
what took place in the Roman Empire when the ancient population
of Latium, and indeed of Italy, gave way to a population of freed-
men or other sorts of people hailing chiefly from the East. It is
very
inexact to speak of an invasion of the Roman Empire by Chris-
peoples of Rome, Latium, and Italy had certain residues with a cer-
tain religion corresponding. The Orientals had different residues
1839
l
tne greater part of the individuals in France who were full-grown
By r 9 rl
at the time of the War of 1870 had passed from the scene; and to that fact was
due, in part at least, the reawakening of nationalism in the country. In the same
way, in Italy, by the year 1913 most of the individuals who had directly suffered
from the Austrian domination in Italy had disappeared; and that made it easier for
the Italian to treat Arabs who were defending their native land as
Government
rebels, and to maintain
try to an "equilibrium in the Adriatic" by forcing the
Greeks of Epirus to submit to domination by the Albanians, exactly as the Italians
of Lombardy and Venetia had once been forced under an Austrian yoke.
1278 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1842
leaders of the French Revolution. Thatf does not prove that the effect
of education iszero. It shows that it {s just one among the many
that figure in the resultant registered in \human conduct.
1842. ft. With a view to influencing a, governments ordinarily at-
tack the manifestations r, s, t. . . . That policy
inspired not so is
power, and still haloed by his victories over France and his founda-
tion of the German Empire, Bismarck seems to have tried to de-
typical.In that case, one country had been divided into three parts.
In the two parts under the dominion of Russia and Prussia, the gov-
ernments combat or modify sentiments, and their policies
tried to
were utterly futile and ineffective. In the section under Austrian
dominion the government took advantage of the same sentiments
of the third year of the campaign against Rome, attentive observers could foresee
that the results of the campaign would be dubious, and it was noted that Prince
von Bismarck was manifesting less enthusiasm for the idea of a national German
Church. The conflict was to continue violent for a number of years; and cir-
. . .
minority that had acquired great importance under the name of the Group of
the Center, whereas the National Liberals were meeting stiffer and more enthusi-
astic opposition every day from Progressives and Socialists." Bismarck, Gedanfycn und
Erinnenmgen, p. 646 (Butler, Vol. II, p. 339) "One should think back to the time
:
when the Center, strong rather in the support of the Jesuits than of the Pope, re-
enforced by the Guelphs (and not only by those in Hanover), the Poles, the Alsatian
Francophiles, the Radical Democrats, the Social Democrats, the Liberals, and the Par-
ticularists, all united in one same sentiment of hostility to Empire and Dynasty,
possessed, under the leadership of this same Windthorst who had become a na-
tional saint since his death, as he was before, a safe and aggressive majority that
served as an effective check to the Emperor and the confederated governments."
2
1843 To tell the truth, Bismarck's mistake seems rather to have lain in an
error of political tactics than in any failure to appreciate the strength of residues
or the importance of using them. In fact, both before and after the Kulturkampf ,
he showed that he had the knack of using residues without trace of scruple. The
fanatical "intellectuals" who
supported the Kulturfympf imagined that Bismarck
shared their beliefs. Really he was just using those gentlemen as his tools. Busch,
Tagcbuchbldttcr (English, Vol. I, p. 220; passage omitted from German), Nov. 8,
"
1870: In October, 1870, rumours were rife that the Pope was leaving Rome: 'They
would not like to see him go/ added Hatzfeldt; 'it is in their interests [of the
Italians] that he should remain in Rome.' The Chief: Tes, certainly. But per-
haps he will be obliged to leave. But where would he go? Not to France, because
Garibaldi is there. He would not like to go to Austria. There remains for him
. . .
but Belgium or North Germany! As a matter of fact, he has already asked whether
I28O THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1^43
3
as instruments of policy,and its work met striking success. Rome
enjoyed the favour and goodwill of the peoples she conquered pre-
cisely because she respected their sentiments. English rule in India
continues to endure on the same grounds; and for identical reasons
Tunis is of all the French colonies the one where French rule is
most popular and most willingly accepted, for there the sentiments,
usages, and customs of the natives have been best respected. Peoples
more readily submit to heavy burdens than to offences against their
manners and customs, however slight and insignificant these may
seem to be. The revolt of the Sepoys in India was provoked, it is
said, by a rumour that the English were tying their cartridges with
strings greased in pork-fat (in those days the cartridge was torn
open with the teeth before being emptied into the gun). Minor acts
of arbitrary disregard in matters of language, religious usage, and,
in Oriental countries, behaviour toward women, are tolerated grudg-
their business. We
should have the Poles on our side. The opposition of the ultra-
montanes would cease in Belgium and Bavaria. [There speaks the statesman who
knows the art of using residues.] But the King will not consent. He is
. . .
terribly afraid! He thinks all Prussia will be perverted and he himself would be
obliged to become a Catholic. ... I told him, however, that if the Pope begged
asylum he could not refuse it. ... And, after all, even if a few people in Ger-
many became Catholic again (I should certainly not do so), it would not matter
much, so long as they remained believing Christians. People ought to be more
tolerant in their way of thinking!' [Such a declaration by a practical man should
be pondered; it is rigorously scientific ( 1851).] The Chief then dilated on the
comic aspect of this migration of the Pope and his cardinals to Fulda, and con-
8
1843 Even in the case of Poland Bismarck seems to have seen clearly at one
time. Busch, Tagebuchblatter , Vol. I, p. 554 (English, Vol. I, p. 308), Dec. 20, 1870:
"
'You have no idea,' said the Chancellor, 'how pleased the Poles arc when they
sec that someone knows their mother-tongue. Not long ago I ran into some poor
devils in a military hospital. When I addressed them in Polish I could sec their
pale faces brighten to a smile. Too bad their gcncral-in-chicf docs not know their
language!' That was an indirect thrust at the Crown Prince, who had the com-
mand of the Polish forces. He
picked up the Chancellor's allusion with a smile:
'That is he said. 'You are always harping on that. But I
just like you, Bismarck,'
think I have told you times without end that I do not like that language and
refuse to learn same, my lord,' Bismarck replied, 'the Poles are good
it.' 'All the
"
soldiers and Great military leaders, such as Caesar and Napoleon,
fine fellows.'
have been past-masters in the art of using sentiments in their soldiers.
1843 BISMARCK AND THE "KULTURKAMPp" I28l
fact that they preferred their French to their German cousins. That
being so, the art of government lies in finding ways to take advan-
tage of such sentiments, not in wasting one's energies in futile efforts
to destroy them, the sole effect of the latter course very
frequently
being only to strengthen them. The person who is able to free him-
his own sentiments is
from the blind dominion of
self
capable of
utilizing the sentiments of other people for his own ends. If, in-
But if only the Pope remains true to me, I shall know how His Majesty
to bring
round/" Ibid., Vol. II, p. in (English, Vol. I, p. 390), Jan. 30, 1871: "The Chief
had told the Frenchman, among other things, that to be consistent in one's policy
was frequently a mistake. One must modify one's course of action in ac-
. . .
cordance with events, with the situation of affairs and not according to one's . . .
opinions. One must not impose one's feelings and desires upon one's country."
Lcfebvre de Behaine, Op. cit., p. 25 (speaking of the outbreak of the KulturJ^ampj) :
"Was not the moment propitious in Germany for beginning the Ktflturfompf, the
outlines ofwhich had already been drawn by Lutz? Would not Rome retreat at
that warning? Everything leads one to believe that that was Prince von Bismarck's
hope early in the year 1872. That thought came out in the speeches he delivered
before the Prussian Chamber on January 30 and 31 during the debate on the
budget of the Ministry of Public Worship. Alongside the rebuke addressed to the
clerical party for working to mobilize the Center group with a view to waging a
more effective war on the new state of things [In that the real cause of the war
that Bismarck is about to declare.], alongside the usual denunciations of the old
Rhenish confederacy, certain words of the Chancellor might have been read as
indicating a disposition on his part to enter on negotiations with the Vatican."
The Pope showed himself not too pliant and Bismarck set out to combat him; but
being a wise and a practical man, he soon realized that he had better things to do
than waste his energies in fatuous arguments in theology. In 1885 he submitted
his dispute with Spain over the Caroline Islands to the Pope's arbitration. Lefebvre
de Behaine, Ibid., pp. 198, 220: "On May 26, 1886, the King of Prussia proclaimed
a law in fifteen articles that abrogated a certain number of items in previous
laws, known as the Maige seize and dating for the most part from the years 1873-75.
>
. . .
Today Church is enjoying a profound peace in Germany. It is
the Catholic
free in itsteachings and has been liberated from all the impediments that it seemed
likely to be called on to suffer twenty-five years ago."
1282 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1844
ing post hoc, propter hoc, one would be tempted to say that where
is most severe, there
legislation against immorality immorality is
most rampant. We may see under our very eyes that measures de-
signed to suppress a manifestation, r, serve only to strengthen other
ceedingly scant even when, as is frequently the case, they have not
made the criminal worse. That is all in accord with the general law
that forcibly to suppress the manifestations of a given group of senti-
ments is often of little or no effect as regards diminishing the in-
tensity of sentiments in that group, and sometimes it enhances them.
Many efforts have been made to remedy that defect in criminal leg-
islation,and, to tell the truth, with no very appreciable results; and
the slight, or rather the insignificant, progress that has been made
has been made through influencing sentiments, a.
cording to peoples, places, and times, and often there are compensa-
tions between the various genera.
1847. 6. Erroneous, therefore, are all those reasonings which,
from the fact that a penalty is ineffective from the standpoint of
logical conduct,
conclude that it is ineffective in general. It is erro-
neous, for instance, to argue that the death-penalty is ineffective be-
cause logically, directly, it does not restrain a man from committing
murder. The penalty works in a different way. In the first place
and the fact cannot be questioned it does away with the murderer
and rids society of at least a few of the persons who have a fond-
ness for killing their neighbours. Then again it serves
indirectly to
invigorate sentiments of horror for crime. That can hardly be
doubted, once one thinks of the effectiveness of so called laws of
1284 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1848
honour, which are without direct penal sanctions but produce such
an atmosphere through apposite sentiments that the majority of
men are loath to transgress them. So the Sicilian will hardly ever
acquired sentiments which accord with those rules and the punish-
ments that are visited on infractions maintain and intensify those
1
sentiments.
To infer, for another example, that the so-called probation law
is innocuous from the assumed fact the real fact probably dif-
is
to their disadvantage. Least of all can he ask the courts to settle any differences
he may have with them. When an attempt is made on his life, he may avenge
himself if possible, but in no case is he to make a complaint to the police.]
1850 RELIGIOUS FREEDOM 1285
the right to commit a first crime; the extreme mercifulness of courts
and juries; the kind-hearted patience of magistrates who allow crim-
6
inals to show contempt them
in public court ( 1716 ), and
for
sometimes to utter personal insults and ridicule the penalties with
which they are threatened; the comforts that have been provided in
certain "modern" under pretext of "reclaiming" the
prisons, where,
criminal, society shows him every consideration and gives him
greater ease than oftentimes he could have in his own home; the
mitigation of penalties already mild; frequent commutations and
pardons all such things allow a large number of individuals to
think lightly of crime and punishment of crime and to glory as
Suppose we
disregard questions as to the efficacy of the protection,
which usually consists in interference with religious manifestations.
That problem we have just discussed. Let us assume for the moment
that the interference is
really effective and proceed from there.
1851. Thelogico-experimental reasoning corresponding to the
derivation just stated would be: "The religious person possesses
sentiments that I desire good citizens to have; but a person can be
devout only if he possesses the sentiments of a specified religion;
therefore I will encourage the sentiments of that religion in my
citizens." The
proposition "A person can be religious only if he has
the sentiments of a specified religion" is
completely discredited by
experience, and many men know that ( 1843 2 ), even if
practical
they see fit not to admit as much in public. Many religions that are
different in forms are manifestations of substantially identical re-
ligious sentiments.The religious spirit, moreover, is ordinarily
stronger in heretics than in the followers of an established orthodoxy
protected by a government. Such a government is, to be sure, pro-
tecting a given theology and specified forms of worship, but
mean-
sidered harmful, it unintentionally damaged other sentiments of the same group,
among them the sentiment of patriotism, which, certainly, it had no intention of
impairing. In 1912, the French school-teachers assembled in convention at Chambcry
voiced sentiments of hostility to patriotism. Many politicians marvelled at such a
thing. But they might readily have foreseen it by giving just a thought to the
work they had themselves been doing. But if the germ inoculated by the French
"intellectuals'* found a favourable medium in a few school-teachers, it found a
sterile environment in the French population at large, especially in the lower
classes. Religious sentiments linger most tenaciously in those classes under one
form or another, and they are the source of those occasional tides of religious feel-
ing which rise and engulf the higher classes. That is what happened in France
with respect to sentiments of patriotism in the years 1911 and 1912.
1852 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1287
time persecuting the very religious spirit that
it is it set out to foster.
A double error is involved in the policy: in the first
place, it con-
fuses derivations and residues, in the manner just stated, mistaking
theology for the religious spirit; then it confuses certain specified
residues with other residues of the same genus or kindred genera.
If the residues underlying a number of different religions are a\, fa,
a* . . . and if the whole sum of sentiments upon which those re-
ligions depend is
strengthened ( 1744), there will be an increase in
the religious spirit. But if #1 is
strengthened at the expense of 2 , a*
.. . the religious spirit is not necessarily intensified; it may actually
be reduced. To see how ineffective governmental protection is as a
means of strengthening religious residues, one has only to compare
the present state of Catholicism in the United States, where all
Christian sects enjoy the amplest freedom, with the state of that
same religion in France at times when it enjoyed governmental
protection, as under Napoleon III.
Another example would be Rome
under papal rule, where there was vigorous suppression of mani-
festations contrary to Catholicism, yet Catholic religious residues
1
were very feeble.
1852. The
error just elucidated has been sensed by many people,
but that perception, ordinarily, instead of being stated in logico-
experimental form has taken the form of a derivation that, from the
logico-experimental standpoint,
is as erroneous as the
theory which
it is used to combat. Dissenters have vaunted the "truth" of their
x
1851 The extent to which the religious spirit in the city of Rome had degen-
erated by the year 1830 or thereabouts may be measured to some degree by the
obscene satirical sonnets in Roman dialect of Belli (Sonnetti romancschi).
1288 THE MIND AND SOCIETY
Such doctrines have at times succeeded in winning wide acceptance;
not by the soundness of their logic but by their correspondence with
sentiments that, originating under changing social conditions, even-
tually have come to conflict with the sentiments that were pre-
ponderant in a day gone by and which confused the religious spirit
in general with some one of its manifestations; and then
again by
their correspondence with sentiments originating in intensifications
of the instincts of combination and similar variations in other
residues.
1853. At this point it is in order to draw a distinction of great
1853
*
A phenomenon depending on the residues of Class III (activity). Human
beings, like animals, feel a need of expressing their sentiments by actions that it is
impossible to connect with the sentiments themselves by any logical or rational
nexus. The dog sees its master and wags its tail. No logical connexion between the
wagging and the dog's affection for its master can be established. If dogs had
moralists, the latter would probably demonstrate by any amount of fine-sounding
1854 RELIGIOUS FREEDOM 1289
betraying a belief on their part that such manifestations being fatuous prattle, the
sentiments from which they derive must be equally so. Such a blunder is worthy
obtaining among social facts. It is all well enough to prefer that powerful senti-
ments should not be accompanied by manifestations that arc not strictly rational
and that the sentiments expressed through Class III residues (activity) should ac-
cordingly be attenuated in virulence; but so long as they retain their vigour, the
person who will have his sentiments must resign himself to accepting their mani-
festations also. It is of course true that among said moralists in France there arc
humanitarians who would abolish the sentiments as well. They dare not say so in
fear of public censure, but at heart they deplore the existence of patriotism, some-
times consciously, sometimes unconsciously, and dream of universal brotherhood.
Not daring to combat the sentiments of patriotism openly, they turn to fighting the
manifestations of it.
1290 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY
accurately defined. We
must therefore be on our guard against any
misapprehension that might arise from the haziness in its meaning.
The complexes called "religions" are made up of residues and
derivations. There are residues that are common to all of them,
logical
we will therefore not linger upon it. Then again we find
people who are inspired to accept Socialism chiefly by residues of
sociality, among which residues of asceticism not seldom play an
usual, individuals who use that faith for personal ends, there remain
under a single canopy of derivations a number of religions differing
according to the residues that are brought into play; and among
them we find a class of residues in which the residues of asceticism
play a far more important part than all other groups. That fact has
been clearly perceived by the men who have governed the Catholic
Church; and they have found ways to recognize without changes
in derivations many varieties of residues, through a secular clergy,
a regular clergy, a laity, various orders of friars, and so on. And
in that we have another example that as usual shows that the art of
nately does not happen they were assigned any important role in
the government of society they would lead it to ruin. The practice
of such a religion by such individuals has no greater utility than
the macerations practised by the anchorites of yore in the African
deserts. Standing apart from real interests, ascetic Socialism pre-
from finding solutions on the basis of a balance
vents social conflicts
good to the bird. We are not for that matter forgetting that humani-
tarianism has had some socially desirable effects. For one thing it
has contributed to the mitigation of criminal penalties; and if among
these some were beneficial, so that society has suffered from the
many that are very bad; because, from the standpoint of senti-
ments, they shut their eyes to realities as the latter stand reflected in
many sentiments that they condemn from failure to grasp their
role in society; and because, from the standpoint of logico-experi-
mental science, they reason not on facts but on derivations, and from
the latter draw, by a logic inopportunely thorough-going, inferences
that are altogether at war with the facts ( 1782 f.). And so for
the democratic religion in general. The many varieties of Socialism,
theory of social utility that is far less rudimentary than any that at
the present time we could sketch even in outline. But at any rate
we are safe in saying that we will get a first approximation to a
solution by leaving derivations out of our calculations; for their
influence is
secondary and therefore to be considered only in later
and finer approximations. On the other hand, we must not fail to
consider the sentiments manifested by the transformations in ques-
tion; and we must consider them not objectively, apart from indi-
viduals, but in their relations to individuals; for the same sentiments
may be useful to some individuals and detrimental to others. Among
the things to ignore, finally, are secondary questions such as the
temporaries who do not share the democratic faith are in the same
situation were those pagans of old who witnessed
on the whole as
the inundation of the ancient world by Christianity. Some people
now vainly imagine, as those pagans imagined, that they can effec-
tively
check the progress of the religion they are fighting by re-
futing its derivations. Others find those theories so absurd that they
disdain giving a thought to them. And in that again they are fol-
1
lowing a precedent set by some of their ancient precursors. But
*
1859 Boissier, La fin du paganisme, Vol. II, pp. 243-44, expresses his surprise
that Macrobius does not so much as mention Christianity, which in his day was
sweeping Rome. "Our surprise is only the greater when we observe the same
pagan writers of the time, the grammarians, the orators, the
silence in almost all the
poets, and even the historians, though it seems very strange that an event such as
the triumph of the Church could be disregarded in an account of that past. Neither
Aurelius Victor nor Eutropius mentions Constantine's conversion, and one gets the
1296 THE MIND AND SOCIETY l86o
reject.
occurs to few, one might say to none, to ignore derivations
It
very difficult and often impossible. Before human beings will really
and regularly perform the conduct r, they must be imbued with the
sentiments underlying the residues, a, of which r is the consequence.
along with r; if they do not have them, there will be no r, but also
no s, and no t. . . .
religions and that explains why there has been a greater mitigation
;
in penalties for crimes of heresy than for other crimes. After the
fall of the Second
Empire in France the interests of the Republicans
conflicted with the interests of the Catholics. As a result penalties
for offences against the Catholic Church, and
by extension, against
all Christian churches, were abolished. The
Empire, meantime, had
impression from them that all the principes of the fourth century were continuing
practice of the ancient cult. Certainly no mere chance brought them all to omit
reference to a religion they detested. It was by design: it was an understand-
ing, the significance of which could escape no one. Silence, haughty, insolent, be-
came with them the last protest allowed the proscribed religion. That tactic, for
that matter, was nothing new in Rome. From the very first day, high society
in Rome had made it a habit to fight Christianity with contempt."
1 86 1 LAW-MAKING 1
297
made itself champion (in words) of the sex religion; the Republic
therefore granted greater liberties in that field; though afterwards,
when the policies of the Empire had ceased to be an issue, a slight
1
reaction followed.
* c
1861 Some pages back ( 1716 ) we quoted one of the numberless instances
where in deference to humanitarian sentiments magistrates and juries allowed
criminals to insult judges on the bench and their attorneys to dispute rulings by
presiding magistrates in open court. Suppose here we show a contrast dating
from a day when tender hearts were not blinding the eyes of magistrates. Edmond
Goncourt, Journal des Goncourt, Vol. I, pp. 42-45 (Feb. 20, 1853), tells how he
and his brotherwere indicted and brought to trial, in 1853, for reprinting in a
newspaper a poem that had appeared without anyone's protesting in a book by
Sainte-Beuve that had won a crown from the French Academy: "Finally our case
was called. 'Prisoners to the dock!' ordered the presiding magistrate. The order
caused a sensation among the spectators. The dock was the detention pen for thieves!
Never had a press case even when tried in Criminal Sessions won a reporter a
Trisoner to the Dock!' The acting State's Attorney opened. In an access of
. . .
Something worse than any crime of Bonnot, Gamier and Company! Goncourt
far
continues: "Then our attorney arose. He was just the defender we had been
looking for. He was far from repeating the pleas of Paillard de Villeneuve in de-
fence of Karr, by making bold to demand of the court how it dared to prosecute
us on the charge of an article that was itself not under prosecution and the author
of which was not in the dock beside us. He groaned, he wept over our crime, rep-
resenting us as callow youths, not all there in the upper story, in fact a little off."
The Court finally denounced the article, but acquitted the defendants as guiltless
of any "intent to insult public decency and sound morals." "In spite of anything
that may be written or said, the undeniable fact is that we were prosecuted in a
police court, seated in the dock with a policeman on either side of us, for quoting
five lines of Tahureau as printed in the Tableau historiqne et critique de la poesie
And here, now, is an example from the field of politics. Ollivier, L Empire
f
liberal,
Vol. IV, pp. 373-74. Ollivier was attorney for Vacherot, who was being prosecuted
for inciting his countrymen to hatred and contempt of the government in a book
called La democratic: "I began my rebuttal as follows: 'Gentlemen, in matters of
this sort the first requisite is extreme cautiousness. I shall make no answer to the
1298 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1862
regards time. In France offences against the Christian Church are en-
tirely exempt
from penalties. In England there are still some few
survivals of punishment for blasphemies. Crimes of sex heretics are
less zealously ferreted out and more lightly punished in France
than they are in England. Similar differences may be noted as
regards common crimes, which are treated with much greater leni-
ency in France than in England. Such contrasts result from the
human beings do their thinking not with the methods of
fact that
the logico-experimental sciences but in deference chiefly to senti-
ment (826f.).
1863. Difficulties in law-making. The obstacles that stand in the
legislator has in view are of two kinds. In the first place, one has
todecide what the law is to be, and to do that solutions are required
not only for the particular problem which we have just been con-
sidering ( 1825), but for the other more general problem as to the
indirect effects a measure will have, the problem, in other words, of
the composition of social forces (2087). Even
assuming that the,
law-maker is to reason
logico-experimentally, he will find that the
necessary scientific elements for solving such problems are at present
lacking, though one may reasonably hope that as
sociology progresses
will some day be in a
it
position to supply them.
1864. But we are still nowhere the law now has to be applied
offensive parts of the prosecutor's address. His
appeal to passions was out of place
here. In entering this enclosure you who are our judges and we who are
defending
this book should all remember that we
are nothing but mouthpieces,
interpreters,
of the law.' The presiding justice interrupted me: 'Maltrc Ollivicr, you have said
something improper. Withdraw it!' I replied calmly and in surprise: Tour Honour,
I have said
nothing improper. I was still under the sway of the words I had been
The president retorted: 'Maitrc Ollivier, you said that the Ministry of
listening to.*
Justicehad made an appeal to passions. That is an impropriety. Withdraw it!' . . .
The Court left the bench, returning a moment later. [Ollivicr was again re-
. . .
quested to withdraw his remark. He refused:] Then, without leaving the bench,
the Court sentenced me to suspension from practice for three months and
adjourned
Vacherot's case for a week to give him time to choose another attorney." If acts
that sectarian fanatics and a
only magistracy consider crimes cannot
servile
be distinguished from acts so regarded by the reasonable desire that almost
every
human being feels not to be murdered, plundered, or robbed, it might in many cases
be the lesser evil if humanitarians would exercise their indulgence
upon the former
rather than upon the latter.
l866 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1299
another; and that in the few cases where those in power have real-
ized a given purpose, they have carried their publics with them by
may have, in addition to the effects desired, other effects that are
not in the least intended; so that one still has to consider both the
intended and the incidental effects and see just what the social
utility
of their resultant will be. That like the
problem that prac-
is
beneficial and others that are negative or harmful; but if one will
1
have the ones, one must of necessity put up with the others.
1866. Whenthe engineer has found the best machine, he has
little
difficulty in selling it,
and even without dispensing with der-
ivations altogether, he can for the most part utilize arguments that
are logico-experimental. Not so the statesman. For him that situation
is
precisely reversed.
His main resort must be derivations, oftentimes
absurd ones. He
can use logico-experimental arguments only by
achieve).
1869. Since the situation here not an easy one to grasp, a graph
is
may help to make it clearer. The picture we set before the reader
people think they are going in one direction and are actually going
in another ( 1873), let us keep to the case where they are
going to
some extent at least in the direction desired. An
individual finds himself, let us say, at h, where he
is
enjoying a certain amount of utility represented
by the index ph. The idea is to induce him to go
on to m, where he will enjoy a greater utility, qm.
To state the matter to him in that fashion would
amount to way of rousing him to ac-
little in the
tion. It is wiser, therefore, to put before his eyes
the point T, located at quite a distance from the
curve km on the tangent hT, where he would
very effective and involve very few embarrassments when they are of a certain char-
acter. That is the case with myths that chance to embrace the strongest tendencies
of a people, party, or class, tendencies that in all the circumstances of life are for
ever presenting themselves to the mind with all the assertiveness of instincts, lend-
ing an aspect of full reality to those hopes of imminent action on which reforms of
the will are based. We know, for that matter, that these social myths in no way
prevent people from managing to profit by all the observations they make in the
I3O2 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1870
1870. Evidently, in order to determine the conditions under which
the individual will be situated at m
one need not bother with T. The
index rT is at bottom arbitrary and has no relation to the real index,
mq, except the fact that progress in the direction of both and T m
lengthens the index of which the value was ph. Furthermore, it is
altogether immaterial that T
should be imaginary and impractical,
so long as m, for its part, is concrete and real.
1871. A
being capable of non-logical conduct only could be
pushed from h to m
unawares. But the human being is a logical
animal. He wants to know why he is moving in the direction hm.
And so a person who is moved by instinct, interest, or other pres-
sures along the course hm
exercises his imagination and hitches his
reasonings more or less closely. The extent to which the trend, hm,
of the curve more or less
approximately coincides with the trend, hs,
of the tangent is the measure of the correspondence of the deriva-
tions with realities.
1872. The fact that m and T are different things and that to get
course of their lives nor from fulfilling their normal functions [Composition of
That can be shown by numberless examples. The first Christians
social forces.].
looked for the return of Christ, and for the total collapse of the pagan world fol-
lowed by the establishment of the Kingdom of the Saints, by the end of the first
generation. No such catastrophe occurred, but Christian thought took such advan-
tage of the apocalyptic myth that certain scholars of our time contend that the
whole preachment of Jesus bore on that theme alone. . . . One may readily see that
actual developments in the Revolution in no way resembled the enchanting pictures
that had enthralled its first converts. But could the Revolution have triumphed with-
out such pictures? . . .
Myths have to be thought of as instruments for influencing
the present, and any discussion as to ways of applying them materially to the course
of history is devoid of sense."
I8 74 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1303
to m one must aim at T has many consequences in addition to those
just noted, and we shall have occasion to advert to them in pages
hereafter.
1873. It may, and sometimes actually does happen, that things
develop not in the manner pictured in Figure 29, but in a manner
pictured in Figure 30. The individual desirous of moving along the
line hT m
order to improve his situation, moves instead from h to /
and so lessens his utility; which, from the index ph, diminishes to
the index vf. Such, among others, are cases where the derivations
have no correspondence with reality whatever, where, that is, the
p v
Figure 30 Figure 31
route hT
cannot be imagined as coinciding with the route hf even
roughly or even for the shortest distance. Oftentimes, further, the
impulse to move towards T actually carries one in an entirely dif-
1
ferent direction. To grasp this situation
again more clearly we may
have recourse to a crude graph. Figure 30 may be thought of as
representing a vertical cross-section of the surface hf over which
the individual has to move. Let us look at a horizontal projection
of that same surface, as in Figure 31. The point h is stimulated by
a force moving in the direction hT; but it encounters certain
obstacles (prejudices, sentiments, interests, and the like) that force
it to move
along the line chfg; and so, under pressure of the force
hT, it moves not towards
at all T
but brings up at /, in something
2
like the movement of a ship tacking against the wind.
1874. We have seen what may conceivably happen. It remains to
determine what actually does happen in the concrete. If we consider
that be it indeed within
history as a whole it is at once apparent
is the case which we decided to ignore at first (
*
1873 That 1869).
2
1873 substance of this paragraph will serve us again later on
The (21481".)
in examining phenomena of the same sort.
1304 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1875
narrow limits acts which have
ideal goals, T, or are performed as
if
they had, must also in many cases achieve results that show a
method and working from the general to the particular, we should have begun with
1876 EFFICACY OF IDEALS 1305
have a society made up of individuals whose conduct, in part,
envisages certain ideal principles, T, either observing certain ideal
norms, or else performing non-logical actions that to an observer
seem to be consequences of such norms, such principles. we Now
want to determine the character and the consequences of the con-
duct performed and its bearing on various utilities (2ii5f.).
Two problems at once arise: i. What are the facts, in reality? 2.
How to observers viewing them from the outside, and
do they look
especially to the authors of theories and doctrines? In the case of
writers and specialists, the solutions of the problems are, in great
part at least, explicit; but for human beings in the mass they are
often implicit, that is to say, without formulating the solutions they
in fact find people conduct themselves as though they were acting
with reference to them. One might better say, to avoid the usual
the subjects we deal with in Chapter XII,* coming down from them to the matters
here in temdrButthat method is not ^ic^best suited to a sound understanding of
It is the qualitative problem thfct confronts us in the concrete whenever
puis^ubject,
we t6\|ch up6jj social matters. That wa virtually the only problem ever considered
}n time*, oast, aX t
it continues to be for almost all writers today. So the concept of
ny greater prccisiopt In tftc case of a special variety of utility, the utility considered
in political economyvthe need came to be felt some time ago and gave rise to the
(theories
of purp ecpnon^ics. In thjis study ;we are trying to extend a similar exactness
io, other sort? of rftility, a^cl we arevfollo\binfc the same course that was followed in
x&nomics/ working, that from the b^ttefr known to the less known, from the
i>,
nirjft thwn the less exact to the more exact. That
iipperfect to the less imperfect,
nannef ot^xposition is less succftict &nd polfched than the deductive method, which
VO/KS injjthfixjppoitcdkection; buKit is^much clearer, much easier, and much more
lelpful for the person who desires to masteis# subject.
1306 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1877
to the second above, and which can be stated in the question: 4. How
actually has the relation between utility and the manner in which
individuals interpret facts been viewed
by people, and especially by
2
writers Just here we are interested in problems i and 2
?
only. They
suggest the following subjects for our examination:
garded as
approximately identical ( 1883-84)
II-2#. The ideals, T, are distinguished sharply and a priori
from the utility, m ( 1885-91)
11-2^-a. Only certain purposes T are considered ( 1886)
II-2-/3. The imaginary purposes, T, and the utility, m, are
set
flatly
in opposition ( 1887)
11-2^-j/. Intermediate cases ( 1888-91)
III. How T is associated as an effect with certain causes ( 1892-
93)
III-i. First
problem ( 1892)
III-2. Second problem ( 1893)
stinct pure and simple. It may also be an instinct with human be-
1876 We have many times already alluded to problems 3 and 4 without so desig-
2
nating them explicitly; and we shall have further occasion to sound them in the
course of this work. Further along ( 1896, 1932), we shall discuss them some-
what generally and in a particular case.
*
1877 Logico-experimental purposes that are realized through the arts and sci-
because of the conflict the individual feels between his own ad-
imaginary principles. That has been the case not only in virtue of
the tendency of the residues of group-persistence, of which the T"s
are made
up, to assume absolute forms or at least an appearance
of concrete reality, but also in virtue of the practical advantage of
not allowing a doubt of any kind to lodge in the mind of the per-
son who is to be persuaded, and of utilizing, for that purpose, the
force which absoluteness, or at least the presumed reality,
confers
i.e., derivatives, express the residue directly, the demand for logic being met by
derivations proper ( 1688). A. L.]
1308 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1879
lose touch with the real world altogether are forced to recognize
the presence of such ideals in the past and at present. Some, however,
say that they will gradually disappear and that at the end of social
evolution mankind will have nothing but experimental aims.
1879. II: Relations of the purpose (ideal}, T, to the point, m, that
individuals actually attain, and to various utilities.
II-i: First problem. The solution of the objective
problem is to
be gathered from the whole sum of investigations that we are now
completing. It was partly to obtain such a solution that we felt
obliged to go so deeply into residues and derivations, for the purpose
of discovering the substance underlying outward forms. may We
say, in brief, that to aim at an imaginary objective, T, in order to
might be; and possible cases are cases in which we assume as non-
existent certain ties that are actually found missing in real cases
(SJ2I 43
1881.
f.).
That
...
is admitted in substance, or at least
implicitly admitted,
by those who wouldreplace imaginary with real purposes and
ideals
so render social life logico-experimental throughout. But as a rule
1 88 1
*
A chemist or a physicist would be amused if an amateur who had never
made a special study of chemistry or physics should presume to pronounce judg-
ment on problems connected with those sciences. And yet such scientists, without
ever having read a book in the social sciences, set themselves up as oracles in con-
nexion with most knotty social problems (1435^). One of them confidently
decides that would be a great misfortune for humanity if Germany did not be-
it
come mistress of Europe, making her ''civilization" triumphant over Russian "bar-
barism." He seems not even remotely to suspect that to determine the effects upon
human evolution of German predominance, or Russian predominance, in Europe is
about as difficult a task as to determine the constitution of matter. That conies about
because the scientist, following the objective method in his chemistry or physics,
unwittingly falls under the spell of the subjective method in turning to the social
sciences. When he is talking about the structure of the atom, he keeps to what ex-
perience has taught him and discards sentiment. When he pronounces on Socialism,
imperialism, German "civilization," Russian "barbarism," and so on, he merely
voices the sentiments which those words or phrases awaken in him, and cares not
a fig about experience (historical observation and the like), of which he is almost
always totally ignorant. That anomaly is all the more striking when we see novel-
ists, poets, and playwrights pronouncing ex cathedra on social and economic matters
on which they are grossly uninformed. What connexion can there be between writ-
1310 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1882
1882. Our
conclusions, therefore, will be that the pursuit of certain
imaginary aims, T, has been in the past, continues in the present, and
will probably continue in any near future, to be very advantageous
for human societies ( 1932); that oftentimes there may be several
concurrent aims, T, T', T" widely differing as regards deriva-
. . .
( 1740, 1850 f.) ; but that all that in no way proves that the pursuit
of other imaginary, theological, or metaphysical aims may not have
been detrimental to society in the past, or may not be in the present
or future 1873, Figure 30). Questions as to the utility of ideals
(
cannot be answered in general. One must specify which ideals one
is
considering, and then go on to determine their relations to other
social facts; and that must be done not only qualitatively, but
stance, rather than in the forms, of the doctrines that have been
current as to the relations of T and m. When they make any ex-
tensive use of derivations they are better analyzed in connexion with
III and IV.
11-20: T and m are not distinguished or are at least regarded as
ing a successful play and objectively solving a problem in social science? There is a
connexion, all the same! And that is where sentiment comes in. The notions such
people express in regard to social problems are absurd, fatuous, idiotic, from the
But from the standpoint of sentiment, they will please the
scientific standpoint.
same audiences that have applauded their plays. Such a public is, for the most part,
incapable of grasping a logico-experimental argument; but it feasts on sentimental
utterances that are suited to its mental powers. Such is the world, and one cannot
imagine how and when it is ever going to change.
1882 2
We are to do that in the chapter next following.
1883 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 13 1 1
a-I-i. A
general who believes in "immanent justice and truth" is better fitted than
an other sort of general to discharge his function, which is to lead his troops to vic-
tory in case of war. Picquart held the belief in question; therefore he must have
contributed to assuring victory for his country in case of war. M. Doumergue, notice,
did not refer to the belief as an adornment over and above Picquart's merits as a
soldier. Of those merits he said nothing; and wisely, for what more he could have
said in Picquart's favour than what he said is very little indeed. A writer in the
Gazette dc Lausanne, Jan. 21, 1914, who was nevertheless kindly disposed towards
Picquart, wrote: "One may wonder and the question has been passionately argued
whether the hero of the Dreyfus affair was as soundly inspired in accepting the
compensation that the abrupt development in events brought his way. The very
peculiar prestige which haloed that attractive and rather enigmatic figure could only
1312 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1883
prosperity.
a-II-2. The utility of having a certain form of government is superior to the util-
ity of winning a war. Those two principles M. Doumergue and those who applauded
him may well have had in mind, but it would have been diflicult to get a clear
statement of them out of those gentlemen. Our many difficulties in demonstrating
the utility of the principle may be obviated if we move on to another order of ideas:
/?.
Observance of the principle stated is an end in itself independent of any con-
sideration of utility.
yg-I.
Our sole concern must be to satisfy "immanent justice and truth": Do what
you ought, come what will! That, substantially, is the rule-of-life of all faiths that
it was the rule of the Christian martyrs. It is not
are at all vigorous apparent how-
ever that M. Doumergue and his friends bear any close resemblance to Christian
martyrs.
/J-II.
We must not worry about war there is not going to be a war, anyhow!
So the important thing is not to have generals who arc good fighters on the field
of battle, but generals who follow the "moral" principles of the party in power. A
believer in "immanent truth and justice" must be preferred to an able general. At
the head of our army we want not a Napoleon Bonaparte, but a St. Francis of
Assisi who holds a paid-up membership in the Radical party. Something like that
may well have been in the minds of M. Doumergue's friends. One must not forget
that they wanted Andre for their Minister of War and Pelletan for their Minister of
Marine and that those two gentlemen utterly disorganized the national defence of
France. M. Doumergue's party, moreover, opposed the three-years law and in every
way showed itself hostile to the army.
So now we are getting closer to the realities underlying the derivation "immanent
truth and justice":
is a mere euphemism for the interests of a group of politicians and
y. It "spec-
ulators" ( 2235). Those individuals found in the Dreyfus affair a ladder for climb-
ing into power, making money, and winning public honours, with the support of
a few "intellectuals" who swallowed the bait that was dangled before them and
took the euphemisms, immanent truth and immanent justice, for realities.
M. Doumergue's derivation has therefore to be translated into the following lan-
guage: "Picquart served our interests, and we are honouring him that we may in-
duce others to do as he did. For the country's defence we care not a hang. Come
what may, we stand by our interests, and the interests of our party."
1314 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1884
stress is laid on T2, often represented as identical with Ti, and mi
and m2
are represented as more or less identical with T2 and Ti,
we get in germ the many theological and metaphysical systems of
ethics. In order to
bring T2 and mi closer together to the point of
identity, theological moralities resort to sanctions emanating from
their particular deities. Metaphysical ethics replace
gods with some
imperative or other ( 1886, 1938) and with no great success, one
must add.
1884. B. The schemer consciously aims at m
and preaches T;
but the same thing is also done by many individuals who are in all
good faith.
Cynically selfish people are rare and downright hypo-
crites equally majority of men merely desire to reconcile
so. The
their ownadvantage with the residues of sociality (Class IV);
realize their own happiness while
seeming to strive for the happi-
ness of others; cloak their self-seeking under mantles of religion,
up a contract in the economic field. Each, in other words, tries to bring the grist
to his own mill, each tries to make his own share as large as possible. Such the ob-
which they strove and are striving. But outwardly they
jectives for said and still
say,
and many believed and still believe, that their aim was and is the ideal, T.
From the manufacturers' side we did not get such very subtle reasonings. They
pointed to their concern for the welfare of the working-classes, the 'legitimate"
remuneration due to men who made an enterprise prosper by the art of combina-
tions, the social advantages of economic freedom, which they always remembered
when fixing wages and always forgot when fixing prices.
From the working-men's side came a flood of subtle theories that were agitated
l886 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1315
1885. \\-2b: The purposes, T, are distinguished sharply and a
priori from the utility, m. Ordinarily it only in appearances that
is
thing that has the look of a theological system, advocating, that is,
ends, T, into the two classes, Th and T\. For them there is but one
class, Th, and the ends Th are the only ends that really exist. They,
therefore, are "real" ends, "true" ends, the ends Tf( being non-
existent, "unreal," "false." Since the purposes Th are the only real
ones in the eyes of such writers, the category Th takes the place
of the category T, to which we alluded in the preceding cases, and
is identical with it.
deities, and, as
is
usually the case, there are some among them who
increase in prestige while others wane or even vanish from the earth.
At one time the auri sacra fames held first place in the hierarchy;
now that demon is quoted very low. In the heyday of Christian
fervour "Pagan Superstition" was in the ascendant as opposed to
"True Religion." In modern times "Private Property" came to dis-
pute the primacy of "Superstition," and Rousseau berated the poor
thing with appalling invectives. But in the days of the French Revo-
lution "Superstition" resumed her former throne, this time with an
society is
"capitalistic." Its ills therefore originate in "capitalism."
There are, of course, other arguments too, but they come down, at
bottom, to the plain assertion that if people had all the things they
wanted they would not resort to crimes and cruelties in order to
procure them. Granting, then, that "capitalism" alone prevents
people from having all the things they want, it remains demon-
strated that capitalism is the root of all evil.
1891. Over against the principle of evil is set the principle of
swered that the poverty and the wealth produced by capitalism have the same effect.
That may be so. Let us see: If the explanation is sound, the situation in question
ought not to arise among people who have just modest incomes. Unfortunately that
is not the case. The woman of the petty bourgeoisie sells herself to get a stylish hat;
the society woman
sells herself to get a string of pearls but they both sell them-
selves. The
conclusion has to be that if all individuals in a given community had
exactly the same income, there would still be women ready to give themselves to
the men who were disposed to supply them with the things they want. The objec-
tion is urged, of course, that our society is corrupt because of the existence of the
capitalistic system; and that objection cannot be answered, for it is an article of
faith and faith transcends experience. Other fanatics, of the breed that organize
leagues against obscenity and the "white-slave trade," and societies for the "im-
provement of morals," deliberately shut their eyes to the light from such facts. It is
an article of faith with those innocent souls that the man always seduces the woman,
and that women therefore must be protected. Yet anybody willing to go to the
trouble of reading the newspapers and following cases in the courts will find that
it is more frequently the woman who misleads the man. Everywhere, in cases of
the unfaithful clerk, the dishonest cashier, the absconding banker, the army officer
1892 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1319
turned spy, some woman is involved, and we get new confirmation of the judge's
apothegm, "Cherchez la jemme." The needs of such women are not the needs of a
modest comfortable standard of living, but the needs of extravagance and display;
and it is to satisfy such demands that men are often led to steal, betray, and some-
times commit murder. If there must be this craze for protection, why worry so much
about the seduction of women and so little about the seduction of men? Why is
there no ingenious brain to invent some other stupid phrase like the "white-slave
trade'* to apply to the case of the poor white man? Only a sick or childish mind
can imagine that it is just the material requirements of getting a living that drive
women to prostitution. With many women it is a case of vanity and love of ex-
travagance. Not a few others turn to the occupation out of indolence; and, in higher
social circles, there arc those who like the profession the way a hunter likes hunting
and the fisherman fishing. There too there is no lack of facts for those who choose
to see them. How many who
have been forcibly redeemed by simple-
the prostitutes
minded uplifters and provided with respectable and comfortable livings, only to
desert them and return to their old occupation for which they felt an incurable
homesickness? But many people refuse to see these facts, and others like them, be-
cause they are not telling the truth when they say they are trying to fight prostitu-
tion for the benefit of womanhood and to destroy the "white-slave trade" for the
benefit of said "slaves." Really all they are doing is coddling a theological antipathy
to pleasures of the senses.
I32O THE MIND AND SOCIETY
into play. It follows that
only those works of literature will live
which associate ideals with powerful residues and important inter-
ests. Such residues are
always available from some one of our classes.
Very effective are certain residues of group-persistence, which, taken
either singly or in combination with other residues (among which
it is tied
vary somewhat more; the derivations and pseudo-scientific
reasonings serving to associate ideals and residues, much much
more.
1893. III-2: Second problem. In doctrines, in general, when ideals
do not stand by themselves as absolutes they are considered conse-
quences of theological or metaphysical principles or of interests; and
the result is those various moralities which we discovered in germ
in examining the relations of T and m ( i883f.). As for the na-
ture of the correlation, bluntly represented as rigorously logi-
it is
was already present in the mind of the searcher, and not infre-
quently in the opinions of the community to which he belongs.
1896 VIRTUE AND HAPPINESS 132!
There is no chance that the theoretical moralist will ever end up
with a theorem that conflicts with his own conscience; and very
rarely with a theory conflicting with the ethics of the society in
which he lives. Conversely, if it is shown that a certain ideal, T, is
not a logical consequence of experimental, or at least "rational,"
pearance of logic to non-logical conduct performed with the ideal, T, in view. Such
devices are resorted to with the explicit, but more often implicit, intention of repre-
senting T and m
as identical. Logical conduct leads to m. If it is to lead to T as
1896
1
We might repeat that the solution has to come from the sum of investiga-
tions which we have been conducting in these volumes. This problem we shall treat
more specially in our next chapter.
1322 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1897
with experience (or with reality) doctrines that show no such ac-
cord.
Very few theorists, on the other hand, have had any inkling of it,
most of them accepting solutions corresponding to II-20. They have
confused "truth" and "utility," holding that it is always useful to in-
dividuals and community that people should view the facts under
their "true" aspect. If "truth" there means conformity with experi-
utility
of such ideas approximates experience or diverges from it
only what "true," "just," "moral," and the like, is "useful." Now-
is
1897
*
O ne should re-read at this point the remarks we made in 1876 *.
1898 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1323
wondered whether individual or community realized happiness by
following such rules. The problem is a more limited one than the
preceding. In the we
are not inquiring as to general rela-
first
place,
tionships, but asking merely whether or not happiness is realized.
That eliminates theological or metaphysical solutions of our \\-ib
type ( 1876), which envisage "duty" without reference to utility.
We can consider only such solutions as take account of some utility
2
or other, be it
imaginary. In the second place, the ideals, T,
real or
"happiness."
1898. To solve the particular problem that we have set ourselves
we must first
give greater exactness to our statement of it. may We
disregard the very serious lack of definiteness in the terms "reli-
gion" and "morality," since they are not essential to the problem.
Things would still be the same were we to speak of the observance
of certain rules, to be designated by any names one chose and there-
fore also by the quite nebulous terms "religion" and "morality."
But there are two points in the statement where the vagueness is
important and cannot be disregarded. The first is the meaning of
the terms "happiness" and "unhappiness" ; and we shall see that
2
1897 Efforts are frequently made to confuse the two kinds of solutions, for it is
not comfortable to leave "duty" floating in the air in that fashion, without any
bearing whatever on the real world. Solutions #2, #3 and 4 of 1902 are designed
to produce just that confusion.
1324 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1899
and religion will he necessarily be happy and if he violates them,
unhappy? Or one may ask: If the individuals constituting a com-
munity observe or violate the afore-said rules will they be happy or
unhappy ?
II. The individuals who observe, or violate, the rules may be dif-
tion; and for that very reason, from the very fact that
questions alto-
gether distinct are dealt with concurrently, affirmative solutions are
available in much greater numbers than negative solutions; and they
are deemed worthy of approval, whereas negative solutions and even
such as cast suspicion of doubt upon the affirmative are deemed rep-
rehensible.
1900. It
may be worth while observing that to give an altogether
affirmative answer to the two questions in 1898-! is to give an
answer that is at least partially negative to the questions in 1898-! I,
and vice versa. In fact, if a man can profit or suffer only by his own
conduct, by observing or violating certain precepts, that is, it fol-
lows that he cannot profit or suffer by the actions of others. And,
conversely, if he can profit or suffer by the conduct of others, it
follows that he does not profit or suffer only by his own.
1901. That is so simple and self-evident that, keeping to strict
lowing terms: "Of existing things they say that some be good, some
evil, some indifferent. Good, accordingly, are virtue, justice, wisdom,
temperance, and other such things; evil the opposites thereof, and
to wit, folly, injustice, and others; and indifferent those things
which work neither benefit nor hurt, such as life, health, physical
pleasure, beauty, strength, wealth, glory, noble birth; and indifferent
likewise, the opposites of these, namely, death, disease, physical pain,
*
1905 Zeno, VII, 101-02 (Hicks, Vol. II, pp. 207-09): Twv tie bvruv <j>aol rd ph ay-
add flvai rd fie mm, rd fie ovfitrepa. 'Ayaftd filv ovv rdq T dperd^ (f>p6vr/aiv fiutaioviwjv,
t t t
ovfierepa baa fiqre cj^eAeZ fiijre pTidnrei, diov C^, vyfeia 7/fiovrj /cd/Uof laxvc, TrAowrof,
fie t t f
good things, eschew the bad, and ignore the indifferent; but in
say-
ing that, all that we
are saying is that by acting on certain norms
one attains the ideal of
acting on those norms. That is all undeni-
able, but it tells one exactly nothing. It is true that in the argument
of the Stoics there is a little
something more. They intimate, by an
association of ideas, that we ought to act so and so, and the moral
adjunct serves to conceal the tautology. Unfortunately, the supple-
ment is a purely metaphysical one.
1906. There is the further effort to confuse the
"good things" as
they are newly defined with "good things" as ordinarily under-
stood. Following that line, in expounding the doctrine of the Stoics,
Cicero has them say: "I ask you, furthermore, who could really
and "surpassingly beautiful." And where the lunatic to deny that what is "mag-
nificent," or "worshipful" (ae/tv6v) 9 is also "beautiful" (itaMv) ?
*
1906 [The whole passage reads: "Their arguments conclude, therefore: Any-
thing that is good is in all respects praiseworthy, but what is praiseworthy is in all
respects honourable. Anything good therefore is honourable. Does that seem suffi-
ciently convincing? ... I ask you furthermore, who could really glory in a life of
wretchedness, and fail to glory in a happy (bcata) one? Only in the happy one,
therefore! Whence it follows that the happy life is worthy of being, so to say, glo-
ried in, which can really (jure) be the lot only of the life that is honourable.
Whence it follows that the honourable life is the happy life." A. L.]
1328 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1907
on paths where ingenious metaphysical inanities dissolve in the light
of experience.
1907. Not a few writers of the ancient world ridiculed the chatter
of the Stoics and their resolve to seem what they were not. Athe-
that "the Wise Man can do all things well; he can even cook a dish
of lentils sensibly"; and replying to the Stoic doctrine that wealth
is
nothing, he quotes, III, 63, lines of Theognetus to the effect that
"the books of the Stoics" had been the ruin of one of the speakers
1
in the dialogue who took that position. Horace also, Saturae, I, 3,
vv. 121-36, makes fun of the Stoics for being mendicants and posing
2
as kings.
1908. The author of the Treatise in Defence of Noble Birth (Pro
nobilitate), which is
generally attributed to Plutarch (Fragmenta et
spuria, pp. 61-80), facetiously describes the conflict that arose be-
tween the metaphysical divagations of the Stoics and realities (XVII,
2) : "But neither he [Chrysippus] nor any of the Stoics need to be
of noble birth; for they are followers of a philosophy that can, as
("If he who is wise is rich, and a good cobbler, and the one handsome man, and a
king to boot, why dost thou seek what thou hast?") Horace has someone answer
that the wise man is a good cobbler the way a singer is a good singer, even when
he is not singing; that is to say, the wise man has all the best qualities latent within
him. And then back comes Horace, vv. 133-36:
every act of our doing. Not under our control are: our bodies,
wealth, fame, public distinctions, and, in short, everything which
is not of our doing. Those things which are under our control are,
are not under our control are inert, slavish, bound, alien [under the
control of others]." That much granted, the rest could not be sim-
pler: "If that only which is yours [things under your control]
you consider yours, and that which is alien [not under your con-
trol], not yours, as yours it is not, no one will ever constrain you
nor bind you; nor will you rebuke or accuse any man; for you will
do nothing against your will, nor have injury of anyone; and you
will have no enemy, since no evil can be inflicted on you." It is true,
of course, that if you say that you do whatever you are forced to
do of your own accord, you may claim that you are doing nothing
against your will. So argued the person who on being thrown from
his horse remarked, "I was just dismounting."
1912. The doctrine of Epictetus and others of the sort, such as the
Christian's resignation to the will of God, are not scientific doc-
trines: they are consolations for people who cannot, or will not,
fight.
It is certain that pain is often alleviated by not thinking about
it and trying to imagine that it does not exist; and something of
the sort observable again in our time, in Christian Science; just
is
as there are instances where the physician, and more likely the
quack, alleviates pain by his simple presence. The favour with which
the doctrine of Epictetus was welcomed was one of the many symp-
toms presaging the imminent vogue of Christianity.
1913. of precepts or norms from
A2i Change of the meanings
objective to subjective. In the Ai type the tautology arose from
changes in the meanings of the terms "happiness," "unhappiness,"
"the good." In this variety it results from changes in the meanings
of the precepts. Needless to say, if we consider only such rules as the
1
1911 Dissertationcs, I, 1-3. See Pareto, Manuale, Chap. I.
1917 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 133!
individual observes with pleasure, we may unhesitatingly assert that
he experiences pleasure in observing them.
1914. If we look at torture objectively, we may say that, in gen-
eral, it is human beings to suffer torture; but if,
a misfortune for
subjectively, we
consider the Christian martyr's feelings, we see that
it is a
blessing in his eyes to be tortured for his faith.
1915. When it is asserted that he who does evil cannot be
happy
because he suffers remorse, it is implicitly assumed that the wrong-
doer is capable of remorse. But it is not hard to see that in many
individuals remorse is either a sentiment present in negligible quan-
tities or not existing at all, and for such people, therefore, the pen-
1
alty threatened almost
not altogether a matter of indifference.
is if
1916. The majority of men and women who set out to reform
society assume, at bottom, that society will be made up of individ-
uals endowed with the sentiments and ideas with which they choose
to endow them, and only under those conditions can they promise
such persons happiness.
1917. Certain Protestant sects that no longer admit the divinity
of Christ are propagating a doctrine that is altogether subjective.
They say that Christ is the type of the perfect man. That is just an
idea of theirs; and they have no way of combating anyone who
might say, to the contrary, that He is the type of the imperfect man.
But such a weapon is available for anyone who believes in the divin-
ity
of Christ; for that divinity is an objective thing, independent of
individual opinion, and the unbeliever can therefore be threatened
with action on the part of the objective entity. But how threaten
him with the action of something that depends upon himself, and
which he can accept, modify, or reject, as he pleases? Furthermore
1915
l
De fmibus bonorum et malorum, II, 16, 51-53: "And so, Torquatus,
Cicero,
when you said that Epicurus declared that one could not live happily unless he lived
honourably, wisely, justly, I had the impression that you were boasting. There was
so much power in your words because of the majesty of the things they stood for,
that you looked taller to me. All the same, the deterrents you mentioned are
. . .
trifling and very weak all that about wicked men being tormented by their con-
sciences, and then by their fear of the punishment that overtakes them or which
they fearmay sometime overtake them. The wicked man must not be thought of as
a timidweak-minded creature who is always tormenting himself, whatever he does,
and fearing everything. Think of him rather as a person who is always shrewdly
calculating his interest, crafty, wide-awake, sly, always figuring how he can sin
again secretly, without witnesses or accomplices."
1332 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1918
as regards theOld Testament, those same people beg the question:
They deny divine inspiration to such portions of the Old Testament
as they deem to be inconsistent with their own ethics. After that, of
course, they can safely conclude that their ethics accords with divine
inspiration.
1918. The that precepts have in a given society at a given
power
time lies chiefly in the fact that they are accepted by the majority
of individuals comprising that society, and that individuals who
violate them experience a sense of discomfort, find themselves ill at
ease. Such precepts are merely an expression, and no very exact one,
of the residues operating in that society. It is therefore bootless to
question is what effect the precepts have upon individuals not pos-
sessing the residues expressed in the precepts and how dissidents are
to be persuaded that they will experience a pleasure, or a pain, that
they do not directly feel. From the standpoint of utility the ques-
tion is whether observance of the precepts is useful to individual,
community, nation, and so on, in the sense given to the term "util-
regarded as "useful." If
prevented from following an
an animal is
important to examine.
1919. Ay. Casuistry: interpretations of precepts and norms. It is
suprema lex often enough transpires. If that fact were stated bluntly,
logical justification, and we would so get one of
it would be a sound
*
1920 Mommsen, Romische Geschichte, Vol. II, p. 14 (Dixon, Vol. Ill, pp.
14-15): "On a mere rumour, which proved to be false, that the Cantabrians and
Vaccaei were marching to the relief of Numantia, the army evacuated its camp dur-
ing the night without orders and took refuge behind the lines that Nobilior had
built sixteen years before. Informed of the flight, the Numantians at once started in
pursuit of the Romans and surrounded them. The Romans now had no alternative
aristocracy. He alone was designated to pay for his own and the common mistake.
That day witnessed the spectacle of a Roman of consular rank being stripped of
his insigniaand led before the outposts of the enemy. The Numantians refused to
receive him (for that would have meant recognition of the abrogation of the treaty),
so that the degraded general spent a whole day in front of the city gates, naked,
with his hands tied behind his back." Florus, Epitoma de Tito Livio, I, 34, 5-8 (II,
18, 5-8; Forster, p. 153): "They decided [in the case of Pompey] to make a treaty
though they might have won a crushing victory. Then Hostilius Mancinus too they
so harassed with continuous slaughter that everybody fled at sight or sound of a
Numantian soldier. Yet in his case also they preferred to make a treaty, being satis-
fiedwith the proceeds of the booty, though they might have been cruel and extermi-
nated his army. But no less outraged at the disgrace and humiliation of this Numan-
tine treaty than at the treaty of the Caudine Forks, the Roman People expiated the
is so convinced of
discredit of the present crime by surrendering Mancinus." Florus
1921 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1335
1921. Thestory of the Caudine Forks seems to have been copied
1
from the story of Numantia. If the
story is true, it furnishes proof
that such casuistry was a common
thing with the Romans; if the
story is false, it serves that
purpose even better; for in fabricating
such a story the Romans must certainly have taken pains to turn
out what seemed to them a good story; and their
copying from ac-
counts of the treaty of Numantia shows that
they found nothing in
those negotiations discreditable to the reputation for
honesty which
they were concerned to preserve and of which they were wont to
boast. That view is confirmed by Cicero; for in the treatise that he
wrote to teach us poor mortals our duties, he points approvingly to
the conduct of the Romans in the episodes at the Caudine Forks
and at Numantia. But Cicero was keen enough to see that to have
done honestly by the Numantians the Romans should have handed
over to them not the consul only, but the entire army, replacing it
the honesty of that procedure, that he goes on to exclaim, I, 19, i (Forster, p. 157) :
"To that extent was the Roman People handsome, distinguished, loyal, pure, mag-
nificent!'* Really, if the rules of justice and honesty can be manipulated in that
fashion, there can be no doubt that observance of them will always redound to the
material prosperity of a people. Vellcius Paterculus, Historia Rom an a, II, i, 4-5:
"That city [Numantia] whether because of its military ability, or the incompetence
of our generals, or the indulgence of chance, reduced, along with others of our
generals, Pompey, a man of great fame and the first of our consuls from the
Pompeian gens, to make a very humiliating peace, and to a no less base and cow-
ardly one, the consul Mancinus Hostilius. Influence saved Pompey from punish-
ment, Mancinus, his sense of shame, for on his own motion he was sent to Nu-
mantia that he might be handed over to the enemy by our heralds, naked, with
his hands bound behind his back. But just as had happened at the Caudine Forks,
the enemy refused to receive him, saying that a violation of faith by a people
could not be atoned for by the blood of one man.'* Those Numantians were good
fighters but very ordinary casuists.
l
1921 In his Storia di Roma, Vol. I, pp. 498-500, Ettore Pais considers the docu-
ment that Livy quotes regarding the peace of the Caudine Forks as fictitious: "The
story was invented to extenuate the moral responsibility of the Romans, who were
later on accused of having turned their backs on the traditional good faith of which
they were wont to boast. Livy's long narrative \_Ab urbe condita, IX, 1-12] is only
one of the many ornaments of the rhetoric, or pseudo-pragmatic, of the annalists,
designed to render less dishonourable first the defeat and then the treachery of the
Romans. . . . But it would be idle for us to show at any length that Livy's account
of the negotiations is unhistorical. A learned and penetrating critic of our day has
noted thatall details in the story were borrowed from later history, and especially
from the treaty of peace concluded with the Numantians by the consul Hostilius
Mancinus (137 B.C.)."
1336 THE MIND AND SOCIETY Ip22
in the situation in which it stood when it was extricated by a pact
2
that the Romans up refused to live to.
"They were surrendered ... in order that the treaty of peace with the Samnites
might be repudiated, and Postumius himself, who was to be the victim, was the
proposer of the bill and spoke in support of it. The same thing was done years later
by Caius Mancinus, who had concluded a treaty with the Numantians without the
authorization of the Senate. He too spoke in favour of the bill [ordering his sur-
render to the Numantians] which F. Furius and Sextus Atilius introduced [before
the comitia] in compliance with a resolution of the Senate. The bill was passed
and he was handed over to the enemy. He deported himself much more honourably
than Quintus Pompey, who in the same situation refused his assent, so that the
bill did not pass." This manipulation of the principle of public honour was
accepted, he belongs to those to whom he has been delivered. If they do not accept
him, as the Numantians did not accept Mancinus, he retains his status unchanged
and his rights of citizenship." [In the De Officiis Cicero recounts with explicit dis-
approval another example of Roman
sharpness. Appointed to arbitrate a boundary
dispute between the people of Naples and the people of Nola, the Roman repre-
sentative urged moderation upon both parties and procured their signatures to con-
tracts accepting much
less territory than they were entitled to. The result was that
a large area wasbetween the boundary accepted by Nola and the boundary
left
accepted by Naples, and this was occupied forthwith by the Roman People. A. L.j
x
1922 La guerre de 1870, Vol. I, pp. 124-26.
1923 THE "EMS DESPATCH" 1337
common against an enemy who for centuries had ever stood pre-
pared, he gave the official communication a particular turn [This
historian would probably find nothing wrong with Pascal's famous
"Mohatra contract" in the Provinciales!] that put the French in the
painful dilemma either of declaring war themselves or bowing to
" 2
affront that Bismarck had contrived to
the give them/ All of
. . .
way?" and replied, "No!" meaning "up his sleeve." Bismarck did not
falsify the Ems despatch he merely gave it a particular turn! It may
well be that the German social democracy is "no worshipper of
country"; but Horst-Kohl certainly seems to be no worshipper of
truth; and by "truth" we mean experimental truth; for there are so
many many "truths" that among them there may easily be one for
3
the personal use and consumption of the historian Horst-Kohl.
1923. Then, a breath later, the same "historian" turns champion
1 "
of the strictest morality. 'If the war broke out
through any fault
of the Germans, then the French are absolutely justified in com-
despatch Bismarck had forced France to take the initiative in the war and respon-
sibility for it and that he had so done a great service to the Fatherland. Had he
acted otherwise the war would not have taken place. 'The war was absolutely
necessary for establishing a united Germany. Had
that opportunity been allowed
to escape, some other pretext would have had to be found, a less adroit one per-
haps, which might have cost Germany the sympathies of Europe.' Bismarck jest-
ingly replied to a newspaper man who was expressing astonishment at his ex-
if that one had missed fire, some other would have been found.'
pedient: 'Oh,
"
'Blessed,' says Hans Delbrikk, 'blessed the hand that falsified the Ems despatch!'
Hohenlohe, Den](wurdigl(eitcn, May 6, 1874, Vol. II, p. 119 (Chrystal, Vol. II, p.
109): "At table Bismarck revived memories of 1870 his discussion with Roon
and Moltkc, who were beside themselves at the resignation of the Prince von
Hohenzollern and the King's good-natured assent; then the Abekcn despatch and
the abridgment of it that he, Bismarck, had made and which rendered war un-
avoidable." But rhetoricians, sophists, and casuists have their uses, because they
bake a bread that is suited to the teeth of the mass of people in a population.
*
1923 Welschinger, he. cit., p. 126.
1338 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1923
Alsace-Lorraine, which is now in our hands, as the prize of vic-
"
tory.' If Horst-Kohl really believes what he says,
he is a man of
extraordinary ingenuousness. How many
changes would have to be
made in the boundaries of modern countries if each of them were
quisite cleverness and resonance. However, only those who can say
quia nominor leo enjoy the privilege of violating norms and finding
obliging casuists to show that they are observing them. As a matter
of fact, the reasonings of those worthy gentlemen convince in gen-
eral only people who are already convinced, or whose vision is
clouded by some strong sentiment by a worship, let us say, of the
sort mentioned by the casuist Horst-Kohl. Their influence, there-
are full to the bindings of deceptions of every kind, and wisely did
against cunning and from those long and laborious preparations which alone can
lead to victory. It is, in short, like persuading an army to use cardboard cannon
instead of steel. "Intellectuals" pride themselves on such idle chatter because they
are manufacturers and sellers of artillery of the cardboard variety not of the
steel.
*
1925 Acne'id, II, v. 390: Bolus an virtus, quis in hoste requirat? "Be it trickery,
be it valour who cares, in the case of an enemy?" Servius annotates (Thilo-Hagen,
Vol. I, p. 281): "Something seems to be missing, as
for instance: 'Who ever asks in
"
the case of an enemy whether virtue or treachery is best in war?*
*
1926 "Phoebidas having done the cruel deed of occupying the Cadmeia in
time of peace, all the Greeks were wroth, and above all the Spartans, especially
those among them who were hostile to Agesilaus. And angrily they inquired of
Phoebidas by whose order he had done that thing, turning their suspicion upon
Agesilaus himself. But Agesilaus did not hesitate to say openly in defence of
Phoebidas that one ought to consider whether such a deed were profitable, for
1340 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1927
Holofernes the end justified the means, and on that account, partly,
the Protestants have banished her book from their Bible (leaving in
2
other things quite the equal of Judith's guile).
1927. The festival of the Apaturia at Athens was probably noth-
ing more than a festival of the phratries or clans; but the Athenians
invented an etymology that a glorification of fraud. As the
made it
ing of such a thing, Xanthus was surprised and turned around, and
straightway Melanthus ran him through with a lance. . . . Where-
Athenian, at the bidding of an oracle, reared a temple to
after the
Not only did he save Phoebidas. He also persuaded the city to take the misdeed
upon and hold the Cadmcia.
itself Shortly therefore the suspicion arose that
. . .
the thing had indeed been done by Phoebidas, but that Agcsilaus had counselled
it." Xenophon, Hcllenica, V, 2, 32: "Agesilaus nevertheless said that if a man had
done aught to the harm of Lacedaemon, he would be justly punished; but that if the
deed were good, it was the law of the forefathers that it should be done without
orders.'* Yet Xenophon also says, Agesilaus, 10, 2, that Agesilaus was the type of
the virtuous man: "The virtue of Agcsilaus seems to me to be a model for those
who desire to be virtuous; for who, by imitating the pious man, would become
impious or the just man, unjust?*' In private matters as well, Agcsilaus was no
stickler for niceties. Plutarch, Agesilaus, 13, 5 (Perrin, Vol.
V, pp. 35-37): "In every
other respect he was a strict observer of the law; but in matters regarding friends
he considered too much justice an affectation. Often quoted in this connexion is
a brief note that he addressed to Hidrieus of Caria: 'If Nicias is innocent, acquit.
he "
If is guilty, for my sake acquit. In any event, acquit.'
2
1926Judith, 9:10-3: She prays God: "Smite by the deceit of my lips the servant
with the prince and the prince with the servant. And make my speech and
. . .
deceit to be their wound and strife." Why should this book not have its place
among the books that justify the Christian experience? There arc so many people
who think just as Judith thought, in time of war!
1928 ZEUS THE DECEIVER 134!
Greeks promise to save Dolon's life and then kill him. In the Odys-
sey, XIII, vv. 256-86, Ulysses utters as
many falsehoods as words and
Athena delighted. Even Dante, Inferno, XXXIII, v. 150, resorts
is
indeed much touted; but she is not welcome there, nor is she lodger or bride
there. She is as it were on the lips of the advocate, not as in the hearts and affections
of the party. Those who take religion on the left, those who take it on the
. . .
right, those who say it is white, those who say it is black, use it in manners so
similar for their purposes of violence and ambition, and they behave so much alike
1342 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1929
1929. Our Machiavelli's one wrong, if wrong one must call it,
*
was in manifesting his contempt for such idiocies when he wrote:
"How the use of treachery in waging war is a thing of glory. Albeit
the use of deceit in any connexion is a reprehensible thing [That
he says just
as an excuse for what he is
going to say, and so does not
mind the contradiction.], nevertheless in the conduct of war it is a
laudable and glorious thing, and he that vanquishes the enemy by
See the horrible impudence with which we marshal divine arguments, and how
sacrilegiously we drop them or pick them up according as fortune has changed our
situation in these public storms. Take the solemn proposition as to whether it is
permitted a subject to rebel and take up arms against his prince in defence of re-
ligion, and remember on what lips its affirmative was to be heard last year as the
main buttress of a party! And the negative, the buttress of what other party! And
now from what quarter the affirmative and the negative are being sounded and
propounded and are arms any less noisy for the one cause than for the other?
And we burn people for saying that truth must be subject to the yoke of our needl
Yet how much worse than merely saying it is France doing 1"
a
1929 Dcca, III, 40, 41.
1931 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1343
selves in order to achieve "happiness" in the ordinary sense of the
word as material well-being. They need answers therefore to the
upon sentiment without too great offence to the latter. The mix-
ture of sentiment andsophistical explanation is essentially heteroge-
neous, and that accounts for the amazing contradictions that are
1
never lacking in such reasonings. Around the equilibrium residue
as a nucleus other residues cluster, and notably those of the II- (sen-
timents taken as objective realities) and of the \\-YI (personifications)
varieties.
1931. These objective solutions, for the very reason that they are
such, are easily contradicted by the facts. The masses at large do not
mind that, not attaching any great importance to theories and ac-
ory and fact or between one theory and another, and do everything
1930
1
We encountered a number of examples in our study of derivations
( 1481 .)
1344 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1931
in their power to attenuate, eliminate or dissemble them. In gen-
eral they do not altogether abandon objective solutions, especially
solutions of an optimistic trend, but strive
by appropriate inter-
man to suffer in this lowly world and then damn him for all eternity to the fire
that issaid to be in the other world, for, one could say, God has willed it so. But
the Mu'tazilites think that that would be an injustice, and that a being that has
2
suffered, be it even an ant, as I have said [For the quotation see 1995 .] . . .
will have a compensation, the divine wisdom making him suffer that he might have
1
a compensation. We, finally, hold ." [For the quotation see just below,
. .
1934 .]
The theory of "final causes" also is a device for eliminating contradictions. Applied
to the conduct of the individual, it asserts that the purpose of such conduct, whether
the individual knows it or not, is always the individual "good" or the "good" of
the community, and by arguments that are sometimes ingenious, but quite often
absurd and childish, it goes on to discover that "good" where no such thing exists.
Following that method, it is easy to show that all actions leading to one same
goal can never be contradictory. The theory has the nine lives of a cat. Demolished
at one point, it bobs up at another, undergoing the most varied metamorphoses.
As has often been remarked, Darwinism degenerated into an application of final
causes to the forms of living beings. Metaphysicists make wide and various use of
the theory as applied to conduct ( 1521), nor do theologians by any means disdain
it. To have their turn with it, a number of writers have fished
up a certain "ex-
cogitation" and other delightful contraptions of that sort.
1932 THE PROBLEM OF EVIL 1345
tradictionsbetween solutions and experience. That, in fact, is actually
the case. We have already seen how derivations are used to create
confusions between individual welfare and the welfare of the com-
1896. The larger and more effective portion of the residues prev-
alent in a society cannot be altogether unfavourable to its
preser-
vation; for if that were the case, the society would break down and
cease to exist. Residues must, in part at least, be favourable to the
kinds, the objections that could justly be urged against the enforce-
ment of a specific derivation originating in certain specific group-
x 1
1932 Note that the problem here being solved qualitatively only
is ( 1876 ,
x
1897 ). Quantitative considerations will be introduced in Chapter XII.
1934 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1347
society,
finds expression in the derivations A, B, C, it is D . . .
fect accord, an accord embracing all the consequences, all the cor-
ollaries, that might be drawn from it, has ever been explicitly as-
serted. The assumptionof accord appears implicitly, however, in
utilitarian systems of ethics ( 1935). There is no lack of other doc-
1932
2
We
have frequently pointed to the logico-experimcntal weakness the ab-
surdity even of certain derivations; but we have also given repeated warnings
that in so doing we had no intention of minimizing in the slightest the social
utility of the residues of which they were manifestations. That usefulness is like-
wise not affected when we point to the harm that is done by trying to enforce
certain derivations. What we have said as to the experimental ineptness of the
derivations of certain religions and the harm that is done in trying to force some
of their derivations upon a public must not be understood, as is commonly the
case, in the sense that the group-persistences functioning in those religions are not
beneficial but harmful. such religions we even include the sex religion, with
Among
which we have frequently had to deal because of absurd and pernicious deriva-
tions connected with it.
1348 THE MIND AND SOCIETY T
935
1
would necessarily follow. Very very often such doctrines are merely
manifestations of vigorous sentiments that mistake desires for reali-
ties, as regards either the welfare of the individual or the welfare of
any exactness, and while taken literally they seem to assert some-
ex-
thing indubitable, the ambiguity of their language, their many
ceptions, their shifting interpretations, sap the
substance of the pre-
cept and draw the teeth of the assertion that the precept is con-
ducive to the welfare of the person observing it.
1935. From ancient times down to our own there have been the-
ories holding that violations of the norms of morality and, among
the ancients, more particularly of the norms of religion, result in
1934
x
Maimonides, Guide of the Perplexed, III, 17, Theory V (Munk, Vol. Ill,
x
pp. 127-27; Friedlander, Vol.
Ill, pp. 72-73) (continuing quotation in 1931 above):
"We [the Jews], finally, hold that everything that happens to a man is a conse-
quence of what he has come to deserve, that God is above injustice and punishes
him only among us who has earned punishment. That is what the law of Moses,
our Master, literally says, to wit, that all depends on merit; and to that purport
also our doctors in general rule. They expressly state that there is 'no death without
sin, and no punishment without transgression.' And further they say: 'To man is
measured with the measure he hath himself used' the text of the Mishnah. They
everywhere declare that for God justice is an utterly necessary thing, in other words,
that He rewards the pious man for his acts of piety and uprightness even when they
have not been enjoined on him by a prophet, and that He punishes each wicked
act that an individual has committed even when it has not been forbidden by a
to the Romans, Camillus says: "Consider from the beginning the events happy and
unhappy of these past years, and you will find that all has gone well with us when
we have followed the gods, badly when we have ignored them." He goes on, 6-10,
to specify the war with Veii and the invasion by the Gauls, remarking that the
former ended happily because the Romans heeded warnings from the gods, the
latter disastrously because they disregarded such admonishments.
1936 REWARD AND PUNISHMENT 1349
made clear whether they will go to the person who has done the
good or evil deed or will extend to others. As regards the person him-
self, pains are taken not to forget a way out, by postponing to some
indefinite time his garnering of the fruits of his conduct it is not
made clear, in other words, whether the idea is to resort or not to
group 82. 3. If one chose to be punc-
resort to the exceptions of our
tiliously exact,
one would have to note a confusion in assigning to
one same individual an act that he has performed at one moment
and the reward or punishment due him after a certain
lapse of time.
1350 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1937
When the reasoning here in question is used, it is
implicitly assumed
that the individual one and the same in successive periods of time.
is
things are stated explicitly and no one seems to care about the in-
non-compromiser, who sees only one side to all questions, but even
with the plain man. In the long run the inconsistencies are lost sight
of they come to seem natural.Most people fail to notice them at
all, and act as if they did not exist. That is a very general fact and
may be observed in every department of human activity. Many
people, for instance, assume implicitly or explicitly that it is possible
to change, to altogether determine, the conduct of human beings
daily dealings with our neighbours. Now those two ways of view-
1
ing things are quite contradictory. The spendthrift and the miser,
1937
x
We have already seen many examples of disquisitions to the point. Here
is one more, of a very very common type: Pseudo-Turpin, Les fais et les gcstes le fort
roy Charlemaine t pp. 232-33 (Charlemaine, of course, is Charlemagne): "The next
day, on the point of three, came Agoulant [a Saracen] to Charlemaine to receive
baptism. At that time Charlemaine and his men were seated at table. Said Charle-
maine: 'Those whom you see gowned in silk, all red, are the bishops and priests
of our faith, who preach to us and impart the commandments of Our Lord. They
absolve us of our sins and bestow on us Our Lord's benedictions. Those whom you
see in black habits are monks and abbots. .And those next to them in white
. .
9
habits are called canons of the chapters (regies). Then Agoulant looked in an-
other direction and saw thirteen paupers clothed in tatters and eating on the
floor without table or table-cloth and with very little to eat and drink. And he
asked Charlemaine what people they were. 'They/ he answered, 'are people of
God, messengers of Our Lord Jesus Christ, whom we feed each day in honour of
the Twelve Apostles.' Then answered Agoulant: Those who are sitting about you
are very fortunate. They eat and drink liberally and are gowned well and nobly.
And why do you suffer those who you say are messengers of your God to be
hungry and uncomfortable and so poorly clothed and seated so far from you and
so badly served? One does a great insult to one's Lord in treating his messengers
in that way. Your religion which you say was so good clearly shows by what 1 see
that it is false.' Whereat he took leave of Charlemaine and went back to his people
and refused the holy baptism which he had decided to receive and the next day
ordered a battle against Charlemaine. Then the Emperor understood that he had
refused baptism because of the poor whom he had seen so badly served, and for
that reason Charlemaine commanded that the poor in the army should be de-
cently clothed and sufficiently provided with wines and meats." Boccaccio's Jew,
Decameron, I, 2, reasons in a manner directly opposite to Agoulant's. He goes to
Rome, notes the contrast between the evangelical purity that the Church preached
and the immorality of the Roman Curia, and asks to be baptized, deeming that
1352 THE MIND AND SOCIETY J
937
we may guess, have heard arguments
and sermons in goodly num-
ber against their sins. If they have not reformed, if lectures and
of all that has been done to suppress it, there are still drunkards
galore, we have to recognize the presence of a force that makes for
( 1761 f.). We
do assert that their influence is not the exclusive
or, in many cases, the preponderant influence; that they are not the
and draw upon for literary effects, ranging from the simple jest
it
the Christian faith must be truly divine, since it is strong enough to resist such
causes of dissolution.Those are legends, tales, of long ago, but if anyone imagines
that the substance revealed under those forms no longer exists in our day, he need
only gaze about him to find similar inconsistencies very readily. Names only have
changed. Out of the twilight of the ancient gods new gods have arisen: the radiant
sun of Science, Progress, Democracy; the brilliant planets of that solar system called
Truth, Justice, Right, Exalted Patriotism, and others still; the luminous satellites
that take the name of Organization, Civilization, Nationalism, Imperialism, Xeno-
phobia, Solidarity, Humanitarianism, and so on, world without end. These new
religions are as packed with contradictions as the old.
1937 REWARD AND PUNISHMENT 1353
be conducted in strict accordance with religious theories. That is the
theme of preachers, ascetics, saints, and extremists of every kind.
He is
against religion if he holds that the necessities of life are sov-
ing the sophistries of the casuists, but puts nothing in their stead, so
allowing the contradiction between doctrine and practical necessities
to subsist dissembled. The reasonings of the casuists have no logical
value. Pascal's precepts have no practical value. Contradictions be-
tween law and practical life, and especially between international
law and the necessities of statecraft, have existed from time im-
memorial: they literally swarm in Graeco-Roman history; they are
interwoven with religious questions in the Middle Ages; they per-
sist in
huge numbers in the centuries succeeding, and are far from
lacking in our own day. We
are dealing, in short, with a very gen-
eral phenomenon, of which the cases we are examining here are
particular instances.
1354 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1938
1938. The
notion of reward or punishment following on conduct
has, besides pseudo-experimental form, two other forms that fre-
its
quently merge into one: the metaphysical and the religious. In the
metaphysical form reward or punishment necessarily follows the
conduct just why, not very clear. This form is
to tell the truth, is
proofs of the assertions we have been making; and the reader must
not be annoyed if in so doing we have to turn to details in them-
selves rather insignificant, for he will remember that theories have
no other value than their capacity for picturing facts whether the
facts be
great or small does not matter and that facts are the only
things that give theories value or deprive them of it. To tell the
truth, if one were to set out to give all the proofs, one would find
oneself obliged to quote the whole of history. There being no room
here for that, we can only do the next best thing, and select a few
cases thatmay serve as typical.
1941. Examples of inconsistencies may be found in virtually every
author who asserts the accord here in question. Sometimes the con-
1944 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1355
tradictionis
explicit, that is to say, in a given work certain passages
will be found to contradict certain other passages; then again, the
contradiction is
implicit it
apparent, that is, in the inferences
is
house with things"; and then that "the wisdom of the poor man
all
doth exalt him and seateth him among the mighty." But how can
that be ? If the poor man was left
poor, his wisdom could not have
filled his house with all
things.
1944. Of the implicit contradiction, will give an example from
I
the ancient Hebrews. They believed, on the one side, that Jehovah
always rewarded the just ("righteous") and pious man with worldly
goods, and punished the unjust and impious by taking such goods
l
away; and, on the other, that the poor man enjoyed the favour of
*
1942 The verse following, 274, seems to be a gloss interpolated in the text:
"But methinketh not that that be the will of Zeus the High Thunderer." But be
it the will of Zeus or not, the fact noted by Hesiod still remains. Other verses also
stand in contradiction. In many places Hesiod insists that the man guilty of an
injustice does not escape the punishment he deserves and that the just man is
rewarded; whereas in describing the iron age in which we, presumably, are living,
vv. 190-93, he says: "No longer in grace will be the man faithful to his oath, nor
the just man, nor the good. Honour rather will be unto him who is guilty of
maleficence and hurt; right will stand in might and reverence will be no more."
*
1944 Piepenbring, Theologie dc I'Anden Testament, p. 208: "It comes out clearly
from the above, and from all documents of the first two periods, that the Israelites
believed only in an earthly remuneration for human acts. In the prophets, with
whom the punishment of sin on the one hand and hope of future salvation on
the other play such an important part, there is not the slightest trace of the notion
that sin may be punished and virtue rewarded in another life. According to the
general opinion of the Hebrews, God recompenses good works and punishes evil
in this world. Every misfortune is a divine punishment brought down upon one
by unfaithfulness, every blessing a reward deserved through fidelity. In a word,
THE MIND AND SOCIETY J
945
2
Jehovah. The two propositions lead to contradictory conclusions.
From the first, man ought to be just ("right-
one infers that the rich
eous"), pious, and pleasing
in the sight of the Lord, and the poor
man unjust, impious, displeasing to Jehovah. The inference from
the second is the exact reverse. The contradiction was a one glaring
and could not escape Hebrew thinkers, who exerted themselves in
various ways to be rid of it; but of that we shall speak later on
I
( 979)"
1945. Peoples have imagined, and still
imagine, that they win
their wars with the help of their gods. The group of associated sensa-
tions called a people is
regarded as a unit, and the conduct of each
single individual the aggregate is instrumental in at-
making up
tracting or alienating the favour of the gods. Sometimes the conduct
of a single individual is sufficient to cause a
punishment, and much
more rarely a reward, for the group as a whole. Sometimes it would
seem as
though the number of individuals had to be large enough
to constitute a considerable
portion of the group.
1946. As for the have own, and the
gods, every people may its
other also; and typical of that situation would be the Greeks and the
Romans with their gods. The Iliad has made ideas of that sort gen-
erally familiar. Finally, again, there may be only one god for two or
rules of "morality" and "justice" as His sole guide. All that, I need
hardly add, does not bear the most casual examination from the
logico-experimental point of view.
Damascus was besieged by the Crusaders,
1947. In 1148 the city of
who were repulsed and had to retreat. Christians and Moslems alike
made each their own god responsible for what happened, and each
side interpreted what happened to its own advantage. On that point
the cupidity of our soldiers. Meantime the Emperor Conrad, seeing that the
. . .
Lord had withdrawn His favour from him and that he was in no condition to
do anything of advantage to our realm, caused his ships to be put in order, took
leave of Jerusalem, and returned to his own states." Now, on the Moslem side,
the Eoo\ of the Two Gardens, Vol. IV, p. 59: "The Mussulman population evinced
very keen joy at the success that Allah had vouchsafed them, and offered numerous
thanksgivings to Heaven, which had hearkened favourably to the prayers that had
been made during those days of trial. Allah be praised and blessed! Shortly after
that sign of divine patronage, Nur ed-din came to the relief of Mo'in ed-din and
effected a junction with him in a village in the neighbourhood of Damascus."
1358 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY T
949
must still this late day, for the Sepulchre of the Saviour
endure to
1
continues in the hands of the infidel.
1949. Needless to recall, because too well known, the old ordeals
and "judgments of God," which, ifwe keep to derivations, are
closely related to the theory that
God punishes evil conduct and
*
1948 Draper, History of the Conflict between Religion and Science, pp. 77, 91,
speaks of the conquest of Jerusalem by Kosroes [This quotation has already been
a
given in part in 1484 A. L.]: "In face of the world Magianism had insulted
.
the ideas of that age the two antagonistic forms of faith had submitted themselves
to the ordeal of the judgment of God. Victory had awarded the prize of battle,
two signs the Mohammedan Church will pass more appropriately than the Chris-
tian as the true Church.*' Bayet, Lemons de morale, p. 156. Probably with a view
to Bayet supplies a great deal of statistic that would
discrediting Christianity,
seem to have do with a treatise on ethics: "The religion with the greatest
little to
number of followers is Buddhism. There are about 500,000,000 Buddhists. [Really?
Bayet has counted them?] Next comes Christianity, which is divided into three
branches: 217,000,000 Catholics, 127,000,000 Protestants, and finally 120,000,000
human beings who belong to the Russian Church." Bayle, Op. cit., s.v. Mahomet 11,
remarque D: "I have noted that as regards triumphs the star of Mohammedanism
has prevailed over the star of Christianity [That could not be said today.], and
that if one had to judge the quality of those religions by the glory of temporal
successes, Mohammedanism would pass as the better. The Mohammedans are so
sure of that that they advance no stronger proof of the justice of their cause than
the striking successes with which God has favoured it ... [Then quoting Hot-
tinger, Historia orientalis, p. 338:] The success of infidel arms is another argu-
ment they use to stress the truth of their religion. Believing that God is
responsible
1950 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1359
*
rewards the good. Bayle alludes to an incident that may serve as
an example of the comical inconsistencies involved in that theory.
The Chevalier de Guise, son of the Due de Guise, who had been
assassinated at Blois in 1588, killed the Baron de Lux in a street in
Paris on January 5, 1613. The Baron's son challenged the Chevalier
to a duel, and was also killed by the latter. "People," says Bayle, "did
not fail to notice the inequitableness of the outcome in two en-
counters in which the points of justice seemed to be the same. If
the Chevalier was entitled to success in his first duel because he was
trying to avenge his father's death, he should have lost in the second
where it was a question of squaring accounts with the son of the
man slain. Yet luck was with him in the second as well as
he had
in the That surprised many people and aroused considerable
first.
may also be that the genius of Bismarck, Moltke, and Roon, as well
for all good happenings, they conclude that the greater their success in their
wars, the more clearly God indicates that He approves of their zeal and their
"
religion.' [A very free translation: Hottinger says: "Secundum motivum est vic-
toria eorum continua contra christianos, quod aliquos multiim movet. Unde victores
se nominant et gloriantur quasi victores totius mundi." A. L.]
x
1949 Op. cit. t s.v. Guise (Charles de Guise, due de Lorraine} , remarque F.
*
1950Busch, Tagebuchbliitter, Vol. I, pp. 103, 106, 332 (English, Vol. I, pp. 80-81,
204; French, Vol. I, pp. 64, 67, 172-73), Aug. 24, 1870: "Count Waldersee for
his part was eager 'to see that Babel [Paris] completely destroyed/ The Chancellor
interrupted: That in fact would not be a bad idea, but it is impossible for many
reasons, the main one that toomany Germans from Cologne and Frankfurt have
1360 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 195!
1951. It is
always a good thing for peoples to believe that their
gods are fighting on their side ( 1932). The King of Prussia was
altogether wise in proclaiming a day of prayer in his decree of July
21, 1870. Said he: "I must first thank God that at the first signs of
war one single sentiment welled up in all German hearts, the senti-
ment of a general rush to arms against oppression and the sentiment
of an inspiring hope in the victory which God will grant to our
[Busch] noticed on the side of the road a milestone with the indication: 'Paris, 241
kilometres.' So we were that near already! Thirty-two German miles from Babel!"
"
. . . 'She [the Countess von Bismarck] is quite well now/ the
Oct. 29, 1870:
Minister [Bismarck] answered, 'only, she is still suffering from her ferocious hatred
of the Gauls. She would like to see them all shot and stabbed to death, down to the
little babies, who, after all, cannot be held responsible for having such abominable
"
parents.' The Countess von Bismarck and her husband considered themselves, and
perhaps were, good Christians.
f
1951
*
L Empire liberal, Vol. I, pp. 30-31.
195* "ETERNAL JUSTICE" 1361
had decided, in spite of the alarums of his diplomats [Who saw a
little
light where that blind man could not be made to see any-
thing.], to place
no obstacle in the way of the free development of
Germany and so to add one more service to those
already rendered
by a generous France to the Germanic peoples in 1789, 1830, and
1848. [Those good German souls probably deserved rewards for their
virtues; but it was hard on the French to have to foot the bill in
the form of those five billions paid to Germany as an indemnity.]
'Ingratitude,' said Cavour, 'is the most odious of sins.' It is also the
clumsiest of calculations. [A gratuitous assertion on Ollivier's part,
without the slightest hint of a proof.] Bismarck designed to drown
in the blood of a common victory the antipathies of the states of the
South, which were still
smarting under their recent defeat. Far more
effectively than that dangerous remedy, a little patience would have
quieted the excitement. [Another assertion without hint of proof.]
A German unity achieved without dismemberment of France, cer-
tain as it would have been of a peaceful future, might have proved
a common blessing for all, and not a calamity. God sometimes
punishes by the gift of success. The future will tell!" Wait, nag of
mine, the grass will some day grow! Meantime, while that future
punishment coming in its own good hour, and which will fall
is
2
1951 Ollivier's history, notice, was a work in seventeen volumes, and pretended
to be a scientific study. It was therefore something entirely different in character
from the proclamations of William I and Napoleon III previously quoted, and from
other such expressions, where the purpose was not to discover truth, but to rouse
popular emotions and guide them into what were regarded as proper channels.
Bismarck goes about things in quite a different way in judging the conduct of
Napoleon III. Busch, Tagebuchblatter, Vol. 55 (English, Vol. I, p. 44; French,
I, p.
"
Vol. I, pp. 30-31), July 27, 1870: 'His policy has always been stupid. The Crimean
War was diametrically opposed to the interests of France, who needed an alliance or
at the very least a good understanding with Russia. And so with the war in Italy.
There he built up a rival for himself in the Mediterranean, North Africa, Tunisia,
and so on [Bismarck said that in 1870; he saw far and clearly.], who some day
may perhaps be dangerous. [Omitted from French:] The Italian people are much
more gifted than the French; only less numerous. The war in Mexico and France's
attitude in 1866 were also blunders, and there can be no doubt that in the hurri-
cane that is breaking today, the French themselves feel that they are committing
1362 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1952
Welschinger, a writer who
from being in complete agree-
is far
3
ment with "The memory of the
Ollivier, also says in his turn:
War of 1870 and the Treaty of Frankfurt that was its lamentable
sequel will for a long time to come saving reparations, which lie in
the secret bosom of eternal Justice be a cause of bitterness between
the two nations." So,
besought for aid by two opposite sides, "eternal
Justice" did not know which way to turn and ended by preferring
the side that had the larger
army and the better prepared, and was
led by the better
generals.
1952. History shows that, as a rule, that is the side she prefers.
When the Theban army broke Spartan power at Leuctra, it was
effectively aided by "eternal Justice," who had decided at last to
French foreign policy, but it proved very useful as regarded domestic policy, giving
the government of Napoleon III a halo of glory so sadly lacking to the regime of
Louis Philippe. Furthermore, the error in foreign policy might easily have been
corrected by an alliance with Russia after the victory. The war in Italy arose from a
combination of humanitarian enthusiasms on the part of Napoleon III and interests
of international "speculators," who were beginning in those days
operations which
have become so extensive and influential in ours. The Mexican venture was
pri-
marily a manifestation of pathological humanitarianism. There is no excuse for the
attitude of Napoleon III in 1866. It was, as usual, the attitude of a humanitarian
with few brains. Thereafter things happened in a whirl. France looked like a
ship
blown rudderless over a stormy ^ea. Under the Republic, French foreign policy was
far superior to what it had been under
Napoleon III, and for the very reason
that it was more like Bismarck's realistic policy. That alone would more than
justify one's preferring the Republic to the Empire [in France]. The Republic's
domestic policy has not measured up to the standards of its
foreign policy, and
there is therefore a danger that the foreign policy may be
paralyzed by the do-
mestic. However, if the Republic is neglecting military preparedness, the Empire
was even more neglectful in that respect, and was more to blame, for it had the
power to force measures that far-sighted republicans, such as M. Poincare, cannot
obtain.
3
1951 La guerre de iSjo, Vol. II, p. 56.
l
1952 History of Greece, Vol. X, p. 178.
1956 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1363
took care that no human precaution should be wanting." That, per-
haps, was what spurred and it is most
"eternal Justice" to action,
assuredly the thing that always should be done under similar cir-
cumstances. It is well enough to talk of "eternal Justice," but it is
better to make one's preparations as though she did not exist.
1953. Nowadays many individuals who have ceased to believe in
the supernatural have changed just the outward form of the deriva-
tion, replacing divine justice with a certain "immanent justice" or
a "justice immanent in things," which is a very handsome, but a
rather vague, entity. "Immanent Justice," however, prefers to operate
in private business rather than in martial enterprise, perhaps be-
cause she counts not a few pacifists among her worshippers
1
(i88 3 ).
1954. It is certain that among the ancient Hebrews and the Greeks
and Romans, the conduct of the divinity did not always dovetail
exactly with the upholding of morality and justice. There was an
added something, designed to assert some sort of divine preroga-
tive. That fact is distasteful to certain theorists, who would be bet-
ter satisfied if the discrepancy did So they bluntly deny it,
not exist.
x
1955 Piepenbring, Histoire du pcuplc d'lsracl, p. 245: "Really, as a consequence
of this supreme power, Jahvc extends favour or mercy to anyone He sees fit, like
the despots of the ancient Orient, who also enjoyed manifesting their power."
1364 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1957
fact that inour day, in such a deluge of science and criticism, many
morality, just as there was recompense for good deeds. The Ion
of Euripides ends with an address that is put into the mouth of the
Chorus and declares that in the end the good find the reward of
virtue and the wicked just penalties for their crimes an idea which
is to be back as the days of Homer. Divine vengeance,
found as far
which nothing but
is the deity's resolve to let no crime go un-
des, were inclined to solve our problem in the affirmative, that they
believed the gods always rewarded the good and chastised the
wicked. A
direct examination of the facts leads to a far different
1
conclusion.
1958. In the first place, in Euripides himself, the purport of not a
few passages is directly opposite to Maury's view. In Helen the
Chorus says that he does not know whether a god, or a non-god,
or someone betwixt and between, governs happenings in this world,
l
1956Histoire des religions de la Grece antique, Vol. Ill, pp. 48-49.
*
1957 The Chorus
in the Ion reads, vv. 1621-22 (Coleridge, Vol. I, p. 317): "Since
in the end the good obtain what they have deserved, so the wicked, as is natural,
can never be happy." Maury also quotes a Chorus in the Bacchae, vv. 882-87 (Cole-
ridge, Vol. II, p. 114): "Slowly but surely cometh the power of the gods, and
chastiseth those who cherish iniquity and in their folly refuse worship to the
gods." Here too, after all, the reference is to people who manage to obtain the
favour of the gods or else incur their wrath; but it is not clear whether because of
virtue or wickedness.
1961 ETHICS IN THE GREEK TRAGEDIES
1365
1
since one seesthem ever fluctuating now this way, now that. Worse
still, in The Madness of Hercules the Chorus says that the good
fare no better in this world than the wicked. 2
1959. Then, looking more closely at the tragedy quoted by
Maury, the Ion, one can hardly say that the conclusion of the Chorus
is so
very moral. Apollo violates the virgin Creusa and begets a son
of her, Ion by name. To conceal her
involuntary infidelity, Creusa
exposes the infant among the foundlings. Apollo proceeds to lie to
Xuthus, Creusa's husband, and misleads him into believing that Ion
is his own child, and the
god naively explains that his purpose in the
deceit to provide a rich and illustrious
is
family for Ion. Creusa
does not know that Ion is the child she abandoned, nor Ion that
Creusa is his mother.
Believing him a bastard of her husband, as the
god has averred, she tries to
poison him, and he, to get even, tries
to kill her. But she recognizes her child from a certain box he
carries, and Athena comes forward to dispel all doubt and confirm
Ion's true descent.
1960. It is not apparent just where, in all that, "the good'' come in
to get "in the end the reward of their virtue." will say nothing We
of Apollo, who is a very fair scoundrel; but not even Creusa seems
any more virtuous than the rest. One could hardly describe her
attempt to poison Ion as a virtue. The best that can be said for
her
is that she succeeded in
seducing a god. Poor Xuthus has done no
harm to anyone; and his reward is to be presented by the god with
a bastard not his own. Ion good enough fellow, if we overlook
is a
his little
slip
in trying to murder Creusa he does neither good nor
evil otherwise.Decidedly, the choice of such a play to show
how the
"good" are rewarded and the "wicked" punished can hardly be
called a convincing one.
1961. As a matter of fact, the tragedy leads, substantially, in an
1958 Helena, vv. 1137-43 (Coleridge, Vol. I, p. 358): "Who of mortal men,
*
having searched the ultimate purpose of things, can aver that he doth find therein
a thing that is god, not a god, or an intermediate being [demon], forasmuch as the
designs of Heaven do turn now hither, now thither, issuing in happenings un-
foreseen?"
1958
2
In Hercules jurens, vv. 655-58 (Coleridge, Vol. II, pp. 191-92), he says that
the good ought to have a double youth and be born again after dying, the wicked
of the gods doth sever the good from the
living only once: "No boundary
wicked."
1366 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1962
accordingly imagine that they find that idea expressed in all ages,
among all peoples, and even in writers whose thinking runs quite
in the contrary direction. It is important to note such facts, because
they indicate the strength, even in our day, of the residues of Class
II
(group-persistences). A writing the history of morals in
scientist
properly, performing our duties to our state and our fellows, duties
that also either have been laid down for us as commandments by the
what, pray, of people such as the atheists and the sceptics who did
not believe all those pretty things? A
twist of the wrist and they
are put out of court in virtue of our epithet "intelligent": we deny
them membership in the category of intelligent beings, and all is
well ( 1471, 1476). Where ever in the Greek authors did Schoe-
mann find that to have the gods "propitious" one needed only to
And why should his body have been dragged around the walls of
Troy? And so on and on. One could continue marshalling such
legends indefinitely, did not the above suffice. To be sure, Plato
repudiates them and condemns them, and of him, perhaps, Schoe-
mann may have been thinking. But in that case he should have men-
1368 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1964
tioned Plato by name and not gone talking about "every intelligent
being."
1964. a fragment of The Heliades (Daughters
Decharme quotes
of Helios) by Aeschylus that reads: "Zeus is the aether. Zeus is also
the Earth. Zeus is also the sky. Zeus is all things and that which is
1
above all
things." And Decharme then adds: "There is
nothing
loftier than a doctrine such as that, and same time,
nothing, at the
more contrary to popular religion. This wholly new conception
. . .
of Zeus, which at the time could have been the dream only of a
few great minds, enables us to appreciate the extent to which the
religion of Aeschylus surpassed that of his time." may disregard We
the subjective portion of the statement; the author has a certain
ideal and calls those who stand more or less close to him "great
minds." Let us look only at the facts. Is it, after all, true that the
points the way to the residues by which the Athenian public was
swayed and that
of greater importance to us.
is
argument: a male, he says, may become a father without the concert of a female,
for Athena was born of Zeus without ever being nourished in a womb.
1966 ETHICS IN THE GREEK TRAGEDIES 1369
1966. Passages in the trilogy that bear on the subject may be
spent itself, behold, new blood!" And then come bits like the fol-
2
pay his debt." Electra asks the Chorus what she must wish for her
father's assassins, Choephoroe, vv. 119-21: "Chorus. That to them go
a demon or a mortal man. Electra. A judge or an avenger, sayest
thou? Chorus. Pray only, someone who will slay them in their
3
turn."
In a word, the fatality that broods over the line of the Atrei'des
is a derivation from the conception of a necessary link between
crime and consequences. Like all derivations of the kind, it is
its
not very definite, and not very logical; and thence the difficulties
one encounters the moment one sets out to determine exactly what,
in particular, the author's doctrine was and, worse still, in general,
what people of the time understood by the word "fate"; for one is
hunting for something that does not exist, in other words, for a
definite doctrine, and no such doctrine is there. It is not, be it
1966
8
The last line reads: 'A7r/U>f n <t*paovo' t OGTI$
I37O TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1967
man doth procreate, and endeth not seedless; but from good for-
tune springeth everlasting misery. But my sense doth differ from
the general. Iniquity in time mature doth breed its like; but a house
that is blessed with a fair progeny." And the Chorus
truly just is
proof of these things," the proof being, substantially, as follows: The law enjoins
silence upon the person who has not cleansed himself, and he has cleansed himself
with blood and with water. The talk is all about one thing: the mechanical
efficiency of expiatory blood and water.
DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 137!
man who protendeth hands undefiled, and he doth live out his days
secure. But the culprit who hideth blood-stained hands, as doth this
man [Orestes], to him do we reveal ourselves in our good time, true
*
witnesses for the slain, avengers of blood."
Both these two types of passages are alike in that they indicate
punishment as the inevitable consequence of crime. They differ as
to the manner in which the punishment comes about. But if
every
crime leads to misfortunes, not all misfortunes are born of crimes:
that to say, punishments are inflicted for deeds that are not viola-
is
the temples of the conquered land, they shall not in their turn be
*
vanquished."
The envy of the
1969. gods, about which the writers of ancient
Greece had so much to say ( 1986), also figures in the trilogy.
Agamemnon, Agamemnon, vv. 946-47, fears he will oflfend the gods
by treading purple carpets; and the Chorus remarks, vv. 1001-07,
that happiness breeds misfortune, that human prosperity is ever
rightly perceived that they raised the problem of the good or evil
which an individual brings upon himself by his own conduct, and
of the good or evil that the gods, or Fate, bring upon him inde-
1967 ^Etimenides (supplement), vv. 732-33, reads: "At the time and day ap-
pointed doth the mortal who spurneth the gods sustain his punishment." Cf.
Euripides, Eacchac, vv. 882-90, quoted above, 1956 *; and Solon, Elegiac, XIII
5
(IV), vv. 27-32 (for quotation see 1980 ).
x
1968 In a fragment of the Niobe (Smyth, Vol. II, p. 432), it is said that "evil
thoughts doth the god inspire in the minds of men when he would ruin a lineage
1*
utterly.
1372 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1971
1
whereas they really bring them upon themselves. The theory is
obvious: Punishment is the fruit of crime, and Zeus is sole witness
of things that happen. Athena in reply, I, vv. 45-62, puts forward
another theory: the woes of men ought only to be punishments for
their evil deeds. Aegisthus was justly punished. But Ulysses
has
done no wrong. He ought not be punished by being kept far from
his homeland. Zeus again has his say, I, vv. 63-75. He has by this
time forgotten his declaration that mortals are wrong in laying the
blame for theirwoes upon the gods. He now says that the woes of
Ulysses are due to the wrath of Poseidon, who is tormenting him
for putting out the eye of the Cyclops. Yet in that act Ulysses could
in no sense have sinned against the norms of justice! And so we get
a third theory: The woes of men come upon them partly because
they do foolish things, and partly because they are tormented by
some god quite apart from any wrong they have done. The other
gods, it is true, do what they can to embarrass Poseidon in behalf
of Ulysses; but they liftnot a finger to help the poor Phaeacians,
whom also Poseidon is punishing, not for any wrong they have done,
but quite to the contrary, for their good deed in helping Ulysses back
to his home in obedience to the divine precept that would have
1
1970 'Tor from us they say that evils come, and they themselves of their folly
have evils beyond what fate hath ordained. E'en now against fate hath Aegisthus
taken the wedded wife of the son of Atreus and him hath he slain on his return,
knowing well the dire disaster that awaited him; for we had sent Hermes, shrewd
slayer of Argus, unto him and admonished him that he slay not Agamemnon and
woo not his wife, for on him would fall the vengeance of Orestes of the line of
Atreus, when he, become of age, should return to his homeland." The god's remarks
arc to be taken in the following sense: "For from us they say that evils come, whereas
they of their folly," etc. That eliminates a formal contradiction between this dec-
larationby Zeus and a subsequent ascription of the misfortunes of Ulysses to the
wrath of Poseidon. But the substantial contradiction remains; for, after all, even if
only a portion of mortal woe comes from the gods, mortals have not been shown
wrong in complaining of the gods for sending that portion. Cf. Iliad, XXIV, vv. 527-
32, and Plato's remarks on the subject in the Respublica, II, 18, 379. Plato concludes,
II, 19, 38oA, that no one should be allowed to say that Zeus is the author of the evils
that befall men; and that even if he be responsible, what he does is righteous and
just, asserving to improve the wicked by chastising them. And no poet, he goes on
to say, should be allowed to teach that a man so punished is unfortunate. In Plato,
metaphysics is superimposed upon theology, and Zeus is little more than an ex-
ecutor of the sentences of metaphysics ( 2349 1 ).
I97 2 ETHICS IN THE GREEK TRAGEDIES 1373
*
is hard to understand how Girard could say that, in the Odyssey,
"if there is an idea on which the whole sequence of events visibly
depends, it is that on the one hand, men draw chastisement upon
themselves by their persistence in evil and that on the other, a bril-
liant reward is held in store for
energetic and patient virtue." A
brilliant reward indeed was handed out to the wretched and
virtuous Phaeacians! The contradictions in the first canto seem not
to have been observed by whoever wrote the poem. Later on doubts
arose and efforts were made to solve the problems to which they give
rise. In his
commentary on Odyssey> I, v. 34, Eustathius ascribes the
misfortunes of human beings on the one hand to Zeus and Fate,
whom he regards as one, and on the other to the imprudence, or
better, to the recklessness (dratffla/Ua) of men who sometimes work
their own undoing. He seems chiefly to consider whether the mis-
2
fortunes are independent of what men do, or dependent on conduct.
The example just given is
1972. one of the many many that might
be offered to show that oftentimes to go looking for the idea a
writer has in a certain piece of literature is a bootless task, and for
the reason that, in such cases, there is no single idea ( 541) in the
mind either of the writer or of the public he addresses. Both writer
and public follow the lead of sentiment, which is satisfied with
propositions that are undefined and sometimes accepts them even
when contradictory. There are two sentiments in people: a senti-
ment inspired by "deserved" misfortunes, and a sentiment inspired
by "undeserved" misfortunes. If every misfortune is said to be de-
Julian ridicules the God of the Hebrews for losing His temper at
very slight provocation; but he forgets that the gods of paganism
were not slower to wrath. As a matter of fact, human beings are
accustomed to ascribe to their gods the character traits of powerful
1
men.
1974. Bayet's booklet, Lefons de morale, which I quote so often
because it is in general use in French public schools and therefore
contains theories that are safe-guarded by the law "for the pro-
tection of lay education," starts out by giving an affirmative solution
to the problem as towhether virtue leads to happiness. We are told
in fact, pp. 1-2, 26 (italics and capitals Bayet's) "Good actions are
:
those which are useful to us: that is to say, those which make us
REALLY HAPPY. Bad actions are those which are harmful to us: that
isto say, those which will make us UNHAPPY. It may be said there-
fore that morality teaches us what we should do in order to be
*
truly happy!' The person therefore who follows the teachings of
1973
*
Julian is Contra impium Julianum, V (Opera, Vol. IX,
quoted by St. Cyril,
p. 746): "What
provocation could be more frivolous than the one which here
kindles God's wrath, if this writer is to be believed!" In point is the incident re-
counted in Num. Chapter 25, where God slays thousands of the Israelites because
they had been marrying women of the Moabites and worshipping the gods of such
wives.
x
1974 p. 6, following Hesiod, he says (see
Bayet further avers, 1942), that
"those who
heed the teachings of morality are always happy. Peace reigns in their
land. They are not called upon to endure the frightful sufferings of war [Of
course, no moral country has ever been the victim of another country's aggression.]
. . the Earth provides them with food in abundance. The bees give them honey.
.
The sheep give them their wool. They are always rich and free from worries, fin
that the goddess Science really seems to be stealing the business of old-fashioned
Superstition ( 1984).] But when men do not heed morality, misfortune falls upon
them." Farther along, p. 163, Bayet describes the misfortunes of the Protestants
under the reign of Louis XIV. If it be granted that "those who heed the teachings
of morality are always happy," it necessarily follows that the Protestants, who were
certainly unhappy, had not heeded the teachings of morality. There are not a few
formal contradictions as well. On p. 146 one may read: "ONE SACRIFICES ONESELF
when one consents to be
unhappy that others be happy. ... In self-sacrifice
may
one not only makes others happy: ONE is HAPPY ONESELF." The same individual is
therefore happy and unhappy at the same time.
1974 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1375
morality will be truly [Mark the word!] happy. But to dispel every
doubt Bayet, after stating his
general theory, proceeds to a par-
ticular case: "It is said that it is our duty not to lie. That means
that if we lie we shall, sooner or later [Mark the restriction!], be un-
theory just stated is true, it follows that if the poor nowadays are
unhappy, it is because they do not observe the norms of morality.
The remedy would therefore be to begin observing
for their troubles
present in both. true that the author of the Odyssey was not so
It is
or untrue ? Are the relations that he finds between them real or un-
real? Those questions seem to have no interest for many writers
who attack Machiavelli or defend him, their whole attention cen-
intelligent people deem that it would be desirable if no history were written (see
Mascardi, Dell' arte historica). [In fact, if the term of comparison between theory
and reality can be suppressed, the theory can be constructed at pleasure.] But look
out our Florentine is accused of enriching himself on the spoils of Aristotle! . . .
preter of Tacitus."
2
1975 Among the many pertinent passages in Machiavelli I will refer again, for
the moment, to the two quoted above ( 1929). Ariosto also says, Orlando Furioso,
IV, i:
For Machiavelli further, cf. Deca, II, 13: "I hold it very true that seldom if ever do
men of low estate rise to high place without use of force and deceit, unless such
place has been devised to them by gift or inheritance, some other having come of it.
Nor do I believe that force alone will ever be found to suffice, but it will be easily
1378 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY J
975
( 130) virtual movements, which concerns the measures suitable
for attaining certain ends. Assailants of Machiavelli accuse him of
commending it. The accusation and the defence may stand side by
side, but neither has anything to do with the problem of determining
what going to happen under certain hypothetical circumstances.
is
found that deceit alone may suffice. And the very things which princes are
. . .
forced to do in the beginnings of their increase, republics also are forced to do, until
such time as they be grown powerful and able to stand on force alone. ... It is
evident that the Romans in their early increase showed no lack of fraud, which has
always of necessity been used by those who from lowly beginnings would rise to
exalted station and which is the less reprehensible the more covert it is, as was that
of the Romans." // principe, 15: "But it being my intent to write something of
profit to men of experience in such matters, I have deemed it the wiser part to fol-
low rather the effectual truth of things than the imagination thereof. And verily
many have imagined republics and principalities that man has never seen, nor
known of in the fact; for betwixt the manner in which men live and the manner
in which they ought to live there is a distance so great that the man who abandons
what is done in favour of what ought to be done learns rather his ruin than his
preservation; for he who would in all circumstances make profession of virtue can-
not but come to ruin amidst the many who are rascals/' To that the Anti-Mac hiavcl,
pp. 167-68, replies: "Machiavelli contends that it is not possible to be altogether
good in this world, the human race being as wicked and corrupt as it is, without
perishing. I say, instead, that if one is not to perish, one must be good and prudent.
Men ordinarily are neither altogether good nor altogether wicked. [The writer either
does not know or is pretending not to know that those arc Machiavelli's very words,
Deca, I, 27. Cf. 1704.] But wicked, good, and indifferent will all alike support a
prince that is powerful, skilful, just. I had much rather wage war on a tyrant than
on a good king, on a Louis XI than on a Louis XII, on a Domitian than on a
Trajan; for the good king will be well served and the tyrant's subjects will join my
troops. . . . No good and wise king was ever dethroned in England even by a
great army. All their bad kings succumbed to competitors who never began a war
with as many as four thousand trained troops. Do not therefore be dishonest with
rascals.Be virtuous and intrepid with them. And you will make your people as vir-
tuous as you arc. Your neighbours will be eager to imitate you and the rascals will
tremble."
1975 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1379
holding their power; and he took two hypothetical cases the case
where the prince has newly acquired power and the case where the
power has been inherited. He might have made similar investigations
along the same lines for other types of political organization; and
still
along the same lines, he might have broadened the scope of
his inquiry and considered the means most suitable for
acquiring
economic or military power, political influence, and other things
of the kind. In so doing he would gradually have
gone on from
the particular concrete case that he actually examined to the
general
problems of virtual movements which sociology considers today.
That would not have been possible in his time, just as it would not
have been possible in the day of his one great predecessor, Aris-
totlethe social sciences had not as
yet been born. That fact only
emphasizes the extraordinary force of Aristotle's genius and still
more of Machiavelli's, in that they were able to attain such heights
with the very imperfect materials supplied them by the
knowledge
of their time. But also serves to
it
emphasize the stolid ignorance of
certain of our contemporaries who are not capable even of
grasping
the importance of the problem studied by Machiavelli, and who
try
to meet him with a mass of ethical and sentimental chatter that has
no scientific status whatever, though they are ridiculous enough in
their presumption toimagine they are experts in the political and
social sciences. An amusing instance would, again, be Ollivier.
8
He
3
1975 Just a few examples ofOllivier's general approach to history: L'Empire
liberal, Vol. V, pp. 61-66, 257-78 (we are not considering the accuracy of Ollivier's
assertions, of course we accept them at face value, as hypotheses for discussion):
"Napoleon III had come back from being bound to a
Italy in the consciousness of
vigorous act of capital importance: the reorganization of his army. It was urgent to
correct defects that the prestige of victory hid from the public, but which he had,
so to say, touched with his hand. It was a laborious task. The laxity in atmosphere
due to the habits contracted in Africa was easy to remedy. . . . Much more difficult
the problem of increasing contingents in case of war. [Ollivier goes on to de-
. . .
scribe the efforts made in that direction and claims that an excellent
reorganization
of the army had been planned.] But to carry out that fundamental reform,
money
was needed, a great deal of money. Now the Minister of Finance, the Budget Com-
mission, and the Legislative Body were all for economies. Had the Emperor come
to ask for new credits to any considerable amount, there would have been a riot
and not only from the Opposition. He would have met in the Legislative Body as
stubborn a resistance as was beginning in Prussia against the Regent's plan for mili-
tary organization along the same lines as Randon's. [Randon was the French War
Minister.] There was this difference in the two situations. The resistance in Prussia
had more strength at its disposal than was the case in France. A long and
mighty
1380 THE MIND AND SOCIETY *975
tries not very hard to establish the concordance of good works
with happiness by postponing the happiness to some future time
( 1951); but that point with him is more or less incidental. The
bulk of his seventeen-volume history is zealously devoted to present-
effortand doubtful of outcome was required in Prussia to rouse the Deputies in the
Landtag. The Emperor, on the other hand, was in a position to checkmate ill will
in the Legislative Body with no great difficulty. It would have made a noise, but it
would have voted the money. But while the Regent in Prussia threw himself head
down into the parliamentary fray, risking everything, the Emperor stopped short at
the distant glimpse of a battle. The why of that difference in conduct holds the
secret of what was afterwards to happen.*'
"What was to happen afterwards" was all in Prussia's favour, and supremely
disastrous to France. It is therefore self-evident that France would have been the
gainer had been inverted, if, that is, her rulers had done what the Prussian
if roles
Regent did and the rulers in Prussia what the Emperor of the French did. Ollivier
however proceeds, p. 65, to state his conception of the reasons for those differences
in the respective procedures: "William was getting ready for a war that he wanted
in order to establish Prussiansupremacy in Germany. Napoleon III did not think
that he needed another war
moral [sic!~] supremacy in Europe
to maintain his
the only supremacy he desired. [It was, and no mistake about it, a disaster for
France that her sovereign should be forgetting force to that extent and thinking
only of "morality."] The Emperor could see no cause for a war, in whatever
. . .
not to know that one must trust not to the weakness of the enemy but to one's own
strength!] He alone
could create a cause of war by trying to seize Belgium or the
Rhine. . . .Had he
harboured that calculation, he would surely have braved the
Legislative Body's resistance to a costly reorganization of the army. But he was
thinking less than ever of expansions and aggressions. [But other people were, and
to ignore that fact may have been very moral but it was certainly very short-
pacem, para helium!" Ollivier draws the picture of an estimable private citizen and
an utterly wretched statesman. Everything he says sounds praises of the former and
damnation of the latter ( 2457). And that is not all. Here we are at the Mexican
venture. Ollivier washes the Emperor clean of any charge of deciding on that ex-
pedition for financial reasons, and adds, p. 257: "And there was no motive of ambi-
tion either." Nor was he tied to the Empress's apron-strings, pp. 257-58: "There has
been more specious allusion to the influence of the Empress. Her imagination
. . .
was of a chivalric turn and flared up at these distant glimpses of glory and honour.
She used her eloquence and her seductive charms to convince the Emperor. He was
all the more accessible to such pressure in that he had private sins to obtain her
forgiveness for. [Exemplary such remorse! But it is not so exemplary to make one's
country pay the ransom for one's sins. Henry IV of France had his petticoats too,
but that did not prevent him from being a good statesman and a good general.]
However, he did not follow her lead blindly, any more than he did anybody else's.
. . .
[But here, at last, are the reasons for the expedition, according to Ollivier:]
His realmotive was different. He was inconsolable at not having realized his pro-
1975 NAPOLEON III
1381
gramme 'From the Alps to the Adriatic* and blotted from the history of his race
the stain of Campo Formio. [What a tender conscience: remorse for his private sins
is not enough. He is remorseful for the sins of his forefathers, and does penance
for them, or rather has the country he is governing do the penance.] But resolved
never again to enter Italy, he was looking about for means of obtaining what he no
longer intended to take by force. [What a gentle kind-hearted soul, and what an
ass!] He had proposed to the English Foreign Office to suggest a sale of Venetia in
concert with him. ... In obtaining a throne for the Archduke Maximilian, Napo-
leon III saw an unexpected opening for the liberation of the captive province. He
hoped that Francis Joseph would be pleased at the gift he was making his family
and later on consent, perhaps, to let go of Venetia in exchange for an expansion on
the Danube. The ghost of Venice stalks the halls of the Tuileries,' Nigra wrote to
Ricasoli, 'and the spectre has taken Napoleon III by the hand and led him to sign
"
the order to overthrow Juarez to make room for the Austrian Archduke.' That
ghost must have said to him: "Till we meet again at Philippi-Sedan!" Bismarck
knew the art and a rich harvest it bore the country he was ruling of laying such
ghosts. But there is still no end. The war of 1866 supervenes. Napoleon III declares
his neutrality and so allows Prussian power to grow to gigantic proportions. He had
forgotten the warning issued by Machiavelli in the Dcca II, 22: "Pope Leo did
not yield to the wishes of the king [of France], but was persuaded by his council-
lors, so it was said, to remain neutral, on the ground that it was not to the interest
of the Church that either the King or the Swiss should become powerful in Italy,
and that if the country were to be restored to her ancient liberties, she must first
be freed from the mastery of them both. .And no case could be more opportune
. .
than the present, since both were in the field, and the Pope's forces were well or-
dered to appear anew on the borders of Lombardy . and the battle was going to
. .
be a bloody one to both sides and the victor would be so weakened that the Pope
could easily assail and vanquish him, so remaining to his glory lord of Lombardy
and arbiter of all Italy. How mistaken that opinion was appeared from the event;
for the Swiss being defeated after a desperate battle, the armies of the Pope and the
Spaniards, far from adventuring to attack the victors, made ready for flight"
( 2472). Describing the events of 1866 Ollivier has a glimmer of the realities. Says
he, Vol. VIII, pp. 189-200: "In view of the disappointments that had followed on
it seemed imprudent, to say the least, to set out just
the spectacular gesture in Italy,
advance the results of a war in which we were hav-
as spectacularly to regulate in
ing no part." But then straightway he falls back into the dark again, and resumes
dreaming. He quotes an article of his own in which he advanced principles to
which he ever after adhered: "Where Right stands is clear. In Italy Right stands
with the army advancing to the deliverance of Venice. In Germany it stands with
the army under Austrian leadership that is advancing to protect Frankfurt and de-
liver Dresden. Right does not allow us to lay hand to the Rhine provinces. Right
forbids Prussia to seize Hanover, Hesse, and the Duchies, and Austria to keep Ven-
ice." How many many places for the most estimable Monsieur Right to keep an
eye on! But when the cannon thundered at Sedan, Metz, and Paris, Monsieur Right
1382 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1976
fortune. Furthermore, in the passage in which he trusts to the future
to change bad luck to better, he does not at all make clear just how
the future going to right the wrongs of people who will be dead
is
before the change for the better comes. He does not seem to have a
3
very definite theory ( 1995 ), nor does he try to explain the dis-
crepancy between the misadventures of the French in 1870 and the
exemplary conduct of their Emperor before that time. Are we to
understand that it is the caseonly the other way round of the
Achaeans, who suffered so grievously from the pride of Agamem-
non ? Or are we to adopt some other explanation ? Ollivier does not
notice that the justifications that he makes of Louis Napoleon's
conduct from the standpoint of personal morality constitute a
thorough-going condemnation of that sovereign's conduct as a
4
statesman.
1976. People of vigorous faith
generally regard the supreme good
as incarnate in their faith and are therefore led to believe that ob-
servance of its norms All the same,
necessarily brings happiness.
when the term "happiness" stands for something tangibly existing
in the experimental world, the assertion of perfect accord between
observance and happiness, or between violation and unhappiness,
is too frequently contradicted by observation of fact to win any
1
wide assent. But ways are found to eliminate the conflict by suitable
was nowhere to be found; and seeing that no one had heeded his prohibitions re-
garding Hanover, Hesse, and the rest, he refused in a pet to interfere with the
annexation of Alsace-Lorraine. There would still be a long story to tell, but enough
for the present. Farther along ( 2455 f.) we shall return to these same facts and
consider them from another standpoint.
4
1975 Ollivier himself shows him as absolutely destitute of foresight on many
occasions: for instance, Op. cit., Vol. V, p. 67: "Bent nevertheless on carrying out
the policy of army decentralization that had been haunting his mind ever since the
Crimean War and which was the only means of effecting a rapid passage from a
peace footing to a war footing, Napoleon III directed Randon to execute it without
any increase in credits, and since it was impossible on that basis, that amounted to
abandoning it. And in fact, from that time on, neither Emperor nor minister paid
any further attention to it." Only a half-wit would consider a thing indispensable
and then order it to be carried out under conditions known to be impossible. And
yet Napoleon III was an intelligent man; but if he saw the better, he followed the
worse under the influence of sentiments that were active in him sentiments corre-
3
sponding to residues of Class II
2454 ).(
*
1976 Piepenbring, Theologie de I'Ancicn Testament, pp. 208-09 (continuing the
quotation in 1944 *) "For a long time these ideas seem to have raised no serious
:
objection, for none is met with in the more ancient texts. But as the events of his-
1977 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1383
All he needs is to lay the blame for the trouble on some other per-
son in the group ( 1979).
1977. 82: Happiness and unhappiness removed in space and in
time. A
person performs the conduct , which is said to be followed M
by a happening, P, it also being possible for P to occur by chance.
It isevident that the longer the lapse of time between the conduct,
M, and the happening, P, the greater the probability that P will hap-
pen by chance; in fact, if the lapse of time is at all long, the chances
that P will are so great as to amount virtually to certainty.
happen
If a
person with a weakness for predicting lottery numbers does not
confine himself to a single drawing but asks for a century's time for
a given number to be drawn, he can be almost certain, not to say
certain, that his
prediction will come true. In the same way, if the
prophecy has a long and indefinite time in which to come true,
there is no danger of being belied by the outcome in predicting
tory and of individual lives came to be better observed and more thoughtfully pon-
dered [It was not so much the observation as the reflection that was lacking. Be-
sides, the general form of statement is defective: those who pondered and those
who gave the matter no thought were different people.] it was seen [Not by every-
body.] that experience gave the lie at every step to the theory of remuneration, that
enumerate the good men who have had bad fortune, nor any less so if I were to
mention all the rascals who have prospered." In his treatise On Tardy Punishments
of Guilt (De sera numinis vindicta, 4; Goodwin, Vol. IV, pp. 144-45), Plutarch piles
derivation on derivation to show that the conduct of the deity is always just, not
forgetting to keep the road home clear by remarking that the ways of the Lord are
inscrutable (a 84 solution, 1902).
1384 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1978
that if a country does wrong it will sooner or later be punished, and
if it conducts itself
nobly, rewarded. No nation in the course of
so, if he will only wait, turn out to his advantage. Anyone speaking
at a given moment and declaring that the future will tell whether a
bad deed punished, a good deed rewarded, cannot be definitely
is
*
Piepenbring, Theologie de VAncien Testament, pp. 208-10 (continuing the
1979
x
quotation in 1976 ) "The difficulty may perhaps have been glimpsed in an earlier
:
period and efforts made to obviate it by saying that God punishes the sins of the
fathers in the children and rewards posterity for the fidelity of the forbears. [Inter-
esting the attempt at justification that Piepenbring then makes:] And one must say
that that principle has some foundation in the law of solidarity and heredity that
can be seen operating in everyday experience, where children often suffer from the
faults of their parents or benefit by their virtues." Piepenbring does not notice that
what he is proving is not at all what he pretends to be proving; he is merely show-
ing that there is a nexus between a child's status and his father's conduct. What he
ispromising to show is that the nexus is of a certain particular kind. It may well
be that the vices and virtues of parents always have consequences for their children;
but that does not prove that the sins of parents always have evil consequences for
the children a usurer or a burglar may leave his son a wealthy man; nor that the
virtues of parents always have good consequences for their children a philanthropic
fatherwho sacrifices himself for the good of others may leave his child in want.
To show that the sins of the fathers are punished, and their virtues rewarded, in
their children, such cases have to be eliminated a fact that Piepenbring completely
disregards, so giving another example of the lack of logic in these matters. He con-
tinues: "But thatrelatively ancient principle also raised objections and inspired the
sarcastic proverb in Jer. 31:29 and Ezek. 18:2: The fathers have eaten sour grapes
and the children's teeth are set on edge.' It was met with the thought that each indi-
vidual bore the penalties for his own sin (Jer. 31:30: "Everyone shall die for his own
iniquity"; Ezek. 18:3: "The soul that sinncth, it shall die"). That was a way of sus-
taining the traditional point of view and avoiding an explanation that attenuated
which the problem raised. But in that case, how surmount the
at least the difficulty
difficulty? It was preached that man has no right to question God, the creature the
Creator, the work its maker (Is. 29:16: "For shall the work say of him that made
it: He made me not?" 45:9 f.: "Woe unto him that striveth with his maker"; Jer.
18, 6: "As the clay in the potter's hand, so are ye in
is my
hand") [Our 84 solu-
tion inscrutable arc the ways of the Lord]; that far from being righteous (just),
man was in reality sinful (Ezek. 18:29 f.: "Are not your ways unequal?" 23:17 .;
Is. 58:3 [Solution A, a verbal solution.], or else that the prosperity of the wicked
f.)
was only a fleeting thing and always led up to a disastrous ending, whereas the
misfortunes of the righteous can be but transitory (Ps. 73:16-24: "Thou didst set
1386 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY
1980. Dionysius the Elder, tyrant of Syracuse, committed every
kind of crime and sacrilege and gaily laughed at it all.
Returning to
his capital after pillaging the temple of Proserpine at Locris, his
ship had favourable winds, and he remarked to his friends: "See
what a good voyage the immortal gods themselves vouchsafe the
blasphemer!" In reporting this anecdote Valerius Maximus mentions
other examples of impiety and concludes: "Albeit Dionysius paid
not the penalty due him, he suffered in the infamy of his son after
his death the punishment which in this life
slowly he evaded. If
them in slippery places"; 9:18 f.; 37; 49; 55:23; 64; 94:8-23; Prov. 23, 17 f.: "Thine
expectation shall not be cut off"). [A 82 solution happiness removed in space and
time.] In some passages the writer even rises to the notion [Note the ethical con-
notation in the term "rises," which is foreign to the experimental domain.] that
misfortune has salutaryeffects on a man just as correction is salutary for the child
(Prov. 3:11 f.: "My son, despise not the chastening of the Lord"; Deut. 8:2-5:
"Forty years in the wilderness to humble thee"; Lament. 3:27-30). [Again Z?2.] In
Isaiah, finally, comes the thought that the righteous may be called to suffer for the
wicked and so to spare them merited punishment (Is. 53:5: "He was wounded for
our transgressions" [#2.]). The problem mentioned so concerned and so em-
. . .
barrassed Hebrew thinkers that one of them felt impelled to sound it to the bottom
and devote the whole Book of Job to it" [A 84 solution, i.e., no solution is found:
inscrutable are the ways of the Lord. All this great varying of derivations is a quest
for a way of reaching a point that determined in advance (
is 1414, 1628)].
a
1980 De dictis jactisque memorabilibus I, i, Externa excmpla, 3.
,
*
1980 Oda, I, 28 (2), vv. lo-ii (30-31):
in order to keep him from considering too long he [the poet] threatens that the
man himself will after all suffer the punishment for his crime." Another scholiast,
Porphyrio, says (Paris, 1519, p. 37): "Negligis immeritis nocituram: The order is
'you think it a light matter to commit a wrong/ But the meaning is: you take me
lightly, and you think it will be easy to trick me. But the deceit will fall upon those
born of you, in other words upon your children." There is no doubt in any event
as to the punishment falling upon the children.
1980 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1387
nelius Sulla passed his whole life in unbroken prosperity, but Faustus
Sulla, his son, was slain by the soldiers of Sittius, and Publius Sulla,
2
his grandson, was among Catiline's accomplices. Dining with one
of his veterans at Bologna, Augustus asked him whether it were
true that the man who had been the first to lay hand to the image
3
of the goddess Anaitis in Armenia had died paralyzed and blind.
The veteran replied that Augustus owed his dinner to one of the
goddess's legs; that he, the veteran, had been the first to lay ax
to the image and that all he owned had come of that bit of plunder.
If we knew the history of all the descendants of the veteran in
ity expiated Sulla's proscriptions." Ethical declamations such as these still circulate
under the name of history. Duruy is even worried about the remorse that Sulla
should have felt, but which seems not to have troubled him. He observes that for
the Romans a striking success justified everything and adds: "That is why the ter-
rible dictator died without remorse. And so it will be with all those who interpose
a false principle between their science and their conduct." The inference, and cer-
tainly not the one Duruy intended, would be that it is a good thing to have "false
principles" if one wants to be happy. But the question is not whether a man's hap-
piness to "false principles," but whether he can be happy in spite of his mis-
is due
conduct, leaving other people, his family, his caste, his country, or perhaps human-
ity at large, to pay the penalty for his sins.
8
1980 Pliny, Historia naturalis f XXXIII, 24.
1388 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1981
Croesus of ever having sinned against gods or men. He said: "The
lot decreed by Fate cannot be voided even by a god. Croesus hath
been smitten for the sin of his ancestral parent of the fifth genera-
tion." Had
he chanced to enjoy a uniformly happy life, his son
might have been called upon to suffer the penalty for the crime of
4
an ancestor of the sixth generation; and so on indefinitely.
1981. Notwithstanding iniquities too numerous to count, the
Romans enjoyed long centuries of prosperity; but nothing prevents
one from assuming that retribution came in the Barbarian invasions.
So the Mohammedan invasions of a later date may have punished
the sins of the Christians, and the Christian invasions of Moslem
lands today the sins of the old Mohammedans. He who seeks finds,
and with no great effort.
1982. The
"responsibility" for crimes, as well as "rewards" for
good behaviour, may not only pass on to posterity but be extended
to communities variously constituted. Wide-spread among the
4
1980 I, 91. In reporting the legend Herodotus finds noth-
Herodotus, Historiae,
ing to criticize in Larcher, however, in a note to his translation of the passage,
it.
quotes a remark by Cicero, DC natura dconim, III, 38, 90: "Do I understand you
to say that the power of the gods is such that even if a man has escaped punishment
for his crimes by dying, those punishments fall on his children, grandchildren, and
descendants? O
wondrous equity of the Gods! Would any state tolerate the pro-
poser of a law of that kind, so that a son or grandson would be condemned if his
father or grandfather had committed a crime?" Larcher himself adds: "The philos-
opher Bio (Plutarch, De sera numinis vindicta, 19; Goodwin, Vol. IV, p. 171) had
preferred to ridicule that idea. 'If a god,' he said, 'were to punish children for the
crimes of their father, he would be more ridiculous than a doctor giving somebody
a medicine because his father or grandfather had at one time been sick.' People were
still without a sound notion of the Divinity in the day of our historian. There was
none such except among the Jews." And he quotes Deut. 24:16 and Ezek. 18:20, but
forgets many other passages to the contrary, and notably, Ex. 20:5: "For I the Lord
thy God am a jealous God, visiting the iniquity of the fathers upon the children unto
the third and fourth generations of them that hate me." Another example of the way
in which a virulent sentiment leads the mind astray. Larcher certainly knew the pas-
sage in Exodus and others of that sort in the Bible, but he disregards them in defer-
ence to sentiment. [Awkward paragraphing led Pareto into telling the anecdote of
Croesus and his oracle twice in this paragraph. I eliminate the first account in the
translation. A. L.] Solon, Elegiae, XIII (IV), On Righteousness, vv. 27-32 (Bergk,
Vol. II, p. 43; Edmonds, Vol. I, pp. 127-28): "The man with a wicked heart does
not for ever remain in secret, but in the end reveals himself utterly. The one has his
merited punishment sooner, the other later. If it seems that some escape and are not
overtaken by the pursuing destiny of the gods, they are smitten in the end. The
price of their misdeeds their innocent children pay, or later, perchance, their grand-
children."
1983 THE SINS OF THE FATHERS 1389
ancients was the belief that a man's sins were visited upon all his
fellow-citizens. Rome
even managed to benefit by the rascality of
some of her consuls, but she never made a theory of it. When
fail to evince
ancient writers any reluctance in admitting that chil-
dren should pay the penality for the parent, they are evidently re-
garding the family as a unit represented by the paterfamilias; and
similarly, when they speak of a city's being smitten for the misdeeds
1
of one of its citizens, they are thinking of the city as a unit. "Just"
in both cases is the punishment of the whole for the sin of the part,
much as a person's whole body suffers "justly" for the deed of the
hand. In that lies the main
residue (group-persistence), and only
the integrity of the individual, his family, and the various groups
to which he belongs. Thence quite spontaneously comes a feeling
that the integrity has to be restored as regards not only the indi-
vidual but also his family and his other affiliations of one sort or
another ( 1231 f.)
1983. Interesting among the various derivations just alluded to
is one to the effect that a city is justly punished for the crimes of any
one of its citizens, since itcould have avoided the penalty by chastis-
1
ing the culprit itself. Incidents in plenty betray the artificial charac-
ter of that derivation. Oftentimes a city or a
community suffered
the punishment before it knew of any crime or offender, and there-
fore was quite unable to punish the offender directly or expiate
the crime in any way. Ancient legends recite hosts of instances where
nations are punished for unknown crimes that are not revealed till
afterwards by prophets or soothsayers. The Achaeans were com-
pletely in the dark as to why the plague was ravaging their camp,
and before they could learn the reason Calchas, protected by Achilles,
had to reveal that Apollo was angry, and the cause of his wrath
1982
*
De sera numinis vindicta, 15-16 (Goodwin, Vol. IV, pp. 166-68).
Plutarch,
*
1983 Glotz, La solidarity de la jamille dans le droit criminel en Grcce, pp.
563-64: "That a city should speedily be punished for the crime of a citizen or ruler
is only just and is easily understandable.
Responsible to the gods, the state had only
to purge itself by a measure of public safety, a 'noxal' repudiation through death
or banishment."
1390 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1984
(Iliad, vv. 93-100). Furthermore, not even after the revelation has
I,
been made does it even remotely occur to anyone that the Achaeans
should have inflicted some punishment or other on Agamemnon,
and the plague ceases not because of any such punishment there
was none, either before or after but because of the satisfaction
given to Apollo. Agamemnon decides to restore Chryseis to her
father of his own accord, because (Iliad, I, v. 117) "He wishes his
2
people safe that it
perish not," and he squares accounts by taking
Briseis away from Achilles. How could the Thebans have avoided
being smitten by the plague, when they were utterly ignorant of
the crimes of which Oedipus had unintentionally become guilty?
In fact the oracle of Apollo does not tax them with any fault. It
merely prescribes an expiation, the way a physician might prescribe
3
a medicine for a patient.
1984. If a nation could suffer by the misconduct of its king, it
could also benefit by his good conduct. Hesiod describes the happi-
ness of peoples ruled by just kings, and their unhappiness if ruled
by unjust ones. In his case, the notion that the conduct of kings is
punished or rewarded in their peoples merges with the experimental
notion that the welfare or unhappiness of a people depends upon
1
its
having a good or a bad government.
2
1983 fir)
airoMaOai. Dugas-Montbel annotates, Vol.
Boi'Ao^' fyw /laov c6ov tppevai
I, p. "Zenodotus suppressed this line as expressing too commonplace an
23:
idea; but taking it in connexion with what goes before, the thought gains in lofti-
ness from the sacrifice Agamemnon is making, since he consents to return his cap-
tive only to help his people. I do not think the criticism of Zenodotus can be sub-
scribed to, and none of the modern editors accept it." Considerations as to the
"commonplaceness" or "loftiness" of this or that "thought" are foreign to Homeric
times. Agamemnon could not have spoken differently; he is simply making clear
("So long as the people pays for the recklessness of its kings.") Elie Reclus, a writer
who cannot be so very well grounded in his antiquity, pictures the Greek king as
something like a Negro chief procuring rain and all sorts of good things for his
subjects by magic. Says he, Les primitifs, pp. 271-72: "Men [according to certain
ancient writers] would ask nothing better than to riot in debaucheries and roll in
crime, were it not for the monarchs who repress greed and violence and bridle the
nations with laws. In those conceptions it is not always easy to distinguish between
1985 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 139!
1985. The groups that suffered for the guilt of a member could
be more or Accidental companionship with the
less fortuitous.
wicked could hurt. That may happen in the experimental world
under certain circumstances. A
person violating the norms of pru-
dence inside a powder-magazine may bring death to everybody in
its
neighbourhood. It is assumed that the same thing happens in
other cases where there no experimental demonstration. Caught in
is
a storm at sea, Diagoras was taxed by the sailors on his ship with
being the cause of their misfortune. He replied by pointing to other
ships that were also in danger on the same course and asking whether
his accusers thought those ships too had a Diagoras aboard. 1 The
answer would seem conclusive to many people; but it was not. If it
be assumed that the atheism of Diagoras could harm people who
were with him on the same ship, it is just as easy to assume that it
could harm everybody in his neighbourhood, even though they were
on other ships. It is a question only of more or of less, of extending
or restricting the area within which the impiety of Diagoras had the
2
effect of causing a storm.
the cases where the god delegates his powers to man and where man receives his
powers from the god. That is why Hindu doctrine taught that Indra never rains on
a realm that has lost its king. Ulysses, the crafty Ulysses, explained to the chaste
Penelope, Odyssey, XIX, v. 108: 'Under a virtuous prince the earth bears barley and
grain in plenty: the trees are laden with fruits, the sheep bear many coats a year
"
and the sea teems with fish. A good leader means all that to us.' If Reclus had
examined the text he was quoting and grasped its meaning, he would have seen
that it does not say that "a good leader means all that to us," but makes the bless-
ings originate $ fvyyraiw, which means, beyond question, "from his good gov-
ernment [his good leading]." The text earlier explains that this king "governeth
with justice" evdiKaiae dvtxw, and that for that reason "the people doth prosper
under him" aper&ffi 6 Aao* vn' avrov.
1985
x
Cicero, De
natura deorum, III, 37, 89: "Idemque \Diagoras\ t cum ci navi-
ganti vectores advcrsa tempestate timidi et pcrtcrriti dicerent non iniuria sibi illud
accidere [No wonder such a thing was happening to them.], qui ilium in eamdem
navem reccpissent, ostcndit cis in eodcm cursu multas alias laborantes, quaesivitque
num ctiam Us navibus Diagoram vchi credcrent."
2
1985 Horace, Oda, III, 2, vv. 29-32:
("Often has a slighted Jupiter classed the innocent man with the blasphemer. Rarely
has Punishment, even be she slow of foot, failed to overtake the rogue accursed who
has gained a start upon her.")
1392 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 1986
1986. The "envy of the gods" (<p06vo<; Oe&v) did not allow a man
to live a whole lifetime in happiness, and it extended to his
posterity and
his community. It is curious to note that Plutarch re-
bukes Herodotus for believing in such a thing, DC Hcrodoti mdig-
nitate, XV (Goodwin, IV, p. 337), but then gives an example of it
1
himself from the life of Aemilius Paulus. In this, as in other in-
stances of the kind, Class II residues are working. Paulus Aemilius
and his children are taken as one unit and no one thinks of dis-
tinguishing the children from the father. The group, the aggregate,
must not be altogether fortunate and is smitten, in fact, in one of
its
parts.
1987. Modern
theorists are in the habit of bitterly reproving an-
cient "prejudices" whereby the sins of the father were visited upon
the son. They fail a similar thing in our own
to notice that there is
society, in the sense that the sins of the father benefit the son and
1
acquit him of guilt. For the modern criminal it is a great good for-
tune to be able to count somewhere his ancestry or other
among
relations a criminal, a lunatic, or just a mere drunkard, for in a
court of law that will win him a lighter penalty or, not seldom, an
without taint of divine envy. Nor was I freed of the fear that my soul had con-
ceived at these things, in sore dread lest some public calamity impend, until I had
experienced a grievous misfortune about my own private hearth. For in these sacred
days I have buried, one after the other, those noble sons who were all I had left to
succeed me."
*
1987 As usual ( 587) derivations prove the pro and the contra equally well.
With Plutarch, De sera numinis vindicta, 16 (Goodwin, Vol. IV, p. 167), the sins
of the father are disasters for the son, the justification being, he says, that children
inherit more or less of their father's character. In the eyes of our modern humani-
tarians the sins of the father benefit the son by winning him, in case he commits a
crime, a lighter penalty or an acquittal, for, say our humanitarians, the father's sins
diminish the son's "responsibility."
1990 REWARD IN HEAVEN 1393
more nor valid than the proof used nowadays to show that the
less
quarrel. A
sympathetic jury acquits her. Let us grant that the woman is excusable
as a victim led to crime by her lover's misdeeds. Yet why should the penalty for
the man's rascality devolve upon a third party who is absolutely innocent? To satisfy
sentiments of languorous pity humanitarian legislators approve "probation" and
"suspended sentence" laws, thanks to which a person who has committed a first
theft is at once put in a position to commit a second. And why should the luxury
of humaneness be paid for by the unfortunate victim of the second theft and not by
society as a whole? In general, assuming that, as some say, the crime is more the
doing of society than of the criminal, it is sound enough to conclude that the crim-
inal should be set free or made to pay some very light penalty; but the same reason-
ing exactly leads to the conclusion that the victim of the crime should, within the
limits of the possible, be indemnified by society. As it is, the criminal only is looked
after and no one gives a thought to the victim.
1394 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 199!
happier"; "It is hard on this man, but might have been worse."
it
The scope of the possible is not definable, and so one can prove any-
pp. 122-23; Friedlander, Vol. Ill, p. 70): "If a manhas an infirmity by birth though
he has not yet sinned, they say that that is a consequence of Divine Wisdom and
that it is better for that individual to be deformed in that way than to have had a
perfect constitution. [Solution ( 82
1978).] We do not know
advantagein what his
lies [Solution #4.], though the thing has happened to him not as a punishment but
for his good. [#2.] They make the same answer when a good man perishes. It is
that he may have all the greater recompense in the other world. [Solution #3.]
They go even farther with their absurdities. When they are asked why God is just
towards man without being so towards other creatures, and for just what sin an
animal has its throat cut, they resort to the ridiculous answer that that is better
for the animal, that God will reward it in another life. [#3.] Yes, say they, even
the flea and the louse that have been killed are to have their recompense for that
from God; and so if the mouse that has been torn to pieces by cat or hawk is inno-
cent, Pivine Wisdom, they say, has required that it be that way with that mouse,
and God will make amends to it in another life for what has happened to it in this."
1994 DERIVATIONS AND REALITY 1395
1993. A hermit, once upon a time, was condemning the judg-
ments of God because he saw men who lived wickedly blessed with
many goods and prosperous, and men who lived virtuously cursed
with many woes. An angel came to him and led him to the abode of
another hermit who had lived long years in penance but was now
minded to return to the temptations of the world. The angel threw
the hermit the latter over a precipice; and pointed out that his
death, which was apparently in ill keeping with his righteous life,
was really its reward, as it
transported him to eternal beatitude. And
so, going on, the angelshowed the hermit other instances where an
apparent evil proved really to be a blessing, and vice versa?*
1994. Let no one imagine that our own age does not produce its
gaze upon men who have lived to advanced old age or given proof
of extraordinary physical or intellectual prowess despite their addic-
tion to wines or other alcoholic beverages, they answer that if such
men had been temperate they would have lived to even greater age
or been physically and intellectually even more remarkable. A
ratherhandsome type of the virtuist once said in a lecture: "We hear
of supreme statesmen and soldiers who were not chaste men, and of
heroic generals who were not chaste men. That is true, but had
they been chaste men they would have been greater men than they
were." In reasoning, or rather ranting, in such fashion, people for-
get that the burden of proof rests with the person who makes the
statement and that appealing merely to the possible is a good way
to mistake fire-flies for lanterns.
x
1993 Etienne de Bourbon, Anecdotes historiques, 396: "A variant of this cele-
brated apologue has been published by Thomas Wright, Latin Stories, No. 7, pp.
10-12 [Dc angelo qid duxit heremitam ad diversa hospitia] following English manu-
Nonveau recueil de jabliaux et contes, Vol. II, pp. 216-35, in the sermons (Con-
dones, Turin, 1527) of Albert of Padua, a preacher of the fourteenth century, in
the English poems of Thomas Parnell {The Hermit], and in the Magnum speculum
exemplorum, Douai, 1605, Vol. I, p. 152. It supplies the theme for an incident in
M. de Voltaire's Zadig, Voltaire replacing the angel with another hermit. Le Clerc,
Histoire litteraire dc la France, Vol. XXIII, p. 128, thinks he can connect it in origin
with the old 'Lives' of the anchorites of the desert. It seems in fact to have come
from the East. It appears in Oriental collections and even in the Koran, XVIII,
many
64. And cf. Luzel, Legendes chrStiennes de la Bretagne, Saint-Brieuc, 1874, p. 14
[read Legendes chretiennes de la Basse Bretagne, Vol. II, pp. i-n]."
1396 THE MIND AND SOCIETY
1995. 54: No interpretation is discoverable inscrutable are the
pressed with objections does he come out with the claim that the
Lord's ways are inscrutable. Of that procedure we have an instance
in the arguments of St. Augustine that may well serve as typical
of its class. It is a general procedure, however, and is frequently en-
3
countered in the writings of theologians and other thinkers.
x
1995 Dante, Paradiso, XIX, vv. 79-81: "Now who art thou that with vision of
a span wouldst sit upon a bench and judge a thousand miles away?" (Norton.)
2
1995 Guide of the Perplexed, III, 17, Theory III (Munk, Vol. Ill, p. 121; Fried-
lander, Vol. Ill, pp. 69-70): "Members of that sect claim that it has been God's
pleasure to send prophets, to command, forbid, terrify, inspire hopes or fears,
though we have no power to act ourselves. He may therefore require impossible
things of us, and it is altogether possible that even though obeying a commandment
we may be punished or, disobeying, rewarded. In a word, it follows from that view
that the acts of God have no final purpose. They carry the load of all such absurdi-
ties for the pleasure of safe-guarding that opinion, and they go so far as to hold
that if see an individual who was born blind or a leper and can ascribe to him
we
no previous sin that could have made him deserve such a lot, we are to say: 'That
isGod's will'; and there is no injustice in it, for they hold that God is at liberty to
inflicttorments on the man who has not sinned and shower blessings on the sinner."
3
1995 In all the works of St. Augustine there is a continuous swinging back and
forth between an assertion that the ways of the Lord are unknowable and the claim
that they are perfectly well known to St. Augustine: Contra adversarium legis et
profetarum (Opera, Vol. VIII, p. 605), I, 21, 45: "The Apostle cries (Rom. n:
4
33-34): O, the depth of the riches both of the wisdom and knowledge of God!
How unsearchable are His judgments and His ways past finding out! For who hath
known the mind of the Lord? or who hath been His counsellor?' " In the DC civi-
tate Dei, all of Chapter XX is a disquisition on the inscrutability of the Lord's ways.
Both good men and evil, the Saint says, partake of this world's goods; then: "We
really know not of what judgment of God this good man be poor and this wicked
man rich; why the one rejoices who, it would seem, should be in torment because
of his corrupt living, whilst the other dwells in sorrow, who would seem to merit
happiness for his commendable behaviour." And he recites many parallel cases. "If,"
1997 "INSCRUTABLE ARE THE WAYS OF THE LORD" 1397
1996. inconsistency of saying that one does not know what
The
one pretends to know very well is ordinarily not noticed because
of a controlling sentiment. At bottom the reasoning is of the follow-
=
"A B. If that fact is not observable, we labour under an illusion,
for in reality, in a manner unknown to me, B." When and A= A B
fall within the domain of
experience, logico-experimental science is
1997. In this case, again, the proposition that "the ways of the
Lord are unknowable" was not invented by the theorists who have
he says, "that were the constant rule, if all the wicked were at all times prosperous,
and all the good unfortunate, one might assume that the cause was a
just judgment
of God, compensating worldly blessings and sorrows with blessings and sorrows
eternal. But it also happens that the good enjoy worldly blessings and that the
wicked are visited with worldly sorrows; wherefore all the more are the judgments
of God unfathomable, and His ways unsearchable." That much clear, the Saint, it
would seem, ought to stop and try no farther to fathom the unfathomable designs
of God. But not at all! From beginning to end in his book the Saint fathoms and
fathoms, quite as if they were discoverable. By the end of Chapter XX, he has
adopted one of our solutions, #3, and predicts that on the Day of Judgment we
shall see the justice of the judgments of God, even of those judgments the justice
of which is hidden from our eyes. Specially interesting his frantic efforts
at present
to find justifications for the fact that the Barbarian invasions had smitten the good
as well as the wicked. First he resorts to a solution of our #2 type: "Those evils,"
he says, I, i, "are to be ascribed to Divine Providence, which is wont to use wars
to correct and punish the sinfulness [corruption] of men"; then, suddenly, he
switches to one of our #3 solutions, averring that Providence sometimes afflicts the
righteous, allowing them thereafter to pass on to a better world, or even to remain
in this world if he has designs for their further service (#4). He dwells on the
point that the pagan temples did not save the lives of their worshippers, whereas
Christian asylums were respected. That takes us altogether away from the matter of
the relations between good conduct or sinful conduct and rewards or punishments.
The temples seem to work their effects some intrinsic property, very
in virtue of
much like lightning-rods, some of which are effective, others not. Then back we go
to the thorny problem of the blessings of the wicked and the sorrows of the good,
I, 8: "It hath pleased divine Providence," he says, "to prepare future blessings for
the good which the wicked shall not have, and for the wicked sorrows which shall
1398 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 1998
utilized it.
They found the sentiment, which is associated with Class
II residues, ready-made in the masses at large, and one after another
person who
snaps his fingers at his "duty" and ignores it. Such
solutions are not free from the usual inconsistencies, since they
assume as known everything of which the author approves, bring-
ing in the unknown only when it becomes necessary to answer the
objections thatmay properly be urged. A
type of such reasonings
would be the following: "A ought to be done because it is a conse-
quence of B" "And why ought B to be done?" "Because it is a con-
sequence of C" And so on until one asks, let us say, "Why ought P
to be done?" The answer to that question is a categorical impera-
tive. These metaphysical solutions are, in
general, for the use and
consumption of metaphysicists. Practical men and the masses at
good Christians, for their part, cannot mourn such loss without manifesting an in-
The pagans were noting the fact that even nuns consecrated to God
clination to sin.
had been violated by the Barbarians. The Saint discusses that point at length, tack-
ing and lulling as usual between solutions of our various types. He draws, I, 26, a
distinction between material and spiritual virginity (a verbal solution of the Ai
type) and says that only the material could have been violated by the Barbarians,
not the spiritual. Why, he asks, I, 28, did God permit such outrages to holy women?
He begins with a #4 solution: "the judgments of God are unfathomable, His ways
unsearchable." But he keeps fathoming and searching all the same, and with no
great effort hits on a Bi solution: Had the nuns in question not perhaps sinned
through pride in their virginity? "Verumtamen interrogate fidcliter animas vestras
ne forte de isto integritatis et continentiae vel pudicitiae bono vos inflatius extulistis,
et humanis laudibus delectatae in hoc etiam aliqttibus invidistis" ("envying others in
your delight in human praises"). In any event, those who have not sinned may
consider that God sometimes permits evil that He may punish it on the Day of
turning from one solution to another, unable ever to settle upon an idea that is
even remotely definite, St. Augustine is a model of which copies too numerous to
count are to be found all the way along down to modern times, to say nothing of
the copies that will be provided by the future. In 1951, we quoted Bismarck's
French antagonist, Ollivier, to the effect that ingratitude is sooner or later punished.
Now that theory is clear and definite. Do not be ungrateful if you are, you will
be punished. If, in spite of your ingratitude, you are at present soaring on the wings
of success, look out do not trust in it: God (or some metaphysical entity) is grant-
ing it you today, the better to punish you tomorrow. That is a solution of the
to
/?2 type. Barring the difference between the person who is rewarded for his conduct
and the person who is punished for the conduct of someone else ( 1975), the the-
ory has the merit of justifying possible divergences between good works and the
attainment of happiness. But further along, Ollivier switches from that solution to
another. Says he, L Empire liberal, Vol. Ill, p. 590: "Just as evil is sometimes
f
crowned with a success that is a scandal to justice, so the good sometimes leads only
to undeserved reverses. In that lies a dispensation of Providence that eludes our
1897-
As regards the first, strict observance of the norms prevailing in
a given community has certain effects that are advantageous
to the individual, to the
community, and to individual and com-
munity; and then again other effects that are disadvantageous
(2121 f.). Ordinarily the advantages outweigh the disadvantages.
Both advantage and disadvantage, however, can be determined
only
by an examination of each particular case.
As regards the second problem, it is to a certain extent bene-
ficial to believe that observance of the norms
prevailing in a com-
munity is always advantageous to individual and community, and
that that belief should be neither doubted nor controverted. That
attitude too has drawbacks, but ordinarily the favourable effects
its
they failed to produce results before that time ? The fact is that the
1
2002 Xenophon, Memorabilia, I, i, 11-13.
I4O2 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 2OO3
natural sciencesmarched part passu with ethics, and sometimes even
fellbehind, so long as they used the same theological, metaphysical
in other words, sentimental method that ethics used. But they
Anaxagoras, who said that the sun was a red-hot stone, as they were
at Socrates, who preached an ethics of which
they did not approve.
In times nearer our own, the "errors" of Copernicus, reiterated by
Galileo, were as zealously persecuted as the moral "errors" of the
heretics. Why now is there a free field for "errors" of the first kind,
while "errors" of the second kind are persecuted by public opinion
at all events and to some extent also
by public authority? It is evi-
dent that the difference in effectsmust be an indication of forces
that are different also. Prominent among these forces must be
counted social utilities. Experimental researches, even if imbibed
or practised by the masses at large, have proved beneficial; whereas
ethical have, under the same circumstances, proved
researches
harmful in that they are for ever shaking the foundations of the
social order. And in that we have proof and counter-proof of the
*
2004 In the fifteenth, sixteenth, and seventeenth centuries the finger of Satan
was seen in everything. If a hail-storm came, if some animal or a human being fell
sick or, what is worse, died under circumstances at all strange, some sorcerer or
sorceresshad to have been at work. The man who was keeping a black cat or black
dog in his house was harbouring the Devil; and if Heaven forefend! he also
kept a toad, no reasonable doubt whatever was left that he was the sorcerer. After
the Eulenburg case in Germany, any two men seen walking together in that coun-
try were suspected of degenerate relations. After the Paterno trial in Italy, any man
seen frequently with a woman was suspected of living upon her shame. In 1913 an
army officer was tried in Milan on an accusation brought by fellow-officers of his,
who had become obsessed with just such suspicions, though the trial proved that
they had no foundations whatever in fact. If those individuals had been living in
the sixteenth century, they would have accused their colleague, with the same con-
viction and the same reasonableness, of being in the pay of Satan. A suicide that
took place in August, 1913, gave a writer in the Giornale d'Jtalia (Aug. 27, 1913)
occasion to make certain reflections that clearly show the fluctuating instability of
public feeling. We
quote the article here, suppressing names as usual, since we arc
interested in the facts strictly in the abstract: "A suicide not for love . What . .
opinion. All the sympathy turned to the woman, all the suspicions upon the young
man. People began to ask why Z [the suicide] had killed herself, and they laid the
blame on X, who had driven her to that act by his cruel indifference perhaps to
be rid of her. From there they went on to insinuate, though in veiled ways, that he
had been living on the poor woman's shame, and the wildest, most astonishing con-
jectures became current. The confusion was worse confounded by a statement made
by Y [representative of Z's family]; and that gentleman for a day or two enjoyed
1404 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 2OC>5
are somehow similar, are of the same general character, and that we
can say the same for S', T', U' . then for S", T" U" and . . ',
. . .
ries, and the excitements of a varied and adventurous life; and she had not had the
stamina to endure a moment
of unjustified discouragement. Investigations by the
police authorities will lead to nothing. The only blame that can be attached to X
is that he did not act with enough decision in
keeping a revolver out of reach of a
woman who had the soul and the brain of a child."
2OO8 THE VARIED FLUX OF SENTIMENTS 1405
more besides. Concrete situations are complicated. Imitation plays a
more or less important part in them, but many other circumstances
also have their influence ( 1766).
2006. Marxism gave rise to an infinitude of similar derivations,
S", T", U" . . .
designed to explain all social phenomenon by
,
chiefly to imitation that the derivations S", T", U" . have been . .
chosen.
2007. That must be kept in mind when we are trying to get at
residues through derivations. Great social currents often produce
we might conclude that a great change has taken place, that the
two periods represent two quite different epochs in civilization;
whereas, at bottom, it is a case of residues that are the same, or
almost the same, expressing themselves in different forms at different
times.
2008. The examples above would be particular cases of phenomena
much more general that may be observed when religious, ethical,
metaphysical, or mythical derivations are adapting themselves to
the necessities of practical life. Theories cannot be entirely severed
from the practical. There must be a certain adjustment between
them, and that adjustment is effected by a series of actions and re-
actions. As we have seen in every
page of these volumes and con-
trarily to ordinary opinion, especially the opinion of moralists, men
of letters, and pseudo-scientists the influence
of practice upon
rapher. We
have three treatises on "economics" in ancient Greek,
two of them attributed to Aristotle (the Oeconomica, though one,
at least, is not his), and the other to Xenophon (the Oeconomicus).
2008 * This single remark is enough to demonstrate the futility of many many
books addressed to the study of political or social phenomena, not to mention
works on economics. I took it into account in my Manuals by considering an objec-
tive and a subjective aspect in every phenomenon.
2013 PROPAGATION OF RESIDUES AND DERIVATIONS 1407
They consist of practical considerations on the art of domestic gov-
ernment for individuals and cities. From such considerations one
goes on to the abstractions of pure economics. From "pure econom-
ics,'* now, the question is to get back again to the study of concrete
only, we have still to learn how and why certain governments have
and others have not; how and why the gold
falsified their currency,
because they will not. Blame for the failure was laid on the poli-
ticians also, for
leading the ignorant astray with their chicanery, and
that, one must say, squares to a very considerable extent with the
facts; but there is still the mystery as to how and why the politicians
came to be able to wield the power they wielded and in that we
get one of those economic situations where the problem is
evidently
subordinate to the sociological problem.
2017. The classical economists envisaged what ought to be; de-
termined on it
by with very very few principles; and
logic, starting
since the logic and the principles were valid for the whole ter-
2019 PROPAGATION OF RESIDUES AND DERIVATIONS 14! I
they thought they could find it in the premises and in the theory.
These, therefore, they declared false they were only incomplete
and set out to reject them entirely, whereas they should have tried to
fill them out.
2018. Suppose a geometrician discovers the theorem of the square
of the hypotenuse. He rightly concludes that a right-angled triangle
with sides three and four metres long respectively will have a
hypotenuse five metres in length. He then decides to transfer the
results of his theory into practice and says: "No matter how the three
sides are assumed to be measured, the three numbers indicated will
always result." An
observer in Paris sets out to verify the statement.
He takes a piece of string and without stretching it at all measures
off two sides, one three metres, the other four metres, in length.
theory will enable one to explain and foresee facts such as the out-
comes of the experiments in Paris and London.
2019. But instead of supplementing the theory in that way, certain
persons come forward, who knows from where, and in order to re-
establish the accord deny the existence of geometry outright, and
reject
the theorem of the square of the hypotenuse because it has
been obtained by an "abuse" of the deductive method and fails to
take due account of ethics, which is so very very important to
jecting the theory of value and replacing that very imperfect concept
so widely current in his day with another, even more imperfect,
which was, bottom, a copy for the worse of Ricardo's. With his
at
get from their science alone the materials they know are needed for
a closer approximation to fact; whereas they should resort to other
sciences and go into them thoroughly not just incidentally for
their bearing on the given economic problem. The economists in
What was just said applies also to many other doctrines that pur-
port to give theories of the phenomena of human society ( 2269,
2273). Any given social science, unless it is
purely and exclusively
1414 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 2O22
descriptive, unless it
confines itself to saying, "In such and such a
case A
was observed, and simultaneously 5, C, . . ." and refrains D
from drawing the slightest inference from that concurrence and
from passing judgment on it in any way at all, necessarily rests on
solutions of problems belonging to a category of which the general
C, D l
. . . . To visualize the situation more readily, suppose we
2022 1 Here we have one
of the many cases in which mathematical language en-
ables one an exactness and a rigour impossible in ordinary language. Let
to achieve
we call them in the text) between A, B, C are then given by certain equations: . . .
System i:
<f> l (x, y . .
.) =o <
2 (x, y ...)== .
All the quantities x, y may be functions of the time t, which may, moreover,
. . .
figure explicitly in the System (of equations) which we have numbered i. This
system, if we assume the time as variable, represents the relationships of A, B, C . . .
and the evolution of those relationships Only a knowledge, vague and im- in time.
perfect as it may be, of System i enables us to have any knowledge at all of those
relationships and their evolution in time. Most writers do not take account of that
system, in fact are not even aware of its existence. But that does not prevent their
taking it, unwittingly, as the premise of their thinking. If it is assumed that the
number of equations in System i is equal to the number of unknowns, the un-
knowns are all determined. If it is assumed that the number of equations is smaller
than the number of unknowns which amounts to suppressing, hypothetically, some
condition ( 130) that really exists s, u, v . . .
may be taken as independent
variables, equal in number to the number of equations suppressed, and x, y . . .
System2:
Bx Sy
I = I, 2 . . .
The total differentials dx, dy represent virtual movements that arise when it is . . .
assumed that the independent variables, s, u, v are changed into s -}- ds, u -\- du. . . .
,
mathematics, the Systems i and 2, or the systems into which they may be assumed
2022 PROPAGATION OF RESIDUES AND DERIVATIONS 1415
reduce the general case of relationship to the particular case of a
relationship of cause and effect between and B, C. It is evident A
that any social science proposing to determine the effects of the
lowing: "If is A
brought in or is modified, what effects, B, . . .
,
C
will arise or be modified?" Solutions of these problems may be asked
and of their synthesis
of the various branches of the social sciences
expressed in sociology. But many writers who deal with the social
through differentiation, from the second to the first through integration. Very fre-
quently the second system is much more easy to establish directly than the first. If
nothing is known of those two systems, nothing known either of the relations that
is
something by that very fact is known about the Systems i and 2. To establish the
relations by considering not what is, but what "ought" to be, is to replace with
products of the imagination the Systems i and 2 that are yielded by experience
and to build on clouds. If there is only one independent variable, s, it is generally
called the "cause" of the "effects" x, y and its increase, ds, is called the "cause"
. . .
of the virtual movements dx, dy. When relations of cause and effect are alone
. . .
Ss Sx Ss Sy
These two systems are much easier to deal with than the systems i and 2, whether
in ordinary or in mathematical language ( 2092 1 ). It is advisable, therefore, to re-
place Systems i and 2 with them as often as possible. In some cases such substi-
tution yields a solution at least approximate of the problem that is being dealt with.
In other cases the substitution cannot be made, and then to replace the Systems i and
2 with the Systems 3 and 4 is impracticable because it would give results that have
nothing in common with reality. From the mathematical standpoint the integra-
tion of System 2 does not, as we have seen, reproduce System i only, but yields
more comprehensive solutions, one of which is the System i. To determine System i
exhaustively, therefore, other considerations have to be brought in. So the integra-
tion of System 4 not only reproduces System 3, but also introduces arbitrary con-
stants that have to be determined by other considerations. That, after all, is very
1416 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 2022
objection of a certain writer, who imagines that equations of type 2 cannot repre-
sent the solution of an economic problem, because they yield multiple solutions,
whereas there can be but one actual solution. To obtain a clearer understanding of
the general theory here set forth, one might study a particular case, such as the
determination of the economic equilibrium, with a system of the type 2. That I do
in the appendix to my Manttale, and in an article already mentioned ("Economic
has other characteristics besides it has, for instance, to be anterior in time to its
freezing. But if, terminology aside, we consider only the experimental relationship
between the two facts, taken apart from all other facts, it is altogether possible to
infer the bursting of the pipe from the freezing of water, and vice versa. In reality
there is a mutual correlation between the temperature that turns water into a solid
and the resistance of the container that holds the water. Resorting to mathematical
theory of fiat money (Pareto, Cours, 276), it is not so much from any ignorance on
their part of economic science as from eagerness to please the ministries and political
parties that use currency issues as a means of levying taxes surreptitiously.
2022 INTERDEPENDENCE IN ECONOMICS 1417
advantageous"; never of course even defining such terms or stating
3
just what utility (2in.)
they have in mind.
Sometimes the better of such writers barricade themselves in some
one department of science and try to refrain from any venturing
into departments in which they sense that a
danger lurks. So classi-
cal economists stoutly maintained that
they kept strictly aloof from
4
questions of politics. Others arrive at an identical point by adhering,
whether through prejudice, ignorance, mental indolence, or some
other brain condition, to ready-made solutions bearing on certain
5
subjects. So many economists accept the solutions of current moral-
ity without subjecting them to an even casual examination. In
former days they accepted the sanctity of private property, and now
that the wind is changing they fall under the spell of a more or
less diluted Socialism. Many writers take for granted the absolute
8
2022 Oftentimes they defend their views by resorting to the fallacy called
ignoratio elenchi evasion of an answer. If doubts are expressed as to the reality
of the relationships that they pretend to establish between A and B, C . .
they.
reply that such doubts emanate from heretics of the predominant religion (in days
gone by, Christianity and the monarchical faith; nowadays the religion of Progress
and Democracy), or from bad citizens, patriots, or
immoral, disreputable indi-
poor
viduals. Now the question really is who
voicing them, but whether the doubts
not is
beliefs frequently in contradiction one with another and the various conceptions
of honesty, and so on, that human beings hold. But not always is any such identity
alleged, and when it is, no experimental proof is, or can be, given of it; whereas
proofs to the contrary abound.
2022 * A
scientist of great merit, G. de Molinari, editor of the Journal des econo-
single element A
is a
necessary preparation for the investigation of
the combined influence of A
plus B. Champions of the economic
interpretation of history had the great merit of perceiving the cor-
relation of Aand B, but fell into the error of interpreting it as a
cause-and-effect relationship, where A
was the "cause" of B. Nor can
they, in turn, be blamed too severely for that; for before the real
character of the correlation of and A B
could be determined, it was
necessary to know that the correlation was there. Now that
progress
2025 CLASS-CIRCULATION 1419
in science has demonstrated the correlation, there is no excuse for
economists to continue in ignorance of it, nor are they excusable in
1
giving the correlation a form that it does not have in reality.
2024. Much has been done for the investigation of the economic
directly to ethics, if
for no other reason, for the reason that not
ous dements* We have more than once found ourselves called upon
to consider the heterogeneous character of society, and we shall have
to consider it all the more closely now that we are coming to our
*
2023 In our chapter next following we are to examine society as a whole,
taking the interdependence of A and B into account in its real form.
2025
*
A first rough sketch of the theory I am about to set forth was published
in my Systemes socialistes.
2
2025 The matter of social hetcrogeneousness and the question of circulation
among its various elements might be examined separately and apart from each other;
but since the phenomena corresponding to them appear in combination in the con-
crete, there will be advantages in considering them together, so avoiding repetitions.
1420 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 2O25
exhaustively here this matter of the diversity of the vastly numerous
social groups and the numberless ways in which they mix is out of
8
the question. As usual, therefore, since we cannot have the more,
we must rest content with the less and
try to make the problem easier
in order to have it more manageable. That is a first step along a
the
540, not to carry the investigation beyond certain limits. When a number of ele-
have at the outset an idea, be it a very rough idea, of the quantitative total of
such influences and then go on to consider just certain elements, A, B . Pf the . .
not aware of that an ignorance that has a number of causes, among which it may
be worth while to note the following: i. Habitual addiction to absolute, meta-
physical considerations, and verbal derivations of the sort that have been dealt
with throughout the course of these volumes ("natural law" or other such entities),
considerations and derivations that are something altogether different from the
quantitative notions of the experimental sciences. 2. An inclination to look, in his-
tory, primarily for the anecdote and the ethical judgment. An element, Q, which
may be having a virtually zero effect upon the phenomenon in hand, may
show very considerable index from the standpoint of anecdote or ethics.
a
Protestantism in its early phases has very fair indices of an anecdotal, moral, and
theological character. Its effects upon the ruling class in France were practically
nil, on the ruling classes in Prussia very considerable. Protestantism should there-
fore be disregarded in studying the French ruling classes, but taken into account in
studying ruling classes in Prussia. There are people who go even farther along
that path of error and place a scandalous love-affair of Julius Caesar's on a par
with his campaign in Gaul, or Napoleon's alleged licentiousness on a par with
his genius as a strategist. Those are the people who for centuries have been pre-
tending that the great and significant changes in human society have not seldom
been due to the whim of a sovereign, the caprice of some female favourite, or other
such spicy details of little or no moment. In the nineteenth century such people
seemed to be losing prestige; but of late they have come into vogue again, curtain-
ing the vacuum of their derivations with pompous verbal flourishes. 3. The pre-
sumption that to get the theory of a situation one must have "all the facts," down
to the most insignificant. If that were true, it would not be necessary to draw any
distinctions in the series A, B P, Q and such elements would all have
. . . . . .
now and never shall. The pretension in question may be excusable in Hegelians,
who withhold the name of science from Newton's astronomy; but it becomes some-
what ridiculous on the lips of people who admit that astronomy is a science and
ought to know, or be silent until they learn, that Newton founded modern astron-
2026 THE "ELITE" 1421
lem only in its
bearing on the social equilibrium and try to reduce
as far as possible the numbers of the groups and the modes of
circulation, putting under one head phenomena that prove to be
4
roughly and after a fashion similar.
2026. Social elites and their circulation*
Suppose we begin by giv-
to determine their significance, greater than the effort required to find one such
is
fact, and greater, far far greater, than the effort required to find one of the less
important facts, Q, R. . . .
Indeed, some of those facts are the more easily deter-
mined in proportion as their influence upon a given situation is slight. Infinitely
required, and less genius, to add one more observation of
less intellectual effort is
to make that effort should turn their talents to more congenial pursuits.
2025
4 A
general theory, of which the one with which we are dealing is only a
particular case, may be found stated in Sensini's "Teoria dell' equilibria di com-
posizione delle classi sociali."
2026 x Kolabinska, La circulation des en Prance, p. 5: "The outstanding idea
elites
9
in the term 'elite is 'superiority.' That
the only one I keep. I disregard secondary
is
very much the way grades are given in the various subjects in
examinations in school. The highest type of lawyer, for instance,
will be
given 10. The man who does not get a client will be given i
reserving zero for the man who is an out-and-out idiot. To the
man who has made his millions honestly or dishonestly as the
case may be we will give 10. To the man who has earned his
thousands we
will give 6; to such as just manage to keep out of
the poor-house, i, keeping zero for those who get in. To the woman
"in politics," such as the Aspasia of Pericles, the Maintenon of Louis
affairs, we shall give zero. To a clever rascal who knows how to fool
many, they have won. And so on for all the branches of human
activity.
2028. We are speaking, remember, of an
not a potential,
actual,
state. If at an English examination a pupil
says: "I could know
if I chose to; I do not know
English very well any because I have
never seen fit to learn," the examiner replies: "I am not interested
in your alibi. The grade for what you know is zero." If, similarly,
someone says: "So-and-so does not steal, not because he couldn't, but
because he is
reply: "Very well, we admire
a gentleman," we him
for his self-control, but his grade as a thief is zero."
2029.There are people who worship Napoleon Bonaparte as a
god. There are people who hate him as the lowest of criminals.
Which are right? We do not choose to solve that question in con-
nexion with a quite different matter. Whether Napoleon was a good
man or a bad man, he was certainly not an idiot, nor a man of little
account, as millions of others are. He had exceptional qualities, and
that enough for us to give him a high ranking, though without
is
x
2032 Kolabinska, Op. cit., p. 6: "We have just enumerated different categories of
individuals comprising the elite. They may also be classified in many other ways.
For the purpose I have in view in this study it is better to divide the elite into two
1424 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 2033
2033. A chesschampion is certainly a member of the elite, but
it is no less certain that his merits as a chess-player do not open the
doors to political influence for him; and hence unless he has other
qualities to win
him that distinction, he is not a member of the
governing Mite. Mistresses of absolute monarchs have oftentimes
been members of the elite, either because of their beauty or because
of their intellectual endowments; but only a few of them, who have
had, in addition, the particular talents required by politics, have
played any part in government.
2034. So we get two strata in a population: (i) lower stratum, A
the non-elite, with whose possible influence on government we are
not just here concerned; then (2) a higher stratum, the elite, which
is divided into two: (a) a
governing elite; (b) a non-governing
elite.
parts: one, which I will call M, will contain those individuals in the elite who share
in the government of the state, who make up what may be more or less vaguely
called 'the governing class.' The other part, N, will be made up of the remainder
of the elite when the part M
has been set off from it."
204 1 CLASS-CIRCULATION 1
425
governing elite also in our day hardly more than the label of king
remains in that status; but if direct inheritance has disappeared, in-
heritance powerful indirectly; and an individual who has in-
is still
by the head of the family also benefits all other members. In Rome,
the man who became Emperor generally raised his freedmen to the
higher class, and oftentimes, in fact, to the governing elite. For that
matter, now more, now fewer, of the freedmen taking part in the
Roman government possessed qualities good or bad that justified
their wearing the labels which they had won through imperial
bounty. In our societies, the social unit is the individual; but the
place that the individual occupies in society also benefits his wife,
his children, his connexions, his friends.
2038. If all these deviations from type were of little
importance,
they might be disregarded, as they are virtually disregarded in cases
where a diploma is required for the practice of a profession. Every-
one knows that there are persons who do not deserve their diplomas,
but experience shows that on the whole such exceptions may be
overlooked.
2039. One might, further, from certain points of view at least, dis-
regard deviations if
they remained more or constant quanti-
less
if there were
tatively only a negligible variation in proportions be-
tween the total of a class and the people who wear its label without
possessing the qualities corresponding.
2040. As a matter of fact, the real cases that we have to consider
in our societies differ from those two. The deviations are not so few
that they can be disregarded. Then again, their number is variable,
and the variations give rise to situations having an important bear-
ing on the social equilibrium. We are therefore required to make a
special study of them.
2041. Furthermore, the manner in which the various groups in a
1426 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 2042
population intermix has to be considered. In moving from one
group to another an individual generally brings with him certain
inclinations, sentiments, attitudes, that he has acquired in the group
from which he comes, and that circumstance cannot be
ignored.
2042. To this mixing, in the particular case in which
only two
groups, the flitc and the non-elite, are envisaged, the term "circu-
1
lation of elites'' has been applied in French, circulation des Elites
ship; and then (2), in the case of various groups, to the ways in
which transitions from one group to the other occur, and to the in-
lutely but also in relation to the supply of and the demand for cer-
tain social elements. A country that is
always at peace does not re-
ally contains the rulers, and a lower stratum, which usually con-
tains the ruled. That fact is so obvious that it has always forced itself
even upon the most casual observation, and so for the circulation of
individuals between the two strata. Even Plato had an inkling of
class-circulation and tried to regulate it artificially (278). The
"new man," the upstart, the parvenu, has always been a subject of
preconception that the higher classes are educators of the masses, and views un-
belief and impiety in the nobility, the Third Estate, and the higher clergy as among
the main causes of the Revolution. He notes the difference between France and
England in that regard and seems on the verge of ascribing to that circumstance
the fact that the revolution which occurred in France did not occur in England.
Says he, Bk. IV, Chap. II, sec. i (Vol. II, p. 118): "In England [the higher class]
speedily perceived the danger. Philosophy was precocious in England, native to
England. That does not matter. It never got acclimated there. Montesquieu wrote
in his travel note-book in 1729 (Notes sur VAngletene, p. 352): "No religion in
England. ... If
anyone brings up the subject of religion, he is laughed at.' Fifty
years later the public mind has about-faced: 'all those who have a tight roof over
their heads and a good coat on their backs' [The expression is Macaulay's.] have
seen what these new doctrines mean. In any event they feel that speculations in
the library must not become preachings on the streets. [They and Taine therefore
believe in the efficacy of such preachings.] Impiety seems to them bad manners.
They regard religion as the cement that holds public order together. That is be-
cause they are themselves public men, interested in doing things, participating in
the government and well taught by daily personal experience. . . . [Yet a few
lines before thatTaine had refuted himself:] When you talk religion or politics
with people, you find their minds almost always made up. Their preconceptions,
2051 HIGHER CLASS: LOWER CLASS 1429
cadence in literature and in the arts and sciences, and in invasions
by Oriental religions and especially Christianity.
2050. The Protestant Reformation in the sixteenth
century, the
Puritan Revolution in Cromwell's
day in England, the French Revo-
lution of 1789, are examples of great
religious tides originating in
the lower classes and rising to engulf the sceptical
higher classes.
An instance in our day would be the United States of America,
where this upward thrust of members of lower classes strong in
Class II residues very intense; and in that country one witnesses
is
[That is all borne out by experience; the following less so.], without foreseeing the
remoter consequences of the premises that they were adopting so gaily. . . .
[Belin makes a further point:] The privileged for that matter were the only ones
who could afford the exorbitant prices that any lover of forbidden books had to
pay."
1430 TREATISE ON GENERAL SOCIOLOGY 2052
viduals belonging to such aristocracies actually possess the qualities
parts, each in
his own field, as to be superior to the average individ-
ual. Under those circumstances the label corresponded to an actual
ity,
in the sense that they lose their vigour, that there is a decline in
the proportions of the residues which enabled them to win their
1
power and hold it. The governing class is restored not only in num-
x
2054 To that point we shall return presently ( 2190 ,)
2O59 CLASS-CIRCULATION 1
43 1
bers, but and that is the more important thing in quality, by
families rising from the lower classes and bringing with them the
2059. Violent movements take place by fits and starts, and effects
therefore do not follow immediately on their causes. After a gov-
erning class, or a nation, has maintained itself for long periods of
1432 THE MIND AND SOCIETY 2059
time on force and acquired great wealth, it may subsist for some
time still without
using force, buying off its adversaries and paying
not only in gold, but also in terms of the dignity and respect that
it had
formerly enjoyed and which constitute, as it were, a capital.
In the first stages of decline, power is maintained by bargainings
and and people are so deceived into thinking that that
concessions,
policy can be carried on indefinitely. So the decadent Roman Em-
pire bought peace of the Barbarians with money and honours. So
Louis XVI, in France, squandering in a very short time an ancestral
inheritance of love, respect, and almost religious reverence for the