V K Chari Aesthetic Experience A Review
V K Chari Aesthetic Experience A Review
V K Chari Aesthetic Experience A Review
A Review
V. K. CHARI
The problem of aesthetic experience is twofold: (i) to establish that
aesthetic experience is qualitatively distinct iTom nonaesthetic experiences, such
as religious, sexual, etc., and (ii) to show that it is in some way relevant to critical
discourse-to
our analysis and appreciation of art works. Critical attitudes
towards the concept have shown extreme reactions-from
the one that denies
that there is an experience called the aesthetic to that which says that it is useless
to standardize it and talk about it, sinc.e it is altogether too'subjective and variable
to be of any use in our di.scourse concerning the arts. Contemporary aesthetics
has, in fact, called in question the very ,notion of the "aesthetic" (Sparshott 1982,
467-86). The protagonists of aesthetic experience insist, however, that there is
a peculiarly distinct sort of experience that arises only in the context of our
encounter with aesthetic objects.
Sure enough, there is some experienceexperience, too, of a pleasurable nature-that
we all derive from works of art
and objects of nature, for otherwise, why would anybody attend to them at all?
But then, there are difficulties in identifying and defining aesthetic objects.
Artworks may be easier to isolate since they are the product of human intention
and purpose, and they are often put out into the world with the label "art" attached
to diem. However, there are also a vast number of crafts or products of human
skill that may be regarded as artworks-regarded,
that is, tor their perceptual
interests. But can they be said to generate aesthetic experience?
The case of
natural objects is even more difficult to deal with. But inasmuch as some of
them evoke feeling in use their identity as aesthetic objects has to be established
purely in terms of the experience they evoke. Even accredited artworks do not
produce the same kind or measure ofi-espouse in all people. with the result that
we do not seam to have a stable entity called aesthetic experience to talk about.
LI__
-'--1 "/.C_pGrtlt/fle
tDtdAull.tlu.
IW. XXIII:
what happens in it. But we would have a hard time, purely in terms of it's
however, a special mode of perception but simply the capacity to perceive the
various elements of the artwork "synoptically" in their Il'I.utual relationships.
n. In subjectivist terms, an aesthetic object is any object, natural or
man-made, to which we bring a special kind of attention-different
trom ordinary
kinds in that it focuses on the object for its own sake and not for any practical/
utilitarian reasons. This is the root take by the "aesthetic attitude" theorists
from Kant down to our own time, although these theorists would seen to assume
that the object must, in some unspecified way, be worthy of contemplation in
virtue of its qualities.
Now, the first approach assumes that qualities are phenomenally object
and hence available for critical analysis. The second makes the perception of an
object as an aesthetic object dependent upon the percipient's adopting a particular
attitude towards it. The aesthetic is a mode of perception, not an aspect of the
object.
On this view, any material thing whatever-a
blackbird
or a
wheelbarrow-is,
at least theoretically, capable of becoming an object of aesthetic
appreciation. III. An attempt to mediate dialectically between the two poles is
that of the phenoIl'l.enologists-Ingarden,
Dufrenne, Iser, etc., (ignoring marginal
ditfererices)-an
approach that is consistently applied to aesthetic questions ably
defended by Mitias (1988 A, 1988 B). According to this, the putative aesthetic
object becomes so both in virtue of certain qualities or properties possessed by
il and lhe percepliun uf lhe percipienl which, in severai ways, cuwpiiwenls,
contributes to, and thus" constitutes the object of appreciation.
In dialectical
terms, there is tirst the artwork which, mediated by perception, emerges as an
aesthetic object. A distinction is made here between what are strictly the material,
objective teatures ofthe art object and the perception ofthem as value-grounding
qualities or aesthetic qualities, between the artwork and the aesthetic object (a
distinction also observed by John Dewey). The aesthetic object is then, on this
view, both objective and subjective in terms onts ontic status. While the complete
idealist would say with Coleridge that "We received but what we give, " the
phenomenologists
would go with Wordsworth in saying that we "half receive
attention these things will not be seen as aesthetic objects. Much depends then
on the perceiver or connoisseur (rasika or sahrdaya in Sanskrit). It is in and by
his percepiion ihai a nUIl-aesiheiic objecL-thai is, an objeci ihai was noi aesiheiic
before-is
transformed into an aesthetic object. But this transformation is not a
real event in the world; it is an appearance. The tog in tbe sea, the painting, the
piece of music or whatever remains just what it was before I perceived i.t as
aesthetic or discovered in it. or projected onto it. some special signiticance or
value. This conclusion is implicit in the aesthetic attitude theory. Even according
to Beardsley's
"aesthetic point of view" theory, it is only when an object is
viewed from that point ol view that it will be recognized as an aesthetic object
. and will come to light in its ovw'Ilcharacter. Here of course the implications that
the object is that the object was already aesthetic (remember that Beardsley is
talking about artkind instances mainly) and it is only perceived fOTwhat it is,
whereas the aesthetic attitude theory assumes that the attitude aione does the
whole work and posits the aesthetic object.
But here the question is whether anything that is not intrinsically what it
is seen to be or regarded as can become what it is not except by an act of the
creative imagination or delusional vision, in which a rope can be seen as a serpent,
10
and profound
hiHs, and cataracts, as in Wordsworth '5 nature poetry. Natural objects. obviously
not being aesthetic by irttention (Amheim ~s "weeping willow" is obviously a
case of pathetic filllacy),need
to be looked at with a special attitude or in a
particular frame of mind in order that they tnay be regarded as aesthetic at a11regarded, that is. for their own sake, for tbe perceptual or imaginative pleasure
that they are capable of yielding. The aesthetic attitude theory, as conceived by
Kant, is based primarily on the model of mute natura} objects which.are innocent
of any aesthetic purpose and which depend on the view~'s perceptual ~ttitude
or point of view to give them any significance aesthetically. . And since the Attitude
is what confers aestheticity on 1he object. the object byitse1fhas no role in the
aesthetic experience. In this case then, *he principle of di$tinction between the
aesthetic and the nonaesthetic should be sought. not in tbeooject,- bunii.
.
interest taken.
But the same is not the case with intentional objects or objects that are
deliberately designed as aestbetic objects or artworks. A poem, a painting. a
sculpture, .8piece of music, a building with decorative motifs, etc. has no other
use to function than to be viewed aestheticaUy.
Thee objects are deliberately
put together in a purposeful manner so that their objective form atone, as an
~embodied intentio~," should be able to reveal the purpose for which they are
iniended. Even where an ariwork is expn:ssiy inbmueu fur sume other purpuse,
such as religious or moral, in its own identity as a formal organization it'.is first
an artwork and then, secoudarily, and instrument of use: tirst.a poem. then a
message~ first a sculpture, then a sacred image. and so on. Works of art are
aesthetic objects in their own constitution and .identiliable by certain built-in
features-such
as, formal devices, presentational or performance context.1:tc..
which serve as markers. They do not, like natural ()bjects, need theesemplastic
imagination of the perceiver for their being what they are perceived to be. Hence
Beardsley understands the term "aesthetic object" as synonymous with "work of
art, .. but insists that unless one regards it nom the aesthetic point of view :one is
not likely to see it for what it is-a demand that is justly made. because an artwork
can go unnoticed Qua artwork with our the awareness or a percipient. it appears
from this that the conditions of what is called aesthetic object are not the same
ina11 cases. and that in defining it we have to draw a line between natural .objects
and J.1lan-made works that are expressly designed as aesthehc objects.
11
they become aesthetic through a specific act of perception and are contingent
on that act for their aestheticity.
The aesthetic character of the artwork, fo~
Dufrenne, is its felt dimension or its affective quality, which is realized only in
the consciousness of the spectator.
For Dufrenne then, neither the formal organization nor the expressed
content of the artwork is yet aesthetic: the meaning of the poem, the melodicrhythmic structure of the music. the representation in the painting or sculpture
are stilI its sensory material body. They lack the "felt dimension" which alone
makes them aesthetic objects. The aesthetic object has a double existence:
as
an art object and as an object aesthetically-that
is, subjectively-realized.
It
is suspended between the formal/objective
structure of the artwork and the
subjective consciousness of the percipient. or better still, it is a tertium quid, a
new reality or creation arising from the union of the two. The dialectical structure
of this argument is obvious and it stems from the phenomenological
premise
that knowledge is at once sub-objective or inter-involved.
The identity of the
object depends on a perceiving subject; there is no object without a subject.
This line of reasoning is applied consistently by Mitias to the question
of aesthetic "qualities. which, he observes. are the real principle of aesthetic
distinction (Mitias 1988b). The aesthetic object, like any material object, may
be broken down into a complex, or more accurately, a congeries of qualities or
properlies.
Dul a uisliuclion may oe math:, aioeii aroilrnriiy, for our purpose,
between the terms "properties,"
and "qualities,"
let us say, has objectivist
implications:
A property is what belongs to the object and what goes into its
constitution,
whereas
a quality-aesthetic
quality,
that is-in
the
phenomenological
view, is that property of the object which is perceived as
being aesthetic, i.e. as having aesthetic value. Mitias does not make this
distinction,
but it is implied in his argument throughout.
Discussing the
ontological status of aesthetic qualities. He argues that aesthetic qualities are
not readymades or the objective properties of the work, but that they "emerge in
perception" as values (1988b,29).
The contemplative look on the tace of da
Vinci's A Musician, the sadness of Valse Triste by Siblius, or the tragicalness of
Anna Karanina, or the look of peace and dignity on the face of Vermeer's Kitchen
Maid are not altogether in the work although they are anchored in it and
determined by its material medium, its ontic base. They are there only as
potentialities
to be actualized
or realized as values in the perceiver's
consciousness.
Consequently they have their locus in aesthetic perception. The
14
objective properties of the work are, on the other hand, such things as the bright
patch of colour representing the flood light streaming through the window in the
Kitchen Maid, the organized notes in a musical piece, or the linguistic structure
and the described events (}f Anna Karanina-and
they form ,the physical base
for the perception of the corresponding aesthetic qualities.
At this point it will be instructive to probe a little into the question of
aesthetic qualities. A review of the scholarly discussion on the subject will reveal
the following (Beardsley 1982; Hermeren): (i)Aesthetic qualities (A-Qualities)
or aesthetic attributions are not all of the same t"jpe: Some are evaluative and
others are descriptive or objective properties perceived as value-grounding or
VG qualities, while yet others are variable depending on the circumstances. (ii)
Some may be attributed literally to artworks, while others (affective or purely
value-based terms) are imputed to artworks and can only apply to them by
metamorphic extension. (Hi) An A-Quality must be some aspect of the object
that is perceived as a value or as being capable of providing aesthetic
gratification.
An aesthetic value may be defined as any property of an object
that is held to be a source of contemplative pleasure to a perceiver and that bears
.
repeated contemplation.
Thus, qualities like "delicate" (meaning, having thin fine lines or
contours), somber (dark-of
colours and landscape), vivid-are
phenomenally
objecii ve or descripLi ve properLies.
"U uilled,"
'<cohereni,'" "~ompieie,'"
"Balanced," "tightly knit," "harmonious"-are
gestalt or structural or "regional"
qualities. "Tragic," 'joyful," "serene," "solemn," "sad," "cheerful, "-are emotion
qualities or expressive qualities, perceived directly in art forms of the self.
.
signit)ring type (literature, tigurative painting and sculpture, expressive dance
and stage acting), but imputed to pure music, landscape, and nonobjective painting
and sculpture, in the nonself-expressive
medium. "Bold," "nervous," "tense,"
"impatient,"
"relaxed,"
"restle.ss,"
are behaviour
qualities,
ascribed
metaphorically to artworks. "Shocking," "stirring," "funny," "trite," "boring,"
''beautiful,'' "impressive." are reaction qualities and value-loaded, and designate
affective responses to artworks. Tbey are applied metaphorically to art works.
it aiso roiiows from (iii)aoove that the so-caiied A-Quaiities-whether
objective or purely evaluative/affective-are
aesthetic values, perceived as such
by a viewer or a community of viewers. Value perception takes someone to
discover tor himsel!"the values in things. Aesthetic judgement is then necessarily
a judgement of values, and to that extent it may be allowed that the percipient
15
imaged person in that the image exhibits it. The erotic behavidur of a dancer or
stage actor is even more manifestly an "expressed value," a valuable experience
equally to the performer and the spectator. In such cases, we can say that the
already actualized affective values of" the artwork are: simply replicated or
reverberated in the consciousness of the spectator. YdU feel what Buddha felt,
or more accurately, what the image "feels," in a manner of saying. But here one
could make a hair-splitting distinction and say that the feeling felt by the spectator
is not the same raw emotion that is expressed by the character or exhibited in the
image. What the spectator feels is "aesthetic emotion" (rasa, in Indian poetics),
and 1tCcordingiy,"om: cou1d give it a 1im~fi1: nomenclature.
wr.Ue this may
hold true of the disagreeable
or painful emotions-like
grief, anger, fear,
disgust-which
turn out to be pleasurable in life as in art. But are ndt even the
disagreeable emotions-Lear's
grief or Christ's agony-qualitatively
the same
as those felt by me wben I identify with those characters-except
that they are
distanced and imaginatively recalled? A maxim in Sanskrit has it that the pdetic
or dramatic experience is the same for the poet, tbe bero, and the audience.
However, you may wish to call these very distanced or "imagined" feelings "art
emotions" arid hence aesthetic values. Hut even so, they can be'seen as already
manifested in the work, at least in their substantial forms.
There is another sense in which aesthetic values may 'be said to be
expressed by lhe arlwurk, nOl existing wereiy as a basis for potenliai reaii~alion.
The artwork, as an iIlocutionary act, was made with the purport of conveying
certain values-valuable
insights or experiences-and
it does so in the only way
possible, namely, through the medium of the art form and the properties
appertaining to it. The serene look of Buddha and the agony of Christ on the
cross are the expressed content of the respective images-expressed
through
visible, objective signs-and
at the same time they are the values purported by
the expressions and found worthy of contemplation by the art lover. In the other
self-expressive mediums too, the work occasions sad or cheerful feelings in the
reader or spectator because the dancer, the actor, the speaker, the poet himself in
his own person or his persona expresses those feelings. These feelings, when
they are repiicated or echded in the reader's or spectator's consciousness are
different from those expressed in the artwork only in the sense that they appear
in a different substratum, where of course they will become intermixed with
subjective elements. Hut they should still be deemed to remain unchanged in
their qualitative essence. Otherwise, they could not even be traced back to the
17
them.
out of the forma! elements of these arts. Thus the sadness of a musical piece is
actually projected onto it and hence metaphorically ascribed, for the music has
no potentiality to occasion sadness in the absence of an invariable relation to
overt expressions of sadness. To say with Langer that it is iconic of forms of
feeling (the appeal to inner happenings).
However, it could arouse emotions in
virtue of some formal features ("Contours," Peter Kivy calls them) that are
isomorphic with features of behaviour expressive of them-such
as,tonality,
rhythm, tempo, etc. (the Bowasma thesis}-in
which case, such features w()uld
be descriptive qualities or properties oftne object, not C<aestheticqualities"arising
out of the contact of the listener's consciousness with the object." The same
argument holds for abstract dance. But the recognition of such values will be, to
a large extent, contingent upon the Hsten~'s personai attunement and cultural
exposure. An Indian audi~nce would not be able to feel any deep appreciation
for Western music or banet, although they can still identify the sounds as music
and the movements as dance movements. But non genuine aesthetic experience
m~y be expected trom such encounters.
In any case, it is only instances of the nonself-expressive
category that
the percipient has to add to the artwork, bringing to it experiential m'aterial from
the storehouse of his consciousness.
But in instances of the other category-in
the self-expressive
mediums-there
is no need for supplementation
by the
iUlligillaiioll. Th~ir illt:auillgs art: cOlltaim:u in tht:ir forms. Ont: pC:fct:ivc:s such
objects, makes out their form and their meaning, and then one may be ~ffected
by them in some way. Hut the objective reality ofthe thing remains unchanged.
There is'no interinanimation or cooperative effort between the art object and the
percipient.
But here the phenomenologist
may point out that what the words of a
poem, the gestures and actions of a performing artist, or the representation in a
painting may be said to contain is only an Hid,eal signification" (Dutrenne, 21 IS)
or a "schema" (Mitias 1988b,32), not the sensuous body of the experience itself,
and that in this sense the aesthetic object is realized and "completed in the
consciousness of the spectator" (Dufrenne. 204). There is the objective reality
of the anwork and then there is the subiective com em which the work siirs up in
the mind-emotions,
images, memories, sensations-the
effects that bring the
object to life as an aesthetic object. Here we must remind ourselves that any
artwork or any act of expression , for that matter, in the verbal, physical, or
plastic medium can go only so far and not hand over experience in the body. 1t
19
can only be a schema. Moreover. the meaning of any sign or sememe (meaning
-bearing entity) comes to light only when there is an uptake. But the meaning is
always there, situated in its context. whether someone decodes it or not. But
this is not the sense intended by the phenomenologist.
The meaning, he would
say. acquires its identity in being experienced. However, the case of the dramatic
arts-stage
acting and dance-which
are in the action medium-is
somewhat
different.
There the contents of the experience are presented directly and
immediately as a live spectacle, as a "happening," not merely as a schema. So
--~~at
the audie~~
only to vibrate in sympathy or relive the event
---..-empathetically.
Even so, no doubt. the numuer .of raiizing the spectacle will
vary from individual to individual. each person bringing to his experience a
wealth of meanings drawn from his personal psyche and his cultural frame of
rcfnence.
But over sucb subjectivereacrions
the art object has no. contr.ot
Much less do tbesereactions
form part of the meaning of the work. Fer all
-CAU.:;;t;,": ~!I that is supported by a semantics-a
sign-signifie,~presser.
expressed (vacya-vacako, in Sans
-re!ation-is
by ~efinition limited and
def"tnite. The elaborations or extensions of meaning, imaginative and conceptual
proliferations, that a'Mona Lisa ora poem by Keats may' spur in the inind ola
person with a fertile imagination, although they no doubt my flow trom the object,
cannot with any justice be called the meaning of that object. No doubt, too, that
invariaOly the object is realized in this subjective fashiou and is, in the process,
enriched by what the individual adds to it in terms of his own constructive
imagination.
aut I should argue that all this does not strictly tall ~ithin the
bounds of what the work itself purports to convey. At any rate, the spectator
cannot be said to be "'constituting," or "'completing" the aesthetic object through
his act of perception.
He can only be extending its meaning, value, or
significance.
For the work itself, as a finished product-whether
a poem, a
play, a picture, or a dance-contains
its own significance, is seU:'complete and
self-revealing (inasmuch as any such thing can be said to be) even without the
mediation olthe spectator's consciousness. Hence its objectivity, its autonomous
status.
We nave seen mat an artifact-regaraiess
of whetner it is com1>ieteiy
objective or partly actualized in consciousness-is
distinguishable from the rest
of the phenomenalworld
by virtue ofits artifactuality. It is either an imitative
reproduction of nature or a tormulation, shaping, or organization ol its elements
(categorical traits), or an expression of ideas and feelings in a conventional
20
medium, although many other artifact~ (machines, tools, etc.) would also qualify
for this designation.
But is the experience generated by it so distinguishable
from other kinds of experiences?
It has been argued by the critics of aesthetic
experience and aesthetic attitude that art is continuous or coextensive with like,
that there are no elementary aesthetic interests or emotions,and
that all the
interests, emotions, and urges that prompt people in real life appear in art as
well. However, something like an aesthetic interest or aesthetic seD,Secan perhaps
be isolated from other life interests-from
the utilitarian, heuristic, religious,
intellectual and the like. First, people enjoy making pictures of things or
producing imitations of objects and actions. This is Aristotle's mimetic instinct.
Second, they like to create shapes. make formal patterns of objects, sounds,
movements, weave structures of different kinds, and so on. This is Aristotle's
instinct for harmony and rhythm. Third, they also like a pleasurable exercise of
their emotions, what HazIitt called ~gusto" (rasa, in Sanskrit), or an excitation
of their senses by colours, sounds, and the like. Fourth, there is the instinct for
ornamentation (alamkarana, in Sanskrit), which is amply demonstrated by all
sorts of decorative motifs appearing in traditional architecture-temples,
churches, aDd mosques-:"'and on images, and by costumes,jewelry,
and "the like,
which serve no other function than simply beautifying the appearance of things
and persons. In both Indian and Western poetics, rhetorical figures are held to
be ornamental additions to the poetic idea, a means of enhancing the meaning.
Artistic activity as well as aesthetic appreciation may be traced to these urges.
There is no need to explain the whys and wherefores of this phenomenon.
So
one can conclude that there is a thing called pure aesthetic value that is distinct
from practical, theoretical, and other values. And if there is such a value, the
experience resulting from the pursuit or contemplation of it must also be distinct
from experiences resulting from other sorts of activities and objects. Aesthetic
activity may be called a self-rewarding activity or play, and an end in itself. But
this feature of the aesthetic experience niay nofbe a sufficient condition for its
being a distinct kind of experience,
since there are evidently many other
activities-games
and sports, for example-there
are also self-rewarding,
in
which case, we can only say that aesthetic activity is but part of a larger family
of autotelic activities.
Besides, as pointed out by Dickie and other objectors,
one may not value an art object' for its aesthetic interest alone. The aesthetic
interest may coexist with the practical, acquisitive, intellectual,
and other
interests. While this may be granted, it is possible to argue that, in its purest
21
state, albeit maybe for a short duration, the aesthetic interest can be isolated and
that the quintessential function of the object that provokes that interest is to
gratify that aesthetic in the viewer, and not to provide sOIne other kinds of
satisfaction.
In nay case, it is necessary to outline the character of this experience
before we can make out a case for it in terms of its possibility and worthwhileness.
Contemporary discussions of this subject have generally followed Beardsley's
formulation-which
has its source in the tradition of Kant and Schopenhaver.
According to Beardsley, the five characteristics
or "internal properties" of
aesthetic experience are: object-directedness,
felt freedom. detached affect,
active discovery, and wholeness.
Attentional focus on the aesthetic object.
disinterestedness
and psychical distance. and the consequent freedom from
mundane. cOnc"..-ert1S
are also common to the phenomenological
and aesthetic
attitude theorists. Both Beardsley and the phenomenologist also emphasize the
affective character of this experience. But for Beardsley, the affective element
is strictly under the control of tbe perceptual elements of the artwork.
Much the same account can be heard from the ancient Indian th~odsts,
chiefly Abhinavagupta
whose formulations of the "Rasa" theory, following
Bharata's NaJya-sasJra. have been taken as canonical over the ages (Abhinava
BharaJi, I & VI). Although the rasa experience is generally equated with aesthetic
experience by scholars, it must be noted that in its original intent it related mainly
to poetry and stage drama and not to the plastic arts or even to music and dance
in their abstract form, taken in isolation from the theatrical context. Poetry was
considered separately as a verbal art and the theatrical spectacle was a mix of
dialogue, action, song, and dance (both pure and expressive). The rasa experience
.
was the total experience of the dramatic spectacle. Both Bharata and his
commentators, including Abhinavagupta, recognize that music and abstract dance
are powerful affective tools, especially in the theatre, but they argue that they
possess no definite emotive significance as they have no semantic or cognitive
content-a
situation consisting of the objects and behavioural expressions of an
emotion. In latter day literature, the rasa concept was applied to the figurative
arts, namely, painting and sculpture (cUra and silpa), and expressiveness was
held to be of the very essence of the art of portraiture, as it was of stage acting
and expressive dance. The association of music with rasa was taken as axiomatic
though it was recognized that musical notes and tunes (ragas) had by themselves
22
24
spectator becomes immersed in the world of the drama to the extent that all his
worldly interests and concerns are suspended for the time being. Hence
Abhinavagur;ta calls. the dramatic experience other-worldly. This is how
"disinterestedness" and "aesthetic or physical distance," which are a necessary,
if not a sufficient, condition of aesthetic experience, are to be understood. In
terms of the rasa theory, aesthetic detaclunent is detaclunent, not from human
concerns, as Dickie understands it, but from concerns of a practical or
immediately personal nature. The pleasure of rasa experience is born of our
deep involvement in matters of life that are equally our own and of the rest of
the world, but appearing at a remove from actual life because of the assumed
otherness and imaginariness of the presentation. There is the awareness in tho
spectator back of his mind that the whole drama is an imaginative exercise or
play. As Dufrenne put it, the world of the artwork is "derealized" .by its being a
.--
nave it too!
.-
.'
,28
n.
.\
The real issue then is not whether there is an aesthetic experience, but
wh:Uts usefulness is for critical discourse. . In evaluating artWorks, we no doubt
judge their goodness in terms of their efficacy to communicate a valuable
experience, and we judge certain1artistit devices or compositional features for
their effectiveness in delivering specific effects. It may also be granted (contra
Dickie) that unity and its family of related qualities, dependently or independently
valuable in works of art, can be predicated of aesthetic experience, although
they are not exclusive to it. But they can be taken as axiomatic and artWorks
analyzed in terms of them, without having to expatiate on their effective or
phenomenally
s~bjective
counterparts,
even as the laws of identity,
noncontradiction, unity of meaning, and so on are the norms in logic and semantic
analysis, but one does not dwell on the states of mind corresponding to these
objective features. thus, in saying that a poem or a play is unified, has a complex
organization,
or that it exhibits emotional tension one has said it all. The
corresponding affects at the subjective level may be expected to follow. Since
any talk about the phenomenally subjective fe~tures will only push us back into
the work, the work alone ought to be our concern, first and last. Here one must
~FERENCES
1. Abhinavagupta.
"Abhinavabharatf,1~iitBbarata,
~.
1971
"5
University,
2.
Quality?"
"Aesthetic
Experience."
Experience
In The Aesthetic
Banaras Hindu
Regained," "What
Essays. Ed. Michael J. Wren and Donald M. Callen. Ithaca and London:
C
3.
4.
Dufrenne,
Michael.
al. Evanston:
Art. Philadelphia:'
The Phenomenology
of Aesthetic Experience.
and participant."
29
experience
is that
S. Hermeren,
Experience.
6.
"In Aesthetic
1988
Aesthetic?
Rodopi: Amsterdam,
1988
7.
Mitias
1989b.
Quality."
In Aesthetic
Quality
and Aesthetic
Experience.
8. Sparshott. Francis E. The Theory a/the Arts. Princeton: Princeton U.P., 1982
V. K. Chari
121 Norice Street
Nepean, Ontario K2G 2Y1
Cana'da
,,
30