We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 207
oe ° “LANGUAGE,
®
® K Trutn AND
®
@ SS __Locie
° ——"@
6
FOUNDED LOGICAL POSI-
TIVISM — AND MODERN
THE CLASSIC TEXT WHICH
BRITISH PHILOSOPHYpig
PELICAN BOOKS
LANGUAGE, TRUTH AND LOGIC
Sir Alfted Ayer was born in 910 and educated asa King’s
Scholar at Eton and as a classical scholar at Christ Church,
Oxford. After spending a short period at the University of
Vienna, he became Lecturer in Philesophy at Christ Church
in 1933. and Research Student in 1935. In 1940 he joined
the Welsh Guards, but was employed for most of the War in
Military Intelligence. He returned to Oxford in r945 as
Fellow and Dean of Wadham College. From 1946 to 1959
he was Grote Professor of the Philosophy of Mind and Logic
in the University of London, He was Wykeham Professor of
Logic in the University of Oxford, and was a Fellow of New
College, Oxford, from 1959 until 1978. From 1978 to 1983
‘he was a Fellow of Wolfson College, Oxford. In addition he
is a Fellow of the British Academy, an Honorary Fellow of
Wadham College and New College, Oxford, and University
College. London, an Honorary Student of Christ Church and
an Honorary Member of the American Academy of Arts
and Sciences; he holds an honorary degree from the univer-
sities of East Anglia, London and Durham, as well as Trent
in Ontario and Bard College in the U.S.A. His principal pub-
cations are The Foundations of Eimpiricad Knowledge; Philo-
sophical Essays; The Problem of Knowledge (Pelican): The
Concept of a Person; The Origins of Pragmatism: Metaphysics
und Common Serse; Russell and Moore: The Anelytical
‘Heritage; The Central Questions of Philosophy (Pelican); Proba-
biltey ard Evidence, Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: Rus-
self; Hume; Freedom and Morality; Ludwig Wittgenstein
(Pelican) and Voltaire, He has also published two volumes of
autobiography and contributed articles to philosophical and
literary journals. Sit Alfred was knighted in 1970 and is a
Chevalier de la Légion d’Honneur.LANGUAGE,
TRUTH AND LOGIC
A. J. AYER
PENGUIN BOOKSPENGUIN BOOKS
Published by the Penguin Group,
a7 Wilghts Lane. London w8 sr England
‘Viking Penguin inc, 40 West 23rd Stroct, New York, New Yurk za0ro, USA.
Penguin looks Austeslia Lid, Ringwood, Wietucia, Australia
Penguin Boos Canada Lud. 2801 Joba Street, Markham, Ontario, Canada t38 11g
Penguin Books (Nz) Lad. 182-190 Walrau Read, Auckland ra, New Zealand
Penguin Books Lid, Registered (flees: Hurmondswarth, Middlesex, England
rst published by Vistar Gollonce 1936
Published in Pelican Rooks r971
13-15 17 19 20 18 16 14 02
Copyright 1936. 1946 by AJ. Ayer
All eights reserved
Printed and bound in Groat Beitain by
Richard Clay Lad, Bungay. Sefale
TO RA.
Except In the United States of America,
thi book Is sold sublect fo the condition
that it shall no, by Way of trade oe otherwise,
be lent, ee-sobd, hited out, or otherwise eiveutated
‘without the publisher's prior consent in any form of
binding a¢ cover cher than that in which It is
Published and without a similar eondition
including this condition being Imposed
‘on the sobsequent porchaserEe ey
CONTENTS
Preface 9
The Elimination of Metaphysics 13
Pp. 13: What is the purpose and method of philosophy? Rejec-
tion of the metaphysical thesis that philosophy affords us
knowledge of a transcendent reality. 14: Kant also rejected
metaphysics In this sense, but whereas he accused meta
physicians of ignoring the limits of the human understanding
we accuse them of disobeying the rules which govern the
significant use of language. 16: Adoption of verifiability as a
criterion for testing the significance of putative statements of
fact. 16: Distinction between conclusive and partial verifi-
cation. No propositions can be conclusively verified. 19: Or
conclusively confuted. 20: For a statement of fact to be genu-
ine some possible observations must be relevant to the deter-
mination of its truth or falsehood. 21: Examples of the kinds
of assertions, familiar to philosophers, which are ruled out by
our criterion. 24: Metaphysical sentences defined as sen-
tences which express neither tautologies nor empirical hypo-
theses, 24: Linguistic confusions the prime sources of meta-
physics. 27: Metaphysies and Poetry.
‘The Function of Philosophy 30
p. 30: Philosophy is not a search for first principles, 30: Bar-
renness of Descartes’ procedure. 33: The function of philo-
sophy is wholly critical. But this does not mean that it can
give an a priari justification of our scientific or common-sense
assumptions. 3.4: There Is no genuine problem of induction,
as ordinarily conceived. 36: Philosophising is an activity of
analysis. 37: Most of those who are commonly thought to
have been great philosophers were philosophers in our sense,
rather than metaphysicians. 38: Locke, Berkeley, Hume as
analysts. 39: We adopt Berkeley's phenomenalism without
his theism. go: And take 2 Humean view of causation. 43:
Philosophy in our sense is wholly independent of meta-
physics. We are not committed to any doctrine of atomism.
44: The philosopher as an analyst is not concerned with the
5physical properties of things, but only with the way in which
we speak about them. 45: Linguistic propositions disguised in
factual terminology. 46: Philosophy issues in definitions.
The Nature of Philosophical Analysis 48
p. 48: Philosophy provides not explicit definitions, such as are
given in dictionaries, but definitions in use. Explanation of
this distinction. 49: Russell's ‘theory of descriptions’ as an
example of philosophical analysis. 52: Definition of an am-
biguous symbol, 53: Definition of a logical construction. 54:
Material things are logical constructions out of sense-
contents. 54: By defining the notion of a material thing in
terms of sense-contents we solve the so-called problem of per-
ception. 55: A solution of this problem outlined as a further
example of philosophical analysis. 59: Utility of such an-
alyses, 59: Danger of saying that philosophy is concerned
with meaning. 61: The propositions of philosophy are not
empirical propositions concerning the way in which people
actually use words. They are concerned with the logical con-
sequences of linguistic conventions. 63: Rejection of the view
that ‘every language has a structure concerning which in the
language nothing can be said’,
The A Priori 64
P. 64: As empiricists, we must deny that any general propo-
sition concerning a matter of fact can be known. certainly to
be valid. 64: How then are we to deal with the propositions of
formal logic and mathematics?. 67: Rejection of Mill's view
that these propositions are inductive generalisations. 71:
‘They are necessarily true because they are analytic. 74:
Kant’s definitions of analytic and synthetic judgements. 73:
Emendation of Kant's definitions. 74: Analytic propositions
are tautological; they say nothing concerning any matter of
fact. 74: But they give us new knowledge, inasmuch as they
bring to light the implications of our linguistic usages. 76:
Logic does not describe ‘the laws of thought’. 77: Nor geome-
try the properties of physical space, 80; Our account of a
priori truths undermines Kant's transcendental system. 81:
How, if they are tautological, can there be in mathematics
and logic the possibility of invention and discovery?ERE TL
Truth and Probability 84
p. 84: What is trath? 85: Definition of a proposition. 85: The
words ‘true’ and ‘false’ function in the sentence simply as
assertion and negation signs, 87: The ‘problem of truth’ re-
duced to the question. How are propositions validated? 83:
‘The criterion of the validity of empirical propositions is nat
purely formal. &9: No empirical propositions are certain nat
even those which refer to immediate experience. 93: Obser-
vation confirms or discredits not Just a single hypothesls but
a system of hypotheses. 94: The ‘facts of experience’ can
never compel us to abandon a hypothesis. 96: Danger of mis-
taking synthetic for analytic propositions. 97: Hypotheses as
rules which govern our expectation of future experience,
101: Definition of rationality, 102; Definition of probability in.
terms of rationality, 102: Propositions referring to the past.
Critique of Ethics and Theology 104
P. 104: How does an empiricist deal with assertions of value?
105: Distinetion between various types of ethical enquiry.
106: Utilitarian and subjectivist theories of ethics consistent
with empiricism, 207: But unacceptable on other grounds.
108: Distinction between normative and descriptive ethicel
symbols. 109: Rejection of intuitionism. 210: Assertions of
value are not scientific but ‘emotive’. 110: They are therefore
neither true nor false. r1z: They are partly expressions of
feeling, partly commands. 113: Distinction between ex-
pressions and assertions of feeling. 113: Objection that this
view makes it impossible to dispute about questions of value.
114: Actually, we never do dispute about questions of value,
but always about questions of fact. 116: Ethics as a branch of
knowledge comprehended ire the social sciences, rr: The
same applies to aesthetics. 119: Impossibility of demonstrat
ing the existence of a transcendent god. 120: Or even of prov-
ing it probable. 120: That a transcendent god exists is a
metaphysical assertion, and therefore not literally significant.
Saying this does not make us atheists or agnostics in the
ordinary sense. 122: The belief that men have immortal souls
is also metaphysical. 123: There is no logical ground for con-
flict between religion and science. 124: Our views supported
by the statements of theists themselves, 125: Refutation of
the argument from religious experience,The Self and the Common World 127
P. 127: The basis of knowledge. 129: Sense-contents as parts,
rather than objects, of sensc-experiences. r30: Sense-
contents neither mental nor physical. 130: Distinction be-
tween the mental and the physical applies only to logical
constructions, 132: The existence of epistemological and
causal connections between minds and material things open
to no a priori objections. 133: Analysis of the self in terms of
sense-experiences. 133: A sense-experience cannot belong to
the sense-history of more than one self. 134: The substantive
ego a fictitious metaphysical entity. 235: Hume's definition of
the self. 136: That the empirical self survives the dissolution
of the body is a self-contradictory proposition. 136: Does our
Phenomenalism involve: solipsism? 138: Our knowledge of
other people, 142: How is mutual understanding possible?
Solutions of Outstanding Philosophical Disputes 144
P. 144: The nature of philosophy docs not warrant the
existence of conflicting philosophical ‘parties’. 245: The con-
flict between rationalists and empiricists. 147: Our own log-
ical empiricism to be distinguished from positivism. 148: We
reject Hume's psychological, as opposed to his logical, doc-
trines. 150: Realism and idealism. 151: To say that a thing
exists is not to say that it is actually being perceived. 154:
‘Things as permanent possibilities of sensation. 155: What is
perceived is not necessarily mental. 158: What exists need
not necessarily be thought of. 158: Nor what is thought of
exist. 159: Empirical grounds for supposing that things may
‘exist unperceived. 261: Monism and Pluralism. 161: Man-
istic fallacy that all a thing’s properties are constitutive of is
nature. 164: Illustrates the danger of expressing ling
propositions in factual terminology. 165: Causality not a
logical relation. 167: Empirical evidence against the monist's
view that every event is causally connected with every other.
168: The unity of science. 168: Philosophy as the logic of
science,
Appendix Uyt
Index 200PREFACE TO FIRST EDITION
Tue views which are put forward in this treatise derive
from the doctrines of Bertrand Russell and Wittgenstein,
which are themselves the logical outcome of the empiri-
cism of Berkeley and David Hume. Like Hume, | divide all
genuine propositions into two classes: those which, in his
terminology, concern ‘relations of ideas’, and those which
concer ‘matters of fact’, The former class comprises
the @ priori propositions of logic and pure mathematics,
and these | allow to be necessary and certain only because:
‘they are analytic, That is, I maintain that the reason why
these propositions cannot be confuted in experience is
that they do not make any assertion about the empirical.
world, but simply record our determination to use symbols
in a certain fashion. Propositions concerning empirical
matters of fact, on the other hand, I hold to be hypotheses,
which can be probable but never certain. And in giving an
account of the method of their validation | claim also to
have explained the nature of truth.
To test whether a sentence expresses a genuine empiri-
cal hypothesis, I adopt what may be called a modified
verification principle. For I require of an empirical hypathe-
sis, not indeed that it should be conclusively verifiable,
but that some possible sense-experience should be rele-
vant to the determination of its truth or falsehood. If a
putative proposition fails to satisfy this principle, and is
not a tautology. then I hold that it is metaphysical, and
that, being metaphysical, it is neither true nor false but
literally senseless. It will be found that much of what or
dinarily passes for philosophy is metaphysical according
3to this criterion, and, in particular, that it can not be sige
nificantly asserted that there is a non-empirical world of
values, or that men haye immortal souls, or that there is a
transcendent God.
As for the propositions of philosophy themselves, they
are held to be linguistically necessary, and so analytic,
And with regard to the relationship of philosophy and em-
pirical science, it is, shown that the philosopher is not in a
position to furnish speculative truths, which would, as it
‘were, compete with the hypotheses of science, nor yet to
pass @ priori judgements upon the validity of scientific
theories, but that his function is to clarify the proposi-
tions of science, by exhibiting their logical relationships,
and by defining the symbols which occur in them. Con-
sequently ] maintain that there is nothing in the nature of
philosophy to warrant the existence of conflicting philo-
sophical ‘schools’, And | attempt to substantiate this by
providing a definitive solution of the problems which have
been the chief sources of controversy between philoso-
phers in the past.
The view that philosophizing is an activity of analysis
is associated in England with the work of G. E, Moore and
his disciples. But while I have leamed a great deal from
Professor Moore, I have reason to believe that he and his
followers are not prepared to adopt such a thoroughgoing
phenomenalism as [ do, and that they take a rather dif-
ferent view of the nature of philosophical analysis. The
philosophers with whom I am in the closest agreement
are those who compose the ‘Viennese circle’, under the
leadership of Moritz Schlick, and are commonly known
as logical positivists, And of these I owe most to Rudolf
Carnap. Further, I wish to acknowledge my indebtedness
to Gilbert Ryle, my original tutor in philosophy, and to
Isaiah Berlin, who have discussed with me every point in
the argument of this treatise, and made many valuable sug:
rogestions, although they both disagree with much of what
T assert. And I must also express my thanks to J. R. M.
Willis for his correction of the proofs.
AL J AYER
1 Foubert’s Place, London
July 1935
arCHAPTER ft
THE ELIMINATION OF METAPHYSICS
Tue traditional disputes of philosophers are, for the most
part, as unwarranted as they are unfruitful. The surest way
to end them is to establish beyond question what should be
the purpose and method of a philosophical inquiry. And
this is by no means so difficult a task as the history of
philosophy would lead one to suppose. For if there are any
questions which science leaves it to philosophy to answer,
a straightforward process of elimination must lead to their
discovery.
We may begin by criticizing the metaphysical thesis
that philosophy affords us knowledge of a reality trans-
cending the world of science and common sense. Later
on, when we come to define metaphysics and account for
its existence, we shall find that it is possible to be a meta-
physician without believing in a transcendent reality; for
we shall see that many metaphysical utterances are due to
the commission of logical errors, rather than to a con-
scious desire on the part of their authors to go beyond the
limits of experience. But it is convenient for us to take
the case of those who believe that it is possible to have
knowledge of a transcendent reality as a starting-point for
our discussion. The arguments which we use to refute
them will subsequently be found to apply to the whole of
metaphysics.
One way of attacking a metaphysician who claimed to
have knowledge of a reality which transcended the pheno-
menal world would be to inquire from what premises his
propositions were deduced. Must he not begin, as other
men do, with the evidence of his senses? And if so, what
valid process of reasoning can possibly lead him to the
13conception of a transcendent reality? Surely from erpiri-
cal premises nothing whatsoever concerning the proper-
ties, or even the existence, of anything super-empirical
can legitimately be inferred. But this objection would be
met by a denial on the part of the metaphysician that his
assertions were ultimately based on the evidence of his
senses. He would say that he was endowed with a faculty
of intellectual intuition which enabled him to know facts
that could not be known through sense-experience, And
even if it could be shown that he was relying on empiri-
eal premises, and that his venture into a non-empirical
world was therefore logically unjustified, it would not fol-
Jow that the assertions which he made concerning this
non-¢mpirical world could not be true. For the fact that a
conclusion does not follow from its putative premise is
not sufficient to show that it is false. Consequently one
cannot overthrow a system of transcendent metaphysics
merely by criticizing the way in which it comes into be-
ing. What is required is rather a criticism of the nature
of the actual statements which comprise it. And this is
the line of argument which we shall, in fact,. pursue. For
we shall maintain that no statement which refers to a
‘reality’ transcending the limits of all possible sense-
experience can possibly have any literal significance; from
which it must follow that the labours of those who have
Striven td describe such a reality have all been devoted
to the production of nonsense.
It may be suggested that this is a proposition which has
already been proved by Kant. But although Kant also con-
demned transcendent metaphysics, he did so on different
grounds. For he said that the human understanding was so
constituted that it lost itself in contradictions when it
ventured out beyond the limits of possible experience and
attempted to deal with things in themselves. And thus he
made the impossibility of a transcendent metaphysic not,
14
(Logic, Epistemology, and The Unity of Science 28) Fabrice Pataut (Eds.) - Truth, Objects, Infinity - New Perspectives On The Philosophy of Paul Benacerraf (2016, Springer International Publishing)