Histoire du structuralisme, 1. Le champ du signe, 1945-1966. Copyright Editions la decouverte, Paris, 1991. AlI rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, without the prior written permission of the publisher.
Copyright:
Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Dosse, François - History of Structuralism. Vol. 1 - The Rising Sign, 1945-1966
Histoire du structuralisme, 1. Le champ du signe, 1945-1966. Copyright Editions la decouverte, Paris, 1991. AlI rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, without the prior written permission of the publisher.
Histoire du structuralisme, 1. Le champ du signe, 1945-1966. Copyright Editions la decouverte, Paris, 1991. AlI rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, without the prior written permission of the publisher.
Copyright:
Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Download as pdf or txt
100%(8)100% found this document useful (8 votes)
3K views492 pages
Dosse, François - History of Structuralism. Vol. 1 - The Rising Sign, 1945-1966
Histoire du structuralisme, 1. Le champ du signe, 1945-1966. Copyright Editions la decouverte, Paris, 1991. AlI rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, without the prior written permission of the publisher.
Copyright:
Attribution Non-Commercial (BY-NC)
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online from Scribd
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 492
History of Structuralism
Volume I: The Rising Sign, I945-I966
Franois Dosse Translated by Deborah Glassman University of Minnesota Press Minneapolis London The University of Minnesota Press gratefully acknowledges financial assistance provided by the French Ministry of Culture for the translation of this book. Copyright 1997 by the Regents of the University of Minnesota Originally published as Histoire du structuralisme, 1. Le champ du signe, 1945-1966. Copyright ditions La Dcouverte, Paris, 1991. AlI rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior written permission of the publisher. Published by the University of Minnesota Press III Third Avenue South, Suite 290, Minneapolis, MN 5541-252 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free paper Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Dosse, Franois, 195- [Histoire du structuralisme. English] History of structuralism / Franois Dosse; translated by Deborah Glassman. p. cm. Includes bibliographical references and index. Contents: v. 1. The rising sign, 1945-1966-v. 2. The sign sets, 1 967-present. ISBN 0-8166-2239-6 (v. 1 : hc : alk. paper).-ISBN 0-8166-2241-8 (v. 1 : pbk. : alk. paper).-ISBN 0-8166-2370-8 (v. 2: hc : alk. paper).-ISBN 0-8166-2371-6 (v. 2 : pbk. : alk. paper).-ISBN 0-8166-2240-X (set: hc : alk. paper).-ISBN 0-8166-2254-X (set: pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Structuralism-History. 1. Title. B84I.4D6713 1997 I49'96'09-dc21 96-51477 The University of Minnesota is an equal-opportunity educator and employer. To Florence, Antoine, Chlo, and Aurlien Structuralism is not a new method, it is the awakened and trou bled consciousness of modern thought. Michel Foucault Contents Translator's Preface Acknowledgments Introduction Part J. The Fifties: The Epie Epoeh Xlll xvii xix 1. The Eclipse of a Star: Jean-Paul Sartre 3 2. The Birth of a Hero: Claude Lvi-Strauss 10 3. Where Nature and Culture Meet: Incest 18 4. Ask for the Program: The Mauss 26 5. Georges Dumzil: An Independent 32 6. The Phenomenological Bridge 37 7. The Saussurean Break 43 8. Roman Jakobson: The Man Who Could Do Everything 52 9. A Pilot Science without a Plane: Linguistics 59 ix x Contents 10. At Alexandria's Gates 67 II. The Mother Figure of Structuralism: Roland Barthes 7 1 12. An Epistemic Exigency 7 8 13. A Rebel NamedJacques Lacan 9 1 14 Rome CaUs (1953): The Return to Freud 99 15 The Unconscious: A Symbolic Universe III 16. Real/Symbolic/Imaginary (RSI): The Heresy II9 17 The CaU of the Tropics 126 18. Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work 14 2 19 Marxism in Crisis: A Thaw or the Deep Freeze Again? 158 20. The French School of Economics Takes a Structural Path 166 21. Get a Load of That Structure! 173 Part II. The Sixties: I963-I966, La Belle poque 22. Contesting the Sorbonne: The Quarrel of the Ancients and the Moderns 191 23 1964: The Semiological Adventure Makes a Breakthrough 202 24. The Golden Age of FormaI Thinking 210 25 Great Confrontations 223 26. Signifying Chains 239 27 Mythology's Earth Is Round 25 28. Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism 26 4 29 Reviews 273 3 Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? 28 4 Contents xi 31. The Althusserian Explosion 293 32. Marxism's Second Wind 309 33. 19 66 Annum mira bile (1): A Watershed Year for Structuralism 316 34. 1966 Annum mirabile (II): Foucault Sells like Hotcakes 330 35. 1966 Annum mirabile (III): Julia Cornes to Paris 343 Part III. A Hexagonal Fever 36. The Postmodern Hour Sounds 351 37. Nietzschean-Heideggerian Roots 38. Growing Pains Appendix: List of Interviewees 395 Notes 41 Bibliography 437 Index 449 Translator's Preface Franois Dosse's History of Structuralism has created quite a stir since its publication in I991. This book, written by a historian, weaves together a rich range of materials-interviews, books, journals, news- paper articles and television programs, disciplinary histories and con- temporary contexts-to produce a denselysaturated and highly read- able account of a productive, prolific, and energetic moment in French intellectuallife when the social sciences exploded and a new paradigm arose. Because the question of whether such a history is possible, and in- deed whether structuralism was itself a movement whose history can be written, Dosse rightly claims the Frenchness of the phenomenon and lays out, with varying intensity, the roles played by the major con- tributors to the phenomenon, the pioneers present at the "structuralist banquet," and their students or other participants. He looks at their works, strategies, institutions, and instruments invested in the effort to establish institutionallegitimation in an academic setting governed by the venerable Sorbonne and the classical humanities, which were more than reticent about any theoretical reinvigoration. If Dosse is right to insist on the Frenchness of structuralism, our interest in this history is even greater on this side of the Atlantic, where structuralism left an indelible mark on American universities, particularly in French departmerits. Minor mirror struggles were waged between the ancients and the moderns, between purveyors of xiii xiv Translator's Preface literary history and philology and more texrually bound readers attuned to the subtle nuances of language and more readily at home in this new, semiological, adventure. And much ta the consternation of more traditional humanists, history and context were largely left to other disciplines as the enthusiasm of a new perspective caught the imagination of a younger generation. Other humanities have been invigorated by the energies of the structural approach-art history, comparative literature, literature, cinema studies-as have been, if to a lesser degree, the social sciences, which were already better anchored in American universities than they were in parallel French institutions during the fifties, sixties, and seventies. More than an approach to reading has changed. Structuralism has brought with it-or is already a piece of that larger movement of which we are now struggling to take the measure-a shift in perspec- tive that listens to many whose voices have long been stifled, assigned to what Foucault calls the underbelly of reason, the place to which reason consigns its nether side. The repressed of history in their sin- gular manifestations and in the major manifestations of social life attracted all the pioneers of structuralism-Saussure, Foucault, Al- thusser, Lvi-Strauss, Lacan, Barthes. Even as they looked to scientific knowledge as an ideal in their polemical engagement with the institu- tions that resisted the presence of these new disciplines, these early structuralists sought out the unconscious structures and logics appar- ent in language, madness, social relations, neurosis, and myth. Struc- turalism was therefore a movement that in large measure reversed the eighteenth-century celebration of Reason, the credo of the Lumires, a movement who se multiple threads and echoes in the works, work, and lives of the major players and on the disciplines shaped our vision of a world. A vision that can never be the same after structuralism, argues Franois Dosse. Volume l, The Rising Sign, covers the first years of the structural- ist phenomenon, ending in 1966, a crowning year for structuralism. Volume 2 chronicles the waning years of the phenomenon. Franois Dosse is a lively writer whose verve drives his verb. 1 have tried to let this energy inform the translation, even if it is gener- ally impossible to reproduce the puns, alliterations, and rhythms of his writing. Many longer sentences were shortened; but if clarity has often sobered style, the consolation might be that English readers can Translator's Preface xv fully appreciate the immense efforts involved in bringing together so many pieces of the paradigm. The question of citations and bibliography has been a vexing one. AlI titles mentioned in the text have been rendered into English; the original French title is given in a note. Where well-known titles are mentioned in passing without any reference to specifie citations or bibliographical adumbration (Sartre's Being and Nothingness, for ex- ample), there is no accompanying note. The case of citations is somewhat more complicated. 1 have quoted extant translations of those authors for whom something resembling standard translations exist-Nietzsche, Foucault, Lacan, Lvi-Strauss. ln the case of ambiguities or variations (where the English translation varies from the French original, is incomplete, or realigns volumes, for example), 1 have indicated the original source and given my own translation. For works where no standard translation exists or where 1 had no access to one, 1 have provided my own translations and given the original source in the note. In the Appendix, the reader will find a list of interviewees and their institutional affiliations. Acknowledgments 1 would like to thank all those who were kind enough to agree to be interviewed. These interviews were entirely transcribed and their con- tribution was absolutely fundamental to the project of writing this history of French intellectuallife. The specifics of the area and current affiliation of each of the interviewees are to be found in the Appendix. Marc Abls, Alfred Adler, Michel Aglietta, Jean Allouch, Pierre Ansart, Michel Arriv, Marc Aug, Sylvain Auroux, Kostas Axelos, Georges Balandier, tienne Balibar, Henri Bartoli, Michel Beaud, Daniel Becquemont, Jean-Marie Benoist, Alain Boissinot, Raymond Boudon, Jacques Bouveresse, Claude Brmond, Hubert Brochier, Louis-Jean Calvet, Jean-Claude Chevalier, Jean Clavreul, Claude Cont, Jean- Claude Coquet, Maria Daraki, Jean-Toussaint Desanti, Philippe Des- cola, Vincent Descombes, Jean-Marie Dolmenach, Jol Dor, Daniel Dory, Roger-Pol Droit, Jean Dubois, Georges Duby, Oswald Ducrot, Claude Dumzil, Jean Duvignaud, Roger Establet, Franois Ewald, Arlette Farge, Jean-Pierre Faye, Pierre Fougeyrollas, Franoise Gadet, Marcel Gauchet, Grard Genette, Jean-Christophe Goddard, Maurice Godelier, Gilles Gaston-Granger, Wladimir Granoff, Andr Green, Aigirdas Julien Greimas, Marc Guillaume, Claude Hagge, Philippe Hamon, Andr-Georges Haudricourt, Louis Hay, Paul Henry, Fran- oise Hritier-Aug, Jacques Hoarau, Michel Izard, Jean-Luc Jamard, Jean Jamin, Julia Kristeva, Bernard Laks, Jrme Lallement, Jean La- planche, Francine Le Bret, Serge Leclaire, Dominique Lecourt, Henri xvii xviii Acknowledgments Lefebvre, Pierre Legendre, Gennie Lemoine, Claude Lvi-Strauss, Jacques Lvy, Alain Lipietz, Ren Lourau, Pierre Macherey, Ren Major, Serge Martin, Andr Martinet, Claude Meillassoux, Charles Melman, Grard Mendel, Henri Mitterand, Juan-David Nasio, Andr Nicola, Pierra Nora, Claudine Normand, Bertrand Ogilvie, Michelle Perrot, Marcelin Pleynet, Jean Pouillon, Jolle Proust, Jacques Ran- cire, Alain Renaut, Olivier Revault d'Allonnes, lisabeth Roudinesco, Nicolas Ruwet, Moustafa Safouan, Georges-Elia Sarfati, Bernard Sichre, Dan Sperber, Joseph Sumpf, Emmanuel Terray, Tzvetan To- dorov, Alain Touraine, Paul Valadier, Jean-Pierre Vernant, Marc Ver- net, Serge Viderman, Pierre Vilar, Franois Wall, Marina Yaguello. Others were contacted but were not interviewed: Didier Anzieu, Alain Badiou, Christian Baudelot, Jean Baudrillard, Pierre Bourdieu, Georges Canguilhem, Cornelius Castoriadis, Hlne Cixous, Serge Cotte, Antoine Culioli, Gilles Deleuze, Jacques Derrida, Louis Du- mont, Julien Freund, Luce Irigaray, Francis Jacques, Christian Jambet, Catherine Kerbrat-Oreccioni, Victor Karady, Serge-Christophe Kolm, Claude Lefort, Philippe Lejeune, Emmanuel Levinas, Jean-Franois Lyotard, Grard Miller, Jacques-Alain Miller, Jean-Claude Milner, Edgar Morin, Thrse Parisot, Jean-Claude Passeron, Jean-Bertrand Pontalis, Paul Ricoeur, Jacqueline de Romilly, Franois Roustang, Michel Serres, Louis-Vincent Thomas. 1 would also like to thank aIl of those whose difficult task it was to read this manuscript in its early stages and whose comments and suggestions made it possible for me to carry out this undertaking: Daniel and Trudi Becquemont, Alain Boissont, Ren Gelly, Franois Gze, and Thierry Paquot. Lastly, for having given me the print runs of a certain number of works of the period, 1 would like to thank Monique Lulin at ditions du Seuil, Pierre Nora at ditions Gallimard, and Christine Silva at ditions La Dcouverte. Introduction Structuralism's success in France during the 1950S and 1960s is with- out precedent in the history of the inteHectual life of this country. There was such widespread support for structuralism among most of the intelligentsia that the resistance and minor objections put forth during what we can calI the structuralist moment were simply moot. We can better understand how so many intellectuals could be at home in the same program if we understand the context .. There were two fundamental reasons for this spectacular success. F i r ~ t , structuralism promised a rigorous method and sorne hope for making decisive progress toward scientificity. But even more fundamentaHy, it was a particular moment in the history of thought, which we can character- ize as a key moment of critical consciousness; for the structuralist pro- gram attracted a particularly broad range of enthusiasts, including the trainer of the national football team who, in the sixties, announced a "structuralist" reorganization of his te am in order to win more games. The triumph of the structuralist paradigm is therefore first of aH the product of a particular historical context, characterized since the .end of the nineteenth century, and particularly since 1945, by the West's progressive slide toward what Lvi-Strauss called a cooler tem- porality. But it is also the product of the remarkable growth in the social sciences, which ran up against the hegemony of the aged ?or- bonne, bearer of scholarly legitimacy and dispenser of the classical humanities. The structuralist program was a veritable unconscious ., xix xx Introduction strategy to move beyond the academicism in power, and it served the twofold purposes of contestation and counterculture. In the academic realm, the structural paradigm successfully cleared the ground for proscribed knowledge that had long been kept at bay, in the margins of the canonical institutions. Structuralism was contestatory and corresponded to a particular moment in Western history. It expressed a certain degree of self- hatred, of the rejection of traditional Western culture, and of a desire for modernism in search of new models. Antique values were no longer glorified; structuralism demonstrated an extreme sensitivity to everything that had been repressed in Western history. Indeed, it is no accident that the two leading sciences of the period-anthropology and psychoanalysis-privilege the unconscious, the nether side of manifest meaning, the inaccessible repressed of Western history. The structuralist period was also a time when linguistics was a pilot science guiding the steps of the social sciences as a whole toward scientificity. In this respect, structuralism was the banner of the mod- erns in their struggle against the ancients. As the disillusionment of the second half of the twentieth century grew, structuralism also became an instrument of de-ideologization for many politically committed in- tellectuals. A specific political moment characterized by disenchant- ment and a particular configuration of knowledge requiring a revolu- tion in order to successfully carry through a reform made it possible for structuralism to become the rallying point for an entire generation. This generation discovered the world behind the structuralgrid. The important quest for a solution to existential confusion pro- duced a tendency to ontologize structure that, in the name of Science and Theory, became an alternative to traditional Western metaphysics. Ambitions were boundless during this period in which boundaries were being redefined and the limits of imposed figures extended. Many struck outalong the newest paths opened up by the flowering of the social sciences. Suddenly, however, everything changed. Tragedy struck struc- turalism...J!uhebeginnin.s of the eighties. In the same fell swoop, mosf of the French heroes of this international epic left the stage of the liv- ing, as if the theoreticians of the end of humanity had all allowed themselves to be carried off simultaneously in a spectacular death. Nicos Poulantzas killed himself by leaping from his window on Octo- ber 3, I979, just after having justified his refusaI to betray Pierre Introduction xxi Goldmann; his suicide was concrete punishment for a purely imagi- nary crime. After lunching with Jacques Berques and Franois Mitter- rand, then chairman of the Socialist Party, Roland Barthes was run clown by a dry cleaner's truck on the rue des coles. Barthes suffered only a slight cranial trauma, but, according to the witnesses who vis- ited him at the Piti-Salptrire Hospital, he let himself decline, and died on March 26, 1980. During the night of November 16, 1980, Louis Althusser strangled his faithful wife, Helen. The eminent repre- sentative of the most rigorous rationalism was judged not to be re- sponsible for his act, and was hospitalized at Sainte-Anne, a Pari sian psychiatrie hospital, before being admitted to a private clinic in the Paris area, thanks to the help of his former philosophy teacher, Jean Guitton. The man of words, the great shaman of modern times, Jacques Lacan, died on September 9, 1981, aphasie. Barely a few years went by before the ill wind of death carried off Michel Foucault. At the height of his popularity and completely immersed in his work on a history of sexuality, Foucault was struck with the new scourge of the century, AIDS. He died on June 25,1984. So many dramatic and proximate deaths reinforced the impression of the end of an era. Sorne went so far as to theorize the coincidence of these tragedies as the revelation of the impasse of a common way of thinking popularly called structuralism. In this view, the break between speculative thinking and the real world leads to self-destruction. Such a juxtaposition is even more artificial than the mediatized glorification of the sixties, when the structuralist banquet rose to the heights of its glory, and along with it, the four musketeers, who were five at the time: Michel Foucault, Louis Althusser, Roland Barthes, Jacques Lacan, and their common father, Claude Lvi-Strauss. This collective shipwreck nonetheless remains a milestone on the French intellectual landscape. The disappearance of the master thinkers, and Jean-Paul Sartre must be counted among them, opened up a new period of doubt. Nostalgia was already in the air at the be- ginning of the 1980s, when it was fashionable to evoke these figures with an ambivalent mixture of awe and fascination heightened by their unusual fates, which had transformed them into something re- sembling heroes. While sorne took pleasure in signing the death certifi- cate of structuralism, the body was still alive and kicking hard, accord- ing to the survey published in Lire in April 1981. When hundreds of writers, journalists, professors, students, and politicians were asked, xxii Introduction "Who are the three living intellectuals of the French language whose work seems to you to have the greatest and most profound influence on philosophy, letters, arts, and sciences, etc.?" they answered: Claude Lvi-Strauss (101), Raymond Aron (84), Michel Foucault (83), and Jacques Lacan (SI). The concept of structuralism has stirred as much enthusiasm as opprobrium. From the Latin struere, derived from structura, the term "structure" initially had an architectural meaning. Structure de sig- nated "the manner in which a building is constructed" (Trvoux Dictionary [1771]). In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the meaning was modified and broadened by analogy to include living creatures. Fontenelle saw the human body as a construction; Vaugelas and Bernot saw language as a construction. The term came to describe the way in which the parts of a concrete being are structured into a whole, and it could apply to a variety of structures-anatomical, psy- chological, geological, mathematical. It was only later that the struc- tural approach appropriated the social sciences. For Spencer, Morgan, and Marx, the term described an enduring phenomenon linking the parts of a whole together, in a complex manner, and in a more ab- stract way. The term "structure"-nowhere to be found in Hegel and only infrequently in Marx, with the exception of the preface to the Critique of Political Economy (I859)-was established in 1895 by Durkheim, in The Rules of Sociological Method. Between 1900 and 1926, structure gave birth to structuralism, which Andr Lalande, in his Vocabulaire, calls a neologism. For psychologists, structuralism is born at the beginning of the century, by opposition to functional psy- chology. But the true origins of the practice, in its modern sense, and on the scale of all the human sciences, cornes from developments in the field of linguistics. Saussure used the term "structure" only three times in his Course on General Linguistics. Later, the Prague school (Trubetzkoy and Jakobson) generalized the use of the terms "struc- ture" and "structuralism." The Danish linguist Hjelmslev claimed to make reference to the term "structuralism" as a founding program, a tendency made explicit by his activity. In 1939, he founded the review Acta linguistica, and its first article addressed "structurallinguistics." From this linguistic kernel, the term produced a veritable revolution in all the social sciences that were at the core of the twentieth century, and each in its turn believed that it received a scientific baptism. Miracle or mirage? The history of science is nothing more, after Introduction xxiii aIl, than the history of the graveyard of its theories. This is not at aIl to say that each of the stages left behind is no longer effective, but simply that any program loses its productivity and necessarily undergoes methodological renewal. With structuralism, however, the changes risked falling into the same traps that the previous method had avoided. Whence the necessity of illuminating the richness and pro- ductivity of structuralism before seizing upon its limits. This is the ad- venture that we will undertake here. Notwithstanding the dead ends into which structuralism has run on occasion, it has changed the way we consider human society so much that it is no longer even possible to think without taking the structuralist revolution into account. The structuralist moment is a piece of our intellectuai history that opened up a particularly fertile period of research in the social sci- ences. Reconstructing its history is complicated because the contours of the "structuralist" reference are particularly vague. In order to understand the principal positions of the period, we have to recon- struct its many methods and personalities, while at the same time, and without being reductionist about it, seeking sorne coherent centers. Be- yond the multiplicity of objects and disciplines, these centers reveal the matrix of a procedure. Different levels are to he sorted out and the many structuralisms underlying the term "structuralist" differenti- ated. We can clarify the fundamental intellectuai issues, which are as theoretical as they are disciplinary, and explore the wealth of individ- ual trajectories, which cannot be summed up in a group history. As it presents the contingencies of fortuitous but essential meetings, this his- tory proposes to amalgamate bodies and hring many explanatory fac- tors to bear without in any way reducing them to any single causality. The social sciences appropriated structuralism in a numher of ways. But heyond the interplay of borrowed ideas, analogies, and a contiguity that we will he obliged to sketch out, as Barthes counseled the future historians of structuralism to do, we can make a distinction that does not coincide with disciplinary boundaries. stru<:- turalism is represented in particular hy Claude Lvi-Strauss, Aigirdas Julien Greimas, and Jacques Lacan, and simultaneously involved an- thropology, semiotics, and psychoanalysis. Contiguous with this search for the Law was a more supple, undulating, and shimmering struc- turalism to he found particularly in the work of Roland Barthes, Grard Genette, Tzvetan Todorov, and Michel Serres, and which we might call semiological structuralism. There is also, finaIly, a histori- XXIV introduction cized or The work of Louis Althusser, Pierre Bourdieu, Michel Foucault, Jacques Derrida, Jean-Pierre Vernant, and, more broadly, the third generation of the Annales faUs into this group. Beyond these distinctions, however, we can identify a commu- nit y of language and goals that sometimes gives the impression that we are reading the same book despite the variations in style and dis- cipline that distinguish a Barthes from a Foucault, a Derrida, or a Lacan. Structuralism was the koine of an entire inteIlectual genera- tion, even if there is no doctrinal solidarity and even less a school or a battle among its various representatives. It is no less difficult to reconstruct the history of this moment th an it is to periodize the structuralist moment. Thefifties clearly saw an irresistible increase in structural phenomena that in the sixties became a veritable structuralist mode that most inteIlectuals adopted. Until 1966, structuralism was in an ascending phase and its growth seemed unstoppable. The year 1966 is a central point of reference. This was the year structura li st activity beamed forth most forcefuIly in intel- lectual life and the intensity of the mixture of a universe of signs shone forth beyond aIl established disciplinary frontiers. Nineteen sixty-seven, however, saw the beginning of the ebb, of criticisms, of distantiation from the structura li st phenomenon, which was every- where showered with praise by the press. If the ebb was latent in 1967, it began before 1968, when the four musketeers endlessly took their distance from the structuralist phenomenon. There was another temporality, however, that was lessaffected by changes in inteIlectual fashion. University research continued to thrive even as the body was about to be buried. This research was like so many weIlsprings of a program that had lost in media glamour what it had gained in pedagogical effectiveness. Not that there was a single academic temporality, for there are always numerous lag times among the humanistic disciplines. For linguistics, sociology, anthropology, or psychoanalysis, for example, structuralism offered an adaptable scien- tific model. Other disciplines, which were better rooted in the univer- sity and better sheltered from epistemological turbulences, such as his- tory, would only be transformed la ter, and adopt the structuralist program at the moment when its wane was becoming general. Tempo- ral lags and disciplinary uncertainties in these inteIlectual exchange games notwithstanding, structuralism made many conversations pos- sible, multiplied the numbers of fruitful colloquia, generated much re- Introduction xxv and an interest in the work and progress related disciplines. This was an intense period enlivened by thinkers who were seeking, in the main, to harmonize their research and their lives. Our vision of the world is still shaped by this veritable revolution. Sorne caU ours the era of emptiness and others caU it postmodern; in either case it invites an approach to man in which a binary opposi- tion, every bit as iUusory, is played out between the human dissolution proferred by structura lis m, and in reaction, the divinization of man. Man the creator, beyond the constraints of his time, is a mirror image of the death of man. Humanity, the lost paradigm of the structural ap- proach, burst forth again in its narcissistic image of the era of the pre- social sciences. The great structural wave carried the social sciences toward shores on which historicity was a stranger. But we are at an important turning point, expressed as a return to an ancient form of writing in the name of a decline in thinking, a 105s of values, and a reliance upon our heritage. The old sawhorses are back: the discreet charms of a Vidalian landscape, the heroes of Lavissian history, the masterpieces of the national literary patrimony in Lagarde and Michard. Beyond this return to a very particular nineteenth century is a particular eighteenth-century vision of man perceived as an abstrac- tion, free from temporal constraints and master of the legal-political system bodying forth his rationalism. Can we, however, reflect upon man as if the Copernican-Galilean revolution, the Freudian and Marxist fractures, and the progress of the social sciences had not taken place? Pointing out the shortcomings of structura li sm does not imply returning to the golden age of the Enlightenment. To the contrary, it means moving forward toward a future in which a historical humanism can be established. It is impor- tant that the faise convierions and the true dogmatisms as weU as the reductionist and mechanistic procedures be clearly pointed out, and the validity of transversal concepts used across disciplines by the so- cial sciences questioned. Not in order to establish a catchaU procedure or a shapeless flow, but to wre5t from the Brownian motion the prole- gomena of a science of man wrought from a certain number of con- cepts and operational structuring levels. We caU upon the advances made in the social sciences to answer to the emergence of a humanism of the possible, perhaps around the transitory figure of a dialogic man. Moving beyond structuralism re- quires returning to it in order to examine the method that was broadly xxvi Introduction adopted by all the social sciences, sketching out the stages of its hege- monie conquest, valorizing the processes that made it possible for a single method to be adopted by the many humanistic disciplines, and understanding the limits and impasses in which the vitality of this at- tempted renewal waned. In order to give an account of this French intellectual chapter of the fifties and sixties, we have asked authors and disciples to comment upon the major works of the period; members of other schools and supporters of other trends have also been asked to cast a critical eye upon these works. A great many interviews with philosophers, lin- guists, sociologists, historians, anthropologists, psychoanalysts, and economists have been incorporated into these pages, and they raise the question of structuralism's importance for their own work and re- search, and the ways of moving beyond it. This two-volume inquiry reveals the centrality of the structuralist phenomenon, despite and be- yond the diversity of viewpoints, and makes it possible to periodize. * That form of criticism that tries to go ever further in deconstruct- ing Western metaphysics and penetrating the fissure in the founda- tions of semiology, to empty out every signified and all meaning so that the pure Signifer can circulate more effectively, belongs to a mo- ment in the Western history of self-hate that we have left behind, thanks to a progressive reconciliation between the intelligentsia and democratic values. But it is not possible, in moving beyond a period denominated by the critical paradigm, to simply return to what pre- ceded. A return is nonetheless necessary in order to better understand this period whose contributions have irrevocably changed our under- standing of humankind. *This inquiry is organized in two volumes, corresponding to the two major phases of the structuralist adventure: the ascension (vol. 1, The Rising Sign, I945-I966), and the decline (vol. 2, The Sign Sets, I967-Present). Part 1 The Fifties: The Epie Epoeh One The Eclipse of a Star: Jean-Paul Sartre The law of tragedy requires a death before a new hero can come on- stage. The reign of structuralism required a death, therefore, and the death was that of the postwar intellectual tutelary figure, Jean-Paul Sartre. Since Liberation, Sartre had had an exceptional following as he brought philosophy to the streets. But from the streets, slowly, began to echo the persistent rumor of new themes. The rising generation would slowly but surely cast Sartre to the sidelines. Sartre experienced a series of interpersonal breaks during the de- cisive decade of what was later called the structuralist phenomenon, and these were as painful as they were dramatic for him. With the years, Sartre was increasingly isolated despite his undiminished popu- larity with the public. He was partly responsible for his painful eclipse because of his own desire to erase the years of his apoliticism and blindness. During the thirties and despite the rising horrors of Nazism, Sartre had remained true to the long-standing khgne 1 tradI- tion of remaining closed off from the world outside, of remaining deaf and dumb, inattentive and indifferent to the social struggles going on around him. His own personal history came back to poison him after the war, and he tried to compensate by closely allying himself with the French Communist Party (PCF) in 1952, at the height of the Cold War, a time when an entire generation of intellectuals was beginning to leave the party because of the ongoing revelations about Stalinism in the Soviet Union. The grand unit y that had reigned at the time of 3 4 The Eclipse of a Star: Sartre the Democratie Revolutionary Union that, on December 13, I948, saw Andr Breton, Albert Camus, David Rousset, Jean-Paul Sartre, and many other intellectuals 2 come together in the same con- cert hall (Salle Pleyel) around the theme "Internationalism of the Mind" fell apart. This was the beginning of a number of breaks for Sartre. Cold War disturbances were to affect the te am of Les Temps modernes and Sartre would pay dearly for "Don't let Billancourt despair!" 3 In 1953, in a bitter polemic, he let Claude Lefort, a linchpin in his editorial team, leave the review. 4 Two other important breaks followed. The first was with Camus and then Etiemble, and the second with Maurice Merleau-Ponty, one of Sartre's close st friends and one of the founding members of the editorial board of Les Temps modernes. The Sartre- Merleau-Ponty relationship had been so harmonious until that point that the two men "were even, briefly, practically interchangeable." 5 But in the summer of 1952, Merleau-Ponty left Les Temps modernes and shortly thereafter, in 1955, he published The Adventures of the Dialectic in which he denounced Sartre's ultra-Bolshevist tendencies. Other adventures were to unfold without Sartre, but the younger generation continued to be fascinated with him. Rgis Debray writes that "for many of us in my high school in the fifties, Being and Nothingness quickened our pulse."6 Yet Existentialism came under fire. The oratory joust pitting Sartre against Althusser at the cole Normale Suprieure (ENS) on the rue d'Ulm 7 in 1960, at which Jean Hyppolite, Georges Canguilhem, and Maurice Merleau-Ponty were in attendance, ended, according to Debray, who was preparing his phi- losophy agrgation 8 at the time, in favor of Louis Althusser. Despite his glory, Sartre came to represent outmoded values and to incarnate the disappointed hopes of the Liberation. This unshakable image would cling to him and he would be its first victim. The Sartrean star was eclipsed because of political issues, but it was also affected by what was beginning to take shape in the intellec- tuaI world. The rise of social sciences was forcing the issue of an insti- tutional existence, so there needed to be a middle ground between the traditional humanities, primarily literature, and the hard sciences. As a result, questions were being asked differently and Sartre, faithful to his position as a philosopher and absorbed in making up for his politi- cal past, was left behind. His status as philosopher had warranted thanks and recognition, but he remained a foreigner to the changes The Eclipse of a Star: Jean-Paul Sartre 5 taking place. If Sartre asked What 1s Literature? in I948, it was in order to dwell on the relationship between an author, the reasons for writing, and the public. The existence of literature and its singularity were givens for him. But by the end of the fifties, this assumption came under question and was contested. The collapse of the tutelary figure that Sartre incarnated created a moment of uncertainty and doubt regarding philosophers who turned to the ascending social sciences to sharpen their critical questioning. Sartrean man exists only by virtue of the intentionality of his con- scious mind; he is condemned to freedom because "existence precedes essence," and only alienation and bad faith clutter the paths of free- dom. Roland Barthes, for example, who defined himself as a Sartrean immediately following the war, progressively abandoned this philoso- phy in order to fully embark upon the structuralist adventure. Exis- tentialism, as a philosophy of subjectivity and of the subject, came under attack and the subject and conscience gave way to rules, codes, and structure. Jean Pouillon: The Man of the Middle Ground One figure symbolized both this evolution and an attempt to reconcile apparent contradictions: Jean Pouillon. He was Sartre's intimate friend and became the sole link between Les Temps modernes and L'Homme, which is to say between Sartre and Claude Lvi-Strauss. Jean Pouillon had met Sartre very early on, in I937, and the two men were to enjoy an untroubled friendship to the end, despite their differ- ent intellectual paths. Pouillon's career was unusual, to say the least. l had been a philosophy professor during the war and then, in I945, Sartre asked me: Do you like doing philosophy? l answered that l en- joyed clowning in front of a class but the problem was the home- work, which had to be corrected, and the low salary. So he told me to go and see a friend of his from Normale Suprieure who had dis- covered something that still exists, the analytic report of the Na- tional Assembly. Given the separation of powers, the legislature was particularly generous in approving the budget of its own administra- tion, which was better paid than were teachers and usually had six months' vacation a year. l took the test and at the same time l was doing what l wanted to be doing, writing for Les Temps modernes. It was doubtless because of that that Claude Lvi-Strauss asked me to join the team at L'Homme in 1960; l was not on a career path, l threatened no one, and no one was jealous of me. 9 6 The Eclipse of a Star: Jean-Paul Sartre At that point, Jean Pouillon knew nothing at aIl about ethnology. But when Tristes Tropiques was published in I9 5 5, Sartre liked the book and asked Pouillon, as a member of the editorial board of Les Temps modernes, to review it. "Why not you?" But rather than sim- ply writing up a review acclaiming the book, Pouillon decided to take things a step further and undertook an in-depth study of the evolution of Claude Lvi-Strauss's thinking, and not just of its culmination in Tristes Tropiques. He therefore read everything that Lvi-Strauss had published, including The Elementary Structures of Kinship and the ar- ticles that were to be published in I958 as Structural Anthropology. More than a simple inventory, Pouillon tried to evaluate Lvi-Strauss's work and, in I956, he published his article in Les Temps modernes entitled "L'uvre de Claude Lvi-Strauss."l0 What had at first seemed to be a gratuitous detour or exotic ad- venture in foreign climes became, for Pouillon and for an entire genera- tion, a lifelong engagement, an existence turned toward new and more anthropological questions, and an abandonment of classical philoso- phy. Pouillon discovered the investigation of alterity: "It is as essen- tially other that the other must be seen."11 He joined in the structural- ist enterprise, which goes beyond empiricism, description, and lived For Pouillon, Claude Lvi-Strauss provided a rigorous model allowing the logical construction of "mathematizable relation- ships."12 Pouillon completely supported Lvi-Strauss's priority of the linguistic model in order to move beyond the scoria of the narrow relationship between observer and observed: "Durkheim used to say that social facts had to be treated like things .... To paraphrase Durkheim, therefore, we must treat them like words."13 In the mid-fifties, then, we witness a veritable conversion, with this small reservation that Jean Pouillon adopted Claude Lefort's ar- guments regarding Lvi-Strauss's relegation of historicity to a sec- ondary position. Here he remained faithful to Sartre's positions on the historical dialectic, opposing the diachronic logic of a bridge game to the synchronic logic of a chess game. But his double allegiance to structuralism and to anthropology was absolute, and from this point on Jean Pouillon attended Claude Lvi-Strauss's seminars at the Fifth Section of the cole Pratique des Hautes tudes. 14 A book review led to a choice about existence and Jean Pouillon could not resist the calI of the tropics. He obtained sorne funding and, on the advice of Robert The of a Star: Jean-Paul Sartre who described Chad as an as yet unexplored territory the ethnologist, he left in 1958. Was Sartre aware that he was undermining himself? Absolutely not, according to Pouillon. Sartre was wrong about the import of Tristes Tropiques, which he had liked because it valorized the ob- server's presence in the observation and the communication estab- lished with members of the indigenous population. 15 Pouillon's greater sensitivity to an ethnology that was more encompassing than explanatory led to his conversion. As he himself put it so well, this was an example of the "fecundity of misunderstandings." ln Chad, Pouillon studied seven or eight groups of a maximum of ten thousand members each, identifying an ever-varying organization of political and religious roles. By contrast, however, "the vocabulary, the lexicon was always the same, identical."16 ln order to understand the se differ- ences, it was necessary to have recourse to a structure not as it was concretized in the daily life of this or that group, but as it offered the possibility of permutations, like the logic of a grammar that lets us fa thorn different possible expressions. ln 1960, when the first volume of Critique of Dialectical Reason was published, Claude Lvi-Strauss invited Jean Pouillon to give a presentation in his seminar. Pouillon was the best specialist on Sartre's thinking, and he devoted three two-hour-Iong lectures to a reading of this work. Typically, the se lectures attracted no more than about thirty people, but on this occasion they were transformed into a "dense crowd invading the lecture hall, and among whom 1 saw people like Lucien Goldmann," 17 which gives sorne idea of how much interest Sartre continued to exert. If Jean Pouillon tried to reconcile Sartre and Lvi-Strauss, he was undoubtedly disappointed by the pub- lication, at the end of 1962, of Lvi-Strauss's response to Critique of Dialectical Reason. His attack at the end of The Savage Mind, and to which we will come back, was violent, but Pouillon was not disco ur- aged and in 1966 he compared the two books in L'Arc, arguing that they were complementary but incommensurable. He still maintains this position today. "It is pleasant to read one or the other of these works without any visual interference: when one is present, the other one is not." 18 If Jean Pouillon was converted to the promising human science of anthropology, Sartre remained quirc distant from the many challenges of the different social sciences. As a philosopher of consciousness, of 8 The of Star: Sartre the subject, considered linguistics to be a min or science and avoided it practically systematically. Psychoanalysis does not square weIl with Sartre's theory of bad faith and of individual freedom, and in Being and Nothingness he considered Freud to be the instigator of a mechanistic doctrine. But Sartre was forced to enter the Freudian labyrinth altogether by accident. In 1958, John Huston asked him to write a screenplay on Freud. This order from Hollywood meant that Sartre had to read aIl of Freud's work, as weIl as his correspondence. On December 15, 1958, Sartre sent Huston a ninety-five-page synop- sis, and a year later he fini shed the screenplay. But the two men ar- gued; Huston found the screenplay long and boring and wanted Sartre to trim it. Sartre lengthened it instead, and ended up withdrawing his name from the film credits of Freud, passion secrte. Sartre therdore knew Freud's work by the end of the fifties, but if psychoanalysis came to interest him little by little, he remained closed to its central tenet of the unconscious. Sartre continued to support the idea that humans can be entirely understood through their praxis, as he tried to demon- .strate in his unfinished work on Flaubert. It was clearly not possible to bring together "these two cannibals"19-Sartre and Claude Lvi- Strauss-without running the risk that one would devour the other. For want of a place, history allowed a man, Jean Pouillon, to thwart any effort at anthropophagia. The Cri sis of the Militant Intellectual Sartre was challenged on a third front as weIl for his notion of the en- gaged intellectual, which belongs to a French tradition going back to the Dreyfus Affair. Sartre embodied the tradition quite magnificently until such time as the intelIectual was no longer alIowed to give an opinion in every realm and was forced to limit remarks to his or her are a of expertise. The intellectual's critical enterprise became increas- ingly limited and confined to specifie events, but it gained in perti- nence what it lost in freedom of intervention. This retreat in the name of rationality also corresponded to a disinvestment, and even a re- fusaI, of history in the large sense. "Structuralism appeared ten years after the end of the war, but the war had ldt us in a frozen world. Nineteen forty-eight threatened another outbreak, the two blocs faced off, the one crying Liberty and the other crying Equality. AlI of this contributed to a denegation of history. "20 Two important structuralist figures clearly expressed this with- The Eclipse of a Star: Jean-Paul Sartre 9 drawal from Sartrean engagement: Georges Dumzil and Claude Lvi- Strauss. When asked if he ever felt any sympathy for the tradition of the committed intellectual, Georges Dumzil answered, "No, 1 even felt a sort of revulsion for those who played this role, and for Sartre in particular. "21 This disengagement cornes from a fundamentally reac- tionary approach that no longer holds out any hope for the future and considers the world with incurable nostalgia for the most distant pasto "It seemed, and continues to seem, to me preferable that not just a monarchie principle but a dynastie principle preserve the country's highest position from caprice and ambition, rather than to live with general elections, as we have done since the Revolution and Bona- parte. "22 We see this same hesitation in Claude Lvi-Strauss before he takes any position on current events or takes sides. To the same ques- tion regarding commitment, Lvi-Strauss answered, "No, 1 consider that my intellectual authority, insofar as 1 am considered to have any, rests on my work, on my scruples of rigor and precision."23 And he contrasts a Victor Hugo, who could imagine himself able to solve his epoch's problems, to our own period with problems that are too complex and diverse for any single man to be able to find his bearings and be committed. The figure of the philosopher as the questioning subject who problematizes the world in its diversity faded, and Sartre along with it. The classifying and often determinist social sciences had free range. Two The Birth of a Hero: Claude Lvi-Strauss Structuralism quickly became identified with one man: Claude Lvi- Strauss. In an era in which the division of intellectuallabor limited a researcher to increasingly fragmented knowledge, Lvi-Strauss sought to balance the material and the intelligible. Torn between a desire to restore the internaI logic of material reality and a poetic sensibility that strongly tied him to the natural world, Lvi-Strauss forged impor- tant intellectual syntheses in much the same way as one writes musical scores. Born in 1908, Lvi-Strauss was constantly exposed to artistic creation in his family milieu: a violinist great-grandfather, a father and uncles who were painters. As an adolescent living in the city, he spent aIl his free time in antique stores and only discovered the intense plea- sure of exotic nature when his parents bought a house in the moun- tains in the Cvennes, in southeast France. There, he regularly wan- dered the countryside for ten to fifteen hours a day. Art and nature were his two passions and they marked him as he straddled two worlds: his thinking broke with precedents, yet his work remained fundamentally aesthetic in its ambitions. Lvi-Strauss rejected the spell of his own sensibility, and, without renouncing it, sought to con- tain it by constructing broad logical systems. His unwavering attach- ment to his initial structural program is apparent here, despite the changes in style. From the time he was quite young, Lvi-Strauss was also inter- ID The Birth of a Hero: Claude Lvi-Strauss II ested in social issues. As soon as he was in high school, he joined the socialist movement. At seventeen, thanks to Arthur Wanters, a young Belgian socialist who had been invited to the family home one sum- mer, Lvi-Strauss read Marx. "Marx immediately fascinated me .... 1 very soon read Capital."l But it was especially in khgne, in the socialist studies group and under Georges Lefranc's influence, that Lvi-Strauss acquired a solid basis for his political involvement. He was increasingly vocal, giving lectures and speaking publicly so often that in 1928 he was elected secretary-general of the Federation of Socialist Students. During the same period, he became secretary to Georges Monnet, a socialist deputy, but had to give up these time- consuming responsibilities two years later in order to prepare his agr- gation in philosophy, about which he was lackluster. His professors- Lon Brunschvicg, Albert Rivaud, Jean Laporte, Louis Brhier-were fundamentally unsatisfying. "1 went through that period a bit like a zombie."2 He nonetheless passed his exams brilliantly in 1930, third in his class. Lvi-Strauss's socialist engagement quickly came to an end be- cause of a minor accident, and a much-awaited letter that never ar- rived. Although he was a pacifist, the trauma of the French defeat at the beginning of the "drle de guerre," as Marc Bloch called it, quickly ended his political involvement. He concluded that it was dan- gerous "to enclose political realities within the framework of formaI ideas."3 Lvi-Strauss never recovered from this disappointment and never again became politically involved in any way, even if, beyond what he espoused, his position as an ethnologist had a political dimen- sion to it. But this turning point was important: rather than 100 king ahead to the world to come, Lvi-Strauss turned, nostalgically, to the pa st at the risk of appearing anachronistic and out of step like his childhood idol, Don Quixote. The CalI of the Sea Lvi-Strauss's career as an ethnologist began, he tells his reader in Tristes Tropiques, one autumn Sunday in 1934 when Clestin Bougl, director of the cole Normale Suprieure called him up to propose that he apply for the sociology professorship at the University of So Paulo. Clestin Bougl naively thought that the outskirts of So Paulo were filled with Indians and suggested that Lvi-Strauss spend his weekends there. So Lvi-Strauss left for Brazil, not in se arch of exoti- I2 The Birth of a Hero: Claude Lvi-Strauss cism hate traveling and explorers")4 but to abandon speculative philosophy and be definitively converted ta this new and as yet very marginal discipline, anthropology. He had already seen one example of such a conversion in Jacques Soustelle. When he returned, Lvi- Strauss organized an exhibit in Paris of what he had been able to col- lect during his two years there and was granted enough money to organize an expedition to the Nambikwara. His work began to be noticed by a small circle of specialists, particularly Robert Lowie and Alfred Mtraux. He was forced to leave France in 1939 and seek refuge from the German occupation. Invited to New York by the New School for Social Research as part of an immense plan to save Euro- pean scholars organized by the Rockefeller Foundation, Lvi-Strauss crossed the Atlantic on the Captain Paul-Lemerle, a ship of hope on which he was accompanied by what the police considered rabble: Andr Breton, Victor Serge, Anna Seghers. At the New School in New York, he discovered that he had to change his name so as not to be confused with the blue jeans, Levi's. Henceforth he would be known as Claude L. Strauss: "Never a year goes by without an order for Levi's, usually from Africa." 5 Beyond these amusing problems, New York became the definitive site for working out a structural anthropology, thanks to a decisive meeting at the New School with a colleague in linguistics, Roman Jakobson. Jakobson, like Lvi-Strauss, was exile d, and taught courses in French on structural phonology. Their meeting proved to be particularly rich, intellectually as well as affectively, and the amicable collaboration that took hold from the beginning never faltered. Jakobson came to Lvi-Strauss's lectures on kinship and Lvi-Strauss attended Jakob- son's courses on sound and meaning: "His classes were dazzling."6 The symbiosis of their respective research gave birth to structural an- thropology. Moreover, it was Jakobson who, in 1943, advised Lvi- Strauss to begin writing the the sis that would became The Elementary Structures of Kinship. Back in France again in 1948, Lvi-Strauss took on sorne tempo- rary assignments as a researcher at the Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS), and then as assistant director of the Muse de l'Homme. He was finally elected, thanks to Georges Dumzil's influ- ence, to the chair of "Religions of Primitive Peoples" in the Fifth Section of the cole Pratique des Hautes tudes. He quickly changed the name of the chair after sorne discussions with black students to the chair for The Birth of a Hero: Claude Lvi-Strauss I3 "Religions of Peoples without Writing Systems." "People coming to talk with you at the Sorbonne could not be called uncivilized!"7 Scientiflc Ambitions Structural anthropology did not, however, burst forth spontaneously from an erudite mind. It was the product of the specific situation of a nascent anthropology, and, more broadly, of the rise of the concept of science in the realm of the study of societies. In this respect, and even if Lvi-Strauss did take his distance and innovate, structuralism fol- lowed on the positivist tradition of Auguste Comte and his scientism. Which is not to say that structuralism shared Comte's optimistic view of a history of humanity progressing by stages toward a positive age. But Comte's idea that knowledge is only interesting if it borrows from a scientific model or manages to transform itself into a science or a theory had made sorne headway: "In this respect, traditional philoso- phy is avoided,"8 which was characterististic of Lvi-Strauss's devel- opment. The other aspect of Comte's influence is his aspiration to- ward "holism,"9 his desire to totalize. Comte condemned psychology just as Lvi-Strauss would later. In sociology as it was taking shape at the beginning of the twentieth century, Durkheim inherited Comte's aspiration to totalize, limiting his object to the social sciences. Even if Lvi-Strauss was converted to ethnology and left for Brazil in revoIt against Durkheim, who did no fieldwork, he could not have escaped Durkheim's influence in the thirties. Raymond Boudon is right to say that "anthropologists took in a bit of holism along with their mother's milk."10 For Durkheim, just as for Auguste Comte, society is a whole that cannot be reduced to the sum of its parts. This would be the basis on which sociology would be constructed. The increasingly popular no.- tions of system and then of structure came to be tied to an ensemble of scientific changes in linguistics, economics, and biology at the turn of the century, particularly insofar as the se disciplines could explain the interdependence of elements constituting their specific objects. Lvi- Strauss, therefore, could not avoid setting himself in Durkheim's lin- eage. Did he not explicitly reiterate Franois Simiand's 1903 challenge to historians in 1949? And yet, Lvi-Strauss and Durkheim took com- pletely different paths. When he was writing The Ru/es of Method, Durkheim favored written sources, which are the historian's tools, and mistrusted information gathered by ethnographers. At the time, I4 The Birth of a Hero: Claude Lvi-Strauss historie al positivism was in full force and it was only later, around I9I2, that Durkheim placed history and ethnography on the same plane, a change in orientation hastened by the founding of L'Anne sociologique. Conversely, for Lvi-Strauss, who had begun his painstaking fieldwork in Brazil, observation preceded any logical con- struction or conceptualization. Ethnology is first and foremost an ethnography. "Anthropology is above all an empirical science .... Empirical study determines access to the structure."ll Observation is not an end in itself, certainly-and Lvi-Strauss crossed swords with empiricism-but it is a first, and indispensable stage. Against Functionalism and Empiricism Lvi-Strauss's first important object of study, the incest taboo, gave him the opportunity to distance himself from Durkheim's position on the same topic.1 2 Given an explanation relegating the incest taboo to an archaic mentality, to a fear of menstrual blood, to outmoded be- liefs, and therefore to a heterogeneous relationship to our modernity, Lvi-Strauss, who refused a definition limited to a single geographical area and temporal era, sought the atemporal, univers al roots of this interdiction that would shed sorne light on its permanence. Lvi- Strauss's intellectual forebears were Auguste Comte, mile Durkheim, and Marcel Mauss, but Marx's influence must not be forgotten. And, as we have already seen, his early and profound knowledge of Marx influenced his entire militant period; Marx was one of his "three mis- tresses,"13 along with Freud and geology. From Marx, Lvi-Strauss re- tained the principle that manifest realities are not the most significant but that the researcher must construct models allowing to reach be- yond material appearances and accede to the bases of reality: "Marx established that social science is no more founded on the basis of events than physics is founded on sense-data."14 Loyal to Marx, and strictly orthodox in his Mar;x:ism, Lvi- Strauss made it clear that he refused to occult the determining role of infrastructures, even if his intention was to construct a theory of superstructures. "We in no way intend to insinuate that ideological transformations engender social transformations. Only the reverse is true. "15 Of course, over the years this Marxist influence, along with the underlying dialogue with Engels, was to disappear com- pletely. But at the beginning in Brazil, Lvi-Strauss clearly seemed to present himself first of all as a Marxist. Apropos of this, he remarked The Birth of a Hero: Claude Lvi-Strauss IJ to Didier ribon that the Brazilians were disappointed to see a non- Durkheimian sociologist. What could anyone be at the time but a Durkheimian? "My bet is that he was a Marxist. He was on the road to becoming the official philosopher for the Section Franaise de l'Internationale Ouvrire.1 6 Clearly, something happened in Brazil that meant that what he was when he got there was not what he was later; it must have been his encounter with the field, but not only that."17 Confronted with anthropological terrain, Lvi-Strauss refused the only two possible directions for research in this domain: evolutionism or diffusionism, and functionalism. Of course he admired the quality of Malinowski's fieldwork, his studies of sexuallife in Melanasia and on the Argonauts, but he denounced his cult of empiricism as wellJls his functionalism: "But the idea that empirical observation of a single society will make it possible to understand universal motivations ap- pears continually in his writings, weakening the significance of data whose vividness and richness are well known. "18 ln Lvi-Strauss's eyes, Malinowski's functionalism fell into the trap of discontinuity, of singularity. Spcial structures and visible social relations were confused and the analysis therefore remained superficial, missing what is essen- tial in social phenomena. With respect to the incest taboo, Mali- nowski never got beyond biological considerations of the incompati- bility of parental feelings and love relationships. Slightly closer to a structuralist approach, Radcliffe-Brown had already used the idea of social structure in his study of Australian kinship systems, seeking a systematic way of classifying each system, and then of making valid generalizations for all human societies. "The analysis seeks to reduce diversity (from two or three hundred kinship systems) to a single order, whatever it might be."19 But Lvi-Strauss considered Radcliffe- Brown's methodology too descriptive and empirical, and it shared with Malinowski a functionalist interpretation that goes no deeper than the surface of social systems. Leaving Anglo-Saxon empiricism behind, Lvi-Strauss found his masters in anthropology among those descendants of the German his- torical school who had left history, proponents of cultural relativism: Lowie, Kroeber, and Boas, "authors to whom 1 willingly proclaim my debt."20 ln Robert H. Lowie he saw the initiator who, as early as 1915, opened the promising path to the study of kinship systems. "The very substance of social life can sometimes be rigorously ana,- I6 The Birth of a Hero: Claude Lvi-Strauss lyzed as a function of the mode of classification of parents and allies."21 After arriving in New York, Lvi-Strauss immediately sought out Franz Boas, who at the time dominated American anthropology and whose range of interests and study was limitless. Lvi-Strauss was even present at the death of the great master during a lunch given by Boas in honor of Rivet's visit to Columbia University. "Boas was very gay. In the middle of the conversation, he violently pushed himself away from the table and fell backward. 1 was sitting next to him and rushed over to lift him up. Boas was dead. "22 Boas's major contri- bution and his influence on Lvi-Strauss were to underscore the un- conscious nature of cultural phenomena and to have considered that the laws of language were central for understanding this unconscious structure. Here was the linguistic thrust coming from anthropology as of 19II, and it was auspicious for the fruitful meeting between Lvi- Strauss and Jakobson. Importing the Linguistic Model Lvi-Strauss innovated in the true sense of the word here, by import- ing the linguistic model into anthropology, which had been linked in France until then with the natural sciences: physical anthropology had dominated during the entire nineteenth century. Lvi-Strauss had easy access to these models of natural science. Back in France again in 1948, he became associate director of the Muse de l'Homme. But this was not the approach that he took. He looked, rather, for a model of scientificity in the social sciences, and in particular in lin- guistics. Why this detour, which proved to be fundamental? "1 have my own little answer, which 1 will give you. Biological, physical an- thropology had been so compromised by aH kinds of racism that it was difficult to borrow from this discipline in order to establish the mirage of a kind of general science, a general anthropology integrat- ing the physical as weIl as the cultural. The historical liquidation of physical anthropology had made theoretical debate unnecessary. Claude Lvi-Strauss arrived on the spot that history had prepared for him."23 The break that Lvi-Strauss represented was aIl the more spectac- ular given the general prevalence of the naturalist and biologist rela- tionship in French anthropology. Anthropology designated the search for man's natural foundations, and it was based on an essentially bio- The Birth of a Hero: Claude Lvi-Strauss I7 logical determinism. The war had swept things clean, however, and Lvi-Strauss could reappropriate the term "anthropology" without any ideological risk. He therefore raised French anthropology to the rank of a semantic field of Anglo-Saxon anthroplogy by establishing it on the pilot discipline of linguistics. 24 Three Where Nature and Culture Meet: Incest Back in France in 1948, Claude Lvi-Strauss defended his thesis, The Elementary Structures of Kinship and his complementary thesis, The Social and Family Life of the Nambikwara, before a jury composed of Georges Davy, Marcel Griaule, mile Benveniste, Albert Bayet, and Jean Escarra. The publication of his the sis the following year was one of the major events of postwar intellectual history and a touchstone for the founding of the structuralist program.1 FQ!!y_ years l a t ~ r , . an- thropologists continue to consider this event as an advent. "What seems most important and most fundamental to me is The Elementary Structures of Kinship, by the will to scientificity it introduced in the analysis of social multiplicity, by its que st for the most encompassing model to account for phenomena that do not appear, initially, to be part of the same categories of analysis, and by the transition from the question of filiation to one of alliance."2 The French school of anthropology experienced a veritable episte- mological revolution with the publication of Lvi-Strauss's thesis; other groups, including, of course, philosophers, were also dazzled. Olivier Revault d'Allonnes, a young agrg in philosophy, was one of these: "This was an important, decisive moment. 1 had just been as- signed to the high school in Lille after my agrgation in philosophy in 1948, and it was fundamentally enlightening. At the time, 1 saw a con- firmation of Marx in The Elementary Structures of Kinship."3 The shock waves extended beyond the small circle of anthropologists and IB Where Nature and Culture Meet: Incest 19 continued to have their eHeet. Ten years after its publication, a young normalien discovered The Elementary Structures of Kinship with equal dazzlement as soon as he got to the cole Normale Suprieure in 1957. Emmanuel Terray was a philosopher who was already attracted to anthropology and who needed ta leave a France fully embroiled in a colonial war that he condemned and against which he militated. At the time, his friend Alain Badiou lent him The Elementary Structures of Kinship because it was difficult to find. "Alain lent me the book and 1 copied one hundred pages from it by hand, which 1 still have. And wh en 1 finished copying the pages, given the effort it had taken, Alain could not but give me the book. That is how 1 have the first edi- tion. For me, at the time, and 1 still hold this opinion, the progress this book reprsented was comparable, in its field, to Marx's Capital or to Freud's Interpretation of Dreams."4 Once again, our young philoso- pher was seduced by giving some or der to an area where apparently total incoherence and total empiricism reigned. His admiration con- firmed his choice of career and a way of life in anthropology. The Universal Constant ln search of constants that would take into account the univers ais of social practices, Lvi-Strauss found the incest taboo, which remains unchanged beyond the diversity of human societies. He made a funda- mental shift in the traditional approach, which usually considered in- cest in terms of moral interdictions without taking its social positivity into account. Lewis Henry Morgan, for example, saw the incest taboo as the species' means of protecting itself against the baneful effects of intermarriage. For Edward Westermarck, the incest taboo could be ex- plained by the wearing effects of daily routine on sexual desire, a thesis completely refuted by Freud's oedipal the ory. The Lvi-Straussian revo- lution consisted in debiologizing the phenomenon and removing it. from the simple structure of consanguinity and from ethnocentric moral considerations. The structuralist hypothesis effected a shift here thanks to which the taboo's char acter of transaction, or communica- tion established by matrimonial alliances, was reasserted. Lvi-Strauss considered kinship to be the principal basis for social reproduction. ln order not to get lost in the labyrinth of the multitude of matri- monial practices, Lvi-Strauss made a reduction, in the mathematical sense of the term, by defining a limited numbei of possibilities as ele- mentary kinship structures: "Elementary structures of kinship are ... 20 Where Nature and Culture Meet: Incest those systems which prescribe marriage with a certain type of relative or, alternatively, those systems which, while defining aIl members of the society as relatives, divide them into two categories, viz. possible spouses and prohibited spouses."5 Based on a nomenclature, these ele- mentary structures allow the circle of relatives and that of relations by marriage, to be determined. Thus, in this type of structure, marriages between sisters, brothers, and first cousins are proscribed whereas marriages between cousins by marriage, and sometimes more specifi- cally between crossed matrilinear cousins, are prescribed. Societies are therefore divided into two groups: the group of possible spouses and that of prohibited spouses. This same system is found among the Aus- tralians in the kariera system and the aranda system studied by Lvi- Strauss. In the kariera system, the tribe is divided into two local groups, each of which is subdivided into two sections; membership in local groups is transmitted patrilineally, but the son belongs to the other section. There is, therefore, first a generational alternation and a marri age system established by the female bilateral crossed cousin (the cousin is bilateral because she is both the daughter of the father's sister and of the mother's brother). The aranda system is similar, but in matrimonial groups. Here Lvi-Strauss groups symmetrical marriages together as restricted exchanges as opposed to other systems, which are also elementary but have an indefinite number of groups and uni- lateral marriages, in which case there are generalized exchanges: "Whereas a bilateral marriage system can function with two lines of descendants, at least three are necessary for a system of unilateral al- lianceto operate. If A takes ms wives from B, he must give his wives to a third line, C, which can later give its wives to B, closing the circle."6 Unlike those elementary kinship systems that try to keep the marriage within the family framework, other, semicomplex structures, such as the Crow-Omaha systems, seek to make marriage and family links in- compatible. In this case, one cannot marry into a clan that has, for as long as can be remembered, already given a spouse to one's own clan. Lvi-Strauss abandoned an analysis made in terms of filiation or blood ties in order to demonstrate that the joining of the sexes is the of a socially regulated transaction: the transaction is a 'social _ cultural fct. Prohibition is no longer therefore perceived as a purely negative fact, but, on the contrary, as a positive fact engender- ing social links. The kinship system can be analyzed as part of an arbi- trary system of representation, much like Saussure's arbitrary sign. Where Nature and Culture Meet: Incest ZI By breaking with the naturalism surrounding the notion of the in- cest taboo, and by making it the reference for the passage from nature to culture, Lvi-Strauss brought about a major shift. social order is born of the organization of an exchange around the incest taboo, which therefore becomes a founding element: "Considered from the most general viewpoint, the prohibition of incest expresses the transi- tion from the natural fact of consanguinity to the cultural fact of al- liance."7 The incest taboo is the decisive intervention in the birth of the social order. Because of its centrality and its aspect as a basic prin- ciple, it cannot be considered to be only a part of the natural order, even if it shares a universal and spontaneous quality, nor only a part of the cultural order, characterized by norms, specific laws, and a re- strictive quality. The incest taboo belongs to both realms at once; it is the meeting point between nature and culture, the indispensable arbi- trary rule that man substitutes for the natural order. There are specific rules in the incest taboo, as weIl as a normative code (culture) and a univers al character (nature). "The incest prohibition is at once on the threshold of culture, in culture and, in one sense, as we shall try to show, culture itself."8 Fundamental structures resulting from this in- terdiction are not to be considered as natural facts that can be ob- served, but as "a grid for deciphering or, in Kantian terms, a design in which aIl the terms or aIl the aspects need not be present for it to oper- ate smoothly."9 With this exemplary study, freed anthro- pology from the nat!l:.ral sciences and placed it immediately and exclu- sively on cultural grounds. Meeting Jakobson The model making this shift possible for Lvi-Strauss was drawn from structural linguistics. In this respect, the birth and developments in phonology created an upheaval in the thinking in the social sciences. For Lvi-Strauss himself, borrowing the model represented a veritable Copernican-Galilean revolution. "Phonology cannot help but play the same renovative role with respect to the social sciences that nuclear physics, for example, has played for aIl of the hard sciences."l0 The growing successes of the phonological method proved the existence of an effective system from which anthropology should draw sorne basic principles in order to apply them to the complex social domain. Lvi- Strauss therefore adopted its founding paradigms, virtually on a term for term basis. Phonology sought to go beyond the stages of conscious 22 Where Nature and Culture Meer: Incest Considering the specificity terms was not enough; the goal was to understand them in their interrelationships, and phonology therefore introduces the notion of system in an effort to construct generallaws. The entire structuralist method is embodied in this project. Lvi-Strauss's exchanges in New York with Roman Jakobson were clearly the source of this contribution. "At that time, 1 was a kind of naive structuralist. 1 was doing structuralism without even knowing it. Jakobson showed me the corpus of a doctrine that had al- ready been constituted in linguistics, and that 1 had never studied. It was an illumination for me."ll Lvi-Strauss did not limit himself to adding a new realm of knowledge to his expertise, however, but incor- porated it into his method and, as a result, his general perspective was fundamentaIly changed. "Like phonemes, kinship terms are elements of meaning; like phonemes, they acquire meaning only if they are inte- grated into systems."12 Lvi-Strauss attended Jakobson's classes in New York, and wrote a preface for their publication in 1976.13 The two important lessons Lvi-Strauss retained for anthropology were, on the one hand, the search for constants beyond the multitude of identifiable variations, and, on the other, avoiding aIl recourse to the consciousness of a speaking subject, whence the prevalence of the structure's u n c o n s c i o u ~ phenomena. For him, these two princip les held as much for phonetics as for anthropology. The two disciplines, however, do not for aIl that lose touch with concrete reality by favor- ing a systematic formalism. Invoking the Russian phonologist Nicolai Trubetzkoy, Lvi-Strauss remarks: "Current phonology does not limit itself to declaring that phonemes are always elements of a system, it shows concrete phonological systems and brings their structure to the fore."14 The structural anthropologist must therefore foIlow the lin- gui st along a path established by structurallinguistics, which has re- jected a diachronic explanation of linguistic evolution in favor of identifying the differential variations between languages. Breaking down the complex materials of a language into a limited number of phonemes is supposed to help the anthropologist in his approach to the systems at work in primitive societies; he must deconstruct in the same fashion, reduce observable reality by being attentive to a number of variables, which are also limited. This would be the case for matri- monial systems organized around the relationship between the law of filiation and that of residence, a relationship every bit as arbitrary as Where Nature and Culture Meet: Incest the Saussurean sign. as his Lvi- Strauss made the Saussurean break his own. While Lvi-Strauss reiterated Saussure's most famous distinction between signifier and signifie d, he adapted it to his own field. Saussure opposed sound and meaning, but for Lvi-Strauss structure became the signifier and meaning the signified. While the model was modified in this respect, when it came to the linguistic perspective on the rela- tionship between synchrony and diachrony, Lvi-Strauss adhered to Saussure's priority of synchrony. This move bore within it the future polemics against history. Having adopted the phonological model, "Claude Lvi-Strauss began the critique of the efficacy of a historical approach, or of consciousness, for a scientific expIa nation of social phenomena." 15 Fascinated by the success of their model, Lvi-Strauss joined the linguists: We should like to learn from the linguists how they succeeded in doing it, how we may ourselves in our own field, which is a complex one-in the field of kinship, in the field of social orgahization, in the field of religion, folklore, art, and the like-use the same kind of rig- oro us approach which has proved to be so successful for linguistics. 16 But to imagine that the anthropologist would simply give up, once he found his master in the linguist, is to not know Lvi-Strauss. On the contrary, his gesture must be seen in a comprehensive perspective inte- grating linguistics into a more general scheme in which the anthropol- ogist would be the prime mover. Interpreting social structures would be the product of a three-tiered "theory of communication":17 the communication of women between groups, thanks to kinship rules, the communication of goods and services, thanks to economic rules, and the communication of messages, thanks to linguistic rules. These three levels were incorporated into Lvi-Strauss's comprehensive an- thropological project in which the analogy between the two methods remained a constant. "The kinship system is a language."18 "If a sub- stantial identity were assumed to exist between language structure and kinship systems, one should find, in the following regions of the world, languages whose structures would be of a type comparable to kinship systems. "19 Lvi-Strauss thereby elevated linguistics to the rank of a pilot science, of an initial model, basing anthropology on the cultural and social, rather than on the physical. Thanks to Jakobson, 24 Where Nature and Culture Meet: Incest Lvi-Strauss understood this strategie role very early on, and we must therefore disagree with Jean Pouillon's reductive evaluation of the im- portance of linguistics for Lvi-Strauss as the simple idea that "mean- ing is always positional meaning. "20 The two major thrusts of the structuralist paradigm are present as early as The Elementary Struc- tures of Kinship, and come from linguistics and mathematics, the for- malized language by definition. Lvi-Strauss benefited from the ser- vices of structural mathematics of the Bourbaki group thanks to a meeting with Simone Weil's brother, Andr Weil, who wrote the math- ematical appendix to the book. In this mathematical transcription of his discoveries, Lvi-Strauss found the continuation of a displacement that was analogous to a shift made by Jakobson: from an attention to the terms of a relationship ta the importance of the relationships themselves between these terms, independent of their content. This double fecundity, rigor, and scientificity, brought to the soft belly of a social science still in its' infancy, could only nourish the dream of having at last reached the final stage of a scientificity equal to that of the hard sciences. "We give the impression that the social sciences will become full-fledged sciences like Newtonian physics. There is that in Claude Lvi-Strauss .... Scientism becomes credible because linguistics seems like something scientific in the sense of the natural sciences .... This is basically the key to success. "21 A fertile path, certainly, but also the key to the dreams and illusions that, for twenty years, hung over the community of researchers in the social sciences. A Resounding Event The publication of The Elementary Structures of Kinship had an im- mediate resounding effect. Simone de Beauvoir took up her pen to re- view it in Les Temps modernes, whose wide readership of intellectu- aIs, in the broadest sense, could immediately make the voluminous thesis well known beyond the limited circle of anthropologists with- out anyone having to read it. Jean Pouillon, for example, only read Lvi-Strauss when Tristes Tropiques was published. It was paradoxi- cal that this highly structuralist work be first noticed by a review that was the organ of expression of Sartrean existentialism. Simone de Beauvoir, who was the same age as Lvi-Strauss and had known him since just before the war from their agrgation teacher-training class, was in the process of finishing The Second Sex. Where Nature and Culture Meet: lncest 25 Simone de Beauvoir had heard from Michel Leiris that Lvi- Strauss was going to publish his thesis on kinship systems. Interested in the anthropological point of view on the question, de Beauvoir asked Leiris to contact Lvi-Strauss on her behalf and ask him to send her the proofs, before finishing her own book. "To thank Claude Lvi- Strauss, she therefore wrote a long review in Les Temps modernes. "22 The article was particularly positive about the value of Lvi-Strauss's theses. "French sociology had been dormant for quite sorne time, until now."23 De Beauvoir agreed with Lvi-Strauss's methods and conclu- sions, and encouraged readers to read him, but at the same time she drew his w o r ~ into the Sartre an purview by giving it an existentialist thrust; clearly she had misread or was trying to co-opt Lvi-Strauss. Remarking that Lvi-Strauss did not say where the structures whose logic he described come from, she gave her own, Sartrean answer: "Lvi-Strauss did not allow himself to venture onto philos op hic al grounds, and he never gives up his rigorous scientific objectivity; but his thinking is clearly inscribed within a broad humanism according to which human existence brings its own justification with it. "24 In early I95I, and once aga in in Les Temps modernes, which con- tributed considerably to the renown of Lvi-Strauss's work, Claude Lefort wrote an article in which he criticized Lvi-Strauss for setting the meaning of experience outside experience itself and giving priority to a mathematical mode! presented as more real than reality. "We would reproach Mr. Lvi-Strauss for perceiving rules rather than be- havior in society."25 In I956, Jean Pouillon answered Lefort's criti- cism, which he considered unfounded, when he was preparing an arti- cle on Lvi-Strauss's work. For Pouillon, Lvi-Strauss neither confused reality with its mathematical expression nor differentiated between them in order to give priority to the second. The mode! was not ontol- ogized since "this mathematical expression of reality is never confused with reality. "26 In the mid-fifties, there was broad support for the structura li st method, but it soon drew criticism from the Anglo-Saxon and French sides when the paradigm became vulnerable, particularly in May I968. Four Ask for the Program: The Mauss Where Lvi-Strauss focused on kinship, a specifically anthropological concern, in The Elementary Structures of Kinship, his Introduction ta the Work of Marcel Mauss (1950) was different. 1 Rather than simply presenting the work of one of the Durkheimian masters of French an- thropology, he used the preface to define his own structuralist pro- gram, and to present a rigorous methodology. Oddly enough, what ini- tially appeared as a modest and ritual preface became something of moment: the first definition of a unified program proposed for aIl the social sciences since the beginning of the nineteenth century, when Destutt de Tracy and the ideologues had attempted to define a vast sci- ence of ideas, a project left unfinished. Another surprising fact was that Georges Gurvitch, a sociologist who la ter became quite hostile toward Lvi-Strauss's theses, had asked him to write this introduction for a collection that he had launched at the Presses Universitaires de France. Georges Gurvitch immediately understood the differences separat- ing him from Lvi-Strauss and he added a postscript to express his reservations, qualifying Lvi-Strauss's interpretation as a very particu- lar reading of Mauss's work. "Things began to sour at that point."2 Algirdas Julien Greimas was right about the importance of this text. In Alexandria at the time, and hungry for inteIlectual nourishment, he had come upon the Introduction ta the Work of Marcel Mauss, which, along with other works, encouraged him in his project of forg- ing a comprehensive methodology for the social sciences. "Perhaps it 26 Ask for the Program: The Mauss 27 was at that point, if books count, that one was going to play the most important role. Structuralism, after aIl, is the encounter between lin- guistics and anthropology."3 Lvi-Strauss relied, therefore, on Marcel Mauss's authority to ground anthropology theoreticaIly and thus open theory up to a model able to account for the meaning of facts observed in the field. Whence the use made of linguistics, presented as the best me ans to make the concept adequate to its object. Lvi-Strauss initiaIly had a position similar to that of modern linguistics: there are only con- structed facts in anthroplogy and the natural sciences. Linguistics therefore became a tool that could lead anthropology toward culture, and the symbolic, by etiminating its old naturalist or energist models. Here again, Lvi-Strauss drew attention to himself with this methodo- logical program with respect to the French ethnological context, by distancing anthropology from technology, and from museums, and by orienting it toward a concept and toward theory. "Everything begins with the museum and everything returns to it. However, Lvi-Strauss leaves the museum in order to invent anthropology theoreticaIly."4 Lvi-Strauss saw Marcel Mauss as the spiritual father of struc- turalism. But, as with aIl choices, this one had an arbitrary and unfair quality about it, which Jean Jamin emphasized when he exhumed Robert Hertz from forgotten memory. Jamin considered that when it came to the archaeology of structuralism, Hertz more than Mauss was the founder of the structuralist paradigm. Robert Hertz died in I9I5, during the First World War, and left sorne texts that are, "to my min d, the founders of structuralism, so much so that the British ethnologist Needham devotes an entire book, Right and Left, to pay homage to Robert Hertz's memory." 5 In one of these texts, we do indeed find structural binarity. "Right-handed preeminence"6 is the discovery of the religious polarity between a sacred right and a sacred left. Robert Hertz demonstrated how lateralization, which may have a biological basis, has above aIl a symbolic basis opposing the pure and auspicious right to the impure and evil left. "This discovery became even more important than is generaIly thought, since Michel Leiris, Georges Bataille, and Roger Caillois would take up this polarization of the sa- cred again in the Collge de Sociologie."7 The Unconscious Lvi-Strauss, however, based himself on Mauss, emphasizing his "modernity."8 Mauss had understood and opened up anthropological 28 Ask for the Program: The Mauss inquiry to the other human sciences, and in doing so, had laid out a prolegomena for future rapprochements. Ethnology and psycho- analysis, for example, discovered a common object of analysis in the symbolic field, which included economic as well as kinship or reli- gious systems. Here again, Lvi-Strauss referred to Mauss who, in I924, defined sociallife as "a world of symbolic relationships."9 Lvi- Strauss carried on in the same vein, citing his own work in which he compared the shaman in a trance with a neurotic. lO Lvi-Strauss clearly aspired to what Mauss had expressed in The Gift ll_to study the total social facto Totality only exists, however, once things have moved beyond social atomism and it has become possible to incorpo- rate all the facts inta "an anthropology, that is, a system of interpre- tation accounting for the aspects of all modes of behavior simulta- neously, physical, physiological, psychical, and sociological."12 The human body is at the center of this totality, an apparent sign of nature but entirely cultural, in facto However, Mauss introduced "an archae- ology of body positions,"13 a program that Michel Foucault adopted and developed further. Lvi-Strauss stressed the overarching importance of the uncon- scious at the heart of the body; this position would become a principal characteristic of the structuralist paradigm. He understood Mauss's intention of giving it a fundamental importance. "So it is not surpris- ing that Mauss ... referred constantly to the unconscious as providing the common and specifie character of social facts. "14 However, it is only through the mediation of language that we can reach the uncon- scious. For this, Lvi-Strauss mobilized modern, Saussurean linguis- tics, which situates the facts of speech at the level of unconscious thought; "it is the same kind of operation which in psychoanalysis al- lows us to win back our most estranged self, and in ethnological in- quiry gives us access to the most foreign others as to another self."15 Lvi-Strauss established the fundamental alliance between two guid- ing sciences of the structuralist period, anthropology and psycho- analysis, both of which were based on linguistics, that other pilot sci- ence offering a veritable heuristic model. Another characteristic of this period, which Lvi-Strauss had al- ready expressed in this text-manifesto and which Jacques Lacan in particular developed, was to take up the Saussurean sign once again, but pushing it toward an emptying of the signified, or in any case di- minishing its importance with respect to the signifier. "Like language, Ask for the Program: The Mauss 29 the social is an autonomous same one, moreover); are more real than what they symbolise, the signifier precedes and determines the signified."16 The totalizing project was defined for ail the social sciences, which are summoned to create a vast semiological program whose driving force would come from anthropology as the only discipline able to synthesize the work of the others. Beyond Lvi- Strauss's definition of the prospect of interdisciplinarity, structural- ism's canonical the sis that the code precedes and is independent from the message, and that the subject is subjected to the signifier's law, was clear at this point. Indeed, it was the heart of the structural under- taking. "The definition of 'a code is to be translatable into another code. This property defines it and is ca lied structure." 17 The Debt to Marcel Mauss If Lvi-Strauss was a bit forced when he credited Marcel Mauss with being at the origin of his structuralist program, he nonetheless paid his debt this way, since Mauss was his principal source of inspiration for the central thesis of The Elementary Structures of Kinship. Mauss's The Gift was a model, in this respect, along with his the ory of reci- procity, which Lvi-Strauss extended and systematized in his work on kinship. The rule of reciprocity, and its triple obligation of giving, receiving, and returning, establish the economy of matrimonial ex- changes. The gift and countergift made it possible to see the network of connections, equivalences, and alliances extending beyond the ma- terial gift by virtue of the universality of its rules. The incest taboo be- came intelligible at this level, as did its universality, which made it a fundamental key for understanding ail societies. "The incest taboo, like exogamy, which is its extended social expansion, is a rule of reci- procity. The sole function of the incest taboo is not to forbid; it is set in place to ensure and found an exchange, directly or indirectly, imme- diately or not."18 Exchange, therefore, plays a central role in the phenomenon of the circulation of women in matrimonial alliances and constitutes a veritable structure of communication that enables groups to establish their relationship of reciprocity. It is not moral reprobation that makes incest illicit, nor a murmur of the heart, but the exchange value establishing a social relationship. Marrying one's sister made no sense to Margaret Mead's informants, the Arapesh, because it would me an depriving one self of a brother-in-Iaw, with whom one would go hunt- 30 Ask for the Program: The Mauss or "The of incest is it is morally culpable. "19 A new era with the The Gif t, which Lvi- Strauss, who absorbed aU of its lessons, compared to the discovery of combinatory analysis in modern mathematical thought. "The prohibi- tion of incest is Jess a rule prohibiting marriage with the mother, sister or daughter than a rule obliging the mother, sister or daughter to be given to others. It is the supreme rule of the gift."20 The Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss brilliantly restored an obvious fecundity and filiation. In addition to the Maussian point of view, Lvi-Strauss's program included phonology's decisive contributions-the work of Trubetzkoy and Jakobson, whose notions of secondary and combina- tory variations, group names, and neutralization made possible the necessary condensations of empirical mate rial. Lvi-Strauss clearly defined the structuralist pro gram here. "For me, structuralism is the theory of the symbolic in Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss: the independence of language and of kinship rules shows that the sym- bolic, the signifier, are autonomous. "21 A Form of Kantianism Lvi-Strauss left the philosopher's territory for other continents of knowledge, but Kantian philosophy has nonetheless left its mark, al- beit inexplicit, on the substructure of the structura li st program in its determination to tie all social systems to constituent categories that operate like noumenal categories. For Kant, thinking is controlled by these a priori categories, which are brought appropriately to bear in different societies. The spirit, however, remains present in each case. Lvi-Strauss borrowed this Kantianism more from phonology than from philosophy; in his definition of the symbolic value zero, he adopted Jakobson's definition of the zero phoneme term for term. For Jakobson, the zero phoneme resembles no other phoneme because it has no differential character and no constant phonetic value whose specifie function is to allow the presence of a phoneme. For Lvi- Strauss, the system of symbols defines any given cosmology. "It would simply be a symbolic value zero, a sign indicating that a symbolic con- tent, in addition to the one which the signifier already bears, is needed, but which can be any value. "22 Like Gurvitch, who considered that Lvi-Strauss's appropriation of Mauss's work deformed its truth, Claude Lefort, in his I951 article in Les Temps modernes, attacked The Elementary Structures of Kin- Ask for the Program: The Mauss 3 l ship and the Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss. He de- nounced the program's will to mathematize social relationships and the consequent loss of meaning implied by it. For Lefort, reducing so- cial phenomena to symbolic systems "seems foreign to his inspiration: Mauss aims at meaning, not at symbols; he wants to understand the immanent intention of behavior without leaving the realm of experi- ence, not to establish a logical order in which concrete reality is seen simply as appearances. "23 Lefort criticized the scientism underlying Lvi-Strauss's program, his belief in a deeper reality lying beneath mathematical reality. Underlying the term "unconscious," he also dis- cerned traces of Kantian idealism that basically meant transcendental consciousness in Kant's sense; expressions such as "unconscious cate- gory" or "category of collective thinking"24 reveal this. Lefort re- versed Lvi-Strauss's idealism by asserting that the empirical behavior of subjects cannot be deduced from a transcendental consciousness but, to the contrary, is established through experience. Both the proclamation of a program and Claude Lefort's critiques provided the rational kernel for all the debates and polemics that developed in the fifties and sixties around the structuralist banquet. Pive Georges Dumzil: An Independent On June 13, 1979, Georges Dumzil was received into the ranks of the Acadmie Franaise.! Welcomed into the Academy, he was invited ta give an overview of his work by none other th an Claude Lvi-Strauss. The choice was no accident, and resulted from their similar, if obvi- ously distinctive, projects. Dumzil, of course, had always been mis- trustful of any assimilation of his work to a model with which he did not agree. He would not, for example, have accepted being included in a history of structuralism, which was foreign to him. "1 am not, 1 do not have to be or not to be, a structuralist."2 His position was un- equivocal and he went so far as to refuse any reference to the word "structure" in arder to avoid any form of co-optation. Burned by his youthful enthusiasm for abstract systems, Dumzil kept himself safely removed from the tumult and confined his work to philology. Dumzil obviously had a special place. The different influences that had given ri se to his work, like his legacy, took a course that is difficult to define. Unlike Lvi-Strauss, he was not the master of any school, nor did he carry a programma tic banner for any particular dis- cipline. He was removed from traditional disciplinary fields that he ig- nored and that ignored him. Georges Dumzil was like an ingenious and independent innovator, the veritable herald of comparative mythology, which he alone shaped. He renewed and inspired much re- se arch without any concern for either appropriating it or seeking insti- tutionallegitimation. Given this, can we go against his will and evoke 3 2 Georges Dumzil: An Independent 33 sorne of the innovations of this adventurer in Indo-European mythol- ogy in the context of the development of the structuralist paradigm? Yes, and as he received him in the Academy, Lvi-Strauss was right in saying that the word "structure," or "structural," would have come immediately to mind had Dumzil not refused it in 1973. The intellectual complicity between these two men dated back to weIl before Dumzil's membership in the French Academy. They had met in 1946 and Dumzil had played a decisive role, first in Lvi- Strauss's election to the cole Pratique des Hautes tudes and then in his election to the Collge de France in 1959. Their relationship was not, however, based only on career moves. Lvi-Strauss had discov- ered Dumzil's work while preparing his agrgation, but this was only a fortuitous initial contact. Later, after the war and as an ethnologist, lengthy meditation upon his discoveries convinced Lvi-Strauss that Dumzil "was the pioneer of the structural method." 3 The two men had, moreover, two common masters: Marcel Mauss, whose impor- tance we saw for Lvi-Strauss and whose courses Dumzil took, and Marcel Granet, who, as Lvi-Strauss recalled, was instrumental in his decision to study kinship relationships. He had come across Marcel Granet's work Matrimonial Categories and Proximate Relationships in Ancient China at his high school in Montpellier. Dumzil was even more influenced by Granet's work because he had taken his courses at the cole des Langues Orientales from 1933 to 193 5. "Listening and watching Granet at work provoked a kind of indefinable metamor- phosis or maturation in me."4 Looking at the structuralist sphere of influence, Dumzil has a place apart that explains his reluctance to be assimilated into the cur- rent: Ferdinand de Saussure, the obligatory reference for every struc- turalist work, is absent from his. Dumzil always considered himself a philologist and as such his work is part of a legacy that precedes the Saussurean "break"; he is in the tradition of nineteenth-century com- parative philology, especially the work of the Schlegel brothers, Friedrich and August Wilhem, of August Schleicher, and particularly of Franz Bopp, who brought to light the lexical and syntactic relation- ships between Sanskrit, Greek, Latin, and Slavic. 5 Dumzil belonged therefore, more to this historicallinguistic current that, as early as the beginning of the nineteenth century, held that different languages with a common root shared a mother language, Indo-European. Dumzil also drew his fundamental notion of transformation from this branch 34 Georges Dumzil: An historical philology, which was essential for birth of a science of language. The ide a met with a ringing success and quickly became the center of most structuralist works. Here again, Lvi-Strauss consid- ered Dumzil to be a pioneer. "With the idea of transformation, which you were the first among us to use, you have provided them [the social sciences] with their best tool."6 Dumzil, of course, did not remain aloof from modern linguistics. If he was basically unaware of Saussure's work, he was nonetheless fa- miliar with that of one of his disciples, Antoine Meillet, and especially that of mile Benveniste, who strenuously supported him in a difficult batde for election to the Collge de France in 1948. AlI the propo- nents of tradition opposed this bothersome pioneer: Edmond Faral, the medievalist, Andr Piganiol, the specialist on Rome, and the Slav- ist Andr Mazon. But the fight led by mile Benveniste, together with the support of Jules Bloch, Lucien Febvre, Louis Massignon, Alfred Ernout, and Jean Pommier, succeeded and he was elected. Dumzil embodied at one and the same time both the Durkheimian will, ex- pressed by Marcel Mauss, for a total social fact, and the idea that so- ciety, mythology, and religion are to be thought of as a whole; this nat- uraUy led him to use the idea of structure. He also shared with the other structuralists a view of language as the essential vector for com- prehensibility, for transmitting tradition, for incarnating the invari- able, ma king the perception of the permanence of ideas underlying words possible. In order to understand the variations of the model, Dumzil used the notions of difference, of resemblance, and of value opposition, so many instruments of a method that can be caUed com- parative or structuralist. Trifunctionalism The real bomb with which Georges Dumzil shook up traditional cer- tainties dated from 1938, although it exploded only after the war. If an epistemological break existed in his many publications that began in 1924, it occurred then. After having groped around in a compari- son between a group of Indian and Roman artifacts, he found an ex- planation for the three principal Roman priests serving Jupiter, Mars, and Quirinus in their paraUel with the three social classes of Vedic India: priests, warriors, and workers. Dumzil's hypothesis that aU Indo-Europeans have a common tripartite and trifunctional ideology dates from this discovery and he continued to work on it until his Georges Dumzil: An lndepenaent 35 death. He thus the archaeologist of the lndo-European imagi- nation and, despite what he said about it, this discovery in fact placed him among the pioneers of structura li sm because his entire reading of Western history was organized around this plan, which he first called a cycle, then a system, and finaUy a structure, and which was trifunctional. For Dumzil, this plan was common to the mental rep- resentations of Indo-Europeans, and took root during a very broad cultural are a and era stretching between the Baltic and the Black Seas and between the Carpathian and Ural Mountains at the end of the third millennium B.e. Dumzil disagreed with Lvi-Strauss; for him, the phenomenon was indeed unique, but could not be tied to the uni- versallaws of the human mind. His method resembled a structura li st method insofar as he did not believe that the trifunctional invariant resulted from successive borrowings from an original kernel. On the contrary, he favored a method of genetic comparison that eliminated the thesis of borrowed elements. In an approach that he termed "ultrahistorical" because it took myths as its object, Dumzil system- aticaUy compared the elements of the Veda and th en of the Mahab- harata with those of the Scythians, the Romans, and the Irish. For him, aU of these societies and periods could be cast into a common structure differentiating between the functions of sovereignty and of the sacred (Zeus, Jupiter, Mitra, Odin), of the warrior (Mars, Indra, Tyr), and, finally, of the (re)productive and nourishing (Quirinus, Nasatya, Njordr). Dumzil's relative isolation can also be attributed to the difficul- ties he encountered in adapting his model, which is not to say that his work had no impact. But having restricted his organizational model to a specifie era made it immediately less available for the generalizing extrapolations that blossomed during the structuralist heyday. More- over-and in this way he also set himself apart from the structuralist phenomenon-Dumzil placed his method midway between a quest for explanatory elements that are exogenous to myths, and a quest for an independent internaI structure to which myths refer. Dumzil was between the nineteenth-century comparatist philologists and the structuralist method by his integration of both the articulation of con- cepts between themselves in their own structure and the aspects of the uni verse dealt with in myths. His hybrid nature and his concern for history ("1 would like to define myself as a historian'')7 inspired enor- mous amounts of work by historians of the third generation of the 36 Georges Dumzil: An Independent Annales who continued along the same lines of his discoveries. Even if the trifunctional plan was unimportant for the Hellenist world, spe- cialists of ancient Greece-Pierre Vidal-Naquet, Jean-Pierre Vernant, and Marcel Dtienne-changed their approach to the Pantheon on the basis of Dumzil's work, and medievalists like Jacques Le Goff and Georges Duby, when considering a society divided into three orders, could not help but wonder about the bases of its tripartite division. But these consequences came in the 1970s, and we will come back to them when we address that period. Dumzil's lessons did not disappear with him, therefore, when he died at the Val-de-Grce hospital in Paris on October II, 1986, at the age of eighty-eight. He was honored in Le Monde by the linguist Claude Hagge, whose article was entitled "La cl des civilisations": "After Dumzil, the science of religions can no longer be what it was before him. Reason gave order to chaos. In place of the charms of a vague notion of religiosity, he substituted the illuminating clarity of structures of thought. This is one of his important lessons."8 The word "structure" clearly stuck to Dumzil despite his wishes, even after his death, but the meaning of a work does not necessarily con- form to the wishes of its author. Georges Dumzil was an initiator, a herald of a structuralist epic. Six The Phenomenologie al Bridge French philosophy was dominated by phenomenological concerns in the 1950s. Consonant with and in the tradition of Husserl's work, the issue was a return to "things themselves," with its coroIlary of inten- tional consciousness oriented always toward things. Phenomenology is very attentive to experience, therefore, to description, and to the concrete, and subjectivity clearly receives priority. Husserl's ambition was to see philosophy evolve from an ideology to a science. The phe- nomenological undertaking was not based on facts, however, but on the essences that constituted the original basis of the meaning of the possibilities of consciousness, correlatively with its object. At the time of Liberation, French phenomenology was above aIl Sartrean, and it emphasized a consciousness able to know itself. Mau- rice Merleau-Ponty, for his part, resumed Husserl's project but ori- ented it more toward the dialectic played out between proffered meaning and the meaning revealed in things. This led him to a dia- logue that was increasingly close to the social sciences, which were rapidly expanding at the time. Merleau-Ponty took up Husserl's idea of purging the givens of experience available to the phenomenologist of aIl the elements inherited from scientific thinking, to which philoso- phy had capitulated. Whence the formula, "Phenomenology is first of aIl the disavowal of science." But he was far from repudiating science, and clearly hoped to reappropriate it into philosophical thinking. As early as the war, Merleau-Ponty had began to carry out this work with 37 38 The respect to biology, and above al! with respect to psychology, cntl- cizing their reifying and mechanistic character. 1 He was equally criti- cal of the idealism of a pure consciousness and therefore increasingly interested in the structures of signification that the new social sciences offered him. These were so many centers of regional ontologies that the philosopher could reappropriate by assembling their overlapping perspectives and renewing their meaning. His ability to do so resulted from the philosopher's position as a subject conceived as transcen- dence toward the world in its entirety. "Merleau-Ponty had the very ambitious project of entertaining a kind of complementarity between philosophy and the social sciences. He therefore tried to keep up with aIl the disciplines."2 The Phenomenological Program Signs was published in 1960 by Gallimard. In a text that was funda- mental for an entire generation, Merleau-Ponty introduced philoso- phers to modern linguistics and to the progress of anthropology, com- ing back to a lecture that he had given in 1951 in which he had shown how important Saussure's work was for inaugurating modern lin- guistics. 3 "Saussure taught us that individually, signs do not signify anything; it is not so much that each sign expresses a meaning but that each one marks a difference in meaning between itself and other signs."4 In the same work, he also dealt with the relationship between philosophy and sociology, deploring the barriers separating them, and calling for a common enterprise. "The separation which we are fight- ing against is no less harmful to philosophy than ta the development of knowledge."5 Merleau-Ponty considered it the philosopher's re- sponsibility to define the range of possibilities and to interpret the em- pirical work do ne by the social sciences; through his hermeneutic ef- forts, the question of meaning is brought to the work of each one. Moreover, the philosopher needs the positive sciences because his thinking must be based on what is known and validated by scientific procedures. The other link that Merleau-Ponty built in this area was aimed at Lvi-Strauss's anthropology. Merleau-Ponty had drawn doser to Lvi- Strauss after his break with Sartre. Elected to the Collge de France in 1952, Merleau-Ponty suggested to Lvi-Strauss two years later that he seek election, which meant sacrificing "three months of a life whose thread was so soon going to break."6 Merleau-Ponty devoted the The Phenomenological Bridge 39 fourth chapter of his book to anthropology-"De Marcel Mauss Claude Lvi-Strauss"-and ardently defended the program estab- lished in 1950 by Lvi-Strauss in his Introduction to the Work of Mar- eel Mauss. "Social f a c t ~ are neither things nor ideas; they are struc- . - 1 tures. . . . Structure takes nothing away from a society's depth or breadth. It is itself the structure of structures."7 A true friendship was born of this intellectual association and Merleau-Ponty's photograph always sat on Lvi-Strauss's desk. But what was Merleau-Ponty seeking in these many dialogues? Did he think that he had to surrender the philosopher's arms to the so- cial sciences? Certainly not, but he believed that the phenomenologi- cal philosopher should appropriate the works of Mauss, Lvi-Strauss, Saussure, and Freud, not so much in order to provide epistemological bases for each of these disciplines as to subject them to a thorough- going phenomenological renewal, which would redefine them philo- sophically, assuming of course that the philosopher accepted the valid- ity of the specialists' information, which he could not verify. The phenomenologist was like an orchestra leader drawing together all the objective results produced by the social sciences and assigning them a meaning, a value in terms of subjective experience and of total mean- ing. "1 remember his class on Lvi-Strauss, where he presented him as the algebra of kinship in need of completion by the meaning of the familial for humans: paternity, filiation."8 Reversing the Paradigm The rapprochement Merleau-Ponty attempted to create in the fifties between philosophy and the social sciences was a forerunner of the paradigm's later reversaI. It was no longer anthropology that was try- ing to situate itself with respect to philosophy, as when Marcel Mauss borrowed the notion of a total social fact from his philosophy profes- sor, Alfred Espinas. On the contrary, it was philosophy, and Merleau- Ponty in this case, that was positioning itself in relationship to anthro- pology, linguistics, and psychoanalysis while the work of Michel Leiris and Claude Lvi-Strauss was being published in Les Temps modernes. Merleau-Ponty therefore opened up sorne very promising horizons when he wrote, "The task is therefore to broaden our reason in order to make it capable of understanding what it is in us and in others that precedes and exceeds reason."9 He opened philosophy up to the irrational through the twin figures of the madman and the sav- 40 The Phenomenological Bridge age. Anthropology and psychoanalysis would thus hold positions of major importance, and indeed they held them in the sixties. But why did philosophy lose its footing here? Why did the phe- nomenological project come up short so quickly? rhefirst answer would be biographical: phenomenology's failure would be the result of Merleau-Ponty's premature death on May 4, 1961, at the age of fifty-four. The man who incarnated the phenomenological enterprise left behind him a construction site where the work had barely been begun, as weIl as nUlllerous orphans. But a more fundamental reason exists, and Vincent Descombes's answer is edifying: "This philosophi- cal project was bound to fail for a very simple reason. The scholarly disciplines were already active in their own conceptual development and did not need Merleau-Ponty or any other philosopher to interpret their discoveries. They were aIl already at work on both levels."10 Re- cuperating the social sciences became a trap for philosophy in the grips of its own doubts, and soon left behind in favor of the promis- ing, young social sciences. Merleau-Ponty played an important role for an entire generation of philosophers whom he awakened to new problems, and they aban- doned philosophy weIl armed to become either anthropologists, lin- guists, or psychoanalysts. This paradigmatic reversaI dominated the entire structuralist period of the sixties. The anthropological land- scape was substantially changed and, with few exceptions, such as Lucien Lvy-Bruhl, Marcel Mauss, Jacques Soustelle, and Claude Lvi-Strauss, who came from philosophy, ethnologists came from very different backgrounds, an effect of fusion rather than of filiation: ll Paul Rivet came from medicine, as did most of the other researchers; Marcel Griaule, who was an aviator first, came from Langues Orien- tales; 12 Michel Leiris came from poetry and surrealism, Alfred M- traux from the cole des Chartes,13 where he was a student with Georges Bataille. It was not a uniform milieu; ethnologists "do not ~ m h r a c e a triballogic."14 It was above aIl thanks to Merleau-Ponty that an entire generation of young philosophers flocked toward these modern sciences. While studying philosophy at the Sorbonne in 1952-53, Alfred Adler dis- covered Merleau-Ponty's work. "Through Merleau-Ponty, we became interested in psychoanalysis, in child psychology, and in the theoreti- cal problems of language." 15 This awakening and the evolution of the political situation complemented each other and by the beginning of The Adler ln Arriv reconfirmed important roie. "Merleau-Ponty was an eminent mediator; it is very certainly thanks to him that Lacan read Saussure."16 That Jacques Lacan discovered Saussure thanks to Merleau-Ponty is an entirely plausible hypothesis, because they often saw each other privately at the beginning of the fifties along with Michel Leiris and Claude Lvi-Strauss. Merleau-Ponty's text on Saus- sure dates from 1951 and Lacan's Rome Report from 1953. Aigirdas Julien Greimas accords him the same importance. The real send-off came from Merleau-Ponty's inaugural lecture at the Collge de France (1952) when he said that we would see that Saussure and not Marx invented the philosophy of history. It was a paradox that made me think of the fact that, before doing the his- tory of events, it would be necessary to construct the history of sys- tems of thought and of economic systems and only afterward to try and understand how they evolve.17 The philosopher Jean-Marie Benoist, a close friend of Lvi-Strauss and author of The Structural Revolution (1975), also confirmed that he had come to read Lvi-Strauss through Merleau-Ponty, whom he read dur- ing his khgne, in 1962. "Merleau-Ponty acted like a precursor phase conditioning the reception of the richness of the structura li st labor."J8 These conversions provoked a veritable hemorrhage from which philosophy would have sorne difficulty recovering and which was only the beginning. One of philosophy's own prodigal children, Michel Foucault, dealt a final blow to the phenomenological project and to the pretensions of a philosophy sitting somewhere above the tus sIe of the empirical sciences. Foucault's critique came only during the sixties, but it developed above aB out of his dissatisfaction with the phenome- nological program dominating philosophy while he was writing his Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity between 1955 and 1960. He blamed philosophy for being tao strictly academic, and for systematicaBy avoiding Kant's question of knowing what our current reality is. Foucault opened his inquiry up to new objects and displaced the phenomenological perspective of an interiorized description of lived experience, to which he preferred bringing problematized social practices and institutions to light. "Everything that happened around the sixties clearly sprang from this dissatisfaction with the phenome- nological the ory of the subject."19 Foucault changed directions as much with respect to the phenomenological problematic as to Marx- 42 The ism. However, been for philosophical inquiry by emphasizing that man is not known, but the knower, and that it is therefore impossible for the knower ta accede ta self-knowledge without a play of reflections ma king quite apparent the invisible split between the face and its representation. Jacques Lacan broadened this point of view before the war in "Le stade du miroir," seeking to bypass biological reductionism, and hop- ing the phenomenologists would help him. Foucault himself began The Order of Things py discussing the famous painting Las Meninas, in which the subject-king is in the painting only thanks to his reflec- tion in the mirror. 20 But phenomenology could not, or was not able to, rip itself from the anthropological cirde and Michel Foucault, in proposing to go further, was therefore proposing a fundamental shift: It is probably impossible to give empirical contents transcendental value or to displace them in the direction of a constituent subjectiv- ity without giving rise, at least silently, to an anthropology-that is, to a mode of thought in which the rightful limitations of acquired knowledge (and consequently of ail empirical knowledge) are at the same time the concrete forms of existence, precisely as they are given in that same empirical knowledge.21 The phenomenological investigation, with its internaI tension be- tween the empirical and the kept apart but equally targeted in the notion of experience, had to he shlfted in order to ask whether man really exists or if he is not the site of the lack of being that Western humanism ignored with utter impunity. Notwithstand- ing the ambition of dedaring itself able to stand within and outside of its own perceptual and cultural field, phenomenology ended up in a dead end because of its will to found the unthought within man him- self, whereas for Foucault, it lies in his shadow, in the Other, in an irrevocable alterity and dualism. The lining must be rent in order to make way for that which escapes the primacy of the "Ego" in the liv- ing, speaking, and working subject and, beyond the empiricism of lived experience, that which allows the sciences of language and of psychoanalysis to blossom. Foucault's goal was to explore the palpa- ble consistency of that which speaks in man, more than of what he means to say. The phenomenological subject is quite dearly elimi- nated from such a project, which soon thereafter would become one of the most important and most highly debated aspects of structura li st philosophy. Seven The Saussurean Break The term "structuralism" applies to a very diversified phenomenon, which is more than a method and less than a philosophy. But its central core, its unifying center, is the model of modern linguistics and the figure of Ferdinand de Saussure, presented as its founder. Whence the period's prevailing theme of returning to Saussure as part of a more general movement of "returns," and including Marx and Freud. The program that sought to incarnate modernity and the rationality that had finallt in the human sciences needed to mo- bilize the pasto Between the two moments of the initial break and of a rediscovery, it would seem that something had been lost. Saussure appeared as the founding father figure, even if many researchers knew his work only secondhand. Saussure offered his solution to the ancient question raised in Plato's Craty/us in which Hermogenes and Cratylus debate two opposing views of the nature- culture relationship. Hermogenes argues that culture arbitrarily as- signs words to things, while Cratylus considers that words copy nature in a fundamentally natural relationship. Saussure's position in this ancient and recurrent debate was to agree with Hermogenes' no- tion of the arbitrary nature of the sign. Vincent Descombes humor- ously evokes the "revolutionary" nature of this discovery and cites Molire's philosophy master in Le Bourgeois gentilhomme (act 2, scene 5) as the originator of the structuralist method.1 The plot is fa- miliar: Monsieur Jourdan writes prose without realizing it, and wants 43 44 The Saussurean Break ta write letter ta a Marquise ta l am dying for love of your beautiful eyes." This simple declaration ri se to five successive alternatives that are broken down into 120 pos- sible permutations and that allow for as many connotations of the same denotation. But the birth of modern linguistics had to wait for the publication of the Course on General Linguistics (CGL),2 which, as we know, was the transcription of students' notes of Saussure's lectures between 1907 and 19II, collected, analyzed, and organized along with the rare written documents left by the master. Charles Bally and Albert Schehaye, two professors from Geneva, published the CGL after Saussure's death in 19 l 5. The heart of his demonstration is to estab- lish the arbitrariness of the sign, showing that language is a system of values established neither by content nor by experience, but by pure difference. Saussure's interpretation of language firmly places it in ab- stract terms in order to better rem ove it from empiricism and from psychologizing. Saussure established linguistics as a new discipline that claimed autonomy from the other human sciences. Once its own rules were established, linguistics was to rally aH the other disciplines by virtue of its rigor and high degree of formalization, and make them adopt its program and methods. The CGL's destiny is rather paradoxical. Franoise Gadet traced its history, showing that when it first c ~ m e out the CGL had rela- tively little effect compared to that of the last thirty years. 3 The num- ber of translations and reprints increased as a function of the rising wave of generalized structuralism: five translations between 1916 and 1960 compared with twelve during the twenty years between 1960 and 1980. Two events were decisive for this success making the CGL the little red book for hard-core structuralists. After the First World War, the Russians and the Swiss came to dominate linguistics, wrest- ing the discipline from the Germans who had dominated it until then but who had essentially defined it as comparative philology. As of the First International Congress of Linguists at The Hague in 1928, an important alliance was established that was to have a brilliant future. "The propositions presented by the Russians (Jakobson, Karcevski and Trubetzkoy), on the one hand, and by the Genevans (BaHy and Schehaye), on the other, made common reference,to Saussure in their description of language as a system."4 Geneva and Moscow were therefore at the beginnings of the definition of the structuralist pro- The Saussurean Break 45 gram. Moreover, this was the first time that the term "structuralism" was actuaIly employed. And it was Jakobson who used it, whereas Saussure had only used the term "system," which he repeated I38 times in the three hundred pages of the CG L. The second event that determined the future of the CGL occurred in France. This was the publication in I9 S 6 of Greimas's article, "L'actualit du saussurisme" in Le Franais moderne (no. 3, I9S6). "In this paper, 1 showed that while linguistics was invoked every- where-by Merleau-Ponty in philosophy, by Lvi-Strauss in anthro- pology, by Barthes in literature, by Lacan in psychoanalysis-nothing was going on in linguistics itself, and it was high time that- Ferdinand de Saussure be put in his right place."s Greimas's article was not the only one on Saussure, and it is clear that during the fifties and sixties, the evolving definition of a total semiological program reaching be- yond linguistics and encompassing aIl the human sciences in a com- mon project, which was the great ambition of the period, was justified and encouraged by Saussure's definition of semiology as the "science that studies the life of signs at the heart of sociallife." The Theme of Rupture ln order to understand the structuralist paradigm, therefore, we have to begin with the Saussurean break, since an entire generation read and considered the CG L to be the founding moment. This alone makes the hypothesis of a break plausible, even if, according to sorne, it was basicaIly a myth. Nonetheless, and in order to better under- stand its influence, we can ask whether or not there reaIly was a break between pre- and post-Saussurean linguistics. Answers vary with the linguist, and nobody is naive enough to believe that linguistic thinking could spring fuIl-blown from a single individual's mind, but sorne in- sist more on the discontinuity of Saussure's thinking, whereas others emphasize a more progressive shift. Franoise Gadet argued in favor of a very clear break between "the ideas of the pre-Saussurean period" and those of the period that opens with Saussure. 6 The descriptive approach, the prevalence of the idea of system, the concern for going from constructed and explicit procedures back to elementary units, Saussure's new orientation of- fered aIl of this and would bec orne the lowest common denominator for the entire structuralist movement. Saussure represented the verita- ble birth of modern linguistics for Roland Barthes as weIl. "There is 46 The Saussurean Break an epistemological change with Saussure: anal ogy ism, imitation replaces derivation."7 Barthes, in his enthusiasm, even presented Saussure as the harbinger of a democratic mode! thanks to a homology between the social contra ct and the linguistic contract. An entire lineage here refers to structuralism's enduring rootedness. Poetry, according to the Schlegel brothers, was supposed to be a Re- public an discourse,8 and there is indeed a debt to German Romanti- cism, which had argued for a notion of art as a structure freed of mlmeS1S. Claudine Normand, a linguistics professor at Paris X who c a m ~ to linguistics starting from the idea of the Saussurean break, saw a break, but not where it was usually situated. "It is difficult to place: the Saussurean discourse is very unclear because it is part of the posi- tivist discourse of the period."9 Saussure's essential contribution was not to discover the arbitrary nature of the sign; all linguists were al- ready convinced of this by the end of the nineteenth century, and all the comparative work had already adopted the conventionalist argu- ment and rejected the naturalist model. However, "he did something else with it; he attached it to the semiological princip le, which is to say, to the theory of value, which allowed him to say that in language there are only differences without any oppositional sign."10 The break would therefore essentially be at the leyel of the definition of a theory of value, in the principles allowing a generalization of the description, and in the project's abstraction. Saussure's idea of system expressed the construction of an abstract, conceptual procedure because a sys- tem cannot be observed, even though each linguistic element depends on it. For Claudine Normand, the diachrony/synchrony distinction was already in the making prior to Saussure, especially in the work being done in dialectology, where synchrony would quite naturally receive precedence in the collection of dialects, for want of written traces. On this matter, Saussure would have only "systematized things that were already being said and done." 11 Jean-Claude Coquet, on the other hand, takes things back to the nineteenth century and even to the end of the eighteenth century, to the important movements that established contemporary linguist\cs. The idea of system predated Saussure. "It is first of aIl a taxonomic idea and we therefore see the first successful efforts among biologists. This is the period of Goethe and Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire. "12 Saussure only consolidated the idea of system, thereby reducing its field of The Saussurean Break ta the system in order ta it the greatest bie impact, but abandoning the historical panchronic aspects. Like Michel Foucault, Jean-Claude Milner sees in Bopp's work the basic foundation for a grammar that leaves the world of the elassi- cal age and of representation behind. Saussure would have simply eleaned up the fundamental principles needed by the linguistics of his period, which is to say, historical linguistics. But historical linguists had needed general linguistics since the end of the nineteenth cen- tury, and needed to renew its links with a time wh en generallinguis- tics existed before being repressed by the historicism of philological research. "There is therefore no reason to prefer the argumentl of discontinuity," since general linguistics is a term that we begin ta find as of the 1880s. 13 Andr Martinet, who contributed consider- ably to Saussure's being read and known, nonetheless considers that Saussure yielded to pressure from sociology by distinguishing between language and speech, and "failed in his plan ta study the linguistic phenomenon in itself and for itself. "14 For Martinet, a program truly establishing structura li sm was defined only with the advent of the Prague Cirele and phonology. "1 am a Saussurean, and 1 say this with the greatest admiration for Saussure: he is not the founder of structuralism." 15 Synchrony Prevails Andr Martinet criticized above all the fact that the important problem of the regularity of phonetic changes, raised during Saussure's time, went unanswered in the CCL. In order to aecount for this phenome- non, structure needed to remain diachronic rather than being limited to synchrony, which is statie: "A structure is something that moves."16 Saussurean categories served, however, as epistemic tools for general- ized structuralism even if different works took sorne liberty with Saus- sure's text in order to adapt it to the specificity of their field. The princi- pal inflection gave priority to synchrony and Saussure illustrated this and its corollary, the insignificance of historicity, with the metaphor of a chess game that is well played when the situation and possible combi- nations of the pieces on the board are visible. "It is altogether unimpor- tant that one get there by one path or another."17 Studying the recipro- cal combination of discrete units reveals the internallaws regulating a language. That the synchronic investigation be independent in order to gain access to the system breaks with the methods of both comparatists 48 The Saussurean Break and ciassical philosophers, who sought the successive borrowings in the different layers of languages as they were taking shape. In this radical change of perspective, diachrony becomes a simple derivative and linguistic evolution is seen as the passage from one syn- chrony to another. Foucault's epistemes come to mind even if the ref- erence to Saussure is not really explicit. Linguistics was freed from the historian's tutelage through this power play, which encouraged its sci- entific autonomy, but at the high price of ahistoricity, resulting in an amputation that may have been necessary to break with the evolution- ism of the time, but that led to aporias because the links between dia- chrony and synchrony were not set in any dialectical relationship. Saussure made it possible to show that the laws of change for a lan- guage and a society differ, and that language is not therefore the sim- ple expression of a racial particularity, as nineteenth-century linguists_ believed as they reconstructed the history of Indo-European s()cieties through known and recognized languages. Linguistic Closure The other fundamental aspect of the Saussurean approach was to see language as hermetic. The linguistic sign does not join a thing with its name, but a concept with an acoustic image whose link is arbitrary; reality, or the referent, is therefore placed ontside the field of study in order to define the linguist's perspective, which is limited, by defini- tion. The Saussure an sign only concerns the relationship between the signified (the concept) and the signifier (the acoustic image), and ex- ciudes the referent. Signs differ from symbols, which retain a natural link in the signifiedlsignifier relationship. "Language is a system that knows only its own order." "Language is form and not substance."18 Therefore, the linguistic unit, by virtue of its phonic and semantic character, always points to all the other units in a purely endogenous combinatory activity. The referential function, otherwise known as denotation, is re- pressed. Referentiality is located in the relationship between sign and referent. Saussure. gave no priority to the signifier over the signified, since both were, for him, as indissociable aithe two sides of a piece of paper, but he defill-the-signifier by its material presence, whereas the signified is characterized by its absence: "The sign is both a mark and a lack: dual from the beginning."19 Jacques Lacan, in particular, ad- dressed this unequal relationship in signification, and reduced the sig- The Saussurean Break 49 nified in of the signifier in a twist that further accentuated the immanent quality of this approach to language. By his immanent ori- entation, Saussure limited his project and escaped any correlation between two of his propositions, "the proposition according to which language is a system of signs and the proposition according to which language is a social facto "20 He enclosed his linguistics within a restric- tive study of the code and thereby cut language off from the condi- tions of its appearance and signification. Saussure chose the ~ i g n rather than meaning, which he banished to the metaphysical past, a choice that came to characterize the struc- turalist paradigm. Such a formalization made it possible to go quite far in describing languages, but rather than a means, formalization be- came an end; as such, it often served to occult, if not to mystify. Two ways of dividing the internaI combinatory of language made it com- prehensible: the linear relationships of contiguity, called syntagmatic, and the relationships that are in absentia, and which Saussure called associational and later encompassed in the notion of paradigm. Saussure was restrictive by definition, but his project of construct- ing a general semiology integrating all those disciplines concerned with the life of the signs at the core of sociallife was very ambitious: "Linguistics is only one part of this general science. "21 But by its impe- tus, linguistics became the pilot science at the heart of the structura li st project, which clearly participates in the realization of this ambitious program wherein all the sciences of the sign converge around the same paradigm. Buttressed by a method that had already yielded results, it was the melting pot of all the human sciences. The exception al and innovative character of this configuration on the French intellectuallandscape should be nuanced when compared with a similar situation prevailing in Germany in the nineteenth cen- tury, at a time when philology and comparative grammar were the first disciplines to become institutionalized as modern sciences. The number of university chairs, of research money, and of reviews con- firms their anteriority. "1 think that comparative grammar had a larger budget than physics in nineteenth-century Germany. "22 Saus- sure's descendants therefore basically equated Saussure with the CCL, but it was only one aspect of his personality; his systeniaticity and for- mali sm were developed like a program even if he lectured in unwritten improvisations, or as a bit of paper folded in fours, according to his students. 50 The Saussurean Break Two Saussures? Saussure's binarism is apparent in' his personal interests and even in his personality. He frequently traveled to Marseilles from his native Geneva, taking with him small note books that he filled with medita- tions on Vedic and Saturnine texts of Indian and Roman sacred po- etry. Two hundred such notebooks were filled up on anagrams and in a cabalistic search for hidden proper names that would reveal both for whom the texts were intended and their ultimate meaning. Disturbed by his discoveries, Saussure even became interested in spiritist sances between 1895 and 1898. In 1898, he was called in by Fleury, a psychology professor in Geneva, to consult on a case of glos- solalia. Miss Smith, under hypnosis, announced that she spoke San- skrit, and Saussure, professor of Sanskrit, deduced that "it was not Sanskrit, but there was nothing that went against Sanskrit. "23 Not that Saussure was the only sC,ientist with a spiritual dimension. We need only recall Newton, who wrote thousahds of pages on alchemy while writing his Principia; the founder of c1assical mechanics and of West- ern rationality was also seeking the philosophers' stone. The second Saussure, as Louis-Jean Calvet called him,24 thought that a language existed beneath language, that a conscious or unconscious encoding of words existed beneath words. However, n.o trace of his search for latent structures appears in the official Saussure of the CCL. Saussure's note books were all carefully kept secret by his family and it was only in 1964 that Jean Starobinski was able to partially publish the anagrams. 25 The discovery opened up an entirely new and different line of research, in the mid-sixties, especially with Julia Kris- teva's work. We can, together with Jakobson, speak about a long- repressed "second Saussure an revolution." The Absent Subject This second filiation would allow a return of the subject, which had been explicitly reduced to insignificance, if not to silence, in the CCL with its critical distinction ~ t w e e n language and speech. This opposi- tion inc1uded the distinction between the social and the individual, be- tween the concrete and the abstract, between the contingent and the necessary, and linguistic science as such had to limit itself to language, which was the only object that could be scientifically explained. Con- sequently, the speaking subject, the man of words, was eliminated: The Saussurean Break 5 l "Language is not a function of the speaking subject, but the product that the individu al passively records. . . . Language, distinct from speech, is an object that can be studied separattilir. "26 Linguistics only acquires the status of a science for Saussure on condition that its spe- cific object-Ianguage-is clearly determined. The dross of speech, of the subjt!ct, and of psychology had to be eliminated. Banished from the Saussurean scientific perspective, the individual becomes the vic- tim of a formalist reduction in which he no longer has his place. This negation, which was already the blind spot on the Saus- sure an horizon, would also become an essential element of the struc- turalist paradigm elsewhere than in linguistics. Ir drives into parox- ysms a formalism that, after having eliminated meaning, excludes the speaker so that "everything happens as if no one were speaking."27 With its initial negations as weil as their consequences, we can see that modern linguistics had to paya heavy price in order to establish itself. But once again, Saussure's singularity has to be seen in relation to nineteenth-century Germany comparatists who sought out true lin- guistic structures, which they considered destroyed by the activity of speaking. According to this current Of thought, the structure of lan- guage was independent of what was done with it and needed to be re- stored. So Saussure, once again, was only systematizing something that had predated him. Behind this language/speech opposition, Oswald Ducrot sees Saus- sure as mixing two levels, "and it would be interesting to distinguish them clearly, which is what 1 tried to dO."28 The opposition between language and speech can be considered first like the distinction be- tween what is given (speech) and what is constructed (language). This indispensable methodological or epistemological distinction remains valid; indeed, it is even the very condition of the scientific enterprise, although it does not presuppose Saussure's second, and arguable, op- position between an abstract linguistic system where the subject has been removed from speech activity, between an objective code and the use made of it by subjects. But the whole Saussurean current of the six- ties revisited the confusion between these two levels, generating the themes of the death of man and of theoretical antihumanism. Scientific hopes were fanned to great heights as the speaking subject was finaily eliminated. Eight Roman Jakobson: The Man Who Could Do Everything Among other things, the success of structuralism in France was the product of a particularly fruitful meeting in New York in 1942 be- tween Claude Lvi-Strauss and Roman Jakobson. Their friendship, born of a misunderstanding-Jakobson thought he had found a drinking partner in Lvi-Strauss-never waned and, on the eve of his death, Roman Jakobson sent his friend an offprint of an article dedi- cated to "My brother Claude." This friendship culminated in the unit y and reciprocal integration of their respective work: Lvi-Strauss borrowed the phonological model into which Jakobson initiated him and Jakobson opened linguistics up to anthropology. They shared methodology, ideas, and dynamism. "The Common Language of Linguists and Anthropologists" is a programmatic chapter in General Linguistics in which Jakobson em- phasized the important roles played by the mathematical theory of communication and information theory for advancing linguistics since Saussure and his contemporary, Peirce'! It was now time for linguis- tics to concern itself with meaning and for the game of hide-and-seek between sign and signification to come to an end. "We are facing the important task of incorporating signification into the science of language."2 A vast and common research program opened up for linguists and anthropologists in which the codes of one language could be substituted for those of the other thanks to the isomorphism of internaI structures. Jakobson, like Lvi-Strauss, sought universals: 52 Roman Jakobson: The Man Who Could Do Everything 53 "The moment has come to address the question of the universallaws of language." 3 He was clearly determined to anchor linguistics in the modernity of the hard sciences and compared recent developments in general linguistics-its transition from a genetic to a descriptive ap- proach-to the transformation of classical mechanics into quantum mechanics: "Structurallinguistics, like quantum mechanics, gains in morphic determinism what it loses in temporal determinism."4 Jakobson was already quite receptive to anthropology before meeting Lvi-Strauss, however, for he was in the double line of Euro- pean linguistics and ethnolinguistics, a branch of American linguistics based on Sapir's and Boas's work on Amerindian languages. This tra- dition had explored paths different from those taken by Saussure, but it had also emphasized the description of languages and the funda- mental importance of linguistic structure. Learning about the coher- ence of Amerindian languages was an urgent enterprise because they were rapidly disappearing. Before coming to settle in America, Roman Jakobson had had an unusual pasto A veritable globe-trotter of structuralism, his pivotaI po- sition and influence were the products of an itinerary that took him from Moscow to New York by way of Prague, Copenhagen, Oslo, Stockholm, and Uppsala-not to mention his very frequent trips to Paris. Retracing his steps amounts to following the international path of the nascent structuralist paradigm. The Linguistic Circle of Moscow Jakobson was particularly receptive to everything having to do with modernity, in the arts as well as in science. Born in Moscow on Octo- ber II, 1896, he became interested in folktales when he was quite young and, by the time he was six, was already a "voracious reader."5 He learned French and German when he was very young and discov- ered the poetry of Pushkin and Verlaine and then Mallarm when he was only twelve! ln 1912, he joined the new and particularly creative futurists, and read the poetry of Velimir Khlebnikov and then that of Vladimir Mayakovski, with whom he became friends, as he did with the painter Cazimir Malevich. "1 grew up in a milieu of painters."6 Like Lvi-Strauss, Jakobson lived close to painting, which was for him the most intense aspect of creative culture. ln 1915, on J akobson's initiative, the Linguistic Circle of Moscow came into being and assigned itself the task of promoting poetic lin- 54 Roman The Man Who Could Do guistics. The first was held in the room of Jakobson's parents' home but it was difficult ta take charge of the Grele at the height of the war un der the czarist regime, and Jakobson quickly joined the Dialectology Committee of the Academy of Sciences. The formalists and futurists therefore were essentially responsible for this push in the direction of linguistics; Saussure came only later, when Jakobson came upon the CCL in 1920, in Prague. As early as 1914-15, however, he made the acquaintance of Prince Nicolai Tru- betzkoy, who spoke to him about the work being done in France under Meillet. Their encounter was decisive. According to Antoine Meillet, Trubetzkoy was the mastermind of modern linguistics and responsible for its definitive renewal, through phonology. The friendship that took hold between Trubetzkoy and Jakobson, especially after 1920, and until Trubetzkoy's death in 1938, was so strong that Jakobson says that, given their very frequent and fruitful impassioned exchanges, he can no longer clearly distinguish between his own thinking and that of his friend. "It was a surprising collaboration; we needed one another."7 He read Husserl, whose Log- ical Quests "had, perhaps, the greatest influence on my theoretical work."8 In early 1917, Jakobson participated in the creation of Opoyaz, a Saint Petersburg society for the study of poetic language. He continued to develop the relationship between theory, poetics, and practice, while frequenting poets including Eikhenbaum, Poli va nov, Yakoubinsky, and Chlovsky. "The linguistic aspect of poetry was de- liberately emphasized in all of these enterprises."9 During that period, Jakobson argued for the immanence of the study of the literary texts and of an internaI coherence ma king the whole greater th an the sum of its parts. Jakobson hoped that linguis- tics would allow him to successfully bridge creation and science, and at the same time he wanted to see linguistics reach the level of a nomo- thetic science. Poetic language offered him a good starting point be- cause, unlike daily language, which is shaped by elements external to its own logic and is heterotelic, poetic language is fundamentally au- totelic. But this formalist enterprise did not square well with Stalin- ism, which was crashing down on Russia in the twenties and thirties. The Prague Circle Unlike his friend E. Polivanov, who stayed behind in Russia, Jakobson left. He went first to Czechoslovakia, where he worked as an inter- Roman Jakobson: The Man Who Could Do Everything 55 preter for the Soviet Red Cross Mission in Prague. "It was an accident of history, which gave rise to the development of structuralism in the West."10 In fact, structuralism could have developed in the Soviet Union and the Soviets could have been in the forefront of linguistic re- search. Linguists like Polivanov who remained in Russia were liqui- dated, along with their work, by the Soviet authorities. Ironically, this repression proved, a contrario, the formalist theses claiming that liter- ature is its own end independent of any historical context and quite clearly showed that writing has political stakes. Jakobson became the Soviet cultural attach to the Prague embassy, thanks to Ambas- sador Antonov, who had taken the Winter Palace in October I9I7 under Trotsky, a crime for which he too was liquidated somewhat later. "Antonov was called back with the entire embassy. They were gunned down from A to Z, ineluding the office boys and the eleaning woman."ll But Jakobson was bored in Prague. He began frequenting Czech poets and translating Russian poets into Czech at their meetings at a time when Russian culture was considered to be that of n enemy country. They improvised translated readings of Gorky and Maya- kovski which provoked impassioned debates and led to an important realization for Jakobson, who suddenly discovered the difference in musicality between these two languages, the difference in tonality between Russian and Czech, two languages that are very close because of their roots and lexical bases, but that had made completely different phonological choices that were nonetheless similar enough that a listener could grasp the fact that only very slight changes would suffice for the pertinent dif- ference to change. 12 Structural phonology was born of this interaction between natural, cultural, and poetic languages. Jakobson also again met Prince Nicolai Trubetzkoy, whom he had known since I9I5 and who had fled the Russian Revolution and taken refuge in Vienna. On October I6, I926, at the initiative of the Czechs Wilm Mathesius, Makarovsky, and J. Vachek, and the E-ussians Nicolai Trubetzkoy, Roman Jakobson, and Serge Karcevsky, the Linguistic Cirele of Prague was born. Its publications began appearing as of I929, and they defined an explicitly structuralist program: "It [the Cirele] took the name of structuralism because its fundamental concept was the structure, conceived as a dynamic ensemble."13 The Prague Cirele was 56 Roman Jakobson: The Man Who Could Do in line with thinking of Saussure, Russian formalism, Husserl, and of the Gestalt, and created ties with the Vienna Grele. hs "1929 theses" were the equivalent of a program for several generations of linguists. These theses strictly distinguished between internaI and manifest language: "In its social role, language has to be defined ac- cording to the relationship that exists between it and extralinguistic reality. Either it has a communication function, which is to say that it is directed toward a signified, or a poetic, function, which is to say that it is directed toward the sign itself."14 The Prague Grcle intended to devote itself essentially to the study of poetic language, which had been neglected until then. Jakobson was vice president of the Grcle and professor at Brno University until 1939. He helped diffuse the Circle's structura li st pro- gram in the West. The first Congress of General Linguistics held at The Hague April 10-15, 1928, also helped. The Prague Grcle came to this congress with its modernist theses carefully prepared beforehand. Given its influence, the first two days were devoted to theoretical questions: "For the first time, we have used the term 'structural and functionallinguistics.' We have posed the question of structure as cen- tral, for without it nothing in linguistics can be considered."15 Jakob- son also had an excellent relationship with the Copenhagen Grcle, which had been created in 1939 by Louis Hjelmslev and Viggo Bron- dal, both of whom were invited to present their work to the Prague Grcle. In fact, Jakobson was published inActa linguistica, the Co pen- hagen Grcle's journal, despite dis agreements particularly with Hjelm- slev, who, in Jakobson's view, wanted to go too far in eliminating all phonic and semantic mate rial from the study of language. But the collaboration between the Prague and Copenhagen Cir- cles was aborted for historical reasons. Following the 1939 Nazi inva- sion of Czechoslovakia, Jakobson fled first to Denmark and then to Norway and Sweden. But with Nazi troops advancing farther and far- ther West, he had to leave Europe in 1941 to seek refuge. He came to the New School for Social Research in New York. A Linguistics Grcle of New York had been established in 1934 and Jakobson therefore landed on receptive ground. He joined the editorial board of Ward, the review founded by the Grcle in 1945. Ward's first issue gave a condensed version of the structuralist program, dealing with the ap- plications of structural analysis in linguistics and anthropology. And since the review sought to consolidate "cooperation between Ameri- Roman Jakobson: The Man Who Could Do Everything 57 can and European linguistics of different schools,"16 it is elear that Jakobson was once again in an excUent position. The 1920S and 1930S in Prague were the most productive and foundational years. Even if the 1929 theses of the Prague Cirele had a Saussurean bent, the Cirele had at the same time put sorne distance between itself and Saussure on a number of fundamental issues. It defined its conception of language as a functional system; however, "the adjective functional introduces a teleology that is foreign to him [Saussure], since it is inspired by Bhler's functions."17 In addition, the theses were less radical with respect to Saussure's break between diachrony and synchrony, which was not considered to be an un- breachable barrier. Jakobson refused this line of division on several occasions, preferring the notion of dynamic synchrony. "Synchronie does not equal static."18 The rational kernel of structuralism was to come less from a linguistic model than from structral phonology, the model of models. In Prague, Nicolai Trubetzkoy was the best specialist in phonol- ogy. His 1939 Princip/es of Phon%gy became a elassic. In it, he de- fined the phoneme by its place in the phonological system. His method consisted of locating phonie oppositions by taking account of four distinctive traits: nasality, the point of articulation, labialization, and aperture. The Saussurean principle of pertinent difference is elear here, as is the search for minimal pertinent units: in this case, the phoneme. Trubetzkoy adopted both Saussure's position of keeping the referent at a distance and his search for the internallaws of the lin- guistic code. Phonology is removed from aU extralinguistic reality, and attempts to describe sonorous material. This culminated in Jakobson's table of aH pertinent traits, organized using twelve oppositional pairs, which were supposed to account for all the oppositions in all the lan- guages in the world. The structuralists' dream of universality would thus be realized. 19 The phonologist's central quest remained that of the invariable underlying the variable. Jakobson considered that from the outset, as far back as early childhood, the phonematic code was binary, like formaI, mathemati- cal language. Binarism is at the heart of-the phonological system, where once again we find Ferdinand de Saussure's dichotomous think- ing. The sign's dualism between signifier and signified, between the sensible and the intelligible, finds its echo in the binarity of the phono- logical system. 58 Roman The Man Who Could Do Receptivity ta Psychaanalysis Thanks to Jakobson's studies on aphasia, the application of the phono- logical model was broadened, particularly to psychoanalysis. His dis- tinction between two types of aphasia made it possible to examine the mechanisms of language acquisition and its specifie laws, and to draw sorne clinical conclusions about two types of dysfunction. Jakobson differentiated between the combination of signs among themselves and their selection, or the possibility of substituting one sign for an- other. In so doing, he adopted the Saussurean opposition between syn- tagma and association, which made it possible for him to distinguish two types of aphasia. "For aphasies of the first type (selection defi- ciency), the context is the indispensable and decisive factor .... The more his utterances are dependent on the context, the better he copes with his verbal task .... Thus, only the framework, the connecting links of the communication, is spared by this type of aphasia at its critical stage. "20 This type of aphasia is contrasted with another in which, rather th an suffering from a deficiency with respect to the con- text, the patient has a problem of contiguity, which produces an agrammatism, or a heap of words. Jakobson linked the two phenom- ena to two important rhetorical figures-metaphor and metonymy. Metaphor is impossible in the first type of aphasia, where there is a problem of similarity, and metonymy is impossible where there are difficulties of contiguity. Jacques Lacan met Jakobson in 1950 and became his close friend. He adopted this distinction and shifted it onto Freud's ideas of con- densation and displacement in order to explain how the unconscious operates. "Phonology became a model for disciplines having sorne relationship with language; so many disciplines had rather weak for- malization. Phonology offered them a system of formalization by pairs of oppositions that were both simple and seductive, because they were exportable; it was structuralism's central element. "21 The phono- logical model was perfected at the end of the twenties, but it only en- joyed a veritable expansion as of the Second World War and had to wait for the end of the sixties in France before becoming institutional- ized. In or der to understand this lag time, we have to take a look at the situation of linguistics in France in the fifties. Nine A Pilot Science without a Plane: Linguistics The same linguistic effervescence that arose in Europe in the thirties spread to France relatively quickly, but there was a particular d i s t o r ~ tion. Institutional sluggishness braked the integration of modern lin- guistics into the university; the discipline laid siege to the fortress of the Sorbonne, but it lost. A veritable strategy of encirclement was nec- essary but the undertaking was aIl the more difficult because the man- darins were weIl established. Antoine Meillet was the grand master of French linguistics, which had its Society for Linguistics and a Bulletin, and kept itself abreast of the ongoing revolution. But although the information may have got- ten through, it remained somewhat removed from the concerns of re- searchers who were profoundly influenced by their classical training and trapped in the sluggishness of the classical Greco-Latin tradition. It was therefore rather difficult for the modern structural methods to make any significant headway. And at the same time, the discipline was receptive and counted such disciples of Saussure as Antoine Meil- let, G-fammont, and Vendrys, although they were more deeply influ- enced by the comparatist Saussure of the end of the nineteenth century than by the Saussure of the CCL. The university, by contrast, was completely cut off from these concerns, and its sIum ber would continue uninterrupted for quite sorne time, despite the repeated assaults. Linguistics in France in the thirties was already heavily centralized, a characteristic that would 59 60 A Pilot Science without a Plane: Linguistics bring the structure crashing down in 1968. Antoine Meillet's author- ity appears to have gone unchallenged at the time and, with few ex- ceptions, the training and therefore the orientation of scholars was classical. Linguists were for the most part grammar agrgs who held a very traditional view of linguistics. There were atypical cases, of course, such as Guillaume, who attracted many disciples from that enclave of modernity, the cole des Hautes tudes: "Guillaume's case is interesting. He worked in a bank. He had thought about linguis- tic problems on his own. Meillet ha'd him named as a lecturer in I9I9-20 at the cole des Hautes tudes."l There was also Georges Gougenheim's very innovative I939 work, Systme grammatical de la langue franaise. But those who took the traditional path leading to the agrgation generally sidestepped the structuralist phenomenon that was being born in linguistics. If modernity had sorne difficulty establishing itself in the prewar period, what was the situation in the fifties? France lagged increas- ingly behind and the Sorbonne remained completely removed from the few places where linguistic research was being carried on. Andr Martinet, who could have dynamized the situation, was in the United States, and he only returned to France in I95 5. Moreover, Meillet's death in I936 and that of douard Pichon in I940 further accentu- ated the difference between France and the rest of Europe and the United States. Robert-Lon Wagner's nomination to the Sorbonne might have provided sorne hope for renewal if he hadn't been given a chair in Old French. Wagner deplored the situation: "It is obviously abnormal that France be the country in Europe where students of French linguistics are the least well considered by those whose func- tion was or will be to teach French."2 There were a few scholars here and there whose work indicated signs of renewal, but they were still quite isolated. Marcel Cohen, for example, taught Ethiopian at Langues Orientales and at the cole des Hautes tudes: "As early as before I950, [Marcel Cohen] was the linguist who showed the most interest in what was new .... Cohen was a very important guide, and one who considerably encouraged me."3 Most of those who were to impose a change at the end of the six- ties were in the middle of their studies at the time, and, for the most part, in very classical disciplines. They were French students in the main, including grammar agrgs like Jean-Claude Chevalier, Jean Dubois, and Michel Arriv who discovered modern linguistics late A Pilot Science without a Plane: Linguistics 6 l because their courses had completely ignored it. Jean Dubois, for ex- ample, had passed the grammar agrgation in 1945, but he only heard of Saussure in 1958! His courses in philology had been totally cut off from generallinguistics: "Classical students, like me, who took courses leading to the grammar agrgation, could very easily not know what linguistics was."4 By contrast, the non-French students, who were further removed from a very traditional curriculum, could more easily discover modern linguistics at the Collge de France, the cole des Hautes tudes, or the Institut de Linguistique, as was the case for Bernard Pottier and Antoine Culioli. These enclaves were marginalized with respect to uni- versity structures, but they laid the foundations of the future revolu- tion. "1 wanted to be a linguist from the outset .... 1 began with Fouch in experimental phonetics at the Sorbonne, but it was above aU at the cole des Hautes tudes that 1 got my training: 1 started there in 1944 and was there on and off until 1955."5 Bernard Pottier was active in linguistic activities and publications rather early, and it was because he was a student in Spanish. Similarly, Antoine Culioli came to linguistics through his training as an Anglicist, like Andr Martinet. ln the mid-fifties, a young generation of linguists was beginning to take its place in the university, but it was still at the periphery, with the exception of Jean-Claude Chevalier, who in 1954 became the youngest assistant at the Sorbonne, thanks to Antoine Culioli. Bernard Pottier became a lecturer in Bordeaux in 1955, Jean Perrot was named charg d'enseignement in Montpellier, and Antoine Culioli and Jean Dubois joined the Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique. Andr Martinet returned from the United States and replaced Michel Lejeune at the Sorbonne. But the certificate in generallinguistics, for which he was responsible, was only offered as one of the options at the end of a bachelor's in foreign languages. The Periphery Encircles the Center . Given the situation in Paris, the winds of change blew from the prov- inces, and the countryside progressively surrounded the Sorbonne, the linchpin of the French university structure. The adplinistration pro- vided a certain dynamism in this strategy of conquest, in the person of Gaston Berget, the director of the postsecondary educational sector, who in 1955-56 created the fust center for linguistic research within the university. Pilot Science without Plane: Linguistics Berger created the Center for Romance ln Ir was here that 1mbs and later Georges Straka organized numerous international colloquia, making it possible for French linguists to keep up with the most up-to-date research and to make their own research known through colloquia proceedings. As early as 1956 a veritable international community came together in Strasbourg around the re- se archers of the center on the theme "current tendencies in structural linguistics," and included Georges Gougenheim, Louis Hjelmslev, Andr Martinet, and Knud Togeby. \ ln the mid-fifties, director Gaston Berger created a lexicology cen- ter in Besanon, where the lexicologist Bernard Qumada had been in residence since 1950. Qumada made Besanon a particularly dy- namic center, expanding beyond lexicology by creating a center for language learning, and then a center for applied linguistics at which "as many as 2,200 summer trainees, often for eight weeks," came to- gether. 6 This training center made it possible not only to diffuse new methods, but also to obtain supplementary funding and therefore to increase the numbers of roundtables. Bernard Qumada invited the entire generation of young linguists to Besanon: Henri Mitterand became his assistant, Aigirdas Julien Greimas, Jean Dubois, Henri Meschonnic, Guilbert, Wagner, Roland Barthes at the moment when Mythologies was pubiished-all came. The Sorbonne, of course, knew nothing of this intense activity, but it was beginning to be weIl known through its publications. Qumada took over the Cahiers de lexicolo- gie in Besanon in 1959, which addressed itself to a broad readership from the outset; fifteen hundred copies of its first issue were printed. "1 was convinced that lexicology was a crossroads discipline that did not much interest linguists but did hold interest for many other disciplines-literature, history, philosophy, the military ... "7 Bernard Qumada was a talented broker for structurallinguistics. In 1960, he began the tudes de linguistique applique based on his activities in Besanon.)t too had a first printing of fifteen hundred copies, subsidized by Didier, a national editor. Berger's ide a of circum- venting the Sorbonne-which had refused to create these research centers-gained ground and made it possible for the young assistant, Jean-Claude Chevalier, to feel less isolated in the aged Sorbonne by participating in the many work groups that were forming. He met the linguists and Communist Party members Jean Dubois, Henri Mit- terand, and Antoine Culioli at the CERM, and his trips to Besanon A Pilot Science without a Plane: Linguistics 63 became more frequent: "We aU met there during vacations-there was Barthes, Dubois, Greimas-and we also had news from our American cousins."8 While linguistics was rather effervescent, literature remained mis- trustful. Structural methods did not easily penetrate the heart of the university organization of the classical humanities, where any mention of logic or science in the field of literature was profoundly incongru- ous. "Paradoxically, we might say that the systematic overvalorization of literature as a privileged subject in the high-school and university curriculum, taught only as literary history, made it impossible to truly renew theoretical thinking before 1955-60."9 Of course, we do find once again sorne isolated innova tors in lit: erary analysis, such as Pierre Guiraud, who, at the 1960 colloquium on modern literature in Lige, presented a paper entitled "For a Semi- ology of Poetic Expression." Leo Spitzer, who also participated in this colloquium, gave three reasons to explain why France lagged behind: first, the fact that the French university was closed in on itself and uni- versity professors were unfamiliar with the work of the Russian for- malists, with Anglo-Saxon New Criticism, or with German research; second, the prevalence of studies of genesis, of traditional literary history; third, the French tradition of the scholarly, didactic practice of textual analysis. Philippe Hamon added a fourth reason: "A quasi- total misunderstanding of linguistics as an autonomous discipline. "10 A renewed approach to literature had to wait for the authority of linguistics to be accepted, which did not happen before 1960. There were sorne individual but important exceptions like Roland Barthes, who linked literature and linguistics and met with immediate and spectacular popularity. "1 remember conversations with Roland Barthes in the fifties when he said that it was absolutely necessary to read Saussure."l1 The French Breach: Andr Martinet Even if he was in the United States until 1955, Andr Martinet nonetheless dominated linguistics in France. Martinet was a grammar agrg, and, as early as 1928, he took advantage of n interesting proposaI made by Vendrys to translate Jespersen's Language. The translation led Martinet to Denmark, where he met Jespersen and Hjelmslev. Martinet had published his first article in 1933 in the Bul- letin de la socit de linguistique and had already introduced innova- 64 A Pilot Science without a Plane: Linguistics tions in phonology, which later became his He published in the Work of the Linguistic Cirele of Prague in I936, and worked with Trubetzkoy. Martinet actively participated in the renewal of European linguistics that was going on in the thirties, and in I937 he was elected to a new chair in phonology created specifically for him at the cole des Hautes tudes. The war, however, forced Martinet into exile, but not in I94I like Jakobson. In I946, the Liberation paradoxically forced Martinet to leave, not because of his own had even been a German prisoner-but because he had married a Swedish woman who had col- laborated with the Germans. He was therefore forced to abandon his familial as weil as his national roots. It was Jakobson who welcomed the exiled Martinet to New York, where he took on sorne particularly important duties as editorial director of Word, the periodical of the New York Linguistic Cirele and the most important linguistics journal in the United States. Martinet was particularly lucky in having been in Europe when Europe was in the avant-garde and then, at Jakobson's side, where he could build bridges between European and Anglo-Saxon linguistics since he taught and directed the linguistics department at Columbia University in New York from I947 to I955. When he re- turned to France in I9 5 5, his fame among linguists was worldwide and yet the reception he met with in France made elear just how marginal linguistics was at the time. "He was in a difficult situation when he ar- rived in France. 1 remember it quite well. 1 was an assistant at the Sor- bonne at the time and he appeared to the literature professors and the historians as a fearful and sc andalous reformer, an antihumanist who had to be pushed out."12 Despite his notoriety, Martinet had to get angry and threaten to resign unless he was given a tenured professor- ship at the Sorbonne. In the same year, I95 5, his major theoretical work, Economy of Phonetic Changes, appeared and was elearly in the line of the Prague Cirele. In it, he argued for an approach to linguistics that appeared more dynarric than Saussure's and that took up the Prague Cirele's emphasis on the communication function of language: That cornes from Prague. The important idea is the notion of perti- nence. Every science is based on pertinence. A science cannot de- velop independently of a metaphysics unless it concentrates on a sin- gle aspect of reality .... Yet, it is because linguistics is useful for communication that we can know what the linguist must seek .... It is senseless to do linguistic structuralism if it is not functional. 13 A Pilot Science without a Plane: Linguistics 65 Martinet therefore focused his study on the choices that language makes possible. His approach was first of all syntagmatic-inventory the possibilities to be established-before it was paradigmatic. Mar- tinet introduced a social dimension into linguistic research by con- sidering the communication function as having its own identity. However, Martinet defined the singularity of linguistic research-in studying language for and through itself-so restrictively that it cut him off from other social sciences and shut him up in the strict de- scription of linguistic function. His goal was to determine the bound- aries of distinctive basic units of language, which he called monemes (first articulation units) and phonemes (second articulation units). He codified these rules of description in what became the international best-seller of the sixties, Elements of General Linguistics. An Untraditional Path: Andr-Georges Haudricourt Andr-Georges Haudricourt was another great French linguist. Essen- tially an autodidact, his rather disconnected path and permanent mar- ginalization bear witness to the difficulties linguistics had in establish- ing itself in France and the meanders it had to take in order to go forward. In I939, the Prague Circle published an article on phonology by Haudricourt, who, in contrast to the classical grammarians, was a very curious personality. He first set foot in school only at the age of fourteen, and lived removed from urban life on a family farm in Picardy, in northern France. Haudricourt learned to write thanks to the teacher's widow in the neighboring town, and he passed the bac- calaurat on his seventh try. He went on to study agronomy and be- came an agronomist in I93I, but he was revolted forever by agron- orny. Three individuals counted considerably for him: Marcel Mauss, "who tamed me," Marc Bloch, who published his mst article in I936 in the Annales, and Marcel Cohen, his teacher become friend. 14 When Cohen joined the Resistance, he gave Haudricourt his library in order to save it from the Germans: "'Go get the books that interest you.' 1 went to Viroflay with wicker baskets, to get the books. "15 Our future linguist was going to get his supplies. At that moment Haudricourt gave up botany for linguistics and changed his specialty within the Centre National de la ltecherche Sci- entifique. Haudricourt is in Antoine Meillet's line: "Linguistics, 1 learned it with Meillet."16 But he grants no scientific recognition either to Saussure-"that poor alcoholic Swiss who died of delirium 66 A Pilot Science without a Plane: Linguistics tremens, it's grotesque!" -or to Jakobson, "that clown from Moscow, very pleasant but who spouted just about any nonsense."1? Haudri- court remained a comparatist, by contrast; his historical approach was very close to that of Meillet. Haudricourt, like Andr Martinet, had a functionalist and dia- chronie view of language. If Martinet supervised a great many theses on African languages, Haudricourt, for his part, made it possible to restore a number of Asian languages. From his interest in botany and linguistics, he adopted a concrete approach to language and rejected logico-mathematical formalism, which was eut off from the social realm. He was a very unusual personality; he considered himself to be the inventor of phonology: "Martinet would be furiously angry but, you see, 1 invented phonology myself."18 Linguistics does not lack for pilots in France, but it nonetheless remained very marginal during the fifties for want of sufficiently solid scholarly and institutional legiti- mation. This lag explains the feverish activity that followed, as well as a certain ingenuity regarding the discovery of theories, which were presented as the expressions of the latest modernity when in fact they were often already in the process of being outmoded. Ten At Alexandria's Gates The Sorbonne remained a fortress, like the Bastille, and was untake- able in the fifties. The paths of renewal were to be sinuous, therefore, and it was necessary to go to the Middle East, to Alexandria, to find one of the essential poles for defining the structuralist paradigm. We meet Aigirdas Julien Greimas, an important linguist, in Alexandria. Born in I9I7 in Lithuania, he had gone to Grenoble to study philoso- phy before the war with professors who upheld the standards of classi- callinguistics and were hostile to Saussure an theses. His professor, Du- raffour, went so far as to compare Trubetzkoy to Tino Rossi in I939, in order to explain to his audience, many of whom were Americans, the meaning of the adjective "idiot." Greimas remembers acquiring the methods of nineteenth-century linguistics with fondness, however. He was forced to return to his native Lithuania, where he spent the war years, first under Russian and then under German occupation, be- fore finding his way back to France in I945 to get his doctorate. He bitterly observed the lack of linguistic dynamism in Paris and turned away from most of the teaching that was going on in order to devote himself to his thesis on the vocabulary of style under the direction of Charles Bruneau. Immediately following the war, a small group was already forming in Paris that included Greimas, Georges Mator, and Bernard Qumada and that discovered and worked on Saussure's work with the intention of creating a new discipline: lexicology. In I949, Greimas became a lecturer in Alexandria. "It was a big 68 At Alexandria's Gates disappointment, 1 thought that we would find the Library, and there was nothing!"l But the Egyptian desert became the birthplace for a dynamic group around Greimas and Charles Singevin. For want of books, about ten European researchers met at least weekly from 1949 to 1958, around a botde of whiskey. What can you talk about together when you have a philosopher, a sociologist, a historian, and a linguist? The only common theme was to think about epistemology. 1 remerv-ber having thrown out the word, because they made fun of me at first, not really knowing very well what it entailed. Phenomenology was in style and they were doing the phenomenology of whatever. 2 Another decisive encounter took place in Alexandria and it too proved to be the beginning of a deep friendship and rich collabora- tion. Greimas and the man who would become the structuralist star, Roland Barthes, met in Alexandria, where Greimas suggested that Barthes, who had come to Egypt at the same time, read Saussure and Hjelmslev. For his part, Barthes had Greimas read the beginning of the manuscript that was to become his Michelet by Himsel(.3 "'It's very good,' commented Greimas, 'but you could use Saussure.' 'Who is Saussure?' asked Barthes. 'But one cannot not know Saussure,' an- swered Greimas, peremptorily."4 Barthes could not stay in Alexandria any longer because of pulmonary problems, but he had gotten a push, and when Greimas saw him in Paris, where he returned every summer, he maintained the valuable contact with his friend Barthes. In speak- ing of Greimas's considerable influence, Charles Singevin commented that "Barthes found the route to Greimas like Saint Paul found the route to Damascus." 5 Greimas, however, had already been converted to modern linguistics and he saw himself as heir to Saussure. This per- spective made the work of the Linguistic Cirde of Copenhagen partic- ularly seductive, and especially the work of Hjelmslev, whom he pre- sented as the only loyal heir to the teaching of the Genevan master: "The true and perhaps only successor of Saussure who has been able to make his intentions explicit and formulate them definitively."6 The Hjelmslevian Filiation Greimas saw Hjelmslev as the veritable founder of modern linguistics for a number of reasons: his very restrictive conception of language reduced to an essence, his emphasis on the Saussurean break with an At Alexandria's Gates 69 even more axiomatic method, and his desire to broaden a method into a vast semiotic field extending beyond strictly linguistic terrain. Hjelmslev defined a new discipline that he called glossematics, in keeping with the Saussure;m tradition. He emphasized the margin- alization of aIl extralinguistic reality and freed the linguist to concen- trate on a se arch for an underlying structure to the internallinguistic order, independent of aIl reference to experience. Hjelmslev defined his project in 1943 in the Prolegomena to a Theory of Language. The work was only translated in France in 1968, by Minuit. Between 1943 and 1968, then, it was essentially Barthes and Greimas who diffused Hjelmslev's work. Saussure's terms were slightly modified: signifierlsignified was expressed as (signifier)/content (signified). These semantic slippages corresponded to a desire to disso- ciate the two levels of analysis so that the structure could be conceived as separate from what it structures, and therefore to force it to a purely formaI level: "Only through typology does linguistics ri se to quite general points of view and become a science."? The mathematical model was even more central for Hjelmslev in his quest for scientificity than it was for Saussure. The structure sub- tending every linguistic sequence had to be found by abstraction based on a code combining associations and commutations. Glossematics took theories of logic as its model at the risk of ma king linguistics sur- reptitiously slip like a general epistemology, a particular case of a comprehensive logical approach, toward an ontologization of the sub- tending structures: "It is not altogether elear whether this algebra be- longs to the hypothetico-deductive phase of research or whether it is part of the way in which language itself functions."8 The princip les of logical reduction perfected by Hjelmslev helped formalism succeed in Europe: in Germany with the discovery of the baroque; in France, Focillon's discovery of the Romanesque in art; in Russia with Vladimir Propp. The same episteme tied this formaI research together. And Hjelmslev was also well known in France, where the "linguistic mi- rage" and the ambition of scientificity were particularly lively in the social sciences during the sixties. From its culminating conceptualiza- tion in the Vienna Cirele with Rudolf Carnap and Ludwig Wittgen- stein, a possible mathematization of the whole of the human sciences quickly seemed conceivable. Hjelmslev helped give form to this some- what illusory hope by his increasingly mathematical reduction of lin- guistic givens. "The postulation of objects as something different from 70 At Alexandria's Gates the terms of relationships is a superfluous axiom and consequently a mataphysical hypothesis from which linguistic science will have to be freed."9 Hjelmslev took the logic of abstraction as far as he could, constructing a self-enclosed scholasticism. This was the orientation that clearly gained the upper hand. There were other possibilities, however, in the Copenhagen Cir- cleo At the same time, Hjelmslev's elder enemy brother, Viggo Brondal, offered a slightly different linguistic orientation, which, although just as rigorous and as concerned with stnkture, was "at the same time, open to history and to movement: there was a dynamic aspect to Brondal, who held that the facts of language should be understood as they developed and not within a closed system."10 A language's sys- tem of internaI relations was not enough, according to Brondal, who agreed with Benveniste. However, "there are periods during which the most strict ideas carry the day, and that was the case for Hjelmslev and Brondal. "11 If Greimas was undisputably Hjelmslev's successor by taking glossematics as his starting point, Andr Martinet also knew Hjelmslev as early as the beginning of the thirties, when he had gone to see Jespersen in Copenhagen. "We remained in touch until his death." 12 Initially their ties were rather close. At the 1935 Phonetics Congress in London, Martinet advised Hjelmslev, who was presenting his thesis as "phonematics," to change its name: "1 told him, no, old boy, it can't he phonematics since we are not interested in substance. There can't be any 'phone.' . . . And the following year, he called it glossematics .... 1 read his work after the war and sweated hlood try- ing to understand it."13 Martinet was the successor to the Prague school, whereas Hjelm- slev, who hated Trubetzkoy, tried to create a different theory; but Martinet could not accept these antifunctionalist theses. He presented Hjelmslev's theses nevertheless at the Sorbonne, where they were unknown until their tardy translation. Paradoxically, Martinet also contributed significantly to making Hjelmslev's work known, even though he did not in the least accept it. "The Prolegomena were trans- lated late. We only had access to a French version of them in 1968. 1 first encountered this book through Martinet's presentation of it,"14 remarks Serge Martin, who applied Hjelmslevian principles to the semiotics of music. 15 Principles eliminated any transcendent element and constructed superposed hierarchies of classes, which constitute a comprehensive structure. 16 Eleven The Mother Figure of Structuralism: Roland Barthes In 1953, a book received unanimous acclaim and quickly became the symptom of new literary demands, a break with tradition and the ex- pression of a profound confusion nourished by Camus's The Stranger: Roland Barthes's Writing Degree Zero. 1 Since his meeting with Greimas in Alexandria, Barthes was no longer the Sartrean that he had been in the immediate postwar period, but he was not yet the lin- guist he would become at the end of the fifties. We can already discern those qualities that drew the largest numbers of foHowers to him, his mobility, his flexibility with regard to theories: quick to embrace them, Barthes was just as quick to disengage from them. A mythic figure for structuralism, Roland Barthes was a subtle and supple incarnation of it wrought of moods rather than of rigor. He was structuralism's best barometer, just as able to sense the disturbances of the moment as those to come. Barthes's extreme sensitivity found the means of expressing itself within the framework of structures, how- ever, although his was a shimmering structure, more a cosmogony incarnating the fusional universe of his relationship with a maternaI image than the implacable mechanism of a binarized structure. Barthes was a weather vane for structuralism. Within him, through a subtle intertextuality, aH the voices and paths of the paraligm came into play. A veritable magnet among the diverse structuralisms, Barthes was loved because he expressed more than a methodological program. He was a receptacle for the multiple variations of values of the period. 7 I 72 The Mother Figure of Structuralism: Roland Barthes Indeed, we need only examine references to his works to discern his position at the intersection of voices and values. The empire of signs continued on in him as an empire of the senses, and it is useful to jux- tapose the mother figure he incarnated with its binary other, struc- turalism's severe father figure: Jacques Lacan. Degree Zero Barthes joined in the formalist current with Writing Degree Zero, fa- voring an ethics of writing freed from Il constraints: "What we hope to do here is to sketch out this connection and to affirm the existence of a formaI reality independent of language and style."2 Barthes ad- hered to the Sartrean theme of freedom conquered through the act of writing, but he innovated, no longer situating the commitment repre- sented by writing in the content but' rather in the form. Language became a finality identified with reconquered freedom. Literature, however, was at a zero point to be reconquered. It had degenerated through its dissolution in a daily language made up of habits and pre- scriptions, and through stylistics, which leads to an autarkic mode, to an ideology in which the author acts as if he were eut off from society and reduced to a splendid isolation. Barthes recalls the theme that is specifie to modern linguistics and to structural anthropology, of the fundamental importance of ex- change, of the primitive relationship that must begin at a nodal or zero point and be defined not by its empirical content but by the fact that it allows content to establish itself relationally. We find the same search for a zero degree of familial relationships in Lvi-Strauss, for a zero de- gree of the linguistic unit in Jakobson, and for a zero degree of writing in Barthes: the search for a pact, an initial contract establishing the writer's relationship to society. In 1953, however, Barthes did not yet have a solid structuralist foundation. He was certainly receptive to Greimas's advice and already knew Brondal and Jakobson somewhat, but these remained for him curiosities among others. He was princi.., pally motivated by tracking down the ideological masks worn by liter- ary expression, a concern that remained constant in his work. Writing Degree Zero was successful because it participated in a new literary sensibility, which the New Novel would incarnate with a new stylistics beyond traditional novelistic norms. Barthes's remiuks have a manifesto quality to them, but there was also a desperation to his quest for a new writing eut off from aIl language of value, appar- The Mother Figure of Structuralism: Roland Barthes 73 ently expressing the impasse of aU forms of writing coming after the novel's high point, which was Marcel Proust. In fact, the work that Seuil published in 1953 was consecrated by the critics. Maurice Nadeau devoted eight pages to it in Les Lettres nouvelles, ending his article by celebrating the young author whom he had discovered in 1947: "An oeuvre whose beginnings must be saluted. They are re- markable. They announce an essayist who stands out from aU the oth- ers today."3 In Les Temps modernes, Jean-Bertrand Pontalis heralded above aU the birth of a writer: "There is a great writer among us and he is more than period furniture, an economic organization, or even an ideology."4 Barthes examined aU alienated forms of writing in his work: polit- ical discourse "can only conf1rm a police universe," inteUectual writ- ing is condemned to being a "paraliterature";5 the novel, with its pre- tensions to universality, is the characteristic expression of bourgeois ideology, which collapsed in the middle of the nineteenth century, al- lowing a plurality of forms of writing by which the writer positions himself in relation to the bourgeois condition. But this plurality, this deconstruction of the universal, is never more than the expression of a period no longer carried forward by the historical dialectic: "What modernity shows us in the plurality of its writings, is the impasse of its own history."6 Insofar as the creator must disrupt the established order and can no longer do so simply by adding his score to the or- chestra already poised to receive him, he can only break, write from and around the lack, the silence: "To create white writing."7 Barthes pursued and shifted Proust's quest for lost time, seeking instead a nowhere place in literature: "Literature becomes the utopia of lan- guage."8 From this was born both a new aesthetic and, for Barthes, the realization of the impossibility of writing like a writer, as well as the beginnings of a theorization of the writing/writer as a writer of modernity. Itinerary While Roland Barthes was theoreticaUy in search of a site that existed nowhere, he was quite deeply rooted in his own childhood, spent en- tirely with his mother in southwest France, in the Basque city of Bay- onne. This very dense period unfolded around his absent (ather, who had died during the First World War, less than a year after Barthes was born. Barthes compensated for this absence by overinvesting in the 74 The Mother Figure of Structuralism: Roland Barthes maternaI image: "We always simulate in the affective relationship, whether amicable or amorous, a certain maternaI space that is a secure place, the space of a gift."9 At the age of ten, Roland Barthes "came up" to Paris, to the Latin Quarter, where he went to Montaigne and Louis-le-Grand high schools and in 1935 began to study classicalliter- ature at the Sorbonne. At the same time, he was active in the theater, and together with Jacques Veille created the classical theater of the Sorbonne, which presented, among other things, Aeschylus's Perseus on May 3, 1936, the day of the Popular Front's victory. But Barthes spent the war in bed, in a sanitorium in Saint-Hilaire-du-Touvet, near Grenoble. By the war's end, he was both a Sartrean-"We discovered Sartre with a passion"10-and a Marxist. At the sanitorium, he had met a Trotskyist typographer, Georges Fourni, a friend of Maurice Nadeau, and Fourni initiated him into Marxism. Barthes's pulmonary illness and its treatment made it impossible for him to take the agrga- tion examination, but he lost the opportunity to pursue a traditional university career. He took up journalism, thanks once again to Mau- rice Nadeau, who asked him to write literary articles for Combat. Barthes took a double detour. Since a traditional university career was not possible, he left France for Romania in 1948, then for Egypt in 1949. When he returned to Paris in 1950 he no longer had any tra- ditional university affiliation and the consequences were significant. First of all, he had met Greimas in Alexandria, as we have seen, but he also developed a lifelong resentment toward the university. Barthes ceaselessly demonstrated his desire for university recognition, a desire made all the keener because he badly tolerated having only a Li- cence.!1 He only felt truly legitimated on the day in 1976 when he was elected to the Collge de France. 12 Until that point, he endlessly strug- gled with himself and confided to Louis-Jean Calvet, "You know, each time 1 publish a book, it's a thesis."13 Here again, Barthes's enduringly tenuous institutional affiliation made his a full participation in the structuralist adventure. Like most of the structuralists, he had to cir- cumvent the old Sorbonne in order to find a place. Mythologies Monthly from 1954 to 1956, Barthes sent Maurice Nadeau an article for Les Lettres nouvelles. He continued to strip contemporary myths and make an ideological critique of mass culture, which, thanks to the reconstruction of the postwar years (the "thirty glorious years," The Mother Figure of Structuralism: Roland Barthes 75 I946-76), began to become a part of French daily life. Barthes mocked petit-bourgeois ideology expressed in the tastes and values of the media, whose role was growing. For him, the ideology under attack masked an essentially ethical meaning, as Flaubert understood it, a concept that was at one and the same time social, ethical, and esthetic and included "everything that nauseates me in the average, the middle-road, the common, the mediocre, and most of aIl, the world of the stereotype." 14 Against the passive acceptance of naturalized values that have be- come unquestioningly accepted stereotypes, Barthes systematically undertook to dismantle and demystify; his project was to demonstrate how a myth functions in contemporary society. Drawing concrete ex- amples from daily IHe, he grouped together fifty-four short studies in what became one of the major works of the period: Mythologies, pub- lished by Seuil in I957. The studies were theorized only in the second part of the book, in the final essay entitled "My th Today." Here, Barthes defined a comprehensive semiological program, which clearly showed his recent linguistic training; he had just read Saussure and discovered Hjelmslev in I956. Formalization therefore followed the studies of myths of contem- porary daily life in which the petite bourgeoisie was the designated adversary: "1 have already demonstrated the petite bourgeoisie's predilection for tautological reasoning."15 These were the false truths that Barthes wanted to upset by stripping them of their artifices. One by one, he took on a number of popular "cult" images, including wrestling, the advertisement for Astra margarine, Garbo's face, steak and french fries, Michelin's Blue Guides, the new Citron, and litera- ture according to Minou Drouet. "Myth Today" owed a double debt. To Saussure (whom Barthes cites twice) for the notions of signifier/signified he uses, and to Hjelm- slev (whom he does not cite) for the distinctions between denotation and connotation and between a language-object and a metalanguage. ln his biography of Barthes, Louis-Jean Calvet points out that Barthes still hesitated about assimiliating Saussurean notions. In the preface to Mythologies, he writes that "myth is language," while at the end of the theoretical essay, the formula is "Myth is a kind of speech."16 Barthes had not yet entirely adopted Saussure's fundamental distinc- tion between language and speech, although by the time he wrote "My th Today," his conversion to linguistics was complete, and that 76 The Mother Figure of Structuralism: Roland Barthes represents in 1957 an essential tuming point in his work, and more generally: "He definitively entered linguistics the way one enters the orders."17 Fascinated by formalism, Barthes saw in semiology the means of elevating his work to a science. He could set content aside in favor of formallogic. He adopted Saussure's synchronic study as weIl, and as a result, aIl of his work took on a spatial rather than a temporal perspec- tive: "The way in which a form is present is spatial."18 Writing Degree , Zero represented yet another break, therefore, for it offered a dia- chronic approach to the relationship to writing. A myth is a particu- lady suitable object for applying Saussurean principles: "A myth's func- tion is to eliminate reality"; "A myth is constructed by the loss of the historical quality of things."19 Barthes could therefore use Saussure's valorization of synchrony as weIl as the referent's marginalization. Barthes's form of writing, his dis crete use of a code within an ac- cessible discourse, and his openness toward science and its critical corollary aIl contributed to his immense popularity and success and guaranteed him a favorably disposed reading public. Mythologies was so successful that it went weIl beyond a normal printing run in the social sciences: 29,650 copies were printed in the collection "Pierres vives" and, as of 197,35,000 copies in Points-Seuil. Even the most diverse intellectual milieus were affected, which furthered disciplinary rapprochements. The psychoanalyst Andr Green was very interested in Mythologies and reviewed it in Critique. He met Barthes on the occasion of his review in 1962, although they already knew each other through their mutual involvement in the theater in the classical theater group at the Sorbonne. Barthes was a director of studies at the cole des Hautes tudes 20 and asked Green to give a presentation on Jacques Lacan in his seminar. Which is what 1 did; it was my Lacanian period, and afterward we had a drink in a nearby caf. Barthes leaned over toward me and sai d, "You see those two over there, they come to aIl my seminars, they torture me, they argue with me in a completely unpleasant way, they want to rip me apart." He was referring to Jacques-Alain Miller and Jean-Claude Milner. 21 A New Aesthetic During the fifties, Barthes was also actively involved in a drama review, Thtre populaire. He frequently saw Jean Duvignaud, Guy Dumur, The Mother Figure of Structuralism: Roland Barthes Bernard Dort, and Morvan Lebesque and supported Jean Vilar's Peo- ple's National Theater, helping Vilar to attract the widest possible public. It was within the context of this drama criticism that Barthes saw and was impressed by a Berliner Ensemble production of Brecht's Mother Courage at the Theater of Nations in I955, and it was a shock. Barthes saw Brecht as the pers on who did in the a ter what he wanted to do with literature or with contemporary myths. Brechtian distantiation and Brecht's aestheticism completely won him over: "Brecht rejects ... aH the sticky or participa tory theatrical styles that lead the spectator to completely identify with Mother Courage, to be- come lost in her."22 Barthes saw in Brecht's theater the outline of a new ethics governing the relationship between playwright and public, a school of responsibility, a shift from psychological pathos to a real understanding of situations. Where the playwright showed in his rev- olutionary, avant-garde art that it was less a question of expressing than of implying reality, Barthes saw the very realization of the semio- logical and critical method. The structura li st project took off with Barthes. His influence was unparalleled during this period, even if he took a fair bit of liberty with respect to strict Saussurean principles or linguistic canons. But he was more an "outsider to structuralism, fundamentally a rhetori- cian."23 Georges Mounin considered Barthes's semiology to deviate from Saussure, who established the rules of a semiology of commu- nication, whereas Barthes only made a semiology of signification: "What Barthes always wanted to do was make a symptomatology of the bourgeois world. "24 For Georges Mounin, Barthes confused signs, symbols, and indices. It is true that, at the time, Barthes gave the no- tion of sign a rather broad sense, which induded everything that had any meaning. He sought the latent content of meaning, which is why Mounin considered it more legitimate to speak about a social psychol- ogy or a psychosociology th an about semiology. Even if professional linguists no longer recognized their object, Barthes's very extensive view of language would considerably con- tribute to the success of the linguistic model and to its role as a pilot SCIence. Twelve An Epistemic Exigency On December 4, I95I, Martial Guroult, an important historian of philosophy, entered the Collge de France. His candidacy was given precedence over that of Alexandre Koyr, a preference that was symp- tomatic of the period. Koyr's philosophical project resembled that of the Annales historians and he kept up regular contact with Lucien Febvre. The project he submitted in his candidacy for the Collge de France emphasized the link between the history of science and the his- tory of mentalits, embodied at that time by Lucien Febvre in his work on Martin Luther and Franois Rabelais, around the notion of mental equipment: "The history of scientific thought, as 1 understand and try to practice it, ... makes it essential to resituate works in their intellec- tuaI and spiritual contexts, and to interpret them as a function of the mental habits, preferences, and aversions of their authors."l Guroult, however, proceeded less by opening a philosophical text onto a com- prehensive historical context than by limiting himself strictly to the mental realm. His success at being elected to the Collge de France therefore "clearly underscores how limited the recognition of a prob- lematics of thehistoricization of truth was during the fifties."2 Martial Guroult had been working since the thirties, removed from media lights and unknown to the general public. In I9 5 I, he suc- ceeded tienne Gilson to the chair of the history and technology of philosophical systems. Beginning with his inaugural lecture (called a lesson), Guroult argued in favor of the fundamental importance and An Epistemic Exigency 79 a history of philosophy, des pite the perceptible between history, presented as and philosophy, which ap- pears, by contrast, as eternal and atemporal. Fusing the historian's skepticism with the philosopher's dogmatism, however, made it pos- sible for the historian of philosophy to move beyond this apparent heterogeneity. Martial Guroult proposed a solution that preserved the history of philosophy by absorbing it as a simple auxiliary science in psychol- ogy, sociology, and epistemology. He hoped that with the method- ology of the historian he could reach and restore "the presence of a certain real substance in each philosophy .... While ma king systems worthy of a history, it is philosophy itself that lifts them out of histori- cal time."3 His historical project sought to negate temporality, dia- chrony, the se arch for relationships, and the genesis of systems. One of the characteristic aspects of the structuralist paradigm is apparent in the attention given essentially to synchrony, even if Guroult owed nothing to Saussure. Guroult justified his inter est in monographs this way, arguing that they make it possible to grasp the singular structure of an author and of an opus in their internaI coherence. Guroult abandoned the search for a structure of structures, but worked at "fin ding out how each doctrine is constructed through and by means of the intricacies of its architectonie structures."4 Guroult's Method Take a specifie philosophical work, imagine it eut off from its roots and from its polemical nature in order to better describe its internaI logic, the links between its ideas, single out the lacunae and the con- tradictions. This was the method Guroult applied to Fichte, Descartes, and Spinoza. "One of the ways of penetrating the notion of structure seems to me to come from Martial Guroult." 5 He had only a limited number of followers and never established a school, but Guroult could count several admirers, such as Gilles Gaston-Granger who was his friend, and a few disciples, such as Victor Goldschmidt. His method, however, corresponded to the spirit of the times and came to constitute the very foundations of the philosophical training of many philosophers. This was true for the young generation at the end of the sixties. Marc Abls took Guroult's philosophy c1ass at the cole Normale Suprieure in Saint-Cloud: "Guroult taught us to read texts in a perspective that could be called structural. However, 80 An Epistemic Exigency one someone was joking and his viewpoint structuralist. He adamantly denied any similarity, considering himself to be a tradi- tionai professor, a true historian of philosophy."6 His teaching was supposed to make students limber for significant intellectual gymnas- tics, and at Saint-Cloud they were subjected to "the little Guroult ex- ercise." Beginning with a philosophical proposition, the exercise con- sisted in demonstrating that the demonstration could have been done another way, and more expediently. "Guroult's method was fascinat- ing for the work done on the text, an consisted in always supposing that it was possible to virtually reconstruct it."7 Guroult's didactic contribution affected an entire period. Another parameter of the structuralist paradigm that we see in Guroult was his preference for immanence freed from causalities ex- ogenous to the philosophical discourse, such as psychosociological causes. Guroult therefore eut philosophical systems off from any rep- resentational function, just as Saussure had eut the sign off from the referent, granting these systems a fundamental autonomy from exter- nal reality. Their interest did not lie in what he called their "intellec- tive mission," because "what is strictly philosophical is precisely the alitonomous reality of the work's structures."8 The historian under- stands philosophical discours es as so many "philosophical monu- ments insofar as they possess this intrinsic value ma king them inde- pendent of time."9 The document becomes a monument and Michel Foucault would later address the question of implicit architectural analogy. Restoring a work's internaI coherence requires an exhaustive, totalizing approach that is in harmony with and very sympathetic to the author's theses, the architectonies of his work, and his argumenta- tion. Guroult, in a word, defended "a holistic doctrine regarding a work."10 Defining a philosophical work as hermetic presupposes a view of the history of philosophy as discontinuous. Michel Foucault knew Guroult's work well and pushed this notion in spectacular ways. Guroult defined his methodological choices for establishing and legiti- mating an interest in the history of philosophy in his foreword to the work on Descartes.!l Relativism and skepticism had to be avoided, des pite the contradictions among the systems themselves. "The histo- rians can dispose of two techniques for this purpose: criticism, strictly speaking, and the analysis of structures." 12 An Epistemic Exigency 8r Guroult's Response to Modernity Guroult's viewpoint fully reflected a period that sought meaning in the depths of subtending structures. If critique is a necessary stage, its task was lirnited to preparing the discovery of the structure bearing the text's ultimate truth. Guroult therefore responded to the chal- lenges of the social sciences and the injunction of modernity when it shelved earlier philosophical systems based on outmoded scientific postulates. He refused to believe that philosophy had accomplished its task; philosophical structuralism, which defended the autonomous reality of philosophical systems, served as a breakwater against phi- losophy's dissolution in the social sciences. Later, others would be bolder and take their inspiration from the same method, but they came from the nascent human sciences and did not barricade them- selves behind philosophicallegitimation. This was the primary reason for the scarcity of Guroult's direct disciples. Structuralism's ringing success had drawn his potential students to other shores; Guroult's ambition had been strictly philosophical, echoing Fichte and Kant, "to realize, thanks to this methodological structuralism, the Coperni- can revolution that they had not been able to accomplish."13 He criti- cized these two philosophers for having remained prisoners of realities and their representations, and he proposed, by contrast, philosophical self-sufficiency. His approach recalled the formalism of the period: "The philosophical objective applied to the objects of the history of philosophy . . . is a way of envisaging the material of this history, which is to say the systems as objects that have a value in themselves, a reality that belongs only to them and can be explained by them alone."14 To the linguists' hermetically closed text, Guroult answered with the closure of the philosophical system on itself. The other link between Guroult and the structuralist phenome- non is the insignificance of the philosophical personality behind the system: intentionality, intersubjectivity, the dialogue begun by the creation of an oeuvre are aIl eliminated in the same way that Saussure and Hjelmslev eliminated the consciousness of the speaking subject from their linguistics. In a certain sense, and even if Guroult succes- sively exarnined Fichte, Descartes, and Spinoza, "we no longer read philosophers, there is no longer any community or intersubjectivity with thern." The relationship is one of discontinuity and of a maxi- mum distantiation from a logic whose coherence-internaI to the au- 82 An Epistemic Exigency thor and external ta the reader-must be restored. Decentering subject made it possible ta undertake sorne particularly productive re- search that defines the manner in which concepts are constituted and validated. Here again, we can recaIl the importance of this philosophi- cal orientation for Michel Foucault. Epistemology Above AlI This impetus gave epistemology a broader meaning. From a strict re- flection on scientific procedures it came to consider the social realm and to establish a real dialectic with ideology. The structuralist period was also one of epistemological reflection. Disciplines questioned their objects and the validity of their concepts and scientific ambitions; scholars tended to abandon philosophy for the social sciences, as Lvi- Strauss had done, and he was not alone. One of the great epistemolo- gists of the period, Jean Piaget, also abandoned philosophy: "The unity of science, our common goal, ... can only take place at the expense of philosophy .... The sciences have aIl dissociated themselves from phi- losophy, from mathematics at the time of the Greeks to experimental psychology toward the end of the nineteenth century."15 Sorne seemed to think that being freed of philosophy's tutelage was necessary to put the social sciences on an equal footing with the exact sciences. Piaget proposed to eliminate aIl questioning from the social sciences, beyond their specific objects, which would produce something like meta- physics. The sole criterion was to increase knowledge in a given realm. Piaget did, however, distinguish himself from the general paradigm by his interest in the historicity of ideas, and his structura li sm can there- fore be caIled genetic, as in his theory of the evolution of infantile per- ception, which, he argued, goes through several stages that he saw as so many systems of transformation aIlowing the child to assimilate new patterns and new perceptual structures.1 6 Each of these stages in- cluded a moment of equilibrium. Epistemological thinking in the social sciences depended on the changes occurring in the hard sciences, where the same formalist inflection was evident. The most striking example is the evolution in mathematics with the Bourbaki group's creation of the famous mod- ern math of the fifties and sixties. Mathematics was applied to groups of elements of an unspecified nature, and was deduced from axioms of the mother structures. The prototype was algebraic structure, the group was the ordering structure, and finally, there was the topologi- An Epistemic Exigency 83 structure. These structural models were as present in Lvi- Strauss's work, through the mediation of Andr Weil, as in Jacques Lacan's work in the topology of Borromean knots and his graphs. But, in a more broadly metaphorical manner and as a scientific condition, the social sciences were nourished by a logico-mathematical discourse that made it possible to generalize and to explain processes of self- regulation beyond the examples in question. Other disciplines also contributed: biology, and experimental psychology with its Gestalt theory, and cybernetics, which permits the perfect regulation and therefore preservation of a structure. But the most important intellectual epistemological phenomenon of the thirties occurred elsewhere. The connection between the for- malism of the hard sciences and logical positivism was being elabo- rate d, on the one hand, with the Vienna Cirele, around Moritz Schlick and Rudolf Carnap, and on the other hand, at Cambridge, England, around Bertrand Russell, as well as with the work of Ludwig Wittgen- stein, who was tied as much to the Vienna Cirele as to Bertrand Rus- sell, whom he joined in Cambridge in 1911. These logicians argued for a unified and coded science, based on formallogic, using a purely deductive method. They proposed a formalization that offered a com- mon goal for all the sciences, integrating mathematics as one among other languages. Since logic has no particular content, it could provide a common framework to account for the uni versa lit y of structures. The Vienna Cirele favored language insofar as the first philosophical problem lies at the level of meaning: logic would bec orne its tool and language its essential object. The legacy of this double logical and lin- guistic thrust was called analytic philosophy. This renewal of logic together with an effervescent theorizing in Europe left France on the sidelines. "France was blocked by the com- bined actions of Poincar and Brunschvicg."17 Whence a lag in the teaching of logic, which was not ineluded in schools of letters, nor in the teaching of philosophy, contrary to what was going on elsewhere. Bearing this in mind, semiotics in the sixties can be seen as an ersatz of this logic that escaped the French. Cavaills: Philosophy of the Concept There was, however, a French philosopher, an epistemologist, whose object of predilection was mathematics and who was associated with the beginnings of the Vienna Cirele: Jean Cavaills. But history would 84 An Epistemic Exigency interrupt the course of his work and his life very and brutally. Cavaills died a hero of the Resistance un der Nazi fire in I944 at age fort y-one. Science was for him demonstration, which is to say logic, and he called this the philosophy of the concept. This notwithstand- ing, Cavaills did not adhere to the Vienna Cirele's extreme formalism and ambition of constructing a grand logic in which mathematics would find its problems resolved. His project was to understand the operation/object dichotomy, the gesture that created the linking of mental operations and that he called ''-the idea of the idea." The fate of his thought, however, would suffer the consequences of his brutal demise. Cavaills's theses were dramatically resuscitated twenty years after his death by the success of the structura li st paradigm, and he can be credited with having laid the theoretical bases for the conceptual structuralism of the sixties. In the work that he was writing while a German prisoner of war, and which came out after the war, Cavaills introduced the concept of structure.1 8 His idea of structure was already the same as the ide a of structure that triumphed after the existentialist parenthesis. Cavaills favored structure to radically contest philosophies of consciousness. Inspired by Spinoza, Cavaills sought to construct a philosophy with- out a subject, and he already faulted Husserl's phenomenology for giving too much importance to the cogito. Here again we see the for- mali st orientation that allowed science, according to Cavaills, to escape the reign of the ambient world and common experience. The structure's truth can only be given by the very rules governing it; there is no structure of structure, no metalanguage. If exogenous elements are to be eliminated from structural analysis, the autonomous and original movement of science unfolding its own laws must be found. And this elosure, this strict autonomization of science, which cons id- ers only its discursive coherence, must be observed. Here aga in we see the parallel with Guroult's approach to philosophical texts as well as to semiological formalism. Bachelard and the Rupture Despite Cavaills's death, epistemological reflection continued in the immediate postwar period, thanks to Gaston Bachelard, who was profoundly influential for a very wide public. Bachelard explored the possibility of constituting a science of science by following the proce- dures and respecting the laws that constitute the sciences themselves. An Epistemic Exigency 85 An entire realm of reflection thus became available to epistemology, but sorne of its investment in the human subject, in experience, and in life must be relinquished. Here, closure is presented as an epistemo- logical rupture that is necessary to make way for the very procedures of rigorous thought. Bachelard attacked evolutionism and proposed relativism. Rela- tivism made it possible to restore a view of scientific development as a long progression, full of inventions as well as mistakes and mistaken paths. In a postwar period that was essentially existentialist, Bachelard remained rather isolated, but his idea of an epistemological rupture had considerable impact later. Louis Althusser adopted and reinforced it in his reading of Marx, and Michel Foucault used it in his discontin- uous notion of history. Canguilhem's Seminal Role The man who succeeded Bachelard at the Sorbonne in 1955 was less well known. Georges Canguilhem was, however, to play a major role in the epistemological thinking of the period. Bachelard's legacy of reflection on the sciences became his and he directed the Institut d'Histoire des Sciences at the University of Paris. The contrast be- tween the two men was striking, however. "Bachelard was a wine- grower from Burgundy who overflowed with vitality, whereas Can- guilhem was hard, a man of high interior tension, a Cathar by virtue of his rigor."19 Admitted to the cole Normale Suprieure in 1924, Georges Canguilhem was a student of Alain. From 1936 on, he taught at a high school in Toulouse where he was in charge of the khgne. "When 1 got to Canguilhem's class in Toulouse, in 1940,1 wanted to study classics. Canguilhem was giving a class on the Copernican revolution throughout history, starting with Kant. When 1 discovered this guy, 1 said to myself, 1 don't give a damn about literature, 1 want to study philosophy. "20 During that period, Canguilhem began to study medicine. He was a pacifist, first, and therefore a loyal disciple of Alain, but he understood the danger represented by Hitler in 1934-35, and had renounced his pacifism, with the "realization that Hitler could not be tolerated."21 He immediately made an important choice in favor of the Resistance. In a France that was essentially pro- Ptain in 1940, Canguilhem refused aU allegiance to the Vichy govern- ment. "1 did not pass the philosophy agrgation to teach Work, Fam- ily, Country,"22 he immediately told Robert Deltheil, the rector of the An Epistemic Exigency Acadmie de Toulouse. He joined the Resistance and worked actively for the Liberation-South network. He was very much affected by the Second World War, but the battle he waged did not encourage his op- timism and he maintained and transmitted a profound pessimism. His was a "tonic pessimism," however, which did not prevent him from taking action. 23 The road toward pro of was fiIled with trials and death stole dou- bly near. During the war and in the medical studies Canguilhem undertook, he was led to think about the proximity between health and illness, life and death, reason and madness. Defending his thesis, "An Essay on Problems concerning the Normal and the Pathologi- cal,"24 in 1943, he became the epistemologist of medical knowledge: "The present work is an effort ta integrate sorne medical methods and advances into philosophical speculation. "25 He questioned the notion of the normal, and demonstrated the fragility of the limits between rational and irrational, arguing that it was useless ta seek a founding moment for the norm, even in sorne Bachelardian break. Canguilhem ta ok a Nietzschean perspective, re- jecting aIl evolutionist views of the continuaI progress of science and reason. In place of the historicist discourse on the construction of medical knowledge, he proposed a search for the conceptual and insti- tutional configurations that made it possible to delineate between nor- mal and pathological. His project led him, therefore, to reject any di- alectical, Hegelian vision. "Canguilhem could not stand Hegel."26 The idea of historical progress was foreign to him, and was the basis of the pessimism in his philosophy. If the trauma of the Second World War lay at the root of his historical despair, Canguilhem had reason for this shaking up of the idea of progress, the consequences of the invention of the steam engine, the principles of energy loss, and therefore Carnot's principle: "Fire's motor force ... has contributed to the deca- dence of the idea of progress by importing concepts developed by the founders of thermodynamics into philosophy .... One quickly saw death on the other side of energy loss. "27 The same princip le illustrated Canguilhem's method and led him to cross disciplinary boundaries and to seek out epistemic coherence within the same period. His transversal cuts established what Michel Foucault later caIled epistemes. Foucault was a direct heir to Canguil- hem, who recognized him as such when he reviewed The Order of Things for Critique. At the end of his presentation of Foucault's work, An Epistemic Exigency 87 Canguilhem asked what Cavaills meant when he caUed for a philoso- phy of the concept, and he wondered if structuralism might not be an answer. Although he referred to Lvi-Strauss and to Dumzil, Michel Foucault was, for him, the philosopher of the concept for the future. Michel Foucault, for his part, emphasized the importance of Can- guilhem's teaching for him and for aU the philosophers of his period: "Take away Canguilhem and you will no longer understand much about a whole series of discussions that took place among the French Marxists, nor will you see the specificity of sociologists such as Bour- dieu, Castel, Passeron ... You will miss an entire aspect of the theo- retical work being done in psychoanalysis, and particularly by the Lacanians. "28 The Sites of Scientific Discourse Canguilhem fundamentally changed the traditional inquiry about the question of origins, which became a way of asking about the site or the institutional setting of a discourse. He established a correlation be- tween a discourse and the institutional setting that both made it possi- ble and constituted its legitimacy. Canguilhem's research on determin- ing the conditions making the enunciation of scientific knowledge possible oriented Michel Foucault's work on asylums, prisons, and madness. Canguilhem also broke with the notion of cumulative scientific progress. He argued for a discontinuist approach within which the in- ternaI frontiers of scientific knowledge were constantly displaced, suc- cessively recast, and reorganized. The history of science was no longer the progressive elucidation or step-by-step unveiling of truth, but was rather marked by aporias and failures. "For Canguilhem, error is the permanent accident around which the history of man's life and his fu- ture are wound. "29 Through his search for the bases of the validity of concepts, Canguilhem opened up a vast field of study and brought to light the relationship between the ways in which different sciences constructed their knowledge and their institutional and social reali- ties. As a result, there was a fruitful opening in philosophical to socio- historical concerns. Canguilhem's influence was also very important for the Althusserian movement. Of course, the attempt to revivify Marxist concepts was rather removed from reflections on pathology, but in both fields of study the issue was the status of science and the validity of its ide as. 88 An Epistemic Exigency Pierre Macherey wrote the first in-depth study of Canguilhem's work in January 1964 and correctly evaluated its importance.3 0 Louis Althusser himself introduced Macherey's article and welcomed this re- newal of epistemological thought that broke not only with descrip- tive, scientific chronicles but also with the idealist approach to the his- tory of scientific progress, whether mechanistic (d'Alembert, Diderot, Condorcet) or dialectical (Hegel, Husserl). Canguilhem represented a revolution in the history of science, which Pierre Macherey enthusias- tically saluted: "With the work of G._Canguilhem, we possess, in the strong sense of the term, and not according to the specialized meaning that Freud gave it-which is to say, in its objective and rational mean- ing-the analysis of a history."31 Canguilhem's antipsychologist positions reinforced the Lacanian rupture in psychoanalysis as well. He essentially made war on psy- chology and attacked its positivism by deconstructing its disciplinary edifice to demonstrate that there were many psychologies,32 He tried to destabilize psychology as a discipline by showing that its knowl- edge was not cumulative and that it brought incompatible paradigms together. Later, in the name of an archaeology and in an analogous way, Michel Foucault took on history itself. Georges Canguilhem also challenged the ethics of psychology by asking whether it was in the service of science or of the police. This mix of questioning, sociologi- cal as well as from the point of view of the history of science and moral consciousness, resulted in a productive French historical epis- temology, but "you have to see that Canguilhem's reflections on psy- chology are not epistemological as epistemology is understood every- where else in France. "33 Georges Canguilhem was an important initiator of a specifically French critical project and we see his influ- ence in the work done during the structuralist period, even if he pre- ferred to remain in the shadows of the paradigm to whose birth he greatly contributed. Michel Serres's Loganalysis This philosophy of the concept, as Cavaills wished it to be named, underwent a spectacular renewal with Michel Serres's work. Cavail- ls's and Canguilhem's thinking converged in Serres, who sought out the characteristic epistemic models of a period regardless of discipli- nary boundaries. The history of science became a series of stages, of synchronic cuts: the paradigm of the fixed point and Leibniz's har- An Epistemic Exigency 89 monics was followed by the modern age in which thermodynamics served as a model not only for all the sciences, but also for mentalits, for literature, and for all visions of the world that are completely per- meated by the dominant models. Serres could therefore see the princi- pIes of thermodynamics in Zola's Rougon-Macquart. As a result, an- other division became possible. Rather than being divided, scientific knowledge and fiction could be joined by their support for the domi- nant paradigm of the period. Mythology encountered science just as the pathological intersected the normal for Canguilhem: "Myths are full of knowledge and knowledge full of dreams and illusions."34 Error once again became consubstantial with truth. Michel Serres was doubtless the first philosopher to have de- fined a comprehensive and explicitly structuralist program in philos- ophy, as early as 196I.35 What he discerned in the critical use of a notion of structure imported from mathematics was the end of a sec- ond revolution in the twentieth century. For Serres, the symbolist nineteenth century culminated in Gaston Bachelard and the substi- tution of archetypal elements-fire, water, earth-for archetypal he- roes. Structuralism opened a new era and Serres baptized its method "logoanalysis." 36 Logoanalysis sought to purify structure of all meaningful content, cutting it off from any semantic content. "A structure is an opera- tional group with an indefinite meaning, bringing together any number of elements with an unspecified content, and a finite number of rela- tionships of an unspecified nature but whose function and certain re- sults concerning the elements are defined."37 Structural analysis would be located above meaning, contrary to a symbolic analysis, which would be crushed beneath it; whence a Kantian notion of structure to which Michel Serres adhered by distinguishing between structure and model, as Kant distinguished between noumenon and phenomenon. This 1961 text promised a very ambitious philosophical program, for although the method came from modern mathematics, it was ex- portable to all other problematic fields. A common paradigm, which Serres called loganalysis, based on cultural accumulation and disper- sion, could therefore encompass all realms of knowledge, from myths to mathematics. For Serres, this conceptual advance also made it pos- sible to once again renew ties with classicism's abstraction and to "understand suddenly the Greek miracle of mathematics and the delirious flowering of their mythology,"38 thanks to the disappearance 90 An Epistemic Exigency of the seholastic partition separating letters from science, ta the universality and the historie transversality of the projeet. In 1960, Merleau-Ponty was defining his phenomenological pro- gram, and in 1961, Michel Serres was preparing to send the struc- turalist program into orbit. It would really take off in the sixties. Thirteen A Rebel Named Jacques Lacan Where Roland Barthes evokes the shimmering image of structuralism, Jacques Lacan is the abrupt other face of the binary framework char- acterizing the structuralist paradigm, an incarnation of the severe father ever tending toward greater scientificity in order to defend ana- lytic practice. Lacan's influence during the sixties was already spec- tacular even before the major part of his work was written, for the Jacques Lacan readers discovered in his crits of I966 had already been engaged in a rupture begun in the early fifties. The unconscious was at the center of the structuralist paradigm, but not only because of the spread of psychoanalytic therapy. It was present in Lvi-Strauss's anthropology as weIl as in Saussure's distinc- tion between language and speech. The unconscious enjoyed an im- portance during this period that favored its expanding influence, and Lacan benefited from this situation. Lacan was born into a Catholic family but renounced his faith rather early on. To symbolize the break, he dropped part of his first name: Jacques-Marie became known simply as Jacques. Later, it be- came clear that this change did not suffice for breaking with a Catholic tradition that suffused a good part of his rereading of Freud. This was the first of many ruptures for Lacan, however, as he moved through different areas of knowledge that nourished his chosen field of specialization-initiaIly neuropsychiatry, and later psychoanalysis. As early as the beginning of the thirties, Lacan embraced aIl forms 92 A Rebel Named Jacques Lacan of modernity, dadaism in the arts to Hegelian thinking in poli ti- cal philosophy. He took Kojve's dasses at the cole des Hautes tudes. "Kojve's teaching exerted an influence over Lacan in the lit- erai sense of the word."l Lacan retained a number of Kojve's lessons on the Hegelian dialectic, particularly on the master/slave relation- ship, and above all his reading of Hegel, emphasizing man's decenter- ing as well as that of consciousness, Hegel's critique of metaphysics, and the priority given to the notion of desire. This notion of desire was particularly dear at the heart of Lacanian theory, which reflected Kojve's reading of Hegel accoiding to which "human history is the history of desired desires."2 Thanks to Kojve, Lacan could daim that to desire is not to des ire the other, but to des ire the desire of the other. If Hegel's teaching informed Lacan's rereading of Freud, his altogether singular mode of writing resulted above all from his interest in and as- sociation with the surrealists. He was a friend of Ren Crevel, had met Andr Breton, saluted the surrealist renewal in Salvador Dali, and, in 1939, he began to live with Georges Bataille's first wife, Sylvia, whom he married in 1953. As early as 1930, Lacan was already quite attentive ta the study of writing in his psychiatrie practice. He describes the case of a certain Marcelle, a thirty-four-year-old erotomaniac and paranoid teacher who believed she was Joan of Arc and imagined that her mission was to rein vigo rate the morals of her time. In or der to de scribe the struc- ture of her paranoia, Lacan began by examining the semantics and style of her letters.3 Later, his analysis of Aime established a decisive change because, as a student of Clrambault, he refused to integrate Freudian theory into psychiatry's organicism, and thus reversed the tra- ditional relationship between psychiatry and psychoanalysis. He in- troduced "the primacy of the unconscious in dinical study."4 The case of the psychotic Papin sisters again underscored the idea of the un- conscious as the constituent structure of the Other, as a radical alterity of oneself. In 1932, Lacan defended his doctoral thesis, "On Paranoia in its Relationship with Personality,"5 which wou Id have a resounding im- pact well beyond psychiatrie cirdes. Georges Bataille and Boris Sou- varine immediately noticed and discussed it in La Critique Sociale. 6 Lacan broke with all forms of organicism, and integrated paranoia, whose structure he defined, into Freudian categories. Structure, how- ever, cannot be the product of a phenomenologie al approach to per- A Rebel NamedJacques Lacan 93 sonality: "The specifically human meaning of human behavior is never as clear as when it is compared to animal behavior."7 As early as his thesis, we can discuss Lacan's return to Freud. He did not return in order to repeat Freud's lessons, but rather to develop them, particu- larly concerning an are a that Freud had given up: psychosis. Because for Lacan, psychoanalysis could only be useful if it could account for psychosis. The Lacan of the the sis was not yet the author of the crits, how- ever, in his geneticism. Influenced by Hegel, Lacan believed that a per- sonality is constituted in successive stages until it reaches what he called the complete personality. This progressive construction resem- bles the transparency of the triumph of rationality at the end of his- tory for Hegel. This moment was therefore still very much a "tribu- tary of geneticism; . . . the first important Lacanian doctrine is an absolutely genetic doctrine."8 In Marienbad in I936, Lacan had the opportunity to express this genetic perspective at the Fourteenth Inter- national Psychoanalytic Congress, with his "The Mirror Stage."9 At that point, Lacan was influenced by the psychologist Henri Wallon, with whom he would later part ways. At the beginning of the thirties, Wallon held that a qualitative stage existed in the child's transition from the imaginary to the sym- bolic, a process Lacan also described, but which he shifted to the un- conscious. This process entails a fundamental moment in which the child discovers the image of his own body, an identification making it possible for the ego to be structured and for the child to move beyond the prior stage of a fragmented body. Psychotics do not make this transition but remain mired in a state of subjective dispersion, forever disintegrated. Like the Hegelian dialectic, the child's mirror stage, which occurs between the age of six and eight months, has three mo- ments. First, the child sees his image reflected in the mirror as that of another that he attempts to understand; here he remains in the imagi- nary. Second, "the child is suddenly led to discover that the other in the mirror is not a real being, but an image."10 Finally, the child real- izes his primordial identification in a third moment, when he realizes that this image he recognizes is his own. But this passage is premature for the child to come to know its own body: "This is nothing more than an imaginary recognition."l1 As a result, the subject will consti- 1 tute his identity on the basis of an imaginary alienation, the victim of the traps of his spatial identification. A Rebel Named Jacques Lacan In I936 moment was presented as a stage, or in the Wal- lonian, genetic sense. Lacan addressed it again in his lecture at the International Congress of Psychoanalysis in Zurich, in I949, but this time his reading was more structura li st than genetic. Indeed, if Lacan kept the term "stage" ("The Mirror Stage as Formative of the Func- tian of the Ego as Revealed in Psychoanalytic Experience"),12 he no longer saw it as a moment in a genetic process but as a founding matrix of identification, of the relationship established by the subject between exteriority and interiority sesulting in a "configuration that cannot be superseded."13 "Stage" therefore no longer corresponded to what Lacan described. Through this imaginary identification, the child was already structured for the future, trapped by what he be- lieved to be his identity, which rendered any future attempt for the subject to gain access to itself impossible. The image of an ego refers to another self. As of the postwar period, therefore, Lacan emphasized the split between the conscious and the unconscious, based on two registers with the one exterior to the other: one's own being inevitably eludes being, the world, and consciousness. This stage became the key mak- ing the split between imaginary and the symbolic possible, the first milestone along the path of the subject's alienation. "We can see in Jacques Lacan's 'Mirror Stage' a veritable structuralist crossroads. "14 There is a discernible double influence in this new approach. On the one hand, structural linguistics and Saussure, whom Lacan had dis- covered just after the war thanks to Lvi-Strauss, and, on the other, Heideggerian themes, which took up where Hegelian dialectics left off. The future post-Mirror Stage construction of the ego, always in- creasingly eluding the forever decentered subject, corresponded to Heidegger's essence of Being, lost a little bit more each day as Being is forgotten: "The progressive discordance between the ego and being will be emphasized throughout the psyche's history."15 As of I949, therefore, Lacan was part of the structuralist para- digm even before his explicit reference to Saussure in 1953; the Mirror Stage, presented as an initial and irreversible structure that can no longer function other than by its own laws, eluded historicity. Pro- gressing from one structure to another was impossible; it was possible only to live with the structure. As of this point, Lacan completely abandoned any Hegelian notion of a possible complete personality that knows itself, which he had articulated in his thesis. The initial A Rebel Named Jacques Lacan 95 structure can never be surpassed by any possible dialectic. The uncon- scious escapes historicity in the same way that it leaves the cogito and self-consciousness in the illusions of the imago. Lacan once more took his distance from the Hegelian dialectic of desire as desire for recog- nition, which for him belonged to the imaginary, and therefore to demand rather than to desire, which only finds its proper place in the unconscious. Lacan adopted Freud's notion of a divided subject, developing its implicit critique of the Hegelian notion of absolute knowledge, considered illusory. "1 would even say that from begin- ning to end, Lacan makes a critique, and the most use fuI possible, of Hegelianism." 16 ln 1956, Lacan took issue with his master and the representative of Hegelianism, Jean Hyppolite, by presenting psychoanalysis as the possible successor not only of Hegelianism, but of philosophy. Hyp- polite had given a presentation in Lacan's seminar at the beginning of the fifties, which was published with Lacan's answerP At issue was the translation of the concept of denegation, or Verneinung. Hyppo- lite refused the underlying psychologism, which presupposes a judg- ment made in the internaI tension between affirmation and denial. His reading aimed at integrating Freudianism as a constituent stage of logos, of the Spirit as Hegel saw it in history; he "wanted, finally, to show how Freud's work could be included in a phenomenology of the contemporary mind. He was ingeniously constructing a new figure of the mind, that of a denegating consciousness. "18 For Lacan, Freud was Hegel's future. Scansion 19 Lacan innovated theoretically and clinicaily. But the step he took made him a rebel, a psychoanalyst broken off from the official organi- zation, the Socit Psychanalytique de Paris (SPP). He spoke before the SPP on a number of occasions in the early fifties to justify his prac- tice of varying the length of his sessions. The issue was to dialectize the transferential relationship by interrupting the session by a scan- sion, or pointed break, listening for the patient's meaningful word and using it to end the session, rather abruptly. These sessions quickly came to scandalize, ail the more so be- cause, as the SPP pointed out, they varied in length but were more often short, and ev,en very short. Lacan's practice became the golden apple of discord with the official psychoanalytic institution. In this re- 96 A Rebel Named Jacques Lacan spect, Lacan completely participated in the structuralist of breaking with the academicisms in power. Of course, with these very short sessions he could earn a maximum amount of money in a mini- mal amount of time. Analysis became more lucrative than being a company president, which was one way among others of legitimating the profession socially and making it possible for analysts to earn a fortune. Lacan's taste for money became legendary: "If you went out to the movies with Lacan, you had to go ta Fouquet's and have caviar. Why caviar? Because that was the mostexpensive thing on the menu," remarks Wladimir Granoff with a smile. 20 (As a Russian, he preferred whole caviar.) In a period of Taylorism, Lacan had a very highly devel- oped sense of an hourly wage. Sorne, however, believed this to be a particularly revealing principle of Lacan's thinking, one of the mas- ter's most important contributions: "Scansion, punctuation, that's what allows an utterance to be structured. What is punctuation? It is the other's time. It is what makes the intervention fundamental, in that it is articulated with the other's time. Without punctuation, the patient talks aH by himself. "21 These short sessions also had the advantage of letting Lacan mul- tiply the number of patients he saw. He wanted to gain a following outside of the school and train a generation of analysts, ma king them loyal disciples to his didactic teaching by involving them in a transfer- ential relationship of total affective dependency on him. So short ses- sions had a market value and provided the means of consolidating the Lacanian rupture. This practice, moreover, goes back to the analytic cure as Freud himself understood it. Freud did not listen to patients in the same way that Lacan did; indeed, there is no mention of the idea of scansion, but "he let certain therapies last three or six months ... , which amounts to the same idea, that of the head of a school who launches his theory on the market."22 Lacan would later be excluded from the SPP because of this practice, and would thus find himself the head of a school. Freud and Lacan therefore shared the sense of a need for a certain proselytism. Long sessions for a short time or short ses- sions for a long time, the goal is more or less the same. Today, even outside the cole de la Cause Freudienne (ECF), sorne grant the prin- ciple of scansion sorne legitimacy, considering that the unconscious is structured like a language. "We can altogether agree that a well- placed scansion intervenes in what the patient is saying, and points to something while at the same time momentarily stopping his speech in A Rebel Named Jacques Lacan 97 the analytic session," Jol Dor remarks, while regretting that this weU- founded and fruitful idea of sessions of varying length was system- aticaUy transformed into extremely short sessions because of unac- knowledged financial reasons. 23 Others, like Wladimir Granoff, believed that the only thing re- sponsible for the practice was Lacan's experience shortly after the war of being unable to resist the desire to put a patient out. Lacan later re- proached himself for having yielded to his impatience and worried about whether or not his patient would return. At the appointed hour, the patient was on his couch. "On that day, the world changes. It changes in the same way each time an analyst does something that transgresses. "24 Lacan then began to shorten his sessions, seeing each time that nothing incited his patients to leave him at aU. Beyond this personal experience, these short sessions as a therapeutic doctrine "were not at aIl interesting, they harmed no one, they never helped anyone, and are not a crime. "25 Rereading Freud The results were impressive. An entire generation of analysts was pro- foundly influenced by Lacan, not only by his seminars, but also, and even more so, by their time on his couch. Short sessions were in- dispensable if Lacan was to have such a wide influence and was to intensify the transferential relationship. In I947, at a moment of great moral distress, Jean Clavreul began an analysis with Lacan. "He was the only one who could listen to me in the way 1 needed. He was someone who metaphorized problems. "26 Serge Leclaire met Franoise Dolto, who sent him to Lacan, and he began an analysis in I949 that lasted until I953. Leclaire thus became "the first Lacanian in his- tory. "27 If sorne began a relationship with Lacan on the basis of a transferential relationship, others ended up on his couch after having gone to his seminars. Claude Cont is one such example. He was in training in psychiatry but was dissatisfied as much by psychiatry as by the way in which Freud was being read. He discovered Lacan in I957 and took his seminars. From that point on, he reread Freud and, like a whole generation, returned to Freud in the way that Lacan was advo- cating. He then spent ten years on Lacan's couch, from I959 to I969. Reading/rereading Freud was one of Lacan's major contributions. Freudian thinking regained its notoriety and a second wind at a time 98 A Rebel Named Jacques Lacan ln the fifties when "it was fashionable to consider Freud as a re- spectable ancestor, but he was no longer read. "28 Lacan, therefore, made the return to Freud possible. He took the place of the Father who pronounces his Law thanks to his charisma, his distribution of sinecures, and his beknighting of vas saIs at the risk of transforming sorne of his loyal followers into simple mimetic repro- ductions of himself. But at the same time, Lacan ensured the une on- tested success of psychoanalytic discipline in France, for at that point, it entered something of a golden age. Fourteen Rome CaUs (19 5 3 ): The Return ta Freud If General de Gaulle became a politician thanks to his rallying cry of June 18, 1940, Lacan was consecrated by his Rome address of Sep- tember 1953. But we too often forget that Lacan was initially a psy- chiatrist, and in this respect the positions he took need to be set in the discipline's epistemological context. In the thirties an important de- bate on cerebral topology in aphasia was being carried on between those who held that the are a of the brain responsible for the language problem could be determined and those who disagreed, arguing that the brain had to be considered as a whole. Psychiatry was at stake. 1 Goldstein, using the theses of Gestalttheorie, rejected the reduction- ism of what for him amounted to functionally localizing a problem within the brain. He took a structural stance according to which neu- ronal changes affect aU cerebral operations. The debate continued beyond the psychiatric world. In 1942, Merleau-Ponty published The Structure of Behavior,2 in which he defended Goldstein's position. The idea of structure, though unlike the one used during the structuralist period, was thus already a central topic in the context where Lacan, a young psychiatrist, was working. Psychiatry remained important for Lacan, not only because of his early training, but also because of his very strong friendship with Henri Ey, who became the pope of psychiatry. Ey worked in hospitals, and became the chief doctor responsible for psychiatric hospitals. He accepted a position near Chartres, in the old abbey of Bonneval, 99 IOO Rome CaUs (1953): The Return ta Freud which he transformed into a forum for important theoretical encoun- ters. Ey organized regular colloquia where psychiatrists and psycho- analysts met. He was, moreover, responsible for training an entire young generation of psychiatrists. "He had considerable moral weight as a result, and became the man behind the idea of structure in psychia- try. The rest of us, young psychiatrists at the time, therefore became completely familiar with structural thinking at a time when structural- ism was ta king off, only the structuralism that was attracting all the attention had nothing to do with that."! Claude Dumzil, the son of Georges, is a symptomatic example of a conversion from psychiatry to psychoanalysis in the mid-fifties. A stu- dent both of Henri Ey and of Daniel Lagache, Dumzil was dissatisfied with psychiatry, which was caught between phenomenological con- cerns, a psychologizing discourse, and a pharmacological wing. Feeling that he was at an impasse, he discovered Lacan's seminars at Sainte- Anne in 1954: "His was really a discourse that stood out from the oth- ers."4 As a result, he began reading Freud's complete works. Lacan's words had the effect of "a strong mental aphrodisiac; it got you work- ing."5 Not only was Lacan's discourse theoretically valuable, but it was also consistent with his clinical experience as a practitioner. For his au- dience, it played the role of free association and interpretation. This cir- cularity also allowed Lacan to control the transferential relationship with his public. His words had an impact beyond their meaning, some- thing that he could theorize. A neophyte at the time, Claude Dumzil remarks: "When 1 got to Lacan's seminar in 1954-55, he was already speaking about the name of the father and 1 heard the father's no. 6 1 understand nothing about the issues, but even then 1 was completely on target."7 50 much so that he began an analysis with Lacan shortly there- after, in 1958. But when Dumzil was on the couch, he discovered a dif- ferent dimension of Lacan. "It was horrible; suddenly the brilliant char- acter became as mute as a carp, the seductive man ripped off your dough. It was no longer theoretical; 1 was being bled."8 Lacan's rejec- tion of psychologism made his discourse seductive, but it was also re- sponsible for the cross he had to bear and for his definitive conversion to psychoanalysis. The same was true for many psychiatrists of the period. A N ecessary Lea p But what was happening in psychoanalysis during the mid-fifties? Freudian thinking seemed to be going in a direction that imperiled its Rome CaUs (1953): The Return to Freud IOI own identity. "The Freudianism we had in 1950 was a sort of medical biological mixture."9 This tendency toward biologizing the psycho- analytic break was rooted in Freud's work itself, and could be based on his phylogeneticism, but Freud remained a prisoner of the posi- tivism of his period in that respect. Nonetheless, the dominant reading of Freud in France in the fifties equated drive with instinct, desire with need. Freud was acknowledged as a good doctor who took care of neurotics with acknowledged skill. There was a double risk, therefore: psychoanalysis could lose its object, the unconscious, to a dynamic psychology, on the one hand, or, on the other hand, every kind of pathology could become a medical problem and psychoanalysis could be absorbed by psychiatry. Lacan's intervention, therefore, created a leap of almost GauIlian dimensions: "His arrivaI on the scene was without a doubt eminently salutary. He stopped a sort of tide of sludge, of illiterate imbecilities in which the official French school of analysis was slogging around."10 Wladimir Granoff illustra tes the state of perdition of analytic thinking in the grips of mortal metastases, with an example of a post- war rule in analytic practice according to which missed sessions had to be paid for. The principles determining this practice were not at aIl secondary, however, but on the contrary, they had an axiomatic value. Just after the war, 1 began a supervisory analysis with someone in whom Parisian society had invested its greatest hopes, Maurice Bouvet. 1 was part of the first generation of his supervisees. During one group supervision, a colleague described the case of a patient who was sick at the moment and was therefore not coming to his sessions. What to do? Bouvet, this great theoretician, after having thought it over carefully, answered: we can make him pay up to a temperature of 101 degrees, but not beyond. Obviously, it was a probe, a thermometer in the discipline's ass. Bouvet was, however, a worthy representative of the discipline, convincing and eminent. ll Here, as elsewhere, Lacan's intervention was salutary because, in addition to his theoretical inspiration, he brought solid scientific guar- antees to analytic practice, strict operational rules that aIlowed him to argue for the scientific autonomy of psychoanalysis with a procedural clarity that validated its degree of scientificity. Cleaning up psycho- analytic thinking and practice was significant for changing the social image of the psychoanalyst, who until that point had been seen a little I02 Rome Calls (I953): The Return tG Freud bit as a dangerous and was going ta be considered from then on as a man of science: At the time, when a psychoanalyst went out at night and invited a woman to dance, he heard, "My God, you are psychoanalyzing me!" Analysts felt like that. Yet, they began at that time to feel as if they were part of a broader activity, the way scientists feel. This was a new identity that was opening up for them at that point. 12 This scientific jolt happened at the right time. The world situation in fact favored it; it no longer offered any redible prospect of mobilizing for collective social change, and that encouraged an inward social atti- tude and a return to oneself. Psychoanalysis became the new "Eldo- rado"13 at the end of the fifties. The Break The key moment of the Lacanian break came in 1953 during an inter- naI rebellion of the Socit Psychanalytique de Paris against Sacha Nacht, who intended to acknowledge only doctors as analysts in the new Institut de Psychanalyse. Sacha Nacht was ousted as director, and Lacan was elected as the new head. But Lacan did not seek the schism; on the contrary, he did everything he could to preserve the unit y of the French school. He was very quickly obliged to resign as director and relinquish his place to Daniel Lagache; Lagache was responsible for the break. Lacan was in the minority and had ta obey; he also re- signed from the SPP. It was in this context of overt crisis that Lacan made his 1953 "Rome Report." Lacan had to cut an attractive French path, therefore, toward the unconscious. In order to do so, he needed to find sorne institutional and theoretical backers. He sought solid supporters in the two popu- lar organizations of the time, the French Communist Party (PCF) and the Catholic church. He gave a copy of his Rome speech to Lucien Bonnaf, a member of the PCF, so that the party leadership could pay attention to the theses he was developing,14 and he sent a long missive to his brother Marc-Franois, who was a monk, and whom he asked to intercede on his behalf with Pope Pius XII, hoping that the pope wou Id grant him a private audience. The pope refused, despite the trinitary order in which Lacan had just redefined Freudianism. These two failed attempts both demonstrate Lacan's concern for giving psychoanalysis a second wind, for putting an end to the crisis by an offensive and dynamic strategy of alliance. Rome CaUs (I913): The Retum ta Freud 103 AU Roads Lead to Rome The Rome Report is a return ta Freud through Hegel, Heidegger, and Lvi-Strauss, and with a touch of Saussure. Lacan had already widened his sphere of influence by that date, since he was one of the most visi- ble of the psychoanalytic figures in France, and he moved his lectures from his wife Sylvia's home to the lecture hall at Sainte-Anne Hospi- tal. To define this new doctrine of a renovated Freudianism ta king shape in the new Socit Franaise de Psychanalyse (SFP), Lacan used the structura li st paradigm, this time explicitly, as the very expression of modernity in the social sciences. He asked that the meaning of the psychoanalytic cure be rediscovered, and aspired to see psycho- analysis attain the level of a science. "To this end, we can do no better than ta return to the work of Freud." 15 This meant first of all putting sorne distance between French psychoanalysis and the fate of Ameri- can psychoanalysis, which had gotten lost in pragmatism. Lacan de- nounced the behaviorism that had affected American psychoanalysis this way, and whose goal, as the work of Erich Fromm and Sullivan indicated, was to ensure that individuals adapt to social norms, and ensure as well that order and normalization be restored. For Lacan, the basis of the return to Freud lay in a particular attentiveness to lan- guage: "Psychoanalysis has only one medium: the patient's speech. That this is obvious is no excuse for our neglecting it."16 Here, Lacan justified his practice of scansion in sessions; arguing that chronometrie halts according to a stopwatch would he better replaced with the in- ternaI logic of the patient's speech. He quite clearly and strenuously asserted the overarching priority of language: "Ir is the world of words that creates the world of things."17 Lacan again addressed the break he had established in his 1949 conference in Zurich on the Mir- ror Stage, hetween the imaginary and the symbolic. Far from a conti- nuity between the two registers, the symbolic allows the subject to distance himself from his captive relationship with the other. In an an- alytic cure, symbolization occurs thanks to a transferential relation- ship toward the analyst, whom the patient invests doubly, attributing him the position of the imaginary other and the symbolic other, of the one who is supposed to know. Analysis therefore satisfies this sym- bolic function, and Lacan bases himself on Lvi-Strauss's Elementary Structures of Kinship: "The primordial Law is therefore that which, in regulating marri age ties, superimposes the kingdom of culture on that 104 Rome CaUs (1953): The Return to Freud of a nature abandoned to the law of mating. The prohibition of incest is merely its subjective pivot. . . . This law, then is revealed clearly enough as identical with an order of language." 18 ln an approach that borrows from Heidegger, Lacan considered that the notion of science had been lost since the Theaetetus, that po si- tivism had accentuated the slow degradation that had made the human sciences inferior to the experimental sciences. As early as I953, Lacan considered that linguistics would make it possible to return to the source, and would thus clearly fulfill its role as pilot , science: "Linguistics can serve us as a guide here, since that is the role it plays in the vanguard of contemporary anthropology and we cannot possibly remain indifferent to it."19 The reference to Lvi-Strauss is explicit and in Lacan's eyes-and we will come back to this-Lvi- Strauss had made more h ~ a d w a y , even regarding the Freudian uncon- scious, than had professional psychoanalysts. The key to his success lay in the implications of the structures of language, and especially phonological structures, for the laws of marriage. Lacan rereads Freud through Saussure, giving priority to syn- chronicity: "Finally, the reference to linguistics will introduce us to the method which, by distinguishing synchronic and diachronie structur- ings in language, will enable us to understand better the different value that our language assumes in the interpretation of the resis- tances and the transference. "20 ln this way, Lacan also fully partici- pated in the structuralist paradigm and encouraged a new reading of Freud in whieh the theory of successive stages is no longer the core concern; he refers them to a basic oedipal structure that is character- ized by its universality and made autonomous with respect to all tem- poral and spatial contingencies. This structure is already in place before any history begins. "What was very important about Lacan's contribution was that he introduced this synchronic perspective in place of a diachronie perspective. "21 Unlike Saussure, whose privi- leged object was language, Lacan privileges speech, a displacement made necessary by psychoanalytic practice. However, this does not mean that speech represents the expression of a conscious subject who is master of what he says. Quite to the contrary: "1 identify myself in language, but only by losing myself in it like an object. "22 Speech is forever cut off from aU access to reality and only uses signifiers that refer to each other. Man only exists by his symbolic function and it is through this function that he must be grasped. Lacan therefore radi- Rome CaUs (1953): The Return to Freud 105 cally reverses the idea of a subject conceived as the product or the ef- fect of language; this is what gives rise to the famous formula accord- ing to which "the unconscious is structured like a language." There is no point in looking for a human essence elsewhere than in language. That is what Lacan meant when he asserted that "language is an organ"; or "the human being is characterized by the fact that his or- gans are outside of him." In his Rome Report, Lacan contrasted this symbolic function, which establishes man's identity, with the language of bees, which is valid only for the stability of the relationship with the reality it signifies. For Lacan, the Saussurean sign cut off from its referent is the quasi-ontological kernel of the human condition: "If we wanted to characterize this doctrine of language, we would have to say, finally, that it is overtly creationist. Language is a creator."23 Human existence has no other site for Lacan than this symbolic level, and he therefore naturally concurs with Saussure and Lvi-Strauss in the precedence of language, culture, exchange, and the relationship to the other. In Rome, Lacan therefore clad himself in and seized upon linguis- tic scientificity. "He was very happy to be able to ground himself in something that had a scientific basis. That was part of the plan of ac- counting for psychoanalysis in a scientific mode."24 Thanks to Lacan, psychoanalysis could defy philosophy by coming to resemble it, by demedicalizing the approach to the unconscious, and by arguing for an approach to it as discourse. It was a renovated, revitalized psycho- analysis, claiming to be the continuation of philosophical discourse, that raised this new challenge to philosophy.25 The Return to Freud by Way of Saussure In I953, Lacan knew Saussure primarily through Lvi-Strauss. After I953, he delved into Saussure directly by working on the Course on General Linguistics. This second reading provided Lacan with an en- tirely new vocabulary, which he appropriated and used brilliantly in I957 in "The Agency of the Letter in the Unconscious." In this major text, Lacan based himself completely on structural linguistics, citing Saussure as fervently as he did his friend Jakobson, who came to see him regularly in Paris, where he stayed in Lacan's wife Sylvia's apart- ment. At that point, Lacan positioned himself within Saussurean con- cepts, which he accepted with sorne modification: "What the psycho- analytic experience discovers in the unconscious is the whole structure 106 Rome Calls (1953): The Retum to Freud of language."26 He took Saussure's algorithm, which, for estab- lished linguistic scientificity-"This sign should be attributed to Ferdi- nand de Saussure"27-although Lacan imposed a certain number of changes on the Saussurean algorithm that he considered very signifi- canto He changed the symbolization, writing "Signifier" with a capital "s" and relegating "signified" to a lowercase "s." ln the same spirit, the Signifier gets placed above the bar- ~ -contrary to its position in Saussure's work. Lacan removed the arrows that, in'the CCL, indicated the insepa- rable reciprocity between the two sides of the sign, like the right and wrong sides of a piece of paper. Finally, while Saussure's bar remains, Lacan does not see it as establishing a relationship between Signifier and signified, but rather as "a barrier resisting signification. "28 Linguists are justifiably perplexed when they see how Lacan uses Saussure, but we clearly understand his point of view, which once again fully belongs to the structuralist paradigm. Lacan eliminates the referent even more radically than Saussure had, and relegates the sig- nified to a secondary position in which it is subjected to the signifying chain in a movement in which Lacan introduces "the notion of an in- cessant sliding of the signified under the signifier. "29 The subject is un- centered as a resuIt and becomes the effect of the signifier referring to another signifier, the product of the language that speaks in him. The unconscious thus becomes an effect of language, of its rules and code: "It is nonetheless true that the philosophical cogito is at the center of the mirage that renders modern man so sure of being himself even in his uncertainties about himself .... 1 think where 1 am not, and there- fore 1 am there where 1 do not think." 30 This new vision of an uncentered and split subject is aItogether consonant with the notion of the subject in other structuralist areas of the human sciences of the period. This subject is in a certain way a fic- tion that exists only through its symbolic dimension, through the sig- nifier. Even if the signifier takes precedence over the signified, its elimi- nation is not an issue. "The analytic phenomenon is incomprehensible with the essential duality of the signifier and the signified." 31 What re- mains is the interaction between these two different levels that Lacan attributes to Freud's discovery of the unconscious; for Lacan, Freud was the first structuralist. The signifier imposes a sort of passion on the signified. As we can see, Lacan twists a certain number of Saus- Rome CaUs (1953): The Return to Freud ID7 surean concepts, and if Saussure would have found the idea of the sig- nified's slippage beneath the signifier completely meaningless, the idea of the unconscious similarly eluded him. Lacan adopted the two major rhetorical figures of metaphor and metonymy, which Jakobson had already used, to account for the way in which discourse unfolds, and he assimilated these two procedures to the operations of the un- conscious. Since the unconscious is structured like a language, it is completely isologous with the rules of these procedures. The Unconscious Structured like a Language Freudian condensation can be assimilated to metaphor and displace- ment relates to metonymy. Metaphor functions like a significant sub- stitution, thereby revealing the autonomy and supremacy of the signi- fier with respect to the signified. Jol Dor's enlightening example of the metaphoric use of the term "plague" to de scribe psychoanalysis, an adjective Freud used when he got to the United States, illustrates the phenomenon: 32 SI sI S2 s2 acoustic image: "psychoanalysis" idea of psychoanalysis acoustic image: "plague" idea of a plague The metaphoric figure will establish a significant substitution of S2 for S1: rill
SI -;t @J This substitution puts S1 under the bar of meaning, which becomes the new signifier and in so doing expels the old signified: s2 (the ide a of illness, the concept of plague). With the figure of metaphor, Lacan showed that the signifying chain determines the order of the signifieds, and in I956 in his seminar, he used Edgar Poe's novella The Purloined Letter to demonstrate how the signifier takes precedence, "the realis- tic imbecility," and the fact that "the signifier's displacement deter- mines the subjects in their actions, in their destiny, in their refusaI, and IOS Rome CaUs (1953): The Return to Freud in their blindnesses."33 In Poe's novella, each of the authors-the King, the Queen, Dupin-is duped in turn and in their respective posi- tions while the letter circulates unbeknownst to any of them. Each of the actors is acted upon by the signifier's (the letter) circulation with- out knowing the signified, its contents. Moreover, in this quest for the letter, the truth is always hidden and Lacan takes up the Heideggerian theme of truth as althia. The signifier, the letter, glitters in its absence. Metonymy is another rhetorical procedure employed by the un- conscious. Metonymie transfer can take a number of forms: substitut- ing the container for the contained ("1 drink a glass"), the part for the whole, the cause for the effect, or an abstract term for a concrete one. Let us again take Jol Dor's example, with the metonymic expression "to have a couch" to signify "to be in analysis."34 The metonymy im- plies a relationship of contiguity with the previous signifier for which it is substituted: S1 s1 S2 s2
acoustic image: "analysis" the idea of being in analysis acoustic image: "couch" the idea of a couch ...... s1 @J Here, unlike in metaphor, the signifier that has been displaced does not slip beneath the bar of signification, while the signified s2 (the idea of a couch) is eliminated: "The notions of metaphor and metonymy are, from Lacan's perspective, two of the fundamental pieces of the structural conception of unconscious processes."35 By their homology with condensation and displacement, these two tropes support Lacan's hypothesis of the unconscious being struc- tured like a language. As a result, he counseled analysts to take pa- tients literally; he is faithful in this to Freud's remarks about an ana- lyst's floating attention to what the patient says. The literality of what is said reveals the signifying chain, the thread of the unconscious. We can understand how the formalist aspect of structuralism is effective Rome CaUs (I953): The Return to Freud I09 in an analysis. And Lacan counsels analysts to familiarize themselves with linguistics: "If you want to know more, read Saussure, and since a clock tower can block even the sun, 1 would add that 1 am not refer- ring to the signature to be found in psychoanalysis, but to Ferdinand, who can truly be said to be the founder of modern linguistics."36 It is the very structure of language itself therefore that gives its status to Lacan's notion of the unconscious, and thereby makes its objectifica- tion possible, its operation accessible. Freud had already said that the dream was a rebus, and Lacan takes Freud literally. But the quest for the final meaning of the rebus is always deferred by the signifying chain, which forever veils the truth, beginning with points de capiton, those elements of a patient's discourse that stop the slip of the signifier, arrest the analyst's attention, and that can of course be observed in the relationships between signifiers and signifieds, but that radically miss the incommensurable and impossible dimension of the Real. Lacan drew his vocabulary from another linguist as well, the grammarian douard Pichon, who had already emphasized the divi- sion between the ego and the "me." Lacan adopted this distinction by separating-and this time radically-the me, condemned to the imagi- nary, and the ego, the subject of the unconscious, which is itself split because of a double structuration forever cutting it off from any ac- cess to the subject of desire, just as Heidegger's Being is inaccessible to being. In 1928, Pichon had introduced the concept of forclusion, which was to become a key concept for Lacan. The issue was to name the failure of the original repression. While the process of repression lets the neurotic work on the return of repressed, "forclusion, on the contrary, never preserves anything that it rejects: forclusion simply and purely eliminates it, or draws a line through it."37 The forclusion that results in psychosis has to do with confusing the signified and the signifier. Using the linguistic sign differently therefore establishes the pathology of the psychotic: "The schizophrenic lives as of that mo- ment in a world of multiple symbols and what changes is the dimen- sion of the imaginary, of concepts. For the pers on who raves, on the other hand, a single signifier can designate any signified. The signifier is not tied to any defined concept."38 When we observe how central the signifying order is for Lacan, we cannot agree with the linguist Georges Mounin when he sees a simple synonym for "meaning in the banal sense of the term"39 in no Rome CaUs (1953): The Return to Freud Lacan's use of the notion of signifier. For Mounin, Lacan was a late- comer to linguistic contagion, the victim of "the typical enthusiasm of those who come to things late."40 Lacan, who, in 1956, summing up the situation of psychoanalysis and evaluating the effects of the struc- turalist phenomenon, once again suggested that when listening to their patients analysts be particularly attentive to their phonemes, phrases, pronouncements, pauses, scansions, cuts, sentences, and par- allels. What really makes Lacan a structuralist, therefore, are the structured linguistic underpinnings of analysis: "J. Lacan is a struc- turalist. He emphasized this in interviews. He even signed his name to the arrivaI of psychoanalysis into this current of thought."41 The role Lacan assigned to language allowed the issues of psycho- analysis to shift from what they had been in the mid-fifties-from medicalization to the fundamental importance of the analytic disci- pline at the center of the human sciences challenging philosophy and leading many philosophers astray because of their attraction to the conversion of psychoanalysis to structuralism, an attraction so power- ful that they abandoned their own discipline to convert to psycho- analysis. But Lacan did not base himself only on Saussure and Jakob- son. To consolidate the success of his enterprise of seduction and his goals of scientificity, he also used structural anthropology and there- fore Lvi-Strauss. Fifteen The Unconscious: A Symbolic Universe In his Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss ln 1950, Lvi- Strauss quoted Lacan to support his theses: For, strictly speaking, the pers on whom we cali sane is the one who is capable of alienating himself, since he consents to an existence in a world definable only by the self-other relationship (note 13): The note reads: That seems to me to be the conclusion that emerges from Dr. ]. Lacan's profound study, "Aggression in psychoanalysis," in the Revue Franaise de Psychanalyse, no. 3, ]uly-September 1948.1 Lvi-Strauss used Lacan's work very early on, even before the Rome Report, but the influence was especially clear in the other direction. Lacan broadly and quite explicitly borrowed from structural an- thropology as inspiration for rereading Freud: "We use the term struc- ture in a way that we believe Claude Lvi-Strauss's use of the term authorizes us tO."2 Lvi-Strauss's anthropological structuralism be- came the basis of Lacan's postwar rupture. Their convergence was such that Lacan constantly appealed to Lvi-Strauss (see the crits [1966]) and used him as the scientific guarantee for his approach to the unconscious. Lvi-Strauss's success in effecting a shift from physical to cultural anthropology by valorizing the linguistic model resembled Lacan's goal of demedicalizing, or debiologizing, Freudian discourse. Lacan used the search for structural in kinship links to extract the unconscious as a structure from psychologizing, behaviorist theories. III II 2 The llnconscious: A Universe This intellectual symbiosis occurred aga in st a backdrop of friendly complicity: "We were very dose friends for several years. We lunched at the Merleau-Pontys' house in Guitrancourt."3 We can be somewhat skeptical about Lvi-Strauss's frequent daims of not understanding Lacan's work, even though it is true that Lacan's baroque writing style quite dearly offended Lvi-Strauss's classicism. More fundamentally, it is certain that although Lvi-Strauss did not need Lacan's rather in- flammatory guarantee, Lacan leaned very heavily on Lvi-Strauss in order to win currency for his theses apd to broaden the intellectual range of psychoanalytic thinking. Lvi-Strauss and Freudianism What can we say about the relationship between Lvi-Strauss and psychoanalysis? Three levels need to be distinguished in order to un- derstand a certain evolution. In the first place, with respect to his training, Lvi-Strauss discovered Freud's work quite early. The father of a classmate at Janson High School 4 was a psychiatrist who worked closely with Marie Bonaparte and was one of the first in France to in- troduce Freud. Thanks to this classmate, Lvi-Strauss became immedi- ately aware of the existence of psychoanalysis. "Between I925 and I930 1 read what had been translated of Freud until then, and this therefore played a very important role in shaping my thinking." 5 The second level is the teaching of Freudian thinking for anthro- pology. Here Lvi-Strauss saw a broadening of the frameworks of the old rationalism, the possible understanding of phenomena that until then seemed to resist any logical interpretation, and the fact that the most obvious realities were neither the most profound nor the most edifying. At this level, Lvi-Strauss remained faithful to Freudian teaching. But there is a third level in which the two disciplines of anthro- pology and psychoanalysis competed in their approach to the human. Yet their relationship was too close, and could only lead to a conflict, especially since Lvi-Strauss had sorne very serious doubts about the effectiveness of psychoanalytic therapy. With respect to the growing success of analysis, therefore, Lvi-Strauss tended to consider Freud's work to be the construction of a singular Western mythology whose logic he could decipher because he, studied myths, and whose strength he could therefore evaluate. "What Freud really did was to construct grand myths."6 The logic of disciplinary confrontation therefore led The Unconscious: A Symbolic Uni verse r 13 Lvi-Strauss ta "harden" (a term he used in 1962 in Tatemism Taday)? his judgment of psychoanalysis, whereas he had initially been fasci- nated by its approach to the unconscious and had been engaged in a constant dialogue with Freud's work. As early as The Elementary Structures of Kinship in 1949, Lvi-Strauss had criticized Totem and Taboo, considering that Freud had developed a myth. But, above all, he wrote two articles on the unconscious during the same year that had the greatest influence on psychoanalysts in general and on Lacan in particular: "The Sorcerer and His Magic" and "The Effec- tiveness of Symbols." These articles were la ter reprinted in Structural Anthropology.8 Lvi-Strauss described the healing activity of the shaman and the relationship he establishes with his audience. In order to de scribe the shaman's gesture, he used the psychoanalytic term of "abreaction," a process that resembles what happens in therapy when the analyst helps the patient to rel ive a traumatic situation that is at the origin of his or her neurosis. Lvi-Strauss borrowed a psychoanalytic structure as an interpretative tool in order to better understand primitive soci- eties, but he nonetheless put some distance between himself and psy- choanalysis as a discipline: "But the distressing trend which, for sev- eral years, has tended to transform the psychoanalytic system from a body of scientific hypotheses that are experimentally verifiable in cer- tain specifie and limited cases into a kind of diffuse mythology inter- penetrating the consciousness of the group, could rapidly bring about a parallelism."9 Lvi-Strauss compared the shamanistic cure to the psychoanalytic cure to show that the parallel between them does not me an that they are similar and that although the terms of the two types of practice are both present, their positions are reversed. The Symbolic Unconscious Lvi-Strauss deeply influenced Lacan with this comparative study; he gave his own definition of the unconscious as not being the refuge of the particularities of a purely singular, individual history, but by de- historicizing the unconscious and affirming its link to the symbolic function: "[The unconscious] is reduced to a term by which we desig- na te a function: the symbolic function."10 Moreover, Lvi-Strauss called for a clearer distinction between the subconscious, the reser- voir-site of specifie memories, and the unconscious, which "is always empty, or more exactly, is as foreign to images as the stomach is ta the l I4 The Unconscious: A Symbolic Universe food which transits through it. The organ of a specific function, it lim- its itself to imposing structural laws."11 The Lvi-Straussian un- conscious is therefore foreign to individu al affects, to content, and to historicity. It is this empty site where the symbolic function takes place. We once again find the familiar hierarchies of the structural paradigm: precedence is given to an invariant over its variations, to form over content, to the signifier over the signified. As we will see, Lacan adopted this approach to the unconscious, allowing him to es- tablish "the bases of a signifying algebra"12 for psychoanalysis in the same way Lvi-Strauss ha:d done for anthropology. In his Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss, Lvi-Strauss laid out his definition of the unconscious because he borrowed it at that time principally from Mauss. Defined by its exchange function, the unconscious was the me- diating term between self and other rather than the subject's private garden. In this major text, Lvi-Strauss defined a path that Lacan would take, the path of symbolic autonomy: "Symbols are more real than what they symbolize, the signifier precedes and determines the signified." 13 The Mind There is cause for misunderstanding here, for the anthropologist's un- conscious is very much removed from the Freudian unconscious, de- spite the analogies we can see between the semantic decoding of myths and psychoanalytic interpretative techniques. For Lvi-Strauss, "the unconscious is the site of structures,"14 and is therefore defined as a system of logical constraints, a structuring whole, "the absent cause of these effects of structure that are kinship systems, rituals, forms of economic life, symbolic systems." 15 This purely formaI, empty un- conscious, this pure container, is a far cry from Freud's unconscious, which is defined by a certain number of privileged contents. In Totemism Today, Lvi-Strauss again cast aside contents and affects in his criticism of the psychoanalytic use of affectivity, emotions, and drives that correspond to the least clear level in humans and cannot lend themselves to scientific explanations. Lvi-Strauss justified the distinction between these two levels by explaining that the intellect can only account for something that is of a similar nature, and that this therefore excludes emotion. This notwithstanding, he claimed the unconscious as the specifie object of anthropology: "Ethnology is first The Unconscious: A Universc IIJ of aH a "16 whose goal, for him, is to restore universal laws governing the operations of the human mind. Of Freudian theory, which unfolds in two dimensions-the one topical in which different strata of the psychic apparatus are differen- tiated, and the other dynamic, of conflicts, reversaIs, and the evolution of forces set into play in the phenomena of repression, condensation, displacement, and censorship-Lvi-Strauss retained only the topical dimension. As a good structuralist, he held on to that dimension "that has to do with the system of sites defining the topology of the psychic apparatus."17 The unconscious makes it possible to localize the sym- bolic function and, at the same time, the universality linking it to the mind. This function is therefore freed of spatiotemporal contingencies and becomes a purely autonomous, abstract, and formai entity. When asked why he avoided the dimension of desire in his notion of the un- conscious, Lvi-Strauss answered: "Is this the fundamental dimension of the unconscious? 1 am not in the least convinced";18 and he consid- ered Freud's argument that dreams are the realization of a des ire a sin- gularly narrow view, a simple mask, a ridiculous smoke screen for hi ding our ignorance of biological reality. Rivalry: Psychoanalysis versus Anthropology In The Jealous Patter, Lvi-Strauss returned to his uninterrupted dia- logue with psychoanalysis, anddearly announced the stakes: the ri- valry between two disciplines that are both working on the uncon- scious. The "jealousy" in the title refers to the anthropologist as he observes the psychoanalyst, who can examine a circumscribed object, an individual therapy, and enjoy his place in the social body. It was therefore Lvi-Strauss himself who set the tone of the discussion by placing himself in the realm of jealousy: "The myths that are analyzed in The Jealous Patter, especially those of the Jivaro, are particularly striking in that they prefigure psychoanalytic myths. Having psycho- analysts daim them for some legitimation had to be avoided."19 He reiterated the criticism he had made of Freud-that he deciphered only according to a single code-and drew a parallel between the psy- chic life of savages and that of psychoanalysts. According to Lvi- Strauss, analysts have simply adopted the anal and oral traits that primitive societies had already discovered: "At almost every step we have encountered perfectly explicit notions and categories-such as the oral char acter and anal character-that psychoanalysts will no n6 The Unconscious: A Symbolic Universe longer be able to daim they have discovered; they have only rediscov- ered them."20 According to Lvi-Strauss, Freud is therefore to be given a place alongside myths but does not even warrant being credited with invent- ing the idea since he only recycled it in a preexisting symbolic uni- verse. The institution al stakes underlying this debate/fight for anteri- ority were even more clear: "Can we see in psychoanalysis anything other than a branch of comparative ethnology, applied to the study of the individu al psyche?"21 Lvi-Strauss even ended his book sar- castically by comparing Sophocles' Oedipus Rex with Labiche's An Italian Straw Hat, in order to grasp the same myth in two different registers. "It is a question of making psychoanalysts eat their hat,"22 Andr Green quite correctly pointed out while addressing a group of anthropologists. Lacan Appropriates the Unconscious according to Lvi-Strauss Lacan would, in his own words, use Lvi-Strauss as his defense. He quoted him in "The Mirror Stage" in 1949, and later even more so, as his many references in the crits attest. However, Lacan did much more than simply use Lvi-Strauss as a scientific guarantee; we might even wonder how far he went in borrowing his anthropological ap- proach to the unconscious and whether or not this influence repre- sented a decisive turning point with respect to Freud. Grard Mendel sees in this appropriation a shift away from Freud's notion of the unconscious toward an intellectual reduction emptying the unconscious of all contents and naturalizing it. The Freudian unconscious is composed of primary processes where repre- sentations and fantasies are played out and momentarily activated or repressed, unlike Lvi-Strauss's notion, which Lacan adopted, of a contentless unconscious: "Believing that he is speaking about the un- conscious, Lvi-Strauss never speaks about anything other than the preconscious .... What is negated here-as it was later in Lacan-is the very existence of a specific unconscious, Freud's decisive contribu- tion."23 In the name of the father Freud, Lacan, in the return of which he so often boasted, imperceptibly slid the unconscious beneath the signifying bar of the structuralist paradigm. Lacan paid a high price for his dialogue and anthropological guarantee: psychoanalysis's spe- The Unconscious: A Symbolic Universe II7 cific object, the basis its scientific identity-the unconscious. "What 1 believe and have always believed is that Lacan thought he was work- ing on the unconscious, but he was working on the preconscious .... It is completely justifiable to say that the preconscious is structured like a language. "24 Nearly ten years later, Franois Roustang, an ex-Lacanian, re- examined the same problem by arguing that Lacan's symbolic uncon- scious was only the transcription of Lvi-Strauss's ide a transplanted to psychoanalysis. 25 Borrowing the symbolic was a decisive moment in Lacan's development for he had initiaIly focused on the imaginary when studying specular images in "The Mirror Stage." He then used Lvi-Strauss to assert the irreducibility, the exteriority, of an uncon- scious that man cannot understand and whose intemallogic would be his to explain. "This exteriority of the symbolic with respect to man is the very notion of the unconscious. "26 Any historical process becomes illusory because of this heteronomy. There is a chain that traps man from as early as before his birth and after his death making him some- thing "like the pawn in the signifier's game. "27 The symbolic order can no more be attributed to an individual than to the social order; it is empty, like Lvi-Strauss's ide a of it, an exchange function. Franois Roustang saw this borrowing as the need for a new dis- placement. Abandoning the underpinnings of the social, "Lacan is forced to substantiate speech and give it sorne power ... in a word, to restore the theology of creation through the word."28 Lacan was tom between metaphysical sirens, between Saint John the Evangelist, whom he cited in an exergue to his discourse, and the model of the hard sciences, including mathematics and physics: "How much should we approach the ideals of the natural sciences, by which 1 mean such as they have developed for us, in other words, physics? WeIl, it's with respect to the se definitions of signifier and structure that the appropri- ate limits can be established. "29 Lvi-Strauss was therefore a model for psychoanalytic discourse in conquering scientificity, and Lacan en- vied him the symbiosis he was able to forge between ethnology, lin- guistics, mathematics, and psychoanalysis. If Lacan undeniably borrowed the fundamental category of the symbolic from Lvi-Strauss and displaced it from anthropology ta psychoanalysis, hypostasizing and radicalizing it with respect to Lvi- Strauss's use, analysts are not unanimous in arguing that Lacan oblit- erated Freud's notion of the unconscious. "It would be completely II 8 The Unconscious: A Symbolic Universe aberrant to say that Lacan could not reach the unconscious in a sys- tem that goes no farther than the first topiC."30 For Jol Dor, the un- conscious as a signifying chain does not invalidate the two Freudian topics but, on the contrary, clarifies them and moves beyond them. Lacan was a student of Lvi-Strauss's rigor, but he displaced the in- struments he borrowed. He adopted the idea of a structure, and of a circuit of exchange as a basis for the social dimension, but "he intro- duces the idea that Lvi-Strauss is mistaken in thinking that women are exchanged between tribes; it's the Rhallus that is exchanged."31 Despite these displacements, a common theme ran through Lvi- Strauss and Lacan in the fifties. Both strove for universality and scien- tificity, for antievolutionism, and for legitimation. Lacan said of his- tory, for example, that it was "this thing he detests for the best of reasons."32 His radical rejection of historicity, which also posed a sig- nificant problem for the analytic use of remembering, made it possible to participate in the structuralist paradigm because synchrony was given precedence. Even if we agree that Lacan reached the Freudian unconscious, we cannot ho Id that his reference to Lvi-Strauss is sim- ply a "support rather than a key that would have allowed him to open this or that secret door."33 Furthermore, Lacan was influenced not only by Lvi-Strauss but also by Monique Lvi-Strauss, a debt he pub- licly acknowledged. He in fact appropriated the formula she threw at him one day and that became a classic of his thinking: "the sender gets his message back, in reverse. " Through his symbiosis with Lvi-Strauss's work, Lacan also sought to include the progress of psychoanalysis within the general anthropological project of reflecting upon the dividing line between nature and culture. Whence the important theme of the Other for Lacan, his thinking about alterity, on what eludes reason, on the site of the lack, on the decentering of errant desire. Where Lvi-Strauss sought out these figures of alterity among the Nambikwara, Lacan de- veloped the power of the forever inaccessible Other, of an eternallack of being. Between Lvi-Strauss and Lacan there was more than a friendly encounter; the two intellectual projects of the fifties share a common kernel of understanding, a common theoretical policy, the same strategy despite the different objects of these two disciplines. Sixteen Real/Symbolic/Imaginary (RSI): The Heresy Quite paradoxically, one of Lacan's important discoveries goes un- mentioned in his Rome Report even though it preceded the lecture by two months: the famous trilogy of the Real, the Symbolic, and the Imaginary, which in July 1953 was announced as the Symbolic, the Imaginary, and the Real. "To my mind this is Lacan's great find."1 Lacan called this his theriac, the name of the best-known medication in antiquity, which long sustained the hope of finding a panacea. This was also his ternary, and later, simply RSI, or his heresy with respect to Freud. "1 think that this idea is the fruit of his use of linguistics. He was engaged at the time in a battie and he needed a policy on theory."2 The innovation therefore dates from 1953, a period dur- ing which Lvi-Strauss's influence was quite important. That the sym- bolic was at this time the first element in the tertiary order is therefore noteworthy. The structuralist influence was quite apparent in this dominant and valorized third or der, set between the Real and the Imaginary. Linguistic binarism became a triadic order, consonant with the struc- ture of Hegelian dialectics and with the Freudian topic separating the id, the ego, and the superego, even if this subdivision had another meaning for Lacan. Lacan reversed Freud; the symbolic governed the structure whereas the id, which Lacan assigned to the Real, was at the core of the drives for Freud. This was the major shift, both in lan- guage and in structure; the unconscious was no longer assigned to a II9 I20 (RSI): The Heresy sort interred Hel! from which it had ta be driven out, but could be grasped at the surface of words and in slips of the tongue. Whence the precedence that Lacan attributed ta linguistic meth- ods in Rome in 1953, even if he did not announce his discovery. In his initial topology, the Symbolic was followed by the Real, which was not to be confused with reality for it was the hidden, inaccessible side of reality; the Lacanian Real is impossible. In the same way that Heideggerian Being was absent from being, the Lacanian Real was the lack of being of reality. The Imaginary was assigned to the dual rela- tionship of the Mirror Stage and condemns the ego, beclouded by its affects, to that which is illusory. In the subject, this triad was articu- lated in an indefinite signifying chain around the initiallack of an in- accessible Real. Lacan's temary order was radically opposed to any empirical perception of desire reduced to the expression of needs. De- sire, for Lacan, was determined by the encounter with the des ire of the Other, with the mas ter signifier that once again pointed to the lack and clarified the demand. In the early fifties, Moustafa Safouan, a young philosopher con- verted to psychoanalysis, was treating a hysterical patient abandoned by his father at the age of four. Safouan was losing hope of under- standing why the image of the father continued to come up in analysis whereas the patient had never really known his father. Safouan was on the verge of giving up and retuming to philosophy when Lacan invited him to participate in the seminar he was giving at his home on the rue de Lille, where he met Didier Anzieu, Pierre Aubry, Serge Leclaire, and Octave Mannoni and began to grasp Lacan's distinction between the Imaginary, Real, and Symbolic father. This in tum helped him better understand his patient and the disastrous effects of his superego, his self-punishing behavior, and his avoidances. "These distinctions changed the way 1 listened, as an analyst, and gave new life to the manner in which 1 responded to what was communicated."3 This new light definitively convinced Safouan that psychoanalysis could be effective and that Lacan's reading was well founded. He himself began a supervisory analysis with Lacan for fifteen years. The Lacanian trilogy begins with the postulate that the subject always signifies more than he is aware of, and that there are signifiers that are uttered without in any way illustrating the subject's mastery over meanmg. RealiSymbolic/lmaginary (RSI): The Heresy UI Is Lacan a Structuralist? The year 1953 was important for two reasons: Lacan's important in- novation of the triple order and his use of the linguistic model in the Rome Report. Eisewhere he had acknowledged the existence of a be- fore and an after: "Y. G. W. O. 1. A. B. L." which has to be read as "You got working on it a bit late."4 As of this point, Jacques-Alain Miller wondered, "Is Lacan a structuralist?"5 and his answer is full of contrasts. Lacan was part of the structuralist phenomenon since his notion of structure came from Jakobson through Lvi-Strauss, but he dissociated himself from structuralism since the structuralists' structure "is coherent and complete whereas the Lacanian structure is paradoxical and uncompleted."6 Unlike hermeneutics, in which the hidden place of structure was to be discovered and decoded, Lacan's structure was in the visible world by the way it undertook to seize the living body in which it speaks, unbeknownst to that body. Unlike Saussure's structure, which established itself by opposition and was defined by the completeness of the signifier and the signifie d, the sub- ject of the unconscious in Lacanian structure remained fundamentally inaccessible, forever split, always beyond any grasp on it, a lack of being, always elsewhere. "In this respect, it seems to me to be an alto- gether peculiar structuralism because it is a the ory that, in the end, takes into account the fact that there is something that cannot be grasped, something that the theory leaves ungrasped."7 We can distinguish between a structuralism based on complete- ness and Lacan's structuralism, based on incompleteness, although both eliminate the subject from the field of investigation. Saussure and Lvi-Strauss reduced the subject to insignificance whereas Lacan overvalorized it, but because it was forever inaccessible, if not eradi- cated, the subject was avoided. Whether organic or social, the world of things remained at a distance . . There was no longer anything organic about the desire of Lacan's subject; it was disconnected from any physiological reality in the same way that the linguistic sign is cut off from any referent. Pierre Fougey- rollas, a Marxist sociologist, rejected this notion: "Freud knew that we desire sexually because we exist as human animaIs and he would have considered the ide a that we exist because we des ire a paranoid whim."8 From Fougeyrollas's point of view, Lacan reinforced Saus- sure's break between signifier/signified and proposed a personal ver- 122 (RSI): The Hercsy sion of linguistic which Franois George humorously dubs "father-version."9 Lacan wanted ta see psychoanalysis accepted as a science on a par with the hard sciences and, more precisely, a science modeled on the physical sciences. In 1953, he refused the factious opposition between the ha rd sciences and the social, or conjectural, sciences. Lacan re- called the problematic relationship between the experimental, formal- ized sciences, including physics, and nature, their anthropomorphism, and consequently the unfounded distiuction between the hard sciences and the soft sciences. Having removed this separating wall, Lacan could aspire to scientificity in psychoanalysis based on the model of the more formaI sciences: "We see how the mathematical formaliza- tion that inspired Boole's logic and even set the ory, can bring to the science of human action this structure of intersubjective time, which psychoanalytic conjecture needs in or der to assure its rigor." 10 Bonneval: The Un-conscious The schism within the cole Psychanalytique Freudienne required that psychoanalysis have a solid base with scientific aspirations and that this be part of its theoretical position. In 1960, after the Rome Report, Henri Ey, a psychiatrist and friend of Lacan, decided to organize a colloquium on the unconscious at Bonneval. The colloquium made it possible not only to bring together the two camps in French psychoanalysis-the Socit Psychanalytique de Paris (SPP), repre- sented by Serge Lebovici, Ren Diatkine, Andr Green, and Conrad Stein, among others, and the Socit Franaise de Psychanalyse, repre- sented by Serge Leclaire, Jean Laplanche, Franois Perrier, and Jean- Bertrand Pontalis-but also philosophers, including Paul Ricoeur, Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Henri Lefebvre, Jean Hyppolite, and psychi- atrists, the most frequent participants in Henri Ey's work groups.!l For Lacan, it was a question of demonstrating the scientificity of psychoanalysis to both the International Psychiatric Association (IPA) and phenomenologists by unsettling their convictions about the cen- trality of consciousness. Merleau-Ponty, while open to psychoanalytic thinking, as he demonstrated elsewhere in 1960, in Signs, disagreed with Lacan's conclusions: "1 am rather uncomfortable when 1 see that the category of language occupies so much space."12 At this collo- quium devoted entirely to the unconscious, psychoanalysis's own ob- ject, many psychiatrists gave up psychiatry in favor of psychoanalysis, Hll;',,"l'''} (RSI): The Heres)' T23 seduced Lacanian discourse, which proposed to most modern and the mst rigorous, and for which linguistics and anthro- pology served as a double guarantee. Two of Lacan's disciples, Jean Laplanche and Serge Leclaire, gave the most important talks at Bonneval. They coauthored a text in which the critical part was written by Laplanche and the more clinical part by Leclaire. Leclaire offered an extremely subtle analysis of the dream of a thirty-year-old Jewish patient (today we know that this was his own dream), intended to completely renovate the traditional treatment of dreams, limited to attempts at remembering and seeking the hidden meaning of what goes unsaid. The unicorn dream, as it was called, let him demonstrate the work and priority of the signifier. "Psychoanalysis proves therefore to be the practice of the letter .... the literaI expression is what gives the representation its particular im- portance."13 His dream illustrated Lacan's theory according to which the unconscious is structured like a language. There was a single point of divergence about which he had hoped for some discussion, which never occurred, regarding the notion of original repression: "At Bon- neval, this discussion took place with Stein, but not with Lacan. Yet the view 1 put forward differed from Lacan's, but at the time, our di- vergence went unnoticed."14 Jean Laplanche, on the other hand, remained in the Lacanian camp, but was somewhat reserved about Lacan's essential formula. That Jean Laplanche, an ex-militant of the Socialisme ou Barbarie group, evoked a certain criticism of this structuralist orientation was not surprising for he reiterated Claude Lefort's criticism of Claude Lvi-Strauss at the beginning of the fifties, although in another con- text. Together with Cornelius Castoriadis and Claude Lefort, Laplanche had been a founding member of this postwar group and had begun to be interested by psychoanalysis in the United States in I946. In New York, he had met Loewenstein, who suggested that he take classes in psychoanalysis at Harvard, and when he came back to France, Laplanche went to visit his ex-khgne professor, Ferdinand Alqui, to ask him for the name of a psychoanalyst in order to begin an analysis. Alqui told him that there was a regular series of extremely interesting lectures given by a certain Jacques Lacan. He was speaking about the Mirror Stage at the time, of identification between doves, pigeons, and pilgrim crickets. l introduced myself I24 (RSI): The Heresy and began an analysis with him. l therefore knew Lacan as a psycho- analyst for years but during that time did not allow myself to go to his seminar in order ta avoid the confusion that he often made be- tween his teaching and his analyses. 15 Laplanche was therefore in an ambiguous and frustrating situa- tion at Bonneval because he was Lacan's disciple with respect to the SPP, but, on the other hand, he wanted to voice a certain number of criticisms. Because they were not discussed, however, these reserva- tions were sacrificed to the logic of ,the different camps. Laplanche adopted the Freudian definition of the unconscious in its topical meaning, as different from the conscious as the preconscious. He ar- gued in favor of the idea of a second structure to account for Freud's distinction between the representation of a thing and of a word, the primary and secondary processes, thus giving a first nonverballevel of language for the representations of things and a second verbalized level for the representation of words. Laplanche deduced that "the un- conscious is the condition of language,"16 reversing Lacan's position and giving metaphoric and metonymic operations a secondary posi- tion, without exhausting the reality of the unconscious: "What slips, what is displaced, is the energy of the drive in its pure, unspecified state."17 Laplanche therefore rejected Lacan's use of linguistics as a model from the beginning. Later, he emphasized his disagreement by stating that the unconscious is not structured as a language, as Lacan would have it: "It is undeniable that there are elements of language in the unconscious, but repression de-structures rather than structures the se elements."18 Today, Laplanche distances himself even further from Lacan's dictum that the unconscious is structured like a language, and asserts even more radically than he did in 1960 first that language is not as structured as it is said to be by reducing it to a binary structure, and that in addition the unconscious is not made of words but of traces of things, and that its operation is completely opposed to struc- ture: 19 "The absence of negation, the coexistence of contraries, the ab- sence of judgment, no retention or maintenance of investments. "20 To Lacan's formulation he prefers "the unconscious is a like-a-language but not structured."21 Lacan, in fact, rejected Laplanche's juncture between thought and language and argued for a radical break in Saussure's algorithm. It was doubtless strategically important for Lacan to anchor psycho- ReallSymbolic/lmaginary (RSI): The Heresy I25 analysis in the discoveries of modern linguistics and to consider that "the hum an is language. "22 Given his epistemological ambitions, Lacan saw in this idea the only possibility for having psychoanalysis be part of the general semiological adventure that was taking off at the beginning of the fifties. But he refused to discuss Laplanche's text at Bonneval because unit y was supposed to reign under his aegis for tactical reasons. Lacan developed another idea, that the unconscious is an effect of language, of a cogito split between truth and knowl- edge, but only gave voice to his disagreement with his disciple in I969 in a preface written for Anika Lemaire's thesis on him. 23 Lacan also presented a paper at Bonneval, which he later re- worked considerably for the crits in I966 with the tide "Position of the Unconscious." In it, he denounced the illusions of a Carte sian cogito and of classical philosophy and its reference to an absolute knowledge la Hegel. Consciousness is entirely absorbed by the ego's specular reflection and therefore assigned to the "function of mis- understanding, which remains attached to it. "24 Lacan saw the Carte- sian cogito as a first moment, a presupposition of the unconscious. The signifier has priority over the subject, which becomes a subject insofar as a signifier represents a subject for another signifier. The sec- ond moment is one of separation or of resplitting, and he illustrated this by the newborn's birth. A newborn is not separated from its mother, as is often and mistakenly said, but from a part of itself, for when the cord is cut, the newborn loses its anatomical complement: "Breaking an egg makes a man but also an omelet."25 This initial break is ceaselessly reiterated in later life, and limits are necessary in order for this little man not to spread out in all directions and destroy everything in his path. This break makes the Real inaccessible and gives a deathlike dimension to the drive that refers back to the Real and is virtually a death drive. The unconscious, on the other hand, refers to the symbolic, and is composed of phonemes and of groups of phonemes: language is its basis. This is what allowed Lacan to say in I966: "Linguistics is surely the science on which the unconscious is based. "26 The Letter sup- plants Being: 27 this i"s the triumphant hour of the structural paradigm in psychoanalysis. Seventeen The CaU of the T ropies In the six years between the two conferences addressing the nonalign- ment of the emerging postcolonial countries, the New Delhi Confer- ence of 1949 and the Afro-Asian Conference in Bandung of 1955, a new and increasingly clear set of demands was being articulated. The traditional East-West split was being redefined; nonalignment was being asserted as a third path. The South was demanding that people of color be recognized with a dignity equal to that enjoyed by Western civilization. It was during this period of decolonization that UNESCO asked Claude Lvi-Strauss to write an essay for a collection addressing the issues of race and modern science, published as "Race and His- tory" in 1952. This decisive text was a major contribution to the theorization of the phenomenon of emancipation that was under way. Lvi-Strauss attacked racial prejudices and his argument made it possible to bring anthropology to bear on debates on society as Paul Rivet had already done before the war, and to make the shift from physical to social an- thropology quite palpable. Lvi-Strauss criticized a historical teleol- ogy based on the reproduction of the same, and proposed a different notion about the diversity of cultures and the irreducibility of differ- ence. By attacking the foundations of a Eurocentrism that was already being significantly jolted by tricontinental revolts of peoples of the third world in the process of shaking off their colonial yoke, he funda- mentally revolutionized the thinking on the subject. After him it was I26 The Cali of the Tropics l 2 7 impossible ta continue to in terms of or the hier arc hic al mold of a Western society proposed ta serve as a model to the rest of the world was broken; Western values were re- jected and their underbelly was explored. By contesting evolutionism, Lvi-Strauss remained true to the Maussian tradition without falling into the trap of localism, in which every society was contained within the little universe of its own particularities. To the contrary, Lvi- Strauss believed that each society was the expression of a concrete universal. Not only was he a guide opening the West to an under- standing of the Other, but he also made it dear that this Other could, in exchange, help the West learn something about itself, help trans- form it insofar as it was a meaningful piece of universal humanity. The structuralist approach became a beginning for understanding the Other through the idea of the intercommunicability of codes. AIl systems can communicate between themselves at the level of the tran- sition from one code to another, but "a direct dialogue cannot take place. Incomprehension cornes from the inability to go beyond one's own system. If anyone contributed to this universal humanism, it was Lvi-Strauss."l Western-centered dosure was opened up to a much larger universe based on cultural polymorphism, enriching the under- standing of what is human. Lvi-Strauss distinguished two kinds of relationship to historicity, contrasting the cumulative history of the major civilizations to the will to dissolve every innovation perceived as a threat to a primitive equi- librium. The West was not alone in this view of a cumulative history, which also operated in other dimes. Moreover, Lvi-Strauss rejected any hierarchy that considered one civilization to be more advanced th an another. Ali considerations of this order became relative by ex- amining the criteria. Western civilization was dearly advanced if tech- nology was the principal criterion, but if other criteria were brought to bear, those civilizations that seemed primitive or that Westerners considered to be the cradles of the world appeared in fact more inge- nious than the West: "If we had used the criterion of how apt a civi- lization is at conquering hostile geography, there is no doubt that the Eskimos and the Bedouins would win hands down. "2 The West lost on all but technological grounds in this game of variables. The same was true for spirituality, or for the relationship between the body and the mind, where the Orient is ahead "by many millennia"3 in its practical exercise of spirituality. In this multiple- uR The Cali of the Tropics criteria list Australians won the for complexity of kinship relationships, and Melanesians for aesthetic daring. Lvi- Strauss drew a double lesson: the evaluation of any given society is relative with respect to given criteria; human enrichment can only come from a process of coalescence of these diverse experiences, the source of new discoveries: "The only fatality, the single defect that can afflict a hum an group and prevent it from fully realizing its nature, is to be isolated."4 Lvi-Strauss spectacularly theorizecl the practice of rejecting colo- nial values. By the some token, he reappropriated those societies from the alterity in which the West had placed them, as much with respect to what we know about them as how we think about them. But differ- ence was not only the expression of the Other's irreducibility; it was also an ideological concept that lent itself to analysis. In this respect, the structuralist paradigm weakened the bases of the West's philoso- phies of totality-Vico, Comte, Condorcet, Hegel, and Marx. We can see the return of a form of thinking born with the discovery of the New World in the sixteenth century. "Western thinking was being fis- sured; Montaigne had seen that its foundations were ruined by a com- pletely heterogeneous element. This has been a constant in the West since the Greeks; power is never exercised without being based on a universal."5 Montaigne had already said that we hastened the ruin of the nations of the New World, and he deplored the fact that the so- called civilizers had been unable to establish a fraternal and compre- hensive relationship between themselves and the Indians. "Race and History" once again voiced this regret. This major essay quickly be- came the breviary for antiracist thinking. The Polemic: Caillois versus Lvi-Strauss Lvi-Strauss's article nevertheless provoked bitter cntlClsm from Roger Caillois. 6 Paradoxically, it was Caillois who would accept Lvi- Strauss into the Acadmie Franaise in 1974, when he succeeded Montherlant. Caillois did not hi de the virulence of the polemic: "The tone of your answer was so abundantly vehement, and your polemical approach so unusual in the debate of ideas, that 1 was speechless."7 As Caillois suggested, Lvi-Strauss's answer was of an unequaled vio- lence, such that he never reprinted "Diogne couch" in any other col- lections of articles. 8 What were the issues of the polemic? Roger Caillois drew an extremely interesting parallel between the The Call of the Tropics I29 emergence of certain philosophies and their periods. What he ob- served was not that philosophy reflected its period but that it fulfilled something that was lacking. Dntil Hegel, Western philosophy had es- sentially conceived of history as linear and universal, whereas the rela- tionship between the West and its empires was still incomplete and precarious. These philosophies saw a single causallink between human evolution and its effects, and exaggerated this view of singular causal- ity, whereas human evolution included very different realities. With the First World War, history truly became global; scholarly research and collective sensibilities valorized plurality and the irreducibility of differences, while at the same time this plurality was evaporating. For Roger Caillois, "Race and History" was the scholarly substance of this second position giving value to plurality, and also expressed the premonition of Western decadence. He reproached Lvi-Strauss for having attributed exaggerated virtues to peoples who had been ig- nored in the past, and he generally criticized his relativism. Caillois pointed to Lvi-Strauss's own contradictions. On the one hand, he considered aIl cultures to be equivalent and incomparable ("Progress in one culture cannot be measured by the references of another. . . . This position can be justified"), while, on the other hand, he claimed that the East was thousands of years ahead of the West in terms of the mind-body relationship.9 Lvi-Strauss's relativism took him too far afield, and Caillois contrasted the superiority of Western civilization, which for him lay in its constant curiosity about other cultures, whence ethnography, and which other cultures never felt the need to invent. "Contrary to what the proverb says, it is not that Lvi- Strauss's eye can't see his shortcomings .... The position is a noble one, but a researcher should spend his time seeing his own shortcom- ings and those of others where they really are."lO Lvi-Strauss's answer was not long in coming and it was brutal. Paradoxically, Sartre's Les Temps modernes again became the forum for developing his theses. The tone was clear from the outset: "Dio- genes proved that movement existed by walking. Mr. Roger Caillois lies down in order to avoid seeing it."ll Lvi-Strauss basically re- peated the major points of his argument without in any way granting any points to Caillois's critique. In response to the allusion to canni- balism, Lvi-Strauss answered that morality was not to be located in the kitchen, and that in terms of the number of people killed, we outdo the Papuans. But it was the violence of the polemic that was I30 The CalI of the Tropics surprising: "Mr. Caillois indulges in an exercse that begins with the antics of the head table, continues with the declarations of a preacher, and ends with the lamentation of a penitent. His style is that of the cynics and we can count him among their numbers."12 "America had its McCarthy and we have our McCaillois."13 Despite the polemical tone, this remained a major pie ce in the batde against racial prejudice in the early fifties. What's more, Caillois's intuition was right: pes- simism was gaining ground in a Europe that was in the grips of an ap- parendy inexorable decline. A Book That Made Its Mark: Tristes Tropiques 14 According to Lopold Sdar Senghor, one of the leaders of Afro- Asianism at the time, the 1955 Bandung Conference was like a global thunderclap. At the same time, civil aeronautics was ta king Western tourists to the most distant cultures. A veritable frenzy of exoticism took hold of the Old World; travel agencies were offering a range of packages for exotic trips for every taste. The gurus of the tourist in- dustry implanted themselves everywhere like so many extraterritorial, self-enclosed islands. Club Med was soon cutting up continents and offering the discovery of the Other for less, behind the fences of its camps, weIl hidden from the natives. It was during this period of shift- ing intellectual interests that Tristes Tropiques-the book event of 1955-appeared. Lvi-Strauss's triumph demonstrated how com- pletely he satisfied the collective sensibilities of the period. He made the spectacular breakthrough he had hoped for in anthropology and for the structuralist agenda, by casting both fully into the glare of the French intellectual world. At the same time, he changed his own image from that of an inhuman scientist. "1 was sick of seeing myself labeled in universities as a machine without a soul, good only for putting men into formulas."15 Curiously enough, Tristes Tropiques resulted from a double fail- ure. Lvi-Strauss had wanted above aIl to write a novel using his ethnographer's experience, but he gave up after thirty pages; the only remaining traces include the tide and a magnificent sunset. The other failure involved his first two attempts to be elected to the Collge de France; he was beaten in 1949 and aga in in 1950. At the time he was convinced that he would never be able to have a university career and so he began writing Tristes Tropiques, "which 1 never would have dared to publish if 1 had been applying for any university job whatso- The Cali of the T ropics I3 l ever."16 This episode was symptomatic of a time when the power and the innovation of the structuralist program lay in the ability to cir- cumscribe the university and to find other avenues of legitimation. Thanks to this detour, Lvi-Strauss could intervene at a more oppor- tune moment, as a travel philosopher. He looked at things with a mix- ture of scientificity, of literature, of nostalgia for lost origins, of guilt, and of redemption that made it impossible to classify his work. The subjectivity of his story demonstrated the link between the se arch for identity and the discovery of the Other, by virtue of the no- tion that ethnography gives us access to the sources of humanity, and, as Rousseau also believed, to a truth about man, who "never creates anything truly great except at the beginning."17 There is a nostalgia for origins in this outlook that only sees human history as the pale repetition of an authentic and forever lost moment of birth. "We will accede to that nobility of thought that consists ... in taking as the starting point of our reflections the indefinable grandeur of man's be- ginnings."18 In this celebration of beginnings, there is sorne measure of expiation for the West and its genocides, of which ethnography was clearly a part. Once a participant in missionary enterprises during the glorious periods of colonization, the ethnographer pleaded his mea culpa at the moment when Western values were being rejected; in ban- daging sorne moral wounds, he became part of the ebb. The tropics were so sad not only because of their acculturation, but also because of the nature of ethnography, whose very object was undeniably be- coming extinct, particularly in the area explored by Lvi-Strauss. Moreover, these civilizations were in the process of being trans- formed, demanding their own identity as they cast off their colonial identity, but also leaving their own traditions behind in order to be- come societies in ferment. Decolonization paradoxically assured the triumph of Tristes Tropiques and created a crisis for the book's orientation, which was based on immobile societies caught up in the tension between conser- vation and extinction: "The world began without man and will end without him."19 Third-world cultures, however, were not trapped in this reductionism and could open up possible channels of change, which clearly required that their identities be reforged. The social ef- fectiveness of anthropology lay not in offering an additional opening that could be inscribed in the program of package tours, but to partici- pate in its era by bringing a scientific perspective to bear on the situa- I32 The Cal! of the tion. This was Lvi-Strauss meant when, after the French defeat at Dien Bien Phu, he said that "fifty years of modest and unprestigious research undertaken by adequate numbers of ethnologists could have found solutions in Vietnam and North Africa like the one England managed in India. "20 If the anthropologist could counsel politicians, Lvi-Strauss de- fined a position as early as 1955 from which he never deviated: a sci- entist rejects all partisan struggles because he is committed to science. He withdrew from action and consideJ:ed his withdrawal to be an in- tangible rule of professional ethics, something like a monk who takes orders and withdraws from society. The ethnographer's function "will be simply to understand these other societies,"21 and in order to do so he had to accept a certain number of renunciations, of mutilations. "To understand or to act, one must choose"-such would seem to be the motta for this man who found ultimate comfort in "the medita- tion of the sage at the foot of the tree. "22 Lvi-Strauss invited us to a veritable dusk of humankind, and he even offered to convert anthro- pology into "entropology," a science that studies the processes of dis- integration. His disengagement in no way excluded the ethnologist's expression of sensibilities as he describes the Other, of course. Lvi- Strauss's sensibility and his extreme receptivity received unanimous critical acclaim and contributed to the immense popularity of Tristes Tropiques. Lvi-Strauss made it possible for us to participate in his enthusi- asm at every step of his discoveries, but, above aU, he went beyond the vogue for exoticism by restoring the underlying logic of the behavior he observed. The observer remained a man of science in search of the laws by which a society functions, requiring him to step outside of himself, despite his involvement in the field. This decentering fasci- nated the inteUectual public and the human sciences embarked on the new adventure of structuralism. Rousseau was still the model here, and Lvi-Strauss vigorously praised him: "Rousseau, our master, Rousseau, our brother, whom we have shown such ingratitude. "23 Ac- cording to Lvi-Strauss, Rousseau was a precursor for having an- swered the Cartesian cogito, "1 think, therefore 1 am," with a question whose answer was unclear: "What am I?" And the ethnologist foUows him in rejecting the evidences of the self in order to become receptive to the Other's discourse: "In truth, 1 am not myself, but the weakest, the most humble of others. This was the discovery of the Confes- The Cali of the Tropics I33 sions. "24 In his Discourse on the Origins of Inequality, Rousseau had already called for the discovery of societies that were unknown to the West, not for reasons of material wealth but in order to discover other customs that might shed light on our way of life: "Rousseau did not limit himself to foreseeing ethnography: he founded it."25 When he wrote his confessions in Tristes Tropiques, Lvi-Strauss also placed the observer who reflects upon himself and his doubts and ambitions back into a context. A Resounding Success The reverberations of Lvi-Strauss's work were spectacular for a book in the human sciences. It was an unclassifiable hybrid accessible to an exceptionally broad public. Until then, only literary or philosophical works could hope to have such an effect by addressing sorne of the major philosophical questions. This had been the case with Sartrean Existentialism, especially in its literary and theatrical versions. Sartre's influence was still important, in fact, and Lvi-Strauss published sorne excerpts of his book in Les Temps modernes. 26 But the response to the book consecrated his emancipation and that of the structuralist pro- gram. Journalists, scholars from aIl disciplines, as weIl as intellectuais of aIl political persuasions took up their pens to salute the event. In Le Figaro, Raymond Aron applauded this "supremely philo- sophical"27 book, which resumes the tradition of the philosopher's journey as he confronts difficulties, following in the tradition of The Persian Letters. For Combat, Lvi-Strauss had "the stature of a Cer- vantes," while Franois-Rgis Bastide saluted the birth of a poet and a new Chateaubriand. 28 In I:Express, Madeleine Chapsal spoke about the writings of a seer: "It has been sorne ten years since a book has come out that speaks to us so directIy. "29 The philosophy columns of Le Monde, written by Jean Lacroix, were devoted to Tristes Tropiques and suggested the paradox in Lvi-Strauss's thinking: "He denounces progress yet no one does better justice to the progress of our culture than he."30 Many commentators were seduced by his reflections on a researcher's involvement and investment in his object, in a quest that has nothing exotic about it: "He invites us first of aIl to find our- selves."31 "The reader of this book, will find above aIl a man. Isn't that what he's looking for, after all?"32 Claude Roy, the literary critic who wrote for Libration, made an exception to the rule of reviewing only literary works and wrote about Tristes Tropiques: "The most in- '34 The Cali of the Tropics teresting book the week i5 not a It is the work of an ethnog- rapher, M. Claude Lvi-Strauss."33 Le Canard enchan (Oerober 3I, I956) ev en spoke about the "refreshing tropics." More substantial surveys were published in the Annales and the Philosophical Review written by Jean Cazeneuve. Lucien Febvre had planned to speak about the work himself beeause it had completely fascinated him, but he died before doing so. Georges Bataille, the di- rector of Critique, wrote a long article entitled "A Human Book, a Great Book," in which he described the displacement of literature to- ward more specialized activities. 34 It was true that Lvi-Strauss's work, like that of Alfred Mtraux,35 was part of this new sensibility, this new relationship between writing and scientificity that goes be- yond the traditional opposition between the work of art and scientific discovery: "From the beginning, Tristes Tropiques presents itself as a work of art, not as a work of science." 36 Its literariness came not only from the fact that it was first of all the expression of a man, his feel- ings, and his style, but also that its general spirit was guided more by what attracted and seduced its author than by the simple transcription of a logical order. This shift of literature toward an ethnographie genre was so mueh an issue that the Goncourt brothers even published a communiqu saying that they regretted being unable to award their prize to Tristes Tropiques. In a long pie ce on Lvi-Strauss's work, Ren Etiemble saw in him a brother, a born heretic. Tristes Tropiques "is a book that you either take or leave. For my part, 1 take it and keep it in the treasury of my library, deeply within me."37 Etiemble agreed with Lvi-Strauss's critical perspective on Western modernity, referring to Gilberto Freyre's work describing how the French, and after them the Portuguese, dis- eovered what would later become Brazil and the physieal and moral degradation of the native populations that followed. "They did not civilize, but there are indications that they syphilized Brazil rather well," recounted Freyre, himself a Brazilian. 38 The enthusiasm was so widespread and so unanimous that certain misunderstandings were inevitable. Sorne were satisfied with a dose of exoticism, although that was what Lvi-Strauss repudiated, while oth- ers, who saw the book as the expression of an individual's sensibili- ties, were rather quickly unbalanced by the future celebration of the death of man, who is simply an ephemeral figure, "a passing efflores- cence." The most famous quid pro quo was the prize given to Lvi- The Cali of the Tropics 13) Strauss on November 30,1956, the for Golden Pen, rewards travel and exploration books. Tristes Tropiques barely won (by a vote of 5 to 4 against Jean-Claude Berryer's In the Land of the White Elephant), although the book opens with the famous \ine "1 hate traveling and explorers" and continues with "The first thing we see as we travel round the world is our own filth, thrown into the face of mankind."39 Lvi-Strauss refused the prize, which earned him a flattering, new \iterary comparison: "The new Julien Gracq. An In- di an specia\ist turns down the Golden Feather. "40 In this concert of praises, the few discordant notes had a difficult time making themselves audible. Maxime Rodinson, for example, published a critique of Tristes Tropiques 41 in which he refused Lvi- Strauss's relativism and argued in favor of a historical dialectic: "Ac- cording to this view of total relativism, nothing permits us to say that knowing Archimedes' principle is more important than knowing about our genealogy. "42 Etiemble's article, which basically praised Lvi-Strauss, made sorne criticisms. Lvi-Strauss went too far in seeing in the birth of writing the means of facilitating servility, a conclusion he drew from his observations of the Nambikwara. Etiemble replied that Hitler and Poujade began by speaking at meetings. As for turning anthropology into entropology, he observed: "Oh, no, not at aIl. ... Lvi-Strauss gives a bit too much importance to cybernetics. "43 Lvi-Strauss answered Rodinson, Andr-Georges Haudricourt, and Georges Granai in his seminar at the Muse de l'Homme on Octo- ber 15, 1956. He accused them of falsely attributing intentions to him for he did not want to construct a model of models, but sim ply to come to sorne partial and limited conclusions. Is there anything here, as Rodinson daims, to reduce Billancourt to desperation? ... Neither in "Race and History" nar in Tristes Tropiques did l intend to dis parage the idea of progress; rather l should like to see progress transferred from the rank of a universal category of human development to that of a particular mode of exis- tence, characteristic of our own society.44 Here, Lvi-Strauss took a defensive position, which he always adopted aga in st any criticism of his ahistoricism. He claimed not to be the bearer of a general philosophy but only of a partieular seientifie method. This answer remained unsatisfaetory, however, beeause it clearly veiled the undeniable philosophie al postulate of the struetural- I36 The Cali of the Tropics ist program. But the moment was not yet ripe in I9 5 5 for the great philosophical debates that would take place in the sixties. Lvi-Strauss was, at the time, at the height of the triumph of a new discipline: anthropology. The Conversion of the Philosophers The response to Lvi-Strauss was not limited to the media. He gener- aUy shook up the inteUectual world, but even more profoundly, he led a number of philosophers, historians, and economists who had bro- ken with their original discipline to the tropics, to answer the caU of foreign dimes. The young generation was aU the more attracted to this concern for reconciling one's own sensibility with a rational study of a living society with which one interacts in that the West no longer seemed to require the same kind of political commitments that it had in the pasto Tristes Tropiques was something like the symptom of a new state of mind in this respect, a wiU to understand the vanishing points without abandoning the rigors of Reason, but by applying them to new objects. Lvi-Strauss was the raUying point for many "converts." Luc de Heusch, an ethnologist already working in the Belgian Congo, today's Zaire, was one of these. A student of Marcel Griaule at the Sorbonne, he had been disappointed not to find his master's grand symbolic con- structions. He returned to France in I9 5 5 and discovered Tristes Tropiques. Although he had only cursorily glanced at The Elementary Structures of Kinship before leaving for Africa, he came back to Lvi- Straussland and adapted the methods used in Indian societies to the Bantus of Central Africa, comparing aU the variations of myths in order to understand African symbolic thinking. Lvi-Strauss's stunning success compensated for ethnology's weak incursion into the university system. The Institut d'Ethnologie had ex- isted since I925 at the Muse de l'Homme, but there was only one de- partment, and a group of teachers whose sole audience was composed of students who had come to earn the only certificate that was both literary and scientific, without any intention of becoming ethnologists. It was above aU an opportunity for philosophers needing a scientific certificate in order to earn their Licence degree to take courses directly linked to their interests. Michel Izard remembered his dissatisfaction. Of course there were clearly defined areas like cultural technology, physical anthropology, or prehistory, "but the rest seemed to us to be The Call of the Tropics I37 completely impoverished. "45 Teaching ethnology was divided either geographicaUy into the large regions of the world or thematicaUy, without any kind of organization. Therefore, the media's impact was essential for convincing the young generation that there was a viable alternative to a traditional career, that an anthropological breach could be made outside the citadel of the Sorbonne. The situation was very similar in linguistics at the same time, and this had a clear effect on their common destiny. In the mid-fifties, Tristes Tropiques and Alejo Carpentier's Le Partage des eaux resonated for Michel Izard like "a caU from else- where. "46 Lvi-Strauss was not proposing a journey to the promised land, however, but to disenchantment. It was the quest for a discovery that bore within it its own failure: "1 was sensitive to the pessimism, to this end-of-the-road aspect."47 Michel Izard therefore converted in the middle of the fifties from philosophy, at the Sorbonne, where he had already learned of Lvi-Strauss thanks to the prestige of Les Temps modernes, in which several of his major texts had already ap- peared. But ethnology was quite marginal in the training he received at the Sorbonne. His professors-Jean Hyppolite, who continued Hegel, Jean Wahl, Maurice de Gandillac, and Vladimir Janklvitch- were not interested in this new field of study. Entire areas were being ignored in this way, including analytic philosophy, epistemology, and linguistics in general. Ethnology was practically nonexistent, with a few exceptions. "We had Mikel Dufrenne as our assistant. His com- plementary thesis had to do with basic personality and he gave a course on American cultural anthropology. Later, and late for me, there was Claude Lefort, a young assistant who had been writing about Lvi-Strauss's work since 1951-52 "48 Michel Izard found epistemology more attractive. He read Georges Canguilhem and Gaston Bachelard and, on the advice of his friend Pierre Guattari, known as Flix, he took the exams for the certificate in ethnology during the year that he was working on his degree under Jean Wahl. At the Institut, he met Olivier Herrenschmidt, who had chosen history and was undergoing his conversion, thanks to a mix of anthropology, linguistics, and the history of religions. Michel Izard also met philosophers who were coming to anthropology, such as Michel Cartry. The year 1956 was supposed to be just a passing diver- sion for him, but what had started out as a detour suddenly took on I38 The Call of the Tropics an altogether different meaning: "By the end the year, 1 had U'A_iU'_U to give up philosophy in arder to do anthropology. "49 If Tristes Tropiques had a real effect on Michel Izard and led him to look toward ethnology for its research possibilities, The Elemen- tary Structures of Kinship helped him to decide to break with philoso- phy. The book's modelization, the promises of scientificity held out by the structuralist program, together with his will to "turn my back on the West, to go elsewhere, beyond our history, the history that pro- duced US,"50 aU contributed. Izard therefore took Lvi-Strauss's semi- -nars in the Fifth Section of the cole Pratique des Hautes tudes (EPHE), as well as classes from Jacques Soustelle and Roger Bastide, with the intention of becoming a professional. At the end of 1957, Lvi-Strauss offered him two research options: he could either work in Khartoum, at the Sudan Museum of Antiquities, in order to create exhibits on the black animist south, although his dossier was not yet substantial enough, or work at the Institute for Applied Human Sci- ences, which was looking for an ethnologist and a geographer to do a study in Upper Volta. Our apprentice ethnologist was involved for a year's time in a study on African territory and his conversion became definitive. The goal of the African expedition was to study a problem of population displacement created by a plan to construct a dam on one of the tributaries of the Volta. The mission was to discover why the area where the displaced population was to be sent had remained so unpopulated. "It was intelligent to ask ethnologists and geographers to study the question, because it was one of the first rimes that un- authorized displacements were being considered and that there was an attempt to understand people's reasons."51 No geographer could be found to accompany Michel Izard, so Franoise Hritier, a historian, joined him. Hritier came from a discipline that was even more eccen- tric with respect to anthropology. As a history student at the Sorbonne between 1953 and 1957, she had considered studying ancient history but her contact with philosophy students, and particularly with Michel Izard, led her to anthropology. So, in 1957, she began to take Lvi- Strauss's courses in the Fifth Section of the EPHE. "It was clear that for someone who had studied history and geography and who was preparing to take the agrgation, these things were absolutely new." 52 Franoise Hritier experienced the triple shock of discovering societies who se very existence was unknown to her, of encountering unimag- The Cali of the Tropics I39 ined rational practices, and an altogether new way of thinking. She was enthusiastic, and went on to take the ethnology certificate. She married Izard during their time in Africa. The Indianist Pole The year 1955 was clearly an important one for anthropology. Louis Dumont returned to France from Oxford and began his course at the EPHE; Fernand Braudel and Clemens Heller began the area studies program in the Sixth Section of the EPHE, which was supposed to bring many disciplines together, including anthropology, to focus on common objects. Dumont's return radically changed Olivier Herren- schmidt's plans. He had been at the Sorbonne and was specializing in the history of religions, and began his training not only in ethnology and linguistics, but with a speciality in Indian studies. Andr Martinet had just returned from America and Herrenschmidt took his courses at the Sorbonne, those of Lvi-Strauss's in the Fifth Section of the EPHE, and those given by Louis Dumont in the Sixth Section. This meeting between the study of Sanskrit, linguistics, and structural an- thropology gave him a second wind and a different sense of Indian studies, which went beyond the stage of monographs based on field- work. A group took shape around Louis Dumont that included the philosopher and Brahman specialist Madeleine Biardeau, who was appointed to the EPHE in 1960, Daniel Thorner, an American econo- mist, and Robert Lingat, a Sanskritist appointed in 1962 to a chair in Southeast Asian law and institutions. "It was a small, highly qualifie d, multidisciplinary team that was marginal to the French Indianist milieu."53 Of course this Indianist pole did not draw huge numbers because it was very demanding, and when Louis Dumont one day found him- self in front of twenty-five people, he immediately assumed that the students had made a mistake: "You are mistaken, 1 am not Ren Dumont, but Louis Dumont." 54 Indian studies remained a bit marginal in anthropology because, more than the other branches of research, they came under the authority of Sanskrit philologists. The breach that Dumont opened was contemporary with the one created by Lvi- Strauss and around the same programmatic axis, allowing the Indian- ists to get out of their ghetto and encouraging contacts with specialists in other cultural areas. I40 The Cal! of the Tropics Leroi-Gourhan and the Technical Pole A third pole contributed to anthropology's success in the mid-fifties. Andr Leroi-Gourhan was nominated in 1956 to the only chair of eth- nology at the Sorbonne, following Marcel Griaule's death. A second chair was created in 1959 and held by Roger Bastide, and a certificate of prehistoric archaeology was created in 1960-6I. Andr Leroi- Gourhan, who represented the archaeological and technical side of ethnology, was responsible for this program, and in this respect his contribution complemented Lvi-Strauss's cultural orientation. Indeed, in a colloquium in 1987, Lvi-Strauss recognized the similarity in the methodology of their undertakings. 55 One of Leroi-Gourhan's important innovations was also to privi- lege synchrony, not as Lvi-Strauss di d, based on Saussure's model, but in his method of excavation, which had ta be horizontal. This led to an important controversy at the end of the forties between horizon- talists and verticalists. Leroi-Gourhan had clear ideas about uncover- ing, and argued that it was necessary that "the earth be removed in order to let things speak horizontally." 56 The same totalizing ambition that was characteristic of the structuralist program was also present here. Leroi-Gouran's notion of ethnographie culture had as its object not so much singular cultural events as the relationships between their different branches. Coherence appeared once the pieces were assem- bled. Hlne Balfet, a student of Andr Leroi-Gourhan who gave courses on technology at the Muse de l'Homme when Leroi-Gourhan was named to the Sorbonne in 1956, clearly represented this bridge between the two poles of the anthropological universe since she was following Lvi-Strauss's work at the same time. These two orientations in anthropologie al research were to re- main separate, however, as they diverged according to their defini- tion of the relationship between work and language. Andr Leroi- Gourhan explained both by the upright position, which freed the hands and allowed them to specialize in work and prehension, leaving the mouth free for speech. However, there is no work without lan- guage, as Marx showed in his famous text on the bee and the archi- tect at the beginning of Capital. What characterized and distinguished the architect's activity is that he constructed his house mentally before building it in reality. But where was the break to be placed? Work or language? The answer differed according to Lvi-Strauss's viewpoint The Call of the Tropics I4I emphasizing language, or Leroi-Gourhan's viewpoint giving priority to praxis. But despite their differences, these two poles dynamized and de- fined the directions of anthropological research for the next thirty years. The structuralist ambition seemed to bring together a commu- nity of researchers from a variety of disciplines and with a range of personalities. The context was that of a third-world pathos, against the backdrop of the beginning of the Aigerian war, the end of the war in Indochina, and the Bandung Conference, in a France that had long refused to address the colonial question and that was suddenly discov- ering a critical reality that so profoundly affected consciousness that it created a fundamental bad conscience. All of this was more than an invitation to travel, a call of the tropics for a young generation un- comfortable in its own society. In the structuralist program, this gen- eration was offered an ambitious and rigorous program that seemed to hold out the promise of reconciling a sensibility disenchanted with reason. Eighteen Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work While anthropology was addressing the question of the Other in the West by disinterring primitive societies from the ignorance to which Eurocentric thinking had long relegated them, a philosopher was writ- ing a history of madness that looked at the unseemly side of Western reason. Beneath the triumph of reason, Michel Foucault hunted the repressed, placing himself from the outset at the edges of Western thinking and of its history. The timing was striking. Michel Foucault began to write Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason in 1956, shortly after Tristes Tropiques was published and the Bandung Con- ference had taken place. The book came out in 1961, shortly before the vian Conference and Aigerian independence. The coincidence of the se political and cultural events is completely fortuitous since Michel Foucault was not a third-world militant at the time. And yet, Madness and Civilization quickly became the symptom of a break with a certain kind of history of the Western subject. Foucault pre- sented a picture of madness, the forgotten and repressed double of reason, which he elevated from its position of exclusion. Pierre Nora had just published The French of Algeria,l and he quickly understood the parallel between his own critique of French ethnocentricity in North Africa and Foucault's critique of the ethno- centricity of reason, for as Aigerians were leaving the French political framework, they carried with them the mark of their own history of Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's \X1ork l 4 J Nora immediately wrote Foucault expressing his enthusi- asm and later published him at Gallimard. The old war horses were tired and no longer heralded, the damned were no longer glorified. The dialectic was caught in its own entanglements in 1956 while Fou- cault emphasized the forgotten and repressed in the work of reason, and he sought a new historical sensibility, forging it by giving voice ta that which history forgot, by following the tracks of reason's opera- tion. He "opened up new horizons by transforming the prison and the madhouse into grounds for reflection ... as sa many theoretical and political issues."2 Just as Lvi-Strauss was making it possible ta consider primitive societies as different by drawing them back into the purview of ratio- nal thought and reflecting upon them, Michel Foucault was on the heels of a similar adventure in which madness forces us ta rethink rea- son, clearly exposing its strengths and weaknesses. Foucault thus hunted the work of repression in the fabrication of artificial rational- izations for the apparently unintelligible; he sought out the travesties of meaning and eut through the masks of power underlying knowl- edge, marvelously illustrating the spirit of his time. "The life that is missing in our lives is ta be found at the geographic extremities (exoti- cism) or heroic horizons (the adventurous past or even the future of science fiction), or in the heights or depths of life." 3 Michel Foucault offered the philosopher a new adventure, by pushing th in king ta its limits and reflecting upon the boundaries, and for this he quickly came ta have an important place in the nascent structura li st galaxy. His role was due in part ta his prestige as a philosopher and ta his capacity ta historicize his abject. Foucault made it possible ta historicize structuralism in a way that Lvi-Strauss had not imagined when he set the primitive paradigm into place. Georges Canguilhem saw in Michel Foucault the philosopher of the concept weIl positioned for drawing together the disciplines of structuralism even if in 1961 Foucault did not yet place himself in the structuralist lineage. This was a new, and at the time uncategorizable, exigency that seemed ta disrupt disciplinary boundaries and end the phenomenological phase of the history of philosophy in France. Where did it come from? Michel Foucault, this exploder of prejudices and of consumer thinking, incessantly sought out truth even if it meant passing for a contrabandist of knowledge. His proposaIs were resolutely mode st; far from presenting himself as the spokesman of "44 Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work the correct way of thinking, he sim ply tried to sketch the contours of the thinkable. In his journey to the nether side of reason, Foucault was also a travel philosopher of sorts, and, like Nietzsche, a "rummager of the gutters" of our civilization. Foucault was a unique philosopher who clearly insisted on being seen as such, derisively rejecting all labels and vigilantly eschewing any attachments, much like a Gidean protagonist. Like Nathanael, this constantly shifting rebel can only be understood if each of the stages of a life that he constructed much like an artwork is examined in order to root his thinking as it evolved. Restoring what made Michel Foucault so unique lets us demonstrate both how he belonged to and how he diverged from the structuralist paradigm, not by reduc- ing his thought to a common mold but by showing how it was articu- lated with it. A Star Is Born Michel Foucault often evoked the difficult relationship between writ- ing and biography. He never revealed much about himself, for which Jean-Paul Aron reproached him shortly before he died of AIDS. He was born Paul-Michel Foucault on October 15, 1926, to a good, con- servative Catholic bourgeois family of doctors who were well estab- lished on both his parents' sides, in Poitiers. His father was a well- known surgeon at the Hospitaliers clinic and his mother, Anne Malapert, came from the Vendeuvre-du-Poitou, about twenty kilome- ters from Poitiers, where she owned a magnificent house called "the chteau." Like Jacques-Marie Lacan, Foucault dropped half his name "because the initiaIs read PMF, like Pierre Mends-France, said Mme Foucault";4 but, more seriously, it would seem that Foucault, who was given his father's first name, changed it out of opposition to the Name of the Father. This biographical detail sheds sorne light on the philosopher-son's later positions and his "constant denial of the dimension of paternity, of the name, one of the keys to his subjective position."5 Whence a complicated and conflictual history with psychoanalysis in general and with Lacan in particular, for Foucault did not agree that speech was one of the sites for the subject's truth. Foucault's fascination with crossing out, with the oxymoron as a rhetorical figure (amorous birds of prey often exemplifying this rhetorical figure), seems ta compul- sively repeat the paternal horizon that he wanted to destroy, without Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work I45 fully succeeding. He insisted constantly on the illusion no one speaks behind his voice, and that no one authors his texts, and in this he fully adhered to the structuralist negation of the author as weIl as the attempt at literary renewal undertaken by Georges Bataille, Mau- rice Blanchot, and Pierre Klossowski. The name of the father was thus a burden with which Foucault broke quite quickly, "a break that was difficult in this milieu. He often said to me that if he did not bec orne a doctor he had to at least be a professor at the Sorbonne."6 Foucault did not bec orne a doctor, but the medical model became a prism through which to understand the human sciences, by using their visible traces and differences negatively, by looking at their underside, much like a doctor who tries, in healing the sick and restor- ing them to health, to understand pathology. In this respect, Michel Foucault created a veritable "medical paradigm in the human sci- ences."7 Foucault had no problems in his high school, Henri IV, in Poitiers until he was about fifteen, at which point his parents put him in Saint-Stanislaus, a Catholic school, in order to finish secondary school and discipline his min d, which was increasingly critical, not to say caustic. "He was incredibly impressive, he was quite corrosive, and cast doubt on all our beliefs."8 This was another key moment in Foucault's biography, one that is essential for understanding how deeply his work was affected by the war. Foucault was given very little to confiding and never revealed his feelings in public, but later he spoke about this period in a very confi- dential context of a Canadian Indian review that preached silence and of which probably no more than ten copies were published. He con- fided what he remembered of his adolescence, in which the war and death were always present: What strikes me when 1 try to remember my impressions is that practically all my emotional memories are linked to the political situation .... 1 think that the childhood of girls and boys of my gen- eration was shaped by these important historie events. The threat of war was always at our doorstep; it shaped our existence. And then the war came .... Perhaps this is why 1 am fascinated by history and by the relationship between personal experience and the events in which we are caught up. 1 think that that was the beginning of my desire for theory.9 Thinking about war was fundamental for Foucault; it was the basis for a central paradigm in his work involving notions of strategy, I46 Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work power tactics, breaks, and power relations. In his approach to govern- ing and to every individual's ability to influence others' behavior at aIl levels of social and private activity, the problematization of war was something like an essential moment since it is where the confrontation with death was played out. This was the area on which he worked at the Collge de France at the end of the seventies and to which he had decided to devote himself after the History of Sexuality.10 He alluded to this future research in the interview he gave when he was invited to the Catholic University at Louvain: "If God grants me life, after mad- ness, crime, and sexuality, the final thing 1 would like to study would be the problem of war and the institution of war in what we might calI the military dimension of society." 11 The young Michel Foucault began his hypokhgne in Poitiers, and began preparing for the entrance examinations for the cole Nor- male Suprieure (ENS) on the rue d'Ulm in Paris. He was almost ad- mitted the first time around and then decided to move to Paris to pre- pare for the exams there. In I945 he found another Henri IV High School, in the heart of the city, and met Andr Wormser, Franois Bdarida, Robert Mausi, and Franois Furet, among others. Thanks to Jean Hyppolite's introducing his khgne students to Hegel, it became clear to Foucault that his field would be philosophy. Foucault found Hyppolite later at the ENS and even succeeded him at the Collge de France. "Those who were in khgne after the war remember Mr. Hyppolite's classes on Phenomenology of Mind: in that voice that never stopped starting and stopping as if it were medi- tating within its own movement, we not only saw the voice of a pro- fessor but we heard something of the voice of Hegel."12 Jean Hyppo- lite had translated Phenomenology of Mind and his courses gave Hegel's thinking the modernity that had been occulted behind his rep- utation as a Romantic philosopher. He had defended his thesis, "Gen- esis and Structure of the Phenomenology of Mind"13 in I947, and it was greeted in Les Temps modernes as a major event that restored Hegelianism's fundamental position in postwar philosophical think- ing, in the legacy of the teaching of Jean Wahl and Alexandre Kojve. Even as late as I975, Foucault sent Jean Hyppolite's wife a copy of The Birth of the Clinic: An Archaeology of Medical Perception,14 and dedicated it "To Madame Hyppolite, in memory of him to whom 1 owe everything."15 One of Foucault's major texts, "Nietzsche, Ge- nealogy, and History,"16 was written for a collective work in honor of Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work I47 Jean Hyppolite. Contributors included Georges Canguilhem, Martial Guroult, Jean Laplanche, Michel Serres, and Jean-Claude Pariente.17 Mental Illness In I946, Foucault entered the ENS on the rue d'Ulm with honors, fourth in his class. Success did not bring psychological stability, how- ever, and in I948 he attempted suicide. It was not easy to live one's homosexuality comfortably at the time and Foucault contacted a psy- chiatrie institute. He had read Freud very early on thanks to a doctor correspondent of Freud in Poitiers, Dr. Beauchamp, and did not stop at taking courses at Ulm. But in addition to the courses at the ENS, he attended a number of Parisian institutes and took courses at Sainte- Anne. He was passionate about psychology and specialized in psycho- pathology. "Madness seemed to hold a certain fascination for him and he brought back innumerable anecdotes from his hospital visits about the world of the confined,"18 recalls Jacques Proust. Foucault's training extended beyond the normal curriculum and content of classical speculative philosophy, and brought him into con- tact with a specifie field that was both theoretical and practical and that also prepared his later and rather rapid shifts, since his very first book, Mental Health and Personality,19 dates from I954 and is de- voted to psychopathology, to psychoanalytic concepts, and to the reading of social representations of madness. He wrote this work at the request of Louis Althusser for the collection "Initiation philoso" phique" directed by his friend Jean Lacroix at Presses Universitaires de France (PUF). Michel Foucault also took courses at the Sorbonne with Daniel Lagache, Jean Hyppolite, named to the Sorbonne in I949, Jean Beaufret, who dealt with Heidegger, Jean Wahl, and Jean- Toussaint Desanti, "but of course, it was Merleau-Ponty's courses that most strongly impressed the young students. "20 In Se arch of the Mind's Limits At the ENS itself, Michel Foucault was most influenced by Louis Al- thusser, the caman 21 of philosophy there since I948. At the beginning of the fifties, Marxism was the important thinking machine and Althusser introduced his audience, including Foucault, to Marx. He even introduced Foucault to the F r e n ~ h Communist Party. "Impulse or adherence, then retreat, 1 no longer remember very weIl," remarked his party comrade Maurice Agulhon, while his colleague in Lille, I48 Reason Raves: Michel Foucau/r's Work Olivier Revault d'Allonnes, remembers having seen Foucault crying upon learning of the death of the "little father of the people," Stalin, in I953. 22 This was the period when the ENS was in fact divided between the "go-tos" (those who go to Mass) and the communists, many of whom were left-wing Christians who took the outstretched hand and joined the French Communist Party. Everyone at the school expected Foucault to pass the agrgation in I950 with flying colors, but he failed the oral exams after having passed the written exam. He had to prepare for the exams again the following year and his second attempt was something like a milestone righting his path on the road to his own destiny. The oral question he selected was unusual-sexuality-and Jean Hyppolite, who was on the committee, had to fight to get it through. The luck of the draw was inspired, for this would become Foucault's major area of work. Having passed the exam, Foucault escaped the purgatory of teaching in a high school because, after a year at the Thiers Founda- tion, he was named a teaching assistant in psychology at the Univer- sity of Lille. He continued to live in Paris and taught at Ulm thanks to Louis Althusser, and became the philosophy caman. Foucault became friends with a group of communists who had been at the ENS- Grard Genette, Jean-Claude Passeron, Paul Veyne, Maurice Pinguet, Jean Molino-who nicknamed him "le Fuchs" (German for fox) be- cause Foucault was slyer than the others and because foxes dig more deeply than others. In I953, "he went to Sainte-Anne every week for a new seminar of an unknown Dr. Lacan whom Foucault admired tremendously. He sometimes alluded to the specular image and to the Mirror Stage, which at the time was the ultimate subtlety. "23 His friend Maurice Pinguet recalls how important the discovery of Nietz- sche was for Foucault in I953: Hegel, Marx, Heidegger, Freud: in I953, these were his points of ref- erence until he met Nietzsche .... 1 see M. Foucault reading the Con- sidrations intempestives in the sun on the beach at Civitavec- chia .... From I953 on, the generallines of a global project were beginning to take shape: an ethical decision inspired by Nietzsche's thinking crowned a genealogical critique of morality and science. 24 In the early fifties, Foucault was also an avid reader of literature and was particularly fascinatecl by Maurice Blanchot's writing, which left his mark on Foucault's style, especially in his systematic use of the Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work I49 oxymoron. As Foucault confided to Paul Veyne, "At the time, 1 dreamed of being Blanchot. "25 His literary sensibility drew him to Samuel Beckett, Georges Bataille, Raymond Roussel, and Ren Char. A veritable fascination with reflecting upon the outside and upon lim- its also took hold then, and his literary influences translated his funda- mental anxiety about death, which was no less calmed by his work in psychoanalysis, to which he always remained a stranger. Foucault, who was quite precocious in his knowledge of Freud and Lacan, was counseled against hospitalization at Ulm by Louis Althusser, and Daniel Lagache later suggested to him that he begin analysis. He did, but he spent no more than three weeks. His relation- ship to psychoanalysis was always ambivalent, a mix of fascination and rejection. But it was thanks to Michel Foucault that a department of psychoanalysis was created in 1968 at Paris VIII-Vincennes, even though he ridiculed those who earned their living by "renting out their ears."26 Exile The search for limits and for thinking the outside led Michel Foucault beyond France in 1955. He chose to leave for Uppsala in August, thanks to Georges Dumzil whom he did not yet know but who had to recommend someone to his Swedish friends for a position as a French reader, a position he himself had held in the thirties. Dumzil had lost touch with the ENS and turned to Raoul Curien for advice; Curien told him about Michel Foucault, whom he called "the smartest person 1 know."27 Georges Dumzil offered the position to Foucault, who accepted it and spent three years in Sweden. When the two men met later, an intellectual complicity and a friendship were born "that never changed until his death. "28 Foucault's participation in the structuralist adventure is due, cer- tainly, to Georges Dumzil. Until then, Foucault had not really found direction in his constant search for an enterprise that would calm his existential anxiety. He was still uncertain as he stood at the crossroads of philosophy, literature, and psychology. Stalin's death in 1953 had been a shock, and the discovery of Nietzsche a substitute. But he was still without the base for the genealogy that he wanted to construct and his meeting with Dumzil-a meeting whose importance he would always reiterate-brought him an answer. In his preface to Madness and Civilization, he wrote, "1 owe a debt to all those who helped me in I50 Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work this rather solitary task, and most of all to Mr. Georges Dumzil, with- out whom 1 would not have undertaken this work. "29 He told Le Monde that Georges Dumzil had been the most important of the in- fluences on him, "thanks to the idea of structure. As Dumzil had done for myths, 1 have tried to discover the structured norms of experience whose shape can be found, with sorne modifications, at different lev- els. "30 Foucault wrote his thesis in the elsewhere of Sweden, seeking the manifestations of madness in the Carolina Rediviva library, where he found a very rich collection of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century medical works that a collector had left to the library. This collection served him well in giving voice to the world of silence. The Thesis On Saturday, May 20, I96I, a major event took place in the Louis- Liard Hall of the Sorbonne, the sanctuary where important theses are consecrated in an immutable ritual. Michel Foucault came to defend his thesis on madness, quite an incongruous object in this temple of the academy. Georges Canguilhem, his director, had told his students, "You must go."31 Pierre Macherey was in attendance with many oth- ers in a room that was packed for the occasion. Foucault was com- pletely unknown to Macherey when he walked into Louis-Liard, but he left it completely and permanently dazzled by this university cere- mony. From then on, he bought each of Foucault's books the day they came out. "Something completely unheard of took place: the mem- bers of the jury were overwhelmed,"32 a jury composed of august pro- fessors including its president, Henri Gouhier, a Sorbonne professor since I948 and a well-known historian of philosophy, Georges Can- guilhem, thesis director, and Daniel Lagache, Jean Hyppolite, and Maurice de Gandillac. "To speak about madness requires the talents of a poet," concluded Michel Foucault. "But you do possess those tal- ents, sir," answered Canguilhem." 33 Michel Foucault raised the problem of the claim to truth of a par- ticular scientific discourse, namely, psychiatry. He studied the condi- tions of its validity and possibility, deliberately planting his probe in the heart of Western history in order to question triumphant reason. "In the case of a science as doubtful as psychiatry, couldn't we more clearly perceive the tangle between the effects of power and of knowl- edge?"34 ln order to displace traditional boundaries, Foucault began with the taboo object of madness, the repressed of Western reason, the Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work r 5 l of its Other, He described and how the pronouncements of nascent and uncertain psychiatrie knowledge were validated, which led him to privilege the historicization of his object. For him, his- torical analysis was an "instrumental position"35 within a political sphere, a means of not sacralizing science. The historicized discourse must ask what gives science its power, discerning everything in it that is not scientific, and look at "how, in our society, the truth effects of science are at the same time the effects of power."36 Madness, his research subject, was to be freed from the many dis- courses holding it captive. Scientific knowledge, whether legal, med- ical, or belonging to the police, was called to the witness stand to examine its contribution to the birth of this figure of the Other of reason. This quest for an object removed from the dredges of sedi- mented discourses corresponds completely to the structura li st theme, which at the time was taking the form of research into the different zero degrees-of writing, of language, of kinship, and of the uncon- scious. The Foucauldian project took its place in it by proposing to "find in history the zero degree of the history of madness, where it is an undifferentiated experience as yet undivided by division itself. "37 This work on the obscure limits of Reason aimed at restoring a life and voice to madness itself, behind the discourses with rationalist pre- tensions. "1 did not want to make a history of this language, but rather an archaeology of this silence."38 Giving Voice to Silence: Madness Michel Foucault constructed his history like a fiction based on sorne founding myths. "His histories are novels,"39 in which positive affir- mations, critical and even nihilistic critiques of canonical fields of knowledge confront the newly defined boundaries. He retraced a path leading us onto the medieval ship of fools, as much a mythical theme borrowed from the Argonauts as a reality of a medieval city that rids itself of its fools by placing them in the hands of boatmen, and up to the eighteenth-century world of asylums. The status of mad- ness changes over time; first an object of exclusion, it later becomes an object of confinement. Foucault discerned a reversaI. During the Renaissance, the figure of the fool was inseparable from Reason. Erasmus discovered the im- manent madness of Reason, and Pascal wrote that "men are so neces- sarily mad that not to be mad would amount to another form of mad- I52 Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work ness. "40 In the century, rationalism claimed an ability ta chaase its abjects and, in the new rules of methad as Descartes had defined them, excluded madness by relegating it ta error, ta the nega- tive, to an illusory dream. Eliminated from the realm of the rational and born as a negative figure, apart, madness even became the decisive divide between the world of reason and unreason, picking up where the old division between Good and Evil had stopped. Madness was a world of non-sense that had to efface itself so that rational thought could prevail. Reduced to silence, immured in a carceral universe, the madman does not yet have his own place, for he is initially interned with paupers. The seventeenth century of Reason reacted by locking up the fear of madness that continued to haunt it. Madness became a menace and the madman's disappearance the condition for the reign of Reason. It thus found itself caught up in the important movement toward confinement whose beginnings Foucault placed with the royal edict of April 27, 1656, which created the Hpital Gnral in which paupers were received and put to work. "The walls of confinement ac- wally enclose the negative of that moral city of which the bourgeois conscience began to dream. "41 In this, he perceived a discontinuity in discursive practices that led to a new relationship to madness as well as to kinship. Whereas until that time, paupers had been included in a spiritual positivity as a possible object of redemption and as a condi- tion of wealth, they were henceforth banished to negativity, as sources of disorder, the mark of divine punishment. The pauper became soci- ety's damned and therefore had to bec orne invisible, like the madman. Michel Foucault remained on the periphery of the social without ever engaging in a social history that wou Id seek sorne general coher- ence in Western society. He was thus already on structuralism's terrain of predilection in which discourse enjoys a maximum degree of auton- orny with respect to social contingencies. He refused to integrate the discursive reversaI that he perceived into a general explanatory frame- work in which he might have established a relationship between the phenomenon of repression described and the historical change of a society in transition from the primarily religious to the ethical- economic, rooted in the mental structures and institutional practices of the modern era. In the classical age, madness was a legal concern and was not yet a me di cal issue. Confinement was thus a legal act. The madman was located "at the meeting point between the social decree of confine- Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work lB ment and legal knowledge that determines the capacities of legal subjects. 42 Of course, the madman was not a prisoner like the others; he was not a beggar, but his bizarre behavior was considered ta be a symptom of a profound animal nature (repressed in the man of rea- son), at the lower limits of humanity. Madmen were therefore chained by their jailers and even displayed in the loggias of Bictre Asylum. The eighteenth century saw a decisive break in the perception of madness and the asylum was born as a specifie institution reserved ex- clusively for those who were mad-a specifie site of madness, a figure finaUy defined and removed from the shapeless heap it had been in the Hpital Gnral. This institutional shift preceded the view of the mad- man as someone ill and in need of care: "A new dimension had to be established that would create a new space and something like another solitude so that in the middle of this second silence, madness could finally speak. "43 Mad speech was examined for signs of this or that clearly defined pathology and an entirely new field of knowledge was taken in hand by the medical world. "This was the apotheosis of the medical figure .... Since the end of the eighteenth century, a medical certificate had become almost obligatory for committing mad people. But within the asylum itself, the doctor's role was the most important insofar as he organized it as a medical space. "44 Its transition from an undifferentiated malady to madness, its situation within time, the con- sideration of a new perspective as well as of the new practices implied by the birth of madness as a specifie figure, the dialectized relationship between knowledge and power, the substitution of medical for judicial power-aU of these were the major lines of Foucault's approach, which went beyond a simple genealogy of madness to a more com- prehensive view of the transition in a culture from power based on Law to a system relying on a norm that has become the criterion of di- vision among individuals: this implies a completely different discur- sive economy. The medicalization of the social body was one response to this process of normalization dividing normal and pathologie al. The new king was therefore the doctor at the center of the division whose lim- its he establishes. Problematizing such different perceptions of the boundaries between the normal and the pathologie al clearly echoed Georges Canguilhem's work, for he had already established the foun- dations of a structural history of science. Michel Foucault's theses re- markably and brilliantly demonstrate the fruitfulness of this method. I54 Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work Madness and Unreason In order to be defended at the time, a thesis had to be published, but in order to get it published, Foucault had ta find an editor willing to ac- cept a manuscript that was nearly one thousand pages long. He asked Brice Parain if he was willing to publish it at Gallimard and was rather hopeful since Parain had already published Georges Dumzil. However, we must remember that Claude Lvi-Strauss had had to take refuge at Plon after Brice Para in refused to publish The Elemen- tary Structures of Kinship. Foucault met with the same categorical rejection. At that point, Jean Delay suggested his collection at PUF, but Foucault "had specifically wanted to avoid the thesis ghetto"45 and do as Lvi-Strauss had do ne with Tristes Tropiques, getting be- yond the circle of specialists in order to reach a broader intellectual readership. Foucault therefore went to Plon, where he knew Jacques Belle- froid, who passed his thesis on to Philippe Aris, the historian in charge of the collection "Civilisations d'hier et d'aujourd'hui." This was to be the first in a long series of contacts bringing philosophy and history together, yielding much fruitful collaboration, but also sorne misunderstandings and dead-end discussions. In I96I, however, the decisive meeting with Philippe Aris was absolutely incongruous. Michel Foucault was a de-fuser of prejudices, a Nietzschean nihilist, whereas Philippe Aris was an ultraconservative, royalist, ex-member of Action Franaise. What made a common ground possible was their shared sensitivity to the phenomena of mentalits. Aris, the author of The Family and the Child in the Ancien Rgime,46 also valorized the premodern period, and had a certain nostalgia for the fetal world prior to the disciplinary partition in which madmen and reasonable men, young and old, would have cohabitated on the basic levels of so- ciability and conviviality. Madness and Civilization was published therefore at Plon thanks to Aris, to whom Foucault would later pay homage. "A thick manu- script came ta my attention: a philosaphy thesis on the relationship between madness and unreason in the classical age, written by an au- thor whom 1 did not know. 1 was dazzled but 1 had to work extremely hard to get it published. "47 When Michel Foucault was writing his thesis in the land of the midnight sun, he twice invited Roland Barthes to visit and enjoyed Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work V1Slts him on each of his trips to Paris. Barthes hailed this work as the first application of structuralism ta history: "Michel Fou- cault describes a structural history that is doubly structural: its analy- sis is structural and the project itself is structural. "48 Roland Barthes quickly saw the link between Lvi-Strauss, Lacan, Foucault, and his own work, although none of them had collaborated in any way. For Barthes, Foucault's work illustrated the conquest of modern ethnol- ogy, and at the same time Foucault had successfully shifted nature to culture by studying what had been considered until then to be a purely medical concern. Just as Lvi-Strauss had analyzed kinship relations as marriage phenomena and Lacan had described the unconscious as being structured like a language, literary writing in the new literary critique became part of an apprenticeship or production of a form of writing that had nothing at all to do with any creative genius. Foucault "refused to con si der madness as a nosographie reality."49 Barthes read Foucault's work essentially as part of a general semiol- ogy constructing vast "smantmes" whose primary goal was to study forms, and in this respect, madness would never be more than an achronic form to be discerned but purified of all substance and tran- scendent content. Maurice Blanchot similarly hailed Foucault's work, in which he saw his own experiment with a form of writing that explored limits and defined a new literary space: "To prepare, beyond culture, a relationship with what culture rejects: the voice of confinement, an outside of writing. Let us read and reread this book bearing this in mind."50 Michel Foucault finally met with a positive reception by the liter- ary avant-garde, which counted a few historians 51 and epistemolo- gistS. 52 But for the most part, Foucault's work did not enjoy the popu- lar success that had been expected and the book did not really get much response from philosophers (neither Les Temps modernes nor Esprit reviewed it), nor from psychiatrists, who considered it a simple exercise in literary style and metaphysics. Madness and Civilization had a fairly modest print run and it was not until The Order of Things 53 that Foucault's work elicited an excitement that never waned from that point on. Three thousand copies were initially printed in May 1961, followed by a modest second printing of twelve hundred copies in February 1964.54 The book missed its intended mark the first time around since the psychiatrie world in no way felt concerned by IJ6 Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work this philosopher, "Ir was thus only in a nonpractical way that Fou- cault's work had an impact." 55 According to Robert Castel, Foucault had a double impact: his work provoked an epistemological break, and it infused mental illness, which had become a positivist concept once again, with its alterity as the other of reason. Foucault's work was consecrated as an original but academic thesis in I96I, but it would have another fate thanks to two events: May I968 and the lively interest it elicited among the Anglo-Saxon antipsychiatrists Ronald Laing and David Cooper. At the end of the sixties, the book fi- nally found a receptive collective audience and a demand for a change in clinical practice; at that point, it became an inspiration to the move- ments protesting the practices of the asylum. Exclusion or Integration? Michel Foucault's structural method was founded on the loss of the substance of madness itself, a figure held prey to captive and fluctuat- ing discourses. Madness loses all substance and consistency in this perspective and disappears within the folds of oppressive reason. Later, in I980, Marcel Gauchet and Gladys Swain proposed a differ- ent thesis, thanks to an argument based on a very careful and detailed study of historie al facts. 56 They looked at the chronology Foucault had proposed and argued that confinement did not really begin in the seventeenth century in France, but rather in the nineteenth century. But, above all, they saw the dynamic of modernity not as alogie ex- cluding madness and alterity but rather as a logic of integration. Foucault's diagnostic error gave rise to the illusion that the pre- modern period was a tolerant, undifferentiated society in which all difference was accepted. However, Marcel Gauchet and Gladys Swain showed that if the madman was accepted at the time, it was only inso- far as he was considered to be the expression of a subhuman species: "In the cultural framework, defined by princip les of inequality and natural hierarchy, absolute difference does not exclude proximity." 57 If madness creates a problem within the framework of modernity and is confined within the asylum, it is not because it is rejected but be- cause the madman is considered an alter ego resembling Reason: "In the modern period, to the contrary, identity is a right and distance is only de facto. 58 The history of madness in modern democratic society seems to be more a history of integration than a history of exclusion. Marcel Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work I57 Gauchet also a danger in numbers of but, unlike Foucault, considered this to be a problem of normaliza- tion, of an integrative utopia, more than a practice of exclusion. Fou- cault, in 1961, completely disagreed with a view of Reason as progres- sive. To the contrary, deconstructing Reason was supposed to enable a magnified image of the enigmatic figure of its Other to burst forth and fundamentaHy weaken the reign of the Lumires in order to better un- veil its oppressive and disciplinary substructures. The issue here is one of a radical critique of modernity and its categories. Madness and Civilization was above aH the symptom of an era, the first step toward a new structural approach adapted to West- ern history, and a valorization of the repressed. The quest for truth took the form of examining the unspoken, ferreting around in the hia- tuses and silences of a society that reveals itself in what it hides. Mad- ness th us became an ideal object for both historical anthropology and psychoanalysis. Nineteen Marxism in Crisis: A Thaw or the Deep Freeze Again? In 1956, a good part of the French intelligentsia underwent sorne dra- matic changes, which had sorne very real effects for the generation of a decade later. Structuralism was born as an intellectual phenomenon that, in a certain sense, took up where Marxism left off. Existentialism was the expression of postwar optimism, but the new relationship to history was more disenchanted. In early 1956, at the twentieth con- gress of the USSR's Communist Party, Nikita Khrushchev, the new secretary-general of the Communist Party, acknowledged Stalin's crimes; the year ended with the crushing of the Hungarian revolution by Soviet tanks. The shock waves breached the sacrosanctity of the Soviet model, which came under criticism by the left. Communist ideology of hope for the future met historical reality to reveal the horrors of the logic of torture and totalitarianism. The seismic shock did not penetrate into the ranks of Billancourt, however, and the French Communist Party (PCF) remained the most powerful political machine outside of Moscow. Intellectuals whose work was based on the search for truth and on the critique of false appearances, however, could no longer un- questioningly accept that which tiU then had constituted their analytic framework. A period of mourning for lost hopes extended from 1956 until 1968, and yet the collective sensibility held to certain unshakable and unchanging ideas. What was it that was so well anchored that po- litical voluntarism failed to triumph? Marxism in Crisis Ti') Postwar Europe was the mst rapid economic changes since the end of the eighteenth century. "We were consid- erabiy behind in our perceptions and we could only measure how important the 'thirty giorious years' had been after they were over be- cause while the y were unfolding we said that nothing was happen- ing." 1 Dntil the n, the Russian Revolution had been seen as the con- tinuation of the French Revolution; 1917 was the realization of the modern democratic ideal and was therefore an extension of 1789. Not only 1789, however, but the ideals and values of the Enlightenment themselves were beginning to be reevaluated in France. And indeed, many would make Boishevism and its fatal destiny weigh heavily on those ideals. Structuralism took root within the context of this cri tic al rereading of Western democratic values. lndependence, liberty, and responsibility were no longer the fundamental principles for the French intelligentsia. "The explanatory substitutes led to the primacy of totalities over that of subjects."2 A critique of modernity and of the formaI nature of democracy began to take shape, but it was no longer made in the name of a waning Marxism, but rather on the basis of Heidegger and Nietz- sche, or by taking refuge in textual cio sure and internaI architectonics. This was also a time when French history was taken firmly in hand, in 1958, by General Charles de Gaulle, who put an end to the structural instability that afflicted politicallife since the end of World War II, and surrounded himself for the first time with technocratic ministers. His choices made it ciear that the cole Normale Suprieure was no longer the institution al mold for the country's future leaders; the cole Nationale de l'Administration (ENA) came to play that role; whereas the cole Normale had up to that point been the institutional incarnation of the reproduction of the humanities, the technocratic graduates of the ENA (narques) now replaced the intellectuals. Ulm reacted. lndeed, it became the epicenter of a structural quake in 1966, and the voice of the most scientific of discourses, in an attempt to slow down the process that was relegating it to a secondary role in training the republic's elite. Since 1958, technical/technocratic thinking had been well esta blis he d, however. "For me, structuralism was very suc- cessful because it was the basis of technocratie thinking and gave it a philosophical, logical daubing, a certain rationality, a kind of vigor. There was more than a single positive encounter between structural- ism and these times, there was a marriage of reason."3 I60 Marxism in Crisis 1956: A Time of Ruptures The priests responsible for the cult questioned the "little father of the people" and brought the edifice of belief crumbling down. Structural- ism provided a life raft for many at a time when institutional Marxism was in its agony: "A kind of ceremonious massacre. . . . This made possible a clean sweep, a big breath of fresh air, a hygienic act. We don't always choose the scent of our deodorant or detergent; they often stink, but they work."4 A period of ruptures began for intellec- tuaIs who could no longer pretend and who subjected their own fetishes to attack. Roger Vailland removed the portrait of Stalin from his office walls. Claude Roy was forced out of the French Communist Party for "having joined in the game of reaction by the enemies of the working class and the people."5 Even Jean-Paul Sartre, who had borne his cross since the beginning of the fifties as an irreproachable fellow traveler of the French Communist Party, published an incendiary article about Hungary in L'Express on November 9, 1956, leading to an irrecon- cilable divorce between him and the party. The numbers of critical ar- ticles and remarks were increasing; it was clearly possible to be right even if it meant being subjected to a continuous flow of insults and calumny. But this form of intimidation culminated at this point since many who joined the anticolonial prote st against the war in Aigeria discovered the shattering proof of the lie of the accusation that they had joined the other side. In 1956, a good many of the postwar trau- mas were swept away for many intellectuals in the West, weil before the cleanup was completed in the East in 1989. The question at the time was how to go on being a Marxist while keeping a historical consciousness. History no longer held out hope of a better future, but was scruti- nized for the failings that had borne the seeds of barbarism. The rift in 1956 "led us to stop being forced to hope for anything."6 According to Michel Foucault, the inteilectual should search out the range of pos- sibilities and impossibilities in a given society rather than be buoyed up by the continuous flow of history or await the arrivaI of a messiah incarnated by the party as a guide to earthly salvation. But even before mapping out a site for research and identity, the party that considered itself to be the foyer of sociability, an adoptive family, and everything surrounding it, with its specifie rites and habits, had to be abandoned. Marxism in Crisis I Gr Pierre Fougeyrollas quit the French Communist Party in I956. "1 was teaching at the Lyce Montaigne in Bordeaux at the time and was a member of the federal office of the PCF of the Gironde. 1 quit be- cause of Hungary. When 1 came to Paris in 1958,1 joined the group Arguments."? Grard Genette also left the PCF in 1956. "At that point, 1 began a three-year detoxification with Socialisme ou Barbarie, where 1 often saw Claude Lefort, Cornelius Castoriadis, and Jean- Franois Lyotard. After having supported Stalin for eight years, 1 needed a centrifugaI force to become a non-Marxist, and Socialisme ou Barbarie scraped things clean."8 As Olivier Revault d'Allonnes put it, "We could have created an association of the class of 1956."9 He had joined the PCF in Lille in 1953, where he found himself in the company of Michel Foucault when both were protesting the war in Indochina. Through his support for Polish October, Jean-Pierre Faye was fas- cinated to discover the rigor of Lvi-Strauss's program in 1956. He had gone to an important and solemn UNESCO reception for Polish representatives in Louis-Liard Hall at the Sorbonne, presided by Fer- nand Braudel. The meeting ended on a spectacular note, with the ar- rivaI of Gomulka, the conqueror of the Polish revoIt and an early vic- tim of the Stalinist purges. At that point, Lvi-Strauss "harangued us from atop some kind of chair, explaining that structure reigned and that econometrics, structural linguistics, and anthropology, which was to become structural a few months later in another book, were the three sciences that would dominate."lO Jean-Pierre Faye wondered how mythologies could function in the modern world, especially after the 1929 crash in the United States, but also after the depression that had affected Vienna in 1873. Taking a structural path seemed promising at the time because of the way, according to Lvi-Strauss, it explained the many, complex correlations between mythology and an economic situation, and between structure and the fluctuations of history. Structura li sm as the Outcome of the Crisis of Marxism For others, recourse to Lvi-Strauss became the basis of a conversion to anthropology. This was true for the Communist philosophers whom we might call the club of four: Alfred Adler, Michel Cartry, Pierre Clastres, and Lucien Sebag. All four had quit the PCF in 1956, and had switched from philosophy to anthropology-a choice that I62 Marxism in Crisis cannot be dissociated from the changes in the political situation. "Nineteen fifty-six was a central date for US."11 Alfred Adler described the intellectual development that had led him from existentialism to structuralism. 12 He had joined the PCF in 1952 at the age of eighteen; his political militancy had led him to Marxism, but he had remained on the sidelines, and defined himself as a Communist in the sense of moral commitment rather than as a Marxist. While studying philosophy and taking courses with Jean Hyppolite, he discovered Hegel. "Hegelian Marxism gave us intellec- tuaI substance so long as political choices came first, and it also gave us a militant content."13 When the events of 1956 unfolded, the PCF became an object of opprobrium, even if it took two years for the ex- clusion to fully take shape. "Nineteen fifty-six is the very condition of the choice of ethnology."14 It was no longer possible to make ethico- political commitment adequate to Hegelian Marxist speculation, and Alfred Adler found himself in Claude Lefort's seminar on The Elemen- tary Structures of Kinship. The discovery of Lvi-Strauss's work was a source of pleasure for the group of four for it had the merit of signify- ing a de-ideologization and of espousing an apolitical discourse: "We discovered Tristes Tropiques. 1 remember that Pierre Clastres was crazy about Tristes Tropiques, and had read it four or five times."15 This conversion led the group to become interested in everything having to do with the birth of the structural paradigm. They read all they could with great enthusiasm, an effective catharsis with respect to the pasto They threw themselves into structural linguistics and began attending Jacques Lacan's seminar at Sainte-Anne Hospital in 1958. Between 1958 and 1963, their appetite for discovery led to a thorough theoretical introduction to ethnology, in relation to other disciplines, as well as to a number of trips to do fieldwork. At that point, the group split in two: Lucien Sebag and Pierre Clastres went to work on Amerindian cultures while Alfred Adler and Michel Cartry left for Africa. "They say jokingly that the only place to find true primitives is in Latin America."16 They aspired to find something more profound than exoticism; for them, it was a matter of locating societies that had been sheltered from the unitary map of Hegelian Marxist thinking, societies that were not classified in Stalinist handbooks. The spirit of discovery was also spurred by a disappointment in speculative philosophy and history, whose creative cycle seemed to have come to an end when Hegelian Marxist theory frayed. Unlike Marxism in Crisis l 63 rpr,pv,,,c' speculative Lvi-Strauss's work a veritable intellectual adventure: "In Tristes Tropiques Lvi-Strauss says that you have to lose a lot of time in order to find the name of a clan. Reading that, we realized that someone had introduced some- thing new." 17 Setting off to do fieldwork, and the ensuing shift in personal and cultural history, were decisive aftereffects of the 1956 quake. The Thaw An ideological thaw shattered the vulgate, therefore, as of 1956. There had been sorne forerunners, of course, particularly among the members of Socialisme ou Barbarie, founded by Cornelius Castoriadis and Claude Lefort in 1949, to which a number of intellectuals turned in 1956. This group developed a radical critique of the left in order to analyze the Stalinist model of a bureaucratie and totalitarian system. For Castoriadis and his group, structura li sm was not an alterna- tive to the vulgate, but a simple adaptation to the mode of domination of modern capitalism, which, in 1958, reigned. The discourse gave ab- solute priority to science; "whereas people were more and more op- pressed in the name of science, they try to persuade them that they are nothing and that science is everything. "18 They denounced structural- ism's elimination of living history and the way in which intellectual thought became infused with technocratie thinking. ln 1956, a new current was born and it fused around the journal Arguments. The group argued for a revision of Marxism, a rejection of the vulgate but also a clarification of the contradictions of modern- ization. Edgar Morin founded and directed the journal and his board included Kostas Axelos, Jean Duvignaud, Colette Audry, Franois Fejta, Dionys Mascolo, Roland Barthes, and Pierre Fougeyrollas. The review was the very expression of the thaw that, in place of the previ- ous dogmatism, offered a real questioning and multidimensionality. "Spring 1956 flowered. Gusts of hope came from Poland, Hungary, and Czechoslovakia. History hesitated between the ebb and the flow .... We realized that what we thought was the bedrock of our doctrine was little more th an an ice floe without any real solidity."19 The review was born of a meeting between Edgar Morin and Franco Fortini, who was already publishing the review Rugionamenti in Italy. "During the years immediately prior to this, 1 had been a half- dead political corpse, 1 was a member of no party, and 1 had been I64 Marxism in Crisis happy to me et sorne friends in Italy ... with whom 1 could dia- 10gue."2o This was an open group that was intellectually vital from the beginning and, unlike any political party organ, it established itself as a simple laboratory or bulletin for ideas. Arguments measured politi- cal problems and offered reflections on our technical civilization and on language in its search for a critical radicality beyond disciplinary discoveries and party blinders. During its first two years, the review focused on mourning its break with the French Communist Party, and then its concerns grew less political, addressing such issues as love, the universe, language. "During its six years of existence, Arguments en- joyed that rare, happy union between affect and thinking."21 This search for a new direction ended prematurely in 1962. "With and without joy and sadness, Arguments was sabotaged by its cap- tains. "22 This sabotage was due in part to the dispersion of the editor- ial board: Pierre Fougeyrollas left for Dakar and Jean Duvignaud was in Tunisia. But, above aIl, one fact became clear, and this was that times had changed and, at the beginning of the sixties, a new kind of thinking was taking up where others had left off: structuralism. "Within the university context, this way of thinking was ta king over, and it offered a scientific solution to aIl of our problems. So, it was over. We had once again bec orne deviants, but we were wise enough to realize it. "23 The Deep Freeze Again? Edgar Morin saw structuralism's success as one more freeze after the thaw. Structural epistemology replaced a totalizing Marxism, but it was equaIly persuaded of its scientificity and adherence to the laws of classical science. Determinism and objectification excluded the sub- ject, which was too uncertain, as weIl as history, which was too con- tingent, to which it preferred a model as rigorous as the natural sci- ences: structural linguistics. Another form of deep freeze was also evident, for there was a clear tendency to swap Moscow for Peking, Hanoi, and Havana. And yet this need to scientize the approach of the social sciences was easy to understand in terms of the errors accumu- lated under Stalin, in the same way that there had been a need to hold on to sorne certitudes. On the one hand, conferring the primary value on structure made it possible to explain the persistent difference in the relationship between determinism and freedom, and between the his- torical task of transformation and the inability to convince people of Marxism in Crisis r 65 its ta Saussure and the notion an un- conscious structure us to better understand something that evolved not as a function of class or of social change, but outside of conscious will."24 On the other hand, with anthropology, as with structurallinguistics, other visions of the world and other systems of representation could be considered: "It became possible for us to renew the dialectical vision, which we had tended to regard as a form of getting beyond oppositions, since the notion of multiplying ever more subtle mediations seemed to us to renew dialectical thinking. "25 Structuralism was the real beneficiary of the crisis in 1956. The bases of its programs had already been well established by the time it took root at the beginning of the century. Structuralism made it possi- ble to confer a certain level of scientificity and operationality in a par- ticular area of thought by preserving the goal of universality that prior forms of commitment had held to, without making this one part of the des ire to transform the world. The enterprise was a limited one: an at- tempt to better understand the world by integrating alterity and the unconscious into it. Twenty The French School of Economics Takes a Structural Path One discipline among the social sciences did not wait for the fifties be- fore reacting to structuralism: economics. Of course, unlike the other social sciences, e c o ~ o m i c s did not draw its model from linguistics. Economists were ahead of others in formalizing their research and were thus able to serve as examples for other disciplines in search of scientific rigor. Lvi-Strauss borrowed the idea of a model from eco- nomics in order to give priority to the scientific aspect of structural anthropology. Economics, however, did not play the role of a pilot science dur- ing the period when structuralism was at its height even if it was at the time the most advanced discipline in terms of the mathematization re- quired by most of the social sciences. Exchanges did exist and Lvi- Strauss's use of theoretical modeling was one such example, but economics nonetheless remained rather removed from the important debates being carried on in the sixties about the structuralist para- digm. This relative marginality resulted from the fact that the mirage of the period was the extension of the phonological model, but institu- tional divisions in the social sciences were such that economists found themselves housed with jurists and both were cut off from literature. "The rue Saint-Jacques really was a very deep river running between economists and literary types. By contrast, contacts with historians were already going on in the Sixth Section of the cole Pratique des Hautes tudes."l In I958, Fernand Braudel proposed the creation of I66 French Economies Takes a Structural Patb 167 a for the social sciences broadly conceived; proposaI was rejected, and the decision to separate letters and the social sci- ences more narrowly from the law school and the school of economics created a long-standing gulf. Economies could not be a hub discipline in the structural paradigm. And yet, economic science produced highly axiomatic results even if it did not spend a long time pondering the epistemological condi- tions of the discipline's creation. Microeconomics in the fifties man- aged a rather complete axiomatization around the idea of a general equilibrium, which appeared to be a totally formalized structure. In economics, there was "a form of structuralism that met the logical conditions of scientificity, in terms of the criteria of the logical con- struction of propositions, and that led to results having universal value."2 The very success of this axiomatization and its practical ap- plications contributed to the lag time in problematizing the results of microeconomics, which, for the most part, remained removed from any critical reflection about its postulates. The Marriage of State and Structure Postwar changes in the relationship between the government and the market in France also pragmatically strengthened the idea of structure in economics. At a macroeconomic level, much thought was devoted to the range of possibilities for government intervention. "This was the golden age of Keynesianism."3 But in the eyes of the Anglo-Saxon tradition, which is marginalist, and where state intervention must be limited to the periphery of a general equilibrium that is considered a given, the situation in France was unusual. After the Second World War, the government that had emerged from the National Council for the Resistance attacked macroeconomic models. Long-term plans, territorial redefinitions, and the nationalization of private enterprise would profoundly change the mechanisms of the French economy. Economic structures themselves needed to be rethought in order to definitively change the overall flows of demand and, therefore, lev- els of activity. At that point, because the state was ostensibly directing national reconstruction and economic modernization, it took charge of the important structural transformations. These imperatives fueled activities that were propitious for regrouping and made possible the creation of "a veritable French school of economics."4 This was one of those rare moments when energies came together, in an are a that r68 French Economies Takes a Structural Path more generally favored fragmented research in a number of direc- tions, in order to examine the unavoidable interconnections between the period's economic and social problems. La Revue conomique was one of the major hubs for this reorga- nization. Directed by Franois Perroux, Jean Weiller, Jean Lhomme, and the Marchal brothers, the editorial board also included Fernand Braudel, and thus symbolized the organic links of a dialogue begun between economists and historians of the Annales. The state created a series of new administrative structures following the war's end in order to effectuate the necessary structural reforms and enlighten pub- lic authorities about the short and middle term. The Institut National de la Statistique et des tudes conomique (INSEE) was created in order to generate economic predictions, and then, in 1952, the Trea- sury created its own programs (Service des tudes conomiques et Financires [SEEF]), which later became the Direction de la Prvision et du Plan, with its economic research centers, the CREDOC (Cen- tre de Recherche en Documentation) and the CEPREMAP (Centre d'tudes Prospectives d'conomie Mathmatique Appliques la Planification). The government's use of economic expertise "took two directions: setting up a national accounting mechanism and creating macroeconomic planning models." 5 The consequences of this organic alliance between the state and the theoreticians and practitioners of macroeconomics underscored the breach with the university of the humanities, and particularly with literature. Claude Gruson, Pierre Uri, Alfred Sauvy, and Franois Per- roux created teams that included relatively few university represen- tatives by contrast with the numbers of civil administrators and engi- neers coming from the Grandes coles. Prospective models of the national economy were developed, therefore, at the highest levels of administrative power in se arch of a certain harmony between the dif- ferent sectors of the economy and the mechanisms of production. 6 Valorizing the structuralist method was therefore quite effective among economists, but their outlook was generally foreign to the viewpoint of literary scholars, and the formalization of their research removed them further still. And yet, this situation did not prevent the creation of a number of bridges making dialogue possible between economists and the rest of the social sciences. Franois Perroux played a fundamental role in this. French Economies Takes a Structural Path I69 Where the Paths Converged: Franois Perroux As of 1955, Franois Perroux was a professor at the Collge de France. He had created the ISEA (Institut de Science Applique) in 1944 and his review, Les Cahiers de l'ISEA, was receptive to philosophical- and, more particularly, epistemological-debates and included articles by Claude Lvi-Strauss and Gilles Gaston-Granger. Franois Perroux's influence was twofold. He borrowed the notion of a generalized econ- orny from Merleau-Ponty but contributed to its dissemination among economists. He also proposed a concept of structure to those liberals who deified a perfect market in which prices operated without restric- tions. "The structure of an economic ensemble is defined by the net- work of links between simple and complex units and by the series of proportions between the flow and the stocks of elementary units and the objectively significant combinations of these units."7 Europeans massively used the structural paradigm in political economy around the 1930S, in reaction to the 1929 crash. But even before the idea of structure was generalized in political economy, Henri Bartoli astutely remarked that "structural sociology and structural economics were contemporary with the birth of sociology and politi- cal economy."8 The ide a of structure was born in the seventeenth cen- tury out of the correlation between the different economic givens seen as so many elements of an overall coherence guiding economic life. Auguste Comte had already placed the physiocrats among the ini- tiators of "social physics." And then Marx sought to distinguish the laws of capital by invoking such structural notions as modes of pro- duction, social classes, and the social relationships to production. He attempted to get beyond a simple description of observable facts in order to discern "the internai organization of the capitalist mode of production, in its ideal."9 If Marx used the ide a of structure to orga- nize a purely conceptual theoretical model, he in no way forgot the other end of the chain; the model is linked to the economic reality of the stage of development of the productive forces in a given social sys- tem. The structure in question after 1945 in the French school of eco- nomics, on the contrary, relied more on empirical and observable facts th an on the ory, and more closely resembled the methodology of histo- rians th an that of anthropologists. This was altogether clear in the work of Franois Perroux, who defined structure by the proportions of flow and stocks of basic units, and that of Ren Clmens, who saw French Economies Takes a Structural Path structure in the "proportions and value relations between costs, prices, revenues, and money in a given context." 10 The German Ernst Wagemann had already used the notion of structure systematically in the thirties. Economists had adopted his definition, notably in France, beginning in 1936 with the structural reforms of the Popular Front. In France, structure was considered "the most permanent."l1 Structure is what resists rapid changes, what makes for an economic situation and inflects it without identifying with it. Structure is marked by the slowness of what are generaUy cyclical economic rhythms set into motion by deep mechanisms. Franois Perroux adopted this vision of structure as an invariant, or as a variant with relatively mild fluctuations, and saw structures as "ensembles of slowly moving quantities, sets of kinds of behavior or of relatively stable behaviors."12 During a I959 coUoquium led by Roger Bastide,13 Andr Marchal proposed his own more dynamic perspective in opposition to Franois Perroux's static notion of struc- ture. Marchal's approach was based on relativizing those economic laws that are valid according to the type of structure or between two structurallimits within an economic system in which a certain multi- dimensional combination evolves.1 4 Andr Marchal examined how the idea of structure had made its way back into contemporary economic thinking.1 5 He saw in this a quest among economists to explain the big historical changes of twentieth-century capitalism: the transition from a competitive capi- ta li sm to a monopoly capitalism, the I929 crash, and decolonization. The conjunction of aU of these changes made it necessary to move beyond the models that eliminated aU external elements. Attempting an Economic Anthropology Andr Nicola's work must be seen within this context of global con- frontation. He defended his thesis in I9 5 7, although his reflection on the notion of structure dated back to I948, his last year in high schoo\.16 He had been very excited by the debate between Tarde and Durkheim and saw in their work a problem that would remain central to aU of his later work: the polemic between the importance of behav- ior (Tarde) and that of structures (Durkheim). Nicola said to himself then that "both are partly right because society stubbornly remains composed of agents who, at the same time, seem to be acted upon by society." 17 In or der to continue thinking, using this contradiction as a French Economies Takes a Structural Path 171 he was led ta a position that went a strictly economic viewpoint; when he found Tristes Tropiques in 1955, he was de- lighted. Not only did he enroll in economics, but in political science as weil, and at the Sorbonne he took philosophy, sociology, and psychol- ogy courses with Piaget, Lagache, Merleau-Ponty, and Gurvitch, and finaIly found himself at the heart of the structural confluence by the end of the Mties. He was a precocious structural economist, slighdy atypical by virtue of his receptivity to aIl the social sciences and by his desire to establish a structural economic anthropology. Econometries But there was an intermediary level between concrete reality and structure, which the economists more than others developed. This was the level of the model, a necessary mediation that produces the most developed formalization. It is here that economics, in the process of becoming econometrics, becomes a completely formalized language. "Constructing mathematical models became one of the most presti- gious branches of economic science, to the immense benefit of the dis- cipline and-why not admit it-to its great mis fortune as weIl."18 The International Society for Econometrics dates from 1930, but it was only after 1945 that econometric models reaIly developed. Cer- tain historical events contributed to their development, and the mod- els were perfected, for example, during the "great aerial bridge over West Berlin."19 When Stalin blocked aIl but aerial access to and from Berlin in 1948, an econometric model had to be designed in order to organize a continuaI routing of airplanes to keep the population in West Berlin from starving. This kind of operational research signifi- candy broadened the use of mathematics as applied statistics in eco- nomic models. Collecting statistical information became much more sophisticated and was important for the extended application of eonometric models. Lvi-Strauss was fascinated by this operation al efficiency and the capacity to take reality into account in a purely for- mal language. It was at the intermediary level of model making espe- ciaIly that economists in the fifties participated in the structura li st par- adigm, more so th an when they invoked a structure's reality, which is bascially nothing more than a way of accounting for the permanence of certain situations. Econometrics enables us to discern a certain number of aporias that become obstacles for the enterprise as it cornes up against the limits of formalism in the social sciences: "Not only I72 French Economics Takes a Structural Path does mathematization push the intellectual undertaking to free itself of reality and to yield to a sort of deductive euphoria deeply contemp- tuous of patient, factual observation and any enthusiasm for analysis, but it also imposes sorne very severe syntactic limits. "20 A number of economists hypostasized their tools when they adopted an econometric methodology, and sorne even went so far as to take these instruments for reality itself. Everything that could not be measured was meaningless. Historicity, which is part of the struc- tural paradigm, was clearly eliminated since nothing can be foreseen in this scheme of things once the model perfectly reproduces itself, except variations in quantity. The same obstacle arises: how to con- struct an analytical apparatus of simple self-reproduction, a truly self- regulating machine that considers all human activity to be meaning- less except for the initial structure, as well as any history of this action. Gilles Gaston-Granger very quickly recognized the danger of a formalism that creates such an illusion. It "cornes from the fact that once the themes have been determined through axiomatic abstraction, we want to confer an ontological privilege over the operations, which, paradoxically, gave birth to them. "21 Twenty-one Get a Load of That Structure! At the end of the fifties, before structuralism was being spoken of, the reference to structure was everywhere in the social sciences. At this point, certain representatives of convergent research interests chose to evaluate the situation and draw up a balance sheet on the use of the concept. The evaluation provided the occasion for the first important multidisciplinary meeting, which gives a good idea of how discipli- nary boundaries were becoming increasingly porous-a situation that a good many researchers had already been using to their benefit. Be- cause man was the common object of a whole series of disciplines, the conceptual approach that was taking shape, and that was overriding studies on intentionality or consciousness, suggested that it was possi- ble to see a common approach take shape that would encompass all thinking in the social sciences. The air was redolent with the possible and proximate victory of the ambitious goal of paradigmatic unity. Two important meetings took place in 1959. In January, Roger Bastide organized an important colloquium on the idea of structure. 1 Maurice de Gandillac, Lucien Goldmann, and Jean Piaget presided over a colloquium at Cerisy on the confrontation between genesis and structure. 2 The reference to structural binarism, which was already being invoked rather frequently, was becoming the necessary path for any researcher to take at sites of innovative research such as the Muse de l'Homme, the Sixth Section of the cole Pratique des Hautes tudes, and certain courses at the Collge de France. At that I73 Get a Load That Structure! point, the search beyond sememes for other emes was general. The colloquium organized by Roger Bastide set the scene for a broad confrontation over the use of the concept of structure in diverse disciplines. tienne Wolff argued that the notion corresponded to a biological given: "Living beings inelude a whole hierarchy of struc- tures."3 He defined several scales of biological structure, of the arrange- ment of cells in tissues, of tissues in organs, and that of the "ultra- structures" made visible by the electronic microscope. Although the level of observation could be defined, the passage from one structure to another remained mysterious and therefore a matter for theoretical speculation. mile Benveniste gave a paper on linguistics, ma king elear that linguistics had played a fundamental role in diffusing the paradigm, which was no longer even that of structure in the eyes of this pioneer discipline: structure had become structural, and finally structuralism. Benveniste recalled the innovators: Saussure, Meillet, the Prague Cirele, Jakobson, Karcevsky, and Trubetzkoy, who had al- ready defined phonology in structural terms as early as 1933: "Con- temporary phonology is characterized above all by its structuralism and its systematic universalism."4 Lvi-Strauss, for his part, considered that anthropology had brought about the decisive changes that made possible the discovery of the structural arrangements at the heart of the social order. He disputed George-Peter Murdock on the se grounds, and rejected the possibility of simultaneously studying structure and process, holding that such an ide a belonged, "at least in anthropology, to a naive phi- losophy."s Daniel Lagache recalled that structuralism took shape in psychology in reaction against atomism and around the psychology of forms, of Gestalt psychology. "It was in this context that structur- alism became one of the dominant characteristics of contemporary psychology." 6 Robert Pags, for his part, recalled for the audience how the idea of structure in social psychology had been polysemic, and how frequently Jacob-Lvy Moreno had used it in sociometrics. Henri Lefebvre gave a paper on the use of structure in Marx in which he made it appear that Marx was the important forerunner of the current revolution, quoting the preface to his 1859 Contribution to a Critique of Political Economy (1859). Even Raymond Aron placed himself within this structural perspective by invoking his desire to see political Get a Load of That Structure! I75 science rise to a higher level of conceptual abstraction. He regretted that the structures in question were still too dependent on a concrete political reality and expressed the wish that "we might discover the basic functions of every political order at a later stage of abstrac- tion."7 Other participants demonstrated the fecundity of the struc- tural approach in their partieular discipline: Pierre Vilar in history, Lucien Goldmann in the history of ideas, Franois Perroux and Andr Marchal in economics. The Consecration of Cerisy: Genetic Structuralism The second confrontation took place in I959 in Normandy, at the sixteenth-century chteau cum colloquium center known as Cerisy-Ia- Salle. The question this time was less one of determining which disci- pline had gone farthest in its use of the ide a of structure than of com- paring the ideas of structure and genesis. The colloquium organizers considered that their work lay in the wake of the structuralist break but they refused to see the social as statie and sought instead to recon- cile dynamic potentialities and permanent factors, in other words, to bring history together with structural coherence. They were the bear- ers of a genetic structuralism: "Genetic structuralism appeared for the first time as a fundamental philosophical idea along with Hegel and Marx."8 Goldmann situated the second stage in the genesis of this new method in the development of phenomenology and especially of Gestalt psychology. Somewhat earlier, Lucien Goldmann had applied genetic struc- turalism in his remarkable study on the links between Jansenism, Pascal's Penses, and Racine's theater. 9 He situated the work of these two writers in relation to the far more vast significant structures of the different currents of Jansenism and the social antagonisms of the seventeenth century. Unlike Lvi-Strauss, however, Goldmann no longer saw the search for structures as incompatible with the search for genesis, and he thus opened up another direction for structural- ism's development, one that was more receptive to history. Jean Piaget, another adherent of genetic structura li sm and one of the collo- quium organizers, criticized Gestalt for its immobility as much as for its Lamarckism, wherein structure was completely ignored. He argued for the inseparability of genesis and structure based on his work in child psychology: "There are no innate structures; every structure im- plies a construction."lO of Thar Structure! Maurice de Gandillac was the third of the orgamzers. He voiced sorne criticisrn of Jean-Pierre Vernant's paper on the Hes- iodic myth of the races. Setting himself squarely in a genetic perspec- tive, de Gandillac criticized Vernant for giving tao much weight ta the internaI structure of Hesiod's myth to the detriment of history: "1 wonder if we can go as far as you have in eliminating temporality from the interpretation of the myth of races."l1 Vernant, who also sought to reconcile history and structure, answered by arguing that Hesiod does indeed use temporality, but not our linear and irreversible temporality. Structural Anthropology and Its Hegemonie Ambitions Structure and genesis squared off at Cerisy. The colloquium had the merit of bringing to light very early on one of the major themes of the future debates concerning the relationship between history and the structural paradigm. The debate is fundamental and there are two sets of issues. The first was the much-disputed place of the discipline of history and the second the manner in which the West conceived its relationship to history. In this respect, structuralism posed a double challenge for historians. When Lvi-Strauss reprinted a whole series of articles in Struc- tural Anthropology in 1958, the collection was something of a mani- festo. His opening article dated from 1949 and defined the ties be- tween ethnology and history.12 Lvi-Strauss's remarks were in the line of Franois Simiand's 1903 challenge to Durkheimian sociology; he observed that history had not renewed itself since, whereas sociology had metamorphosed itself, particularly through the prodigious prog- ress that had been made in ethnological research. The 1929 break with the Annales was forgotten in passing, doubtless for the sake of the polemic in order to better discredit a dis- cipline that, in his eyes, was condemned to monographs and ideo- graphs. Lvi-Strauss dernonstrated that structural anthropology dis- tinguished itself from evolutionism by breaking with the biological model and by hypothesizing a radical discontinuity between nature and culture. Not that he challenged the validity of history; in this re- spect, he disagreed with the functionalist school, and particularly with Malinowski, for having too easily sidestepped historical givens in favor of functions: "For to say that a society functions is a truism; but to say that everything in a society functions is an absurdity."13 Faced Ger a Load of That Structure! 177 with the excess of history in the diffusionist method with the functionalists' negation of history, Lvi-Strauss proposed a third di- rection for structural anthropology. He showed that ethnography and history are related by their ob- ject (alterity in time and space), by their goal (to go from the specifie to the general), and with respect to their methodological demands (the critique of sources). They therefore resemble each other, but if they are to work in concert their distinctions would have to be made in the re- lationships between ethnology and history, two disciplines with dis- tinct but complementary perspectives. "History organizes its data in relation to conscious expressions of social life, while anthropology proceeds by examining its unconscious foundations." 14 What made the unconscious accessible to ethnology, as we have seen, was the lin- guistic model, and especially phonology. What also became clear through the se distinctions was that only ethnology claimed a scientific, nomothetic project for itself, defined by the transition from the specifie to the general, which alone allows the transition from the conscious to the unconscious. The ethnologist must therefore appropriate historie al materials in the same way that he uses ethnographie inquiry, but he alone can claim to have access to "the complete range of unconscious possibilities. These are not unlim- ited." 15 The traditional opposition between history and ethnology, based on the distinction between the type of sources, between the study of societies without writing systems and those with a written culture, is of only secondary importance in Lvi-Strauss's view. Rather than the object of study, it was the orientation of the scientific project that was fundamental, and we can see how Lvi-Strauss's project chal- lenged historians, especially since he considered the ethnologist to be no more than the first step toward a final synthesis that alone cou Id forge a social or cultural anthropology that aims for a comprehensive understanding of man from the hominids to the present. Structural Anthropology coherently grouped together a number of articles deal- ing with anthropology's place in the social sciences, the relationship between language and kinship, artistic representations in Asia and America, magic and religion-in other words, a range of very diverse objects that seemed to ignite what Lvi-Strauss called a "Copernican revolution ... which will consist of interpreting society as a whole in terms of a theory of communication." 16 The structural version of anthroplogy proclaims its hegemonic I7S Get a Load of That Structure! intentions in the realm of knowledge about humankind, and Lvi- Strauss defines it broadly enough to de scribe allievels of social reality: "But as soon as the various aspects of sociallife-economic, linguis- tic, etc.-are expressed as relationships, anthropology will become a general theory of relationships."17 This point of view lets anthropol- ogy receive its analytic models from mathematics, the formaI language par excellence. By grouping complete series of variables as a group of permutations, the structuralist programs aspired to discover the very law of the group under study. In this analytic structure, the group's structure is understood through the procedure of repetition, based on the invariable whose function is to flush out the structure of the myth from its diverse enunciations. Here aga in, history and ethnology are opposed in their capacity for modelization. Structural ethnology can claim a mechanical modeling: "Anthropology uses a 'mechanical' time, reversible and noncumulative,"18 whereas history must limit iself to a contingent, noniterable temporality that requires statistics. The time of history "is statistical." 19 Those societies that Lvi-Strauss calls cold resemble mechanical machines that infinitely use the energy shaped at the outset-the clock, for example; hot societies resemble thermodynamic machines, such as the steam engine, which functions through temperature differ- entials. They produce more work, but consume more energy by pro- gressively destroying it. This last society seeks ever wider and more numerous differentials in order to go forward and renew its sources. Temporal succession should influence the institutions in cold societies as little as possible. The most radical and destabilizing challenge Lvi- Strauss makes to historians is that structural anthropology leans on what is considered the most modern and the most efficient advances in the social sciences. Having resolutely situated anthropology on cul- tural grounds, Lvi-Strauss takes advantage, with respect to histori- ans, of having a theoretical perspective that should one day make it possible to decode the inner structures of the brain. There is a kind of structuralist materialism in him, for, according to his analyses, struc- ture is occasionally considered to be an analytic grid and, at other times it springs directly from concrete reality: "Claude Lvi-Strauss is a materialist. He constantly says as much. "20 Structural anthropology can therefore flourish without bound- aries, according to Lvi-Strauss; it makes it possible to move beyond the traditional culture/nature split. Similarly, structural anthropology Get a Load of That Srructure! can cast its net more widely ta whole of humankind. The structuralist manifesta of 1958 doubly challenged history and philos- ophy in this respect. Philosophy, which reflects in the first place on how the human mind functions, sees its object of inquiry co-opted by anthropology, which, in the name of an enterprise that has the advan- tage of scientificity, claims, at the end of its long road, to reach mental fortresses and their internai structures. The greatest advance made possible by Lvi-Strauss in the history of anthropology was "to work, in the first place, on relationships. This was structuralism's own con- tribution; it amply demonstrated the tremendous fecundity of this ori- entation. To work on relationships more than on objects made it pos- sible to escape typology and typological classification, which had long been obstacles for anthropology."21 Ontologizing Structure ln 1959, Claude Roy considered Lvi-Strauss's que st to be a modern revival of "the old and untiring quest for the Grail of the Argonauts of the intellect, the alchemists of the mind: seeking the Grand Corre- spondence, the pursuit of the First Key. "22 Roy saw Lvi-Strauss as the great lama, the shaman of the twentieth century. There was a certain bitterness in this backward quest for the philosophers' stone; Lvi- Strauss had not forgotten the nightmare history had become, and in his disenchantment he sought to escape the present. Jean Duvignaud pictured Claude Lvi-Strauss as "the vicar of the tropics,"23 who adopted in his own name the nostalgic dream of an original purity among the first men of the Savoyard vicar (Jean-Jacques Rousseau). Lvi-Strauss answered Duvignaud's 1958 criticism of the struc- turalist method for which he proposed a pluralist approach to society, in a letter in which he defended, and even carried further, his point of view: "1 don't know what human society is. 1 work on certain perma- nent and univers al modes of human societies, and on certain levels of analysis that can be isolated."24 Duvignaud raised a criticism dealing with the problem of the status of freedom and the place of collective dynamism in the anthropological project. In the same letter, Lvi- Strauss answered that "the question is not pertinent. The issue of free- dom has no more meaning at the level of observation at which 1 place myself than it does for someone who studies man organically."25 For Lvi-Strauss, the issue was definitively removed from struc- tural anthropology and he took the natural sciences as his epistemo- I80 Get a Load of That Structure! logical model. Man, therefore, can only attest to his own impotence, his inanity before mechanisms that he will eventually render compre- hensible but over which he has no control. Lvi-Strauss's position re- sembled the scientist illusion of the positivists, for whom theoretical physics embodied scientificity. In a somewhat similar way, by taking phonology as its model, structural anthropology rejected any form of social substantialism and causality in favor of a notion of the arbitrary. It aimed more toward the meanders of neuronal complexity, which seem to hold an ontolog- ical key, the veritable structure of structures, the final underpinning of structurality. Lvi-Strauss's Linguistie Underpinnings: A Strategie Choice Georges Mounin used Structural Anthropology to define Lvi-Strauss's ties with linguistics during the period covered by the articles, which is to say between 1944 and 1956. He questioned the validity of the lin- guistic ideas used by Lvi-Strauss and, as a linguist, argued that in this volume Lvi-Strauss essentially borrowed the ideas of structure and opposition from phonology, whereas these "are not specifically lin- guistic. "26 Moreover, Lvi-Strauss rejected functionalism, and this prohiited him from linking these ideas to that of function, which is central in phonology. Identifying phonemes with signifying elements has no linguistic relevance: "The phoneme only helps to construct a morpheme's signifier; it is not part of the signified. "27 Even if Lvi- Strauss found many parallels between kinship structures and struc- tures of language to the point of saying that "treating marriage regula- tions and kinship systems as a kind of language,"28 he still remained reticent, as an anthropologist, about any reductionism in the service of linguistics. In 1945, he counseled against "hurrying to transpose the linguist's analytic methods, "29 and refrained, in 1956, from want- ing "to reduce society or culture to language. "30 Georges Mounin presented Lvi-Strauss's relationship to linguis- tics as confused, clumsy, and full of regrets, albeit supremely clever, for Lvi-Strauss had no intention of becoming a linguist; he wanted to use the powerful thrust of linguistic rigor to propel the much broader project of structural anthropology. In this respect, Fernand Braudel understood much more clearly the intention, the stakes, and the risks Get a Load of That Structure! I8I of Lvi-Strauss's strategy. Braudel was a historia n, and he was careful to preserve the historian's position at the forefront of the social sci- ences. At the same time, he was aware that this was a real challenge, and could threaten the position of the Annales school within the Sixth Section of the EPHE, over which he had presided since the death in 1956 of Lucien Febvre. He answered Lvi-Strauss in a manifesto- article that appeared at the end of 1958 in the Annales: "conomies, socit, civilisations." In it, Braudel argued for the longue dure as the common language of the social sciences that the historian would fed- erate. 31 This answer or riposte from the historians significantly turned historical discourse in the direction of a structuralization. History Veers toward Structure Before the structuralist challenge, historians had already shifted their centers of interest. When Marc Bloch and Lucien Febvre created the review Annales d'histoire conomique et sociale in 1929, they were al- ready adopting Durkheim's program, and the result was a change of direction toward a longer dure, toward examining phenomena and their underlying causes in depth, which had been too easily buried by the postivist school in favor of a short-winded history narrowly con- ceived as politico-military. The fashion for structures emphasized this shift in the historical discourse away from the tendency to valorize change and toward an attention to immobile stretches of time. As early as his 1947 thesis, "The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World at the Time of Philippe II,''32 Fernand Braudel had altered the historian's vision by relegating the hero of the period, Philippe II, to a minor role and by focusing on immobile stretches, on the fixed points of the geo- historical framework of the Mediterranean world. In the line of Franois Simiand, and therefore of the Durkheimian school, Ernest Labrousse's 1949 thesis, "The French Economic Crisis at the End of the Ancien Rgime,"33 written in the Division of Letters and Social Sciences, had similarly shifted the historian's vision; he had resituated the revolutionary crisis of 1789 within a triple temporality of seasonal variations embedded within cyclical oscillations that were, in their turn, integrated into movements of longue dure. Labrousse had thus made it possible to add a structural situationalism to Franois Simiand's use of economic circumstances: "The historian- economist was struck with the frequency of repetition. "34 Not that I82 Get a Load of That Structure! events were eliminated; but they underwent a procedure of elucida- tion as an end point that should be explained by statistical curves: "Our history is at once sociological and traditional. "35 And yet, Ernest Labrousse reigned over the Sorbonne during the fifties and di- rected much historical research oriented toward a social and eco- nomic history attentive to structural phenomena. It was in this context, with elements drawn from both an eco- nomic situation and a structure set into a dialectic, that Pierre Vilar undertook his research on Catalonia. He had been an ENS student in 1925, had published his thesis in 1962,36 and in a Labroussian per- spective, he directed a seminar at the Sorbonne on the idea of struc- ture: "The whole problem in history is to combine structure and circumstances. Therefore, 1 reflected a lot on structures. Claude Lvi- Strauss interested me when he showed that he was observing things that were structurally logical. "37 If the historian borrowed a logical and abstract dimension from anthropology, he nonetheless kept to a con- crete and observable content, and within his field favored phenomena of crises like abcesses of fixation, or like so many poles around which structural givens crystallized, as if these poles dynamized them. The research was rigorous and relied heavily on strong statistical infor- mation and had a comprehensive ambition: its name was Ernest Labrousse in the fifties. "We were aIl anxious to ask him for the sis subjects-Maurice Agulhon, Alain Besanon, Franois Dreyfus, Pierre Deyon, Jean Jacquart, Annie Kriegel, Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie, Claude Mesliand, Jacques Ozouf, Andr Tudesq ... ," Michelle Per- rot recounts. 38 For Perrot, Labrousse incarnated modernity, and she visited him in the spring of 1949 in order to propose a subject dealing with feminism-a subject that made her master smile. He suggested instead that she work on the workers' movement during the first half of the nineteenth century. For Michelle Perrot, Ernest Labrousse incarnated a concern for rigor, a concern to reach beyond the altogether too familiar impres- sionism of the discipline of history: "Labrousse wanted to rediscover causality and laws; this was in keeping with both Marxists and posi- tivists. "39 Given this outlook, Labroussian historians were very recep- tive to the structuralist phenomenon and to the anthropological chal- lenge of the end of the fifties. They were on familiar ground when they read Lvi-Strauss, and in a similar quest for invariants, even if their ob- ject was different by nature: "There is a phrase in Claude Lvi-Strauss Get Load of That Structure! 83 that l m my 'Workers on Strike, France (1 ' at the beginning of section entitled 'Structures,' and that amounts tu saying that when there are laws somewhere, they must be everywhere, a fundamental remark for the social sciences. "40 Historical Anthropology: Jean-Pierre Vernant The structura li st undertaking broadened after Jean-Pierre Vernant's lecture at Cerisy in 1959. Vernant had passed the agrgation in phi- losophy in 1937 and came, in fact, rather late to Greece, in 1948, but he did not leave his field of study to become a Hellenist. He had been a disciple of Louis Gernet and y gnace Meyerson and recognized the triad of mile Benveniste, Georges Dumzil, and Claude Lvi-Strauss as his other masters. His research was psychohistorical; he was inter- ested by mental forms, which he called "the interior man," and inves- tigated the nature of work, technical thought, the perception of the categories of time and space in the imagination, and the imagery of ancient and classical Greece. "Man is made of the symbolic. Sociallife only functions through symbolic systems, and in this respect 1 am pro- foundly structuralist. "41 Following the publication of Structural Anthropology, Jean-Pierre Vernant therefore gave a paper at Cerisy on structure in the Hesiodic myth of the races, and his article was published shordy thereafter. 42 Vernant's article had an explicidy structural thrust, which was doubly enriched through discussions with Georges Dumzil about trifunc- tionality and by the revolution that Lvi-Strauss had realized in his study of Amerindian myths. Vernant sought to apply his analytic grid ta Greek myths and in so doing effected a major methodological shift that created possibili- ties for an entire productive school that took shape around him, estab- lishing a historical anthropology of ancient Greece. In making the work he was analyzing comprehensible, he did not proceed like classi- cal Hellenists, who sought to date the traditions they found in their work, but focused instead on explaining the fundamental articulations and the code underpinning the myth in question. The myth of the races opens Hesiod's Works and Days; it proposes a theogony that recounts how the archaic order of Greece can be explained by the suc- cessive batdes between generations of divinities, until Zeus took com- mand and established an immutable order. Hesiod's tale therefore ap- r84 Ger Load of That Structure! pears chronological, following the succession races of gold, of silver, of bronze, of iron, and finally of heroes. Jean-Pierre Vernant reduced and displaced the myth. In the first place, he held that the !ive ages correspond in fact to a functional tri- partition "whose dominance over lndo-European religious thought has been demonstrated by Georges Dumzil. "43 Hesiod, therefore, framed his thinking in a tripartite structure when he reinterpreted the myth of the races. But, above ail, Vernant took up binarism, Lvi- Strauss's oppositional framework, in order to show that time does not unfold chronologically in the Hesiodic vision of the races, but accord- ing to "a system of antinomies. "44 A binary structure opposing dik (justice) and hubris (exaggeration) is repeated during each age. Hes- iod's tale, in this framework, has a didactic mission with respect to his brother, the cultivator Perses, to whom he speaks in order to preach the value of work as destiny and respect for dik-a lesson that ap- plies to ail social categories in Greek society. Vernant's demonstration depended on reorganizing mythic mater- ial in order to bring out the major principles at work in Hesiod's mythic discourse: "The dik/hubris opposition is put to a melody, in music, through a Dumezilian functional tripartite organization."45 For Jean-Pierre Vernant, Hesiod's founding myth was a plea for jus- tice, made necessary because it took place during a period of transi- tion during which the Greeks were in se arch of what is just and what is not just, and at a time when the old forms of dik no longer held. Vernant did not propose a purely formalist or antichronological approach, therefore, because he referred the myth to a concrete geopolitical situation in which it is like "the presage of a universe in which the law of the polis, the political nomos, will be the fundamen- tal element. "46 He therefore successfully combined an analysis of a mythic discourse with a sociohistorical context, giving it the value of a symptom, thereby reconciling history (genesis) and structure. Vernant later again emphasized the trifunctionality of the tale's internai struc- ture, however, as a result of criticism he received: 1 would no longer say trifunctionality because if it functions for the first two ages (gold and silver), which do indeed represent sover- eignty and the bronze race and the race of heroes and war, it is not the same for the iron race, which is more complex than the third function of production. This was the time of Hesiod and it was therefore not topica1. 47 Ger a Load of That Structure! IB5 Vernant was therefore obliged to reintroduce historicity into his analysis by considering the fifth age in the chronological succession of the four others. He admits to having go ne too far in structuralizing the historical vision, but his rereading nonetheless made it possible to dialectize the dik/hubris, justice/exaggeration dichotomy, which 1S essential for analyzing categories of thought in ancient Greece. Lvi-Strauss's Consecration A chapter came to a close on January 5, 1960, on the occasion of Lvi-Strauss's inaugurallesson at the Collge de France: the heroic age of structura li sm was over, while broad vistas of the paradigm's intel- lectual triumph stretched ahead. The entrance of the man who at the time embodied the rigor of structuralism's scientific program symbol- ized its success; this was official recognition of the rich effervescence that was under way, a decisive consecration at the dawn of the sixties. This venerable institution was also undergoing a minor internaI revolution by creating, for the first time, a chair for social anthropol- ogy. It is true that Marcel Mauss had taught at the Collge, but he taught anthropology from a chair in sociology. In his inaugural lesson, Lvi-Strauss defined his project in line with Ferdinand de Saussure's discussion of semiology. This social an- thropology took as its true object the very broad spectrum of the life of signs at the he art of society. He clearly expressed his debt to struc- tural linguistics, mobilized as the hard scientific underpinning of his own anthropological project. He also expressed the global nature of his program by carefully avoiding becoming disconnected from the social realm and reality for the sake of the symbolic nature of his ob- ject: "Social anthropology ... does not separate material culture from spiritual culture."48 Moreover, he considered that the neuronal uni- verse would offer the key to understanding the true sources of the symbolic universe: "The emergence of culture will remain a mystery so long as we are unable to understand, at the biological level, the brain's modifications of structure and function. "49 Beyond this scientific thrust, Lvi-Strauss's lesson was also part of a particular moment in French historical conscience, or of "Western bad conscience. In a breathtaking way, Claude Lvi-Strauss orches- trated this grand theme of third-world sentimentalism and the struc- turalist sails were filled with third-world winds."so Pierre Nora's eval- uation was confirmed at the end of Lvi-Strauss's inaugurallesson, for I86 Get a Load of he in this the adar of sulfur: Structure! confined his were like You will allow me, therefore, dear colleagues, after having rendered homage to the masters of social anthropology at the beginning of my lesson, to reserve my final remarks for the savages whose obscure tenacity provides us with the means of assigning their real dimen- sions to human acts: men and women who, even as l speak, thou- sands of kilometers from here, in sorne savanna eroded by brush fires or in a rain-drenched forest, return to their camp to share a meager pitance, and together evoke their godS. 51 Lvi-Strauss ended this very beautiful reminder of his field experience with the wish to remain within the Collge de France as both a stu- dent and a witness to these Indians of the tropics condemned to ex- tinction by our civilization, the last of the Mohicans. If the Collge de France represented the ultimate consecration for Lvi-Strauss, it was also a trompe l'oeil; the real research teams were at the university and the Collge alone did not resolve the problem of isolation or the possibility of creating a discipleship. This was not Lvi-Strauss's fate, however, for he immediately created a laboratory for social anthropology, which depended on the CNRS, the Collge de France, and the EPHE and which meant that he was immediately sur- rounded by researchers able to benefit from the prestige of the Col- lge. He was well aware that in order to realize such an ambitious project he needed solid institutional bases. This was the context in which, in 1961, Lvi-Strauss created a new review, L'Homme, so that there would be a French counterpart to Man in England and the American Anthropologist in the United States. By his choice of codirectors for this professional anthropologi- cal publication, Lvi-Strauss clearly laid out his ambitions for a scien- tific structural anthropology, as well as his program. Two other pro- fessors from the Collge de France joined him on the editorial board: mile Benveniste represented structural linguistics as the very model of scientificity on which Lvi-Strauss determinedly based his work, and Pierre Gourou, a tropical geographer, clearly represented the old vitality of the French school of geography in the Vidalian tradition. Lvi-Strauss made another attempt at the takeover the Durkheimians had tried at the beginning of the century of a school of geography long on the wane because it had joined forces with the Annales historians. Lvi-Strauss quickly enlarged his team, which he thought was a bit Get a Load of That Structure! I87 too much of a "Collge de France dub," and asked Andr Leroi- Gourhan, Georges-Henri Rivire, and Andr-Georges Haudricourt to join. The absences were significant, for there were no historians, de- spite the fact that their work had drawn much doser to the anthropo- logical program since the creation of the Annales. Lvi-Strauss's an- swer reflected the institutional stakes dividing the two disciplines: "In 1960, history and ethnology, which had come so much doser together, were, dare 1 say, rivaIs for the public's attention."52 The same year, Lvi-Strauss's interviews with Georges Charbon- nier gave an ide a of the ambitions of his program and of the metamor- phosis that he hoped for in the social sciences in general, which should draw their inspiration from the natural sciences, going so far as to identify with them: "We might say that ethnology is a natural science or that it aspires to shape itself based on the example of the natural sciences." 53 Crossing the Rubicon to join the natural sciences supposed a rela- tionship with progress, history, and man that sought to reduce them in order to give precedence to a quasi-mechanical model; this in the framework of a cooling down of temporality and of a significance that escaped the individual and established itself on the basis of a logical time, without his knowledge. The structuralist challenge to the social sciences did not lack for grandeur. Throughout the fifties it had dearly demonstrated its fertility by embracing different figures of alterity. On the strength of its promises, this program was soon to flourish, during the sixties. Part II The Sixties: I963-I966, La Belle poque Twenty-two Contesting the Sorbonne: The Quarrel of the Ancients and the Moderns On the threshold of the sixties, the aged and venerable Sorbonne con- tinued to reign undisputed over the country of the mind. Indeed, it engaged only with great difficulty in any discussion of its orientation. The Sorbonne oversaw the heritage of a literary method whose con- cern for historical and philological exactitude had made it appear rig- orous and modern in the nineteenth century. But university erudition, strengthened by an already ancient break, turned a deaf ear to the epistemological challenge that had begun to raise its voice in the fifties. Faced with triumphant positivism and the atomization of its method, the structura li st thrust took on the guise of veritable anti- mandarin trench warfare whose primary weapon was the construc- tion of more modern and holistic scientific models. This combat reached its climax in May 1968, when the old edifice collapsed. The weight of the Sorbonne had relegated those who con- tested it to a position of margina lit y, forcing them to seek out support and new disciplinary alliances, to define an ambitious program and the broadest possible readership/electorate in order to surround, deflect, and eject the mandarins in place. Institutionally, therefore, "structural linguistics embodied the contestation of modernity with respect to the dominant model."l For those invested with the role of preserving the dominant model, the role of reflection on language was entirely secondary, not to say elementary, insofar as it had been lim- ited to language acquisition in the early classes of primary school. Contesting the Sorbonne Since mastery was complete, the crown- ing study of literature was removed from studying its mechanisms. The study of literature, indeed, was limited ta purely aesthetic consid- erations removed from linguistics, which could, however, be part of the pro gram of studying foreign languages. Linguistics was simply a technical tool, dismissed with a certain condescension from the noble literary environment of creative genius. "In the tradition al curriculum of literary studies, the study of language was dependent on and infe- ri or to work on the literary text."2 Andr Martinet Returns The only real, noteworthy exception in the aged institution was Andr Martinet's course in general linguistics. He had come back from the United States in 1955 and was internationally known. His notoriety, however, made little impression in the traditional humanities, where he was suspect and barely tolerated by those who initially confined him ta a small enclave where, they believed, he would be forgotten. He was finally given a course ta teach at the old Linguistics Institute, but in a small classroom that could hold only about thirty students. The room quickly overflowed with students and Andr Martinet im- mediately found himself directing about thirty theses of Africanists who were 100 king for a way ta describe their languages. Since walls cannot be moved, university authorities had to find a bigger classroom for Martinet, who every year required more chairs for students who poured into his courses. In 1958, he was given Guizot lecture hall but it was only adequate for two years. In 1960, he held class in the Descartes lecture hall, which could hold up to four hundred students. "In 1967, the Descartes amphitheater was too small and they gave me Richelieu which, if you include the annexes, can ho Id up to six hun- dred people."3 His trajectory within the Sorbonne clearly reflected the growing enchantment with linguistics in the sixties. Richelieu consecrated Martinet. Despite his complaints about the inhuman amount of work, his course had become requisite for anyone wanting to become a modern semiologist, especially because, in addi- tion to his universally recognized pedagogical talent, he was an excep- tion in France. An entire student public could arm itself in his courses for the antimandarin criticism that was to grow throughout the six- ties. "We were young, we were against those who were old, and it happened that the avant-garde movement of the time was structural- Contesting the Sorbonne l 93 ism SO, let's bec orne structuralists."4 For the young generation, struc- turalism played a role of stripping things clean and became a provi- sional morality much in the manner of Descartes. In a context of contestation against the powers that be, the at- tacks were once again directed against any form of vague psycholo- gism among the specialists of traditional history, "the veritable pox of the French university and not only among literature people, but also among philosophers."5 A Lonely Innovator: Jean-Claude Chevalier Jean-Claude Chevalier, a young teaching assistant in French grammar, defended his thesis, "The Idea of Complement among Grammarians," in 1968.6 The preface carefully presented the term "epistemology" in quotes as if he were handling an explosive element in his milieu. He used the central ide a of the period, rupture, and recalls the euphoria of contestation as something like a "hygienic pleasure."7 But theoreti- cally, he was looking for a conceptual break, a way of moving things forward in a new direction. This conception of a future rupture led to valorizing breaks in the pasto Chevalier therefore saw a certain discon- tinuity in 1750 among grammarians, who until then had only used the term "origin," and henceforth would use the ide a of complement. "Things shifted from a morphological system to a semantic system of syntax, implying a considerable change. "8 Jean-Claude Chevalier did not, however, think of himself as an innovator at the time. He was just doing the work of an honest histor- ical grammarian and he was quite unaware of the fact that Louis Althusser and Michel Foucault were engaged in similar work. Even at that point, however, Julia Kristeva remarked in Critique that Jean- Claude Chevalier's work was an essential element in shaping the rup- ture that was winning over all the avant-garde intellectuals. Todorov Encounters the Void With the exception of Martinet's enclave, which was limited to teach- ing how language functioned, nothing was going on at the Sorbonne in literature using the new methods of structurallinguistics. When the young Bulgarian Tzvetan Todorov arrived in Paris in the spring of 1963, he was utterly discomfited by the resistance he encountered. Todorov had come from the University of Sofia after finishing his university studies, and he was looking for an institutional setting in I94 Contesting the Sorbonne which to develop research on what he was already calling the theory of literature. For him this meant thinking about literature without drawing on external elements, be they sociological or psychological, but he might as weIl have been looking for a needle in a haystack. Bearing a letter of recommendation from the de an of letters in Sofia and confident of getting a positive response, he contacted the director of the Sorbonne to learn about the possibilities there. "He looked at me as if 1 came from another planet and explained to me, quite coldly, that there was no literary theory going on in his university, nor were there any plans for it in the future."9 Rather confused, Todorov thought at the time that there had been sorne misunderstanding and he asked if there might be a program in stylistics, but the de an wanted him to specify in which language. This conversation between deaf men continued and Todorov began to feel increasingly uncomfort- able because "1 couldn't say to him, French stylistics, since 1 was stut- tering in an entirely doubtful French. He would have told me to go and study French first."l0 Of course it was a question of general sty- listics and the Sorbonne director reiterated that this field of study did not exist. It was only thanks to completely fortuitous circumstances that Todorov finally managed to find a place in Paris, where what was to be called poetics constituted a field of study. Having established rather pleasant contact with the director of the Sorbonne library (thanks to her father, who was a librarian in Sofia), Todorov began to take heart by plunging into the holdings of the library. The librarian informed him that her nephew's work might help introduce him to the ale a tory paths of Parisian modernity. So Todorov went to meet the nephew, Franois Jodelet, who was a teaching assistant in psychology at the Sorbonne. Jodelet took him to meet another assistant at the Sorbonne who was working in literature and whose name was Grard Genette. "So 1 met Genette. He immediately understood what 1 was looking for and told me about someone who was working on this sort of thing: Roland Barthes. He told me that 1 had to take Barthes's seminar."ll Literary Dissatisfaction If you studied English at the Sorbonne, you stood a chance of coming into contact with structuralism. Marina Yaguello came to the Institut d'Anglais in I963 in this way, at the same time that Antoine Culioli, who had been an assistant in Nancy until then, was appointed. Culi- Contesting the Sorbonne I95 oli's work on Old English and on yowei variation made it not only to take a synchronie approach, but an approach that was also "completely structuralist insofar as when each vowel moves, the whole system moves with it."12 Linguistic training was not aimed at the majority of French litera- ture students at the Sorbonne. Franoise Gadet was enrolled in litera- ture but deeply dissatisfied by the teaching, and had gone to one of An- toine Culioli's classes ta take notes for a friend who was absent. The course was a revelation for her. "1 said to myself, there things are really rigorous and demanding." 13 Gadet therefore chose to do a linguistics certificate at the Licence level and found herself with Martinet. She switched from literature to structurallinguistics because structuralism meant choosing rigor. "When you experienced the atmosphere in the Sorbonne in the sixties, you understood that there was nowhere else to go. When you understand just how much of a graveyard it was, you understand why structuralism was so a ppealing. "14 Professors of literature at the time included, among others, Grard Castex, Jacques Deloffre, Marie-Jeanne Durry who was a poet and Apollinaire specialist, and Charles Ddyan, an Armenian prince who taught comparative literature. They were all conscientious professors but they emptied their lecture halls after a single class. "1 saw it with my own eyes in Ddyan's class. Fifty people had been at the first class and three were at the second," recalls Philippe Hamon who, like so many in his generation, chose linguistics in the mid-sixties. "It was the first time that a science called human could attain such a degree of rigor; the discourse was clear, it could be demonstrated, repeated, and reproduced."15 lisabeth Roudinesco began studying literature at the Sorbonne in 1964, and quickly felt the same dissatisfaction. She had to face the fact rather quickly that her interests were in no way sus- tained by the classes she took: "When you studied literature, the line of demarcation was: have you read the latest Barthes? There were two camps. Besides, what they taught us was idiotic."16 In literature at the Sorbonne, therefore, there was a very marked split between two lan- guages and two types of interest. The widening rift between the teach- ers and their students provoked a considerable degree of frustration but also created a buildup of tension that would later explode. Litera- ture students were not alone in their frustration, however, for philoso- phy students were equally dissatisfied. As Franois Ewald described things, "The Sorbonne was a complete void,"17 and he was dissatis- I96 Contesting the Sorbonne fied with Raymond Aron's haughty, sardonic sideward glance at Jean- Paul Sartre's Critique of Dialectical Reason. This feeling of cosmic void was so palpable that Franois Ewald and his friend Franois George conceived of a project-which never bore fruit--of starting a review along the lines of Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, and which would be entided Les Cahiers pour l'poch. They wanted to express the feeling of the end of history, of a world on the wane, which completely corresponded to the new structuralist sensibility. Ewald had quickly encountered this sensibility through the people he knew at Ulm from Les Cahiers pour l'analyse. At the Sor- bonne, he took a course with one of the members of that group, Jacques-Alain Miller, as well as Lacan's seminar. "This makes me a child of structuralism. 1 was raised on Bachelard, Canguilhem, and French epistemology."18 This deep sense of expectation was answered by the dynamism in the social sciences and their veritable explosion in the sixties. But should we see in the attraction of literature students, historians, and philosophers to structuralism an expression of the growing pains of sciences worried about institutionalization and seeking to drape them- selves in greater rigor? "1 would sooner speak about the senility of the social sciences because 1 don't see how they would be considered inau- gural," answers Roger-Pol Droit, who saw in the structuralist ambi- tion the high point of Durkheimianism in sociology and anthropology and would take a quarter century to discover an instrument of objecti- fication, provided by the linguistics of the thirties. "It's more a ques- tion of a belated history in which the social sciences probably discov- ered something like the expression of their modernity."19 Of course this desire for renovation can be considered in relation to an older Durkheimian exigency, but insofar as this tradition had only been half-successful, its program, renewed by linguistics, was the banner of modernization at a Sorbonne that remained largely indifferent to change. The Foyers of Modernity The sixties offered a particularly effervescent spectacle in the strategy of circumventing the principal academic institution. Innovation hailed from the periphery: it reached Paris via the provinces, or took root in marginal enclaves of the capital: "This university is incapable of doing anything new. "20 The philosopher Cournot had already observed dur- Contesting the Sorbonne 197 the that the French university, until the Re- naissance, almost provoked the reform that would culminate in the development of universities in northern Europe. But since then, when- ever the habitus of Homo academicus needed a slight push, a new in- stitution had to be created: the Collge de France, the ENS, the EPHE, and the CNRS. The events of the sixties therefore bore this legacy, which required a revolution to reform a system. Even at the very pin- nacle of the paradigm, the celebra tory concert of publishing houses, reviews, and the press should not make us forget that the tradition al institution kept its grip on legitimacy. "Structuralism never reigned; it would be incorrect to say that it di d, and especially in literature. "21 Institutional frameworks did eventually provide the context for much research that was breaking with the past and making it possible for a great deal of work to be accomplished on many fronts with a common, new orientation. Textual structurality was shifting the se arch for textual genesis more and more radically, function was replacing the notion of oeuvre; literary analysis came to adopt the Russian for- malists' notion of immanence. A common program allowed for very different kinds of research, which depended on the linguistic model to unseat the preeminent creative subject, considered fundamental until that point. The structural totality of the text was becoming most im- portant, but a text whose internaI ratio na lit y necessarily escaped au- thorial grasp because its enunciation escaped authorial knowledge. In the na me of logic or aesthetics, criticism tended to bec orne confused with an essentially descriptive thrust; different levels of resemblance or opposition were brought into relationship, or criticism was specifi- cally linguistic. The decade that began in I960 was therefore a partic- ularly intense period for the linguistic model, which was principally structuralist, and its methodological effort. 22 Strasbourg was one of the high spots of this structuralist renewal and Georges Straka, professor of philology, was its central figure. Straka was a friend of Greimas and he published semiotic articles in Les Travaux de linguistique et littrature,23 a review created in I963 with an initial print run of one thousand issues distributed by Klinck- sieck. He organized colloquiums, brought French and foreign linguists together at Strasbourg, and made their work known thanks to Klinck- sieck's support, as well as through the influence of the University of Strasbourg, which had already seen the great historiographical revolu- tion of the Annales in I929. I98 Contesting the Sorbonne The university at Besanon was the other site of innovation and convergence, but its vitality was completely contingent; the youngest recruits were forced to take up their walking stick and begin their ca- reers in excentric universities, and Besanon was a particularly distant and enclosed location. Young researchers such as Bernard Qumada, Georges Mator, Henri Mitterand, and Louis Hay who were con- demned to work together found themselves there. Interdisciplinarity was deliberate and bridges were built between professors in the de- partments of letters and sciences in order to apply laboratory methods to the social sciences. "An interdisciplinary dialogue went on every- where, in the train, at restaurants. Henri Mitterand, who was always practical-minded, said that if Les Cahiers du rapide 59 were ever pub- lished, they would be far superior to most of the institutionalized jour- naIs. "24 There was a real hunger for learning and for belonging to modernity at Besanon, something that characterizes a young and en- thusiastic generation. "We were interested in aU the new things that came our way. "25 The works of Barthes, Greimas, and Lvi-Strauss were aU very enthusiastically received during this period of high intel- lectual tension. Alongside the Germanist Louis Hay, there was young Henri Mitterand, a grammarian and philologist who remembers the publication of Jean Dubois's the sis, "Political and Social Vocabulary in France between I849 and I872,"26 as a fundamental event. Dubois incited an entire generation to look for paraUels between discursive structures beyond the structures of class and vocabulary. The dy- namism at Besanon made it possible to reach beyond the university enclave; before becoming a place to which everyone swarmed, Be- sanon was a place where a whole inteUectual community, including Parisians and foreigners, could meet and thereby minimize the geo- graphical distance between people like Jean-Claude Chevalier in Lille, Jean Dubois in Rouen and then Paris, and Greimas in Poitiers. There were, of course, significant nuances in the work being undertaken. Barthes was the big reference point of the period, and he was more interested in how codes worked in a text than was Greimas, who wanted to find the system behind the text that com- manded the working of the human mind. But, beyond these differ- ences, there was "this setting into place of the critic as an explorer of immanence,"27 a notion developed by Knud Togeby, a professor in Copenhagen who was a disciple of Louis Hjelmslev. Togeby had pub- lished Immanent Structures of the French Language 28 in I965, and Contesting the Sorbonne 199 term became the cry of an entire young g e n e r a ~ tion of new critics. Clearly, the east of France was in its heyday and the winds blew with sorne strength. As of 1960, Nancy also became a dynamic r e ~ search center when Bernard Pottier created a Society for Automatic Translation, which attracted linguists and scientists to a colloquium on the topic as early as 1961. This branch of linguistic analysis would convert professional scientists to linguistics. In the early sixties, Mau- rice Gross, an engineer at the State Arms Laboratory who was as- signed to the Center for Calculus, remarked: "1 didn't have the vague st idea about what a linguist was. 1 didn't even know that such a thing existed."29 Automatic translation made it possible for Maurice Gross to become a linguist and to leave for Harvard in October 1961 where he met Noam Chomsky. The period was also propitious for re- se arch teams and for a certain reorganization of research that could only be carried on at the periphery of the great institutions but that compensated for the absence of modernization at the Sorbonne. The French Communist Party still wielded sorne political influ- ence at the beginning of the sixties, and many intellectuals were active in its ranks or were satisfied with their roles as fellow travelers. How- ever, one important Communist linguist named Marcel Cohen was responsible for a Marxist research group that included a good number of the structurallinguists. The group met regularly at the homes of its different members, including Jean Dubois, Antoine Culioli, Henri Mit- terand, and Andr-Georges Haudricourt, among others. Quite quickly, however, political changes as much as Marcel Cohen's concept of lin- guistic work, which was considered too restrictive, created a diaspora among the old Marxist research group: "Cohen's idea of Marxism was sociological and Durkheimian .... Marcel Cohen always thought ill of the Americans."30 According to Andr-Georges Haudricout, who recognized the importance of this group at the time, Cohen's sectari- anism had a significant impact on the group's cohesion: "Poor Cohen was very totalitarian: for him, there was the party and the others."31 The group turned its curiosity to the Russian formalists of the twen- ties and toward Soviet linguistics-Vinogradov-with the ide a of con- structing a sociology of language that would not encompass the struc- turalist ambitions. Whence its rather swift disappearance, despite its major role as a place for fruitful encounters. 200 Contesting the Sorbonne Growing Effervescence The excite ment that was ta king ho Id in a number of areas was a veritable explosion of curiosity, which could not express itself in the official Socit de Linguistique de Paris (SLP). In 1960 the Socit d'tudes de la Langue Franaise (SELF) was created in Paris by three auditors of Robert-Lon Wagner's course: Jean-Claude Chevalier, Jean Dubois, and Henri Mitterand. Robert-Lon Wagner, a professor at Hautes tudes, was decisive for diffusing structural linguistics in France. He was a medievalist who had been trained as a philologist and was the first to introduce Benveniste, Jakobson, and Hjelmslev in his seminars. "He played a seminal role."32 The SELF was born of necessity and in reaction to a sarcastic re- mark made by Michael Riffaterre, a professor at Columbia University who was quite disappointed by Jean-Claude Chevalier's personal li- brary. Chevalier decided therefore to have a small group of friends pool their discoveries. Every month it met to hear presentations by semanticians like Greimas, lexicologists like Guilbert or Dubois, syn- tacticians like Chevalier, or stylisticians like Meschonnic. Articles ap- peared shortly thereafter. This "public welfare committee among the lost"33 would quickly grow. Its disappearance in 1968 was due not to failure but, on the contrary, because its catalytic role had succeeded, given the importance of the movement that was under way. Other groups came together in the sixties, among them Enseigne- ment pour la Recherche en Anthropologie Sociale (EPRAS) at Hautes tudes, where, in 1966, Greimas created a two- or three-year pro gram of experimental teaching at the master's level with the help of Oswald Ducrot and Christian Metz, and the Association Internationale de Linguistique Applique (AlLA), created in 1964, where seminar par- ticipants numbered as many as two hundred. "The seminar in Nancy in 1967 brought crowds of researchers. Practically the entire future team at Vincennes was there."34 The Sixth Section at the EPHE was another breeding ground for renewal, especially with Roland Barthes's seminar, which in 1964 addressed the question of cuisine. Barthes had been named directeur d'tudes 35 in 1962 for a research project titled "Sociology and Semiol- ogy of Signs and Symbols." Beyond the particularly active work in literature, Lvi-Strauss's work also spurred much new research. Published in 1958, Structural Anthropology had a triple effect on Contesting the Sorbonne 20I the literary world in ferment: 36 the fecundity of the phonological mode! in one of the disciplines of the humanities, the anachronic read- ing of the Oedipus myth, and the myth's transformational formula. Two years later, Lvi-Strauss directly addressed a literary work with a polemical article titled "Vladimir Propp's Morphology of the Folk- tale," which had many repercussions.37 And in 1962, his fa mous col- laborative study with Roman Jakobson on Baudelaire's "Les Chats" was published, demonstrating that the sonnet is entirely determined by phonetic choices. 38 These incursions into literary territory revealed the ability of the method to contend with a vast area, in the name of a general semiology. These were so many confirmations of the scien- tificity and promises of their program for those working in literature and newly converted to linguistics. In 1962, Jean Rousset's Form and Signification, subtitled Essays in Literary Structures,39 also lent support to the immanence of literary analysis. In keeping with Paul Valry's thinking and writing, which became the major literary reference for the new aesthetics, Rousset adopted the ide a that form is rich in ideas. "It is the structure of the work that is inventive. "40 Rousset avoided any subjective judgment of a work in order to better concentrate on discerning its formaI structures, borrowing not from linguistics but from the renewed literary criticism and reflection on rhetoric of Lo Spitzer and Gatan Picon; his work would be important in the program of literary structuralism. He took one of the important ideas of the literary structura li sm of the sixties from Lo Spitzer's German stylistics, which was to consider an isolated work as a complete and self-sufficient organism whose inner coherence can be studied: "Madame Bovary is an independent organism, an ab- solute, a whole that can be understood and elucidated by itself. "41 Jean Rousset broke with the kind of criticism that went beyond the work and dissolved the work in its context and genesis to the ex- tent that everything except the work itself was present. This restora- tion of the literality of the work would be firmly invoked against the representatives of traditionalliterary history. The weapons of this new criticism were initially found in Jungian psychoanalysis, archetypes, and authorial imagination, taking inspiration largely from Gaston Bache!ard's intuition, and later from Jean-Pierre Richard's thematic criticism and Georges Poulet's systematized reflection on temporality. Later, this new criticism looked to linguistics for the weapons that would enable it to adopt a rigorous scientific program. Twenty-three 1964: The Semiological Adventure Makes a Breakthrough The year 1964 marked the end of the Sorbonne's undivided reign. Pe- ripheral and marginal activity won its first important victory thanks to the spectacular rise in the numbers of students enrolled in letters and the social sciences in the mid-sixties-an effect of the baby boom. Nanterre was created in 1964, and this new campus gave a good number of the renovators the chance to hold a university job near Paris. Bernard Pottier and Jean Dubois, both linguists, made their way into the institutional ranks this way. This was the beginning of a shift that gained numbers and speed and drew peripheral institutes like the EPHE toward departments of letters. Whereas Strasbourg and Be- sanon had already clearly understood what was taking place, things in Paris took on an entirely different cast, of course. General linguis- tics was simultaneously starting to have an institutional existence in- dependent of language departments and traditional philology, and consequently attracted a considerably broader audience than the nar- row scope of specialists. Linguistics seemed at that point to be the common denominator for anyone involved with language. Jean Dubois played a major role in this, particularly since he was an editor at Larousse, a tenured professor in a Parisian university, and a member of the selection board at the CNRS, a post that put him into frequent contact with Louis Guilbert, Robert-Lon Wagner, Aigirdas Julien Greimas, Bernard Qumada, and so on. In addition, he directed research projects, selected members of Nanterre's linguistics depart- 202 ment, and was on the tenure-granting board for a whole generation of French linguists. He was also a close friend of Roland Barthes, who had known his brother Claude Dubois when they were both at the sanatorium. Although their background and political leanings were not always consonant-Bernard Pottier was conservative and worked in Spanish while Dubois was a member of the French Communist Party and his field was French linguistics-the overriding feeling was one of belonging to a community of structural linguists. "One day, Pottier came to find us, saying, come help, Martinet is in trouble at the Sorbonne, and Dubois and 1 left to save him." 1 Jean Dubois was responsible for a number of dynamic research groups, which counted among their members linguists like Claudine Normand, Jean-Baptiste Marcellesir, and Denise Maldidier; he was even able to attract specialists from other disciplines to linguistics. He recruited Joseph Sumpf, for example, as an assistant in the Iinguistics department at Nanterre in 1967 to do sociolinguistics. Sumpf had been working at the CNRS since 1963 in educational sociology, and at the Centre d'tudes Sociologiques, where Liliane Isambert was his direct or. He was aiso in Pierre Naville's seminar, where the question of the necessity of formalization for reaching the notion of structure was being discussed. There were anthropologists as well in this same semi- nar, including Claude Meillassoux and Colette Piot. "Naville's ideas about formalization came from Saussure and Piaget, but 1 couldn't say that it was his major concern."2 Joseph Sumpf worked on the function of the philosophy class in the French school system. His research Ied him to create a corpus of interviews and papers from classes, and he went to see Jean Dubois with this material to work out a method of analysis. "Jean Dubois in- troduced me to linguistics and to Harris, and this was the basis on which he recruited me to Nanterre."3 Structuralism thus became a particular approach to analyzing a mass of documents comprised of signs or traces; it offered a tool for discerning their internaI coherence. Lecturing before a group of Tunisians in 1965, Michel Foucault described this process as "deixology," the analysis of a document's in- ternaI constraints: "It is a question of finding what system determines the document as a document."4 When considered an essentiallevel of hum an practices, deixology established "the methodological impor- tance, the epistemological importance, and the philosophical impor- tance of structuraIism." 5 One of the characteristics of the structuralist revolution was to redefine the traditional split between a work that has been critically classified and consecrated and the remains of the fact of writing. Rather than splitting these two aspects of writing, all writing traces were considered in a relationship that established the literary work as a complete document. Desacralized, it became noth- ing other th an language, a simple writing effect upon which another act of writing is superposed. This discursive economy modified the contours of disciplinary boundaries, which are in fact effaced to bring a fundamentally linguistic analysis to the fore. Literary analysis be- came important in its synchrony, true to the Saussurean bases of lin- guistic analysis, but to the detriment of a temporal approach. No longer perceived as an expression of its time but as a fragment of space in the internaI logic of its own mode of operation, the literary work was approached in terms of contiguous, syntagmatic, and para- digmatic relationships. External or contextual causes, indeed causa lit y itself, fall to the wayside before questions of the simple communi- cation of a range of different codes organized around a given number of poles. Communications 4: A Semiological Manifesto In 1964, an issue of Communications was published that presented the structural linguistic model in literature as the program of the future. Issue 4 of Communications was a veritable semiological manifesto. In it, Tzvetan Todorov wrote his first article in French: "La description de la signification en littrature." In it he defined a stratigraphy of analytic levels and differentiated between phonematic distribution, where content has no impact, and a grammatical level, which he de- fined as the form of the content who se substance is a matter of sem an- tics and which plays a decisive role for meaning in literature. Todorov suggested taking a radically formalist approach, and although he ac- knowledged that literature bears traces of other signifying systems deriving from social or nationallife, "the study of these systems obvi- ously remains outside literary analysis strictly speaking."6 In the same issue, Claude Brmond examined the possibilities and limits of formaI analysis using Vladimir Propp's Morphology of the Folktale. He argued for an autonomous semiology to replace tradi- tional content analysis. Propp had transcribed approximately a hun- dred Russian folktales according to a li st of thirty-one functions that made it possible to give an exhaustive account of the actions in the en- tire corpus folktales examined. Brmond argued a method of formai analysis that would be a descriptive tool, in contrast to the concerns of traditionalliterary historians: "In their obsession with re- solving questions of genetic ascendency, they forget that Darwin was only possible after Linn."7 Propp's method was particularly suggestive for Brmond, who was interested in understanding the conditions un der which it be- comes possible to make generalizations, or rules. However, Brmond adopted sorne of Lvi-Strauss's criticisms of 1962 and rejected Propp's teleological hypotheses, which certainly aUowed him to create a more perfect model, but the cost was high since he could not include aU of the material of folktales. Reducing themes to their invariant function necessarily limited his choices. Brmond preferred to differentiate the levels of analysis in order to adopt a methodical approach to narra- tion: on the one hand, the classificatory work, that of the comparative study of different forms of narrativity, and, on the other hand, estab- lishing a relationship not between forms but between "the narrative stratum of a message and the other strata of meaning."8 Roland Barthes's "Les lments de smiologie" came out in this same issue of Communications. This article translated a seminar he had given in the Sixth Section of the EPHE and was directed toward a wider audience of researchers. But it became a manifesto for the new science. The theoretical presentation was also a framework for Barthes's research since he was in the process of writing The Fashion System. 9 Barthes was enjoying a veritable "methodological eupho- ria"10 at the time and even abandoned his own writing in or der to undertake research with scientific aspirations. Caught between his writer's sensibilities and his aspirations as a semiologist, Barthes sup- pressed the writer in himself more strenuously than at any other time. "There are two phases in Roland Barthes. In the first, he believed in the necessity and possibility of establishing a science of man. In the same way that the natural sciences were forged in the nineteenth cen- tury, couldn't the twentieth century be the century of the sciences of man ?"ll In its article form, what later became Elements of Semiology gave a didactic presentation of Saussure's and Hjelmslev's teachings with an eye toward constructing this new semiologie al science. Barthes used Saussure's oppositions between language/speech, signifier/signifie d, and syntagm/system, and remained strictly orthodox in his structural- 206 I964: The Semiological Breakthrough ism in this regard. He described three distinct levels of structure (lan- guage in Saussure's sense), norm (language as material form), and use (language as a group of habits of a given society). It was thanks to Hjelmslev that the idea of language, based on this trilogy, could be radi- cally formalized and replace Saussure's language/speech dichotomy with structure/use. Of the linguistic revolution, Barthes retained the general concern for constructing a new science, and reversed Saussure's vision of semi- ology as the future of linguistics. He saw the semiological program as a subset of linguistics 12 and called for all the research being done across disciplines to clearly bear witness to the capacity of linguistics. Semiology, the science of the future, appeared as the science par excel- lence of society in that it signifies: "The sociological implications of the language/speech concept are clear."13 However, Barthes did not see the first positive signs of the cre- ation of semiology in sociology. While other disciplines were giving clear signs of their interest, sociology remained recalcitrant toward the notion of immanence. Barthes saw these signs in the history practiced by the Annales under Fernand Braudel, who distinguished between event/structure; in the anthropology of Lvi-Strauss, who adopted the Saussurean postulate of the unconscious nature of lan- guage; in the psychoanalysis of Lacan, "for whom desire itself is ar- ticulated as a system of signification." 14 For Barthes, sociology defined itself as a socio-Iogic in which meaning is the product of the process that brings signifier together with signified whether it be in a Saus- surean or a Hjelmslevian perspective. Four disciplines played important roles in this semiology of the future: "Today, economy, linguistics, ethnology, and history form a quadrivium of pilot sciences."15 Semiology was to delineate its own boundaries and limits and would be organized around the principle of pertinence, which meant the field of signification of the objects analyzed in themselves based on a situation of immanence. The cor- pus would have to be homogeneous, therefore, and would, by defini- tion, reject all other systems, whether psychological, sociological, or whatever. This science would be ahistorical: "The corpus should eliminate diachronie elements as much as possible; it should coincide with a state of the system, a slice of history."16 And the instrument used in this search for meaning was to be found primarily in conno- tative linguistics, which adopted the Hjelmslevian opposition between Jean-Paul S'Htre (photo }{of',cr-Vlollcr, copyright Lipniuki,Violit'ti Ccriw(,olloqulllll1, '055: "\Vhatls phil'hoplw)" !rom Ictr to righrl J(ostas AXl'I"c" i\Llrtin Heidegger, J\1rs, Heidegger lcopnighr Archives de Pontigny-Cerisy) Cerisy Colloquium, l '! Sh: "Thcory of History," From ldr to rigbt: Unknowll, Raymond Aron, R, P. D:ll1ieiou, CLllldc km-Claude Michaud (':Op\'flght ArchiH's cLe Pontigny-Cerisy) Roman Jakobson (photo Editions de ",lillllit) Claude lvi-Strauss, 1963 (photo Magnum, copyright Henri Cutier-Bresson) Louis Hjelmslev (photo f:ditions de Minuit) Georges Curvitch (photo Presses Universi- taires de France) Andr \ iartinet, ] 957 (photo Presses Uni- ITrsiuircs de France) Jean Piaget (copyright press and information service oi the University of Gcncva) Jean Duvignaud (copyright Univers al Photo) Algirdas Julien Greimas (photo ditions du Seuil) Paul Ricoeur, 1961 (copyright Univers al Photo) Michel Serres (photo ditions de Minuit) Pierre Bourdieu (photo ditions de Minuit) Louis Althusser (photo D.R.) The office of Tel Quel. From left to right: Jean-Loup Dabadie, Jean-Edern Hallier, Jean-Ren Huguenin, Renaud Matignon, Jacques Coudol, Jean Thibaudeau, Philippe Sollers (photo ditions du Seuil) Jacques Lacan (photo ditions du Seuil) Edgar Morin (photo ditions du Seuil) Roland Barthes (photo Magnum, copyright Henri Cartier-Bresson) Michel Foucault, 1963 (photo ditions Gal- limard, copyright Andr Bonin) Pierre Nora (photo ditions Gallimard, copyright Jacques Robert) Georges Balandier (photo Presses Universi- taires de France) Georges Dumzil (photo ditions Galli- mard, copyright Jacques Sassier) Cerisy Colloquium, I964: "Man and the Devi\." Maurice de Gandillac, Catherine Backs- Clment (copyright Archives de Pontigny-Cerisy) 27 denotationlconnotation, and which Barthes had used ln "My th Today." In order to better consolidate this ambitious project of construct- ing a semiological program, Barthes assembled the major part of the articles he had written as chronicler between 1953 and 1963 in Criti- cal Essays. The collection can be read as a semiology in gestation, ar- ticulated by trial and error, a form of scientific bricolage that focused more intensely th an ever before on the problem of the sign, influenced by Jakobson's binary thinking and Trubetzkoy's analyses in terms of differential positions. "Barthes's internaI revolution became apparent at that point, between 1962 and 1963."17 Barthes Defines Structuralist Activity Barthes defined his structuralism in this collection of articles as some- thing that could not be limited to a school because this supposed a nonexistent community of research and solidarity among authors. How, then, could one define structuralism? "Structuralism is essen- tially an activity .... The goal of all structuralist activity ... is to re- constitute an object in such a way as to reveal the rules by which the object functions. The structure is therefore, in fact, a simulacrum of the object."18 There was thus a common goal of this activity, bringing together the diversity of disciplines engaged in the search for struc- tural man, beyond the singularity of each researcher. Structural man was a producer of meaning, and the method used would essentially address the act of producing meaning more th an the content of mean- ing. Structuralism was "an activity of imitation,"19 a mime sis based on an analogy not of substance but of function. Barthes invoked a number of precursors, including Claude Lvi-Strauss, Nicolai Trubet- zkoy, Georges Dumzil, Vladimir Propp, Gilles Gaston-Granger, Jean- Claude Gardin, and Jean-Pierre Richard. In addition, it was now pos- sible to move beyond the distinction between artistic and literary work and scientific work. In this respect, Barthes placed this activity that uses linguistics to construct a science of structure on the same level as the one that created Butor's writing, Boulez's music, or Mon- drian's painting; all belong to the same simulacrum of the object that semiology examines. Barthes's approach was very Saussurean. Structura li sm was not a simple reproduction of the world per se, but generated new categories that are irreducible to either reality or rationality. Structuralist activity 208 1964: The Semiological Breakthrough referred to function, to an examination of the conditions of thought, of that which makes meaning possible, and not its specifie content. And in its effort to uproot natural and immutable meaning from its ideological base, the structuralist program embodied a radical critique of the dominant ideology, which presented itself as something natural and immutable. A semiologist was charged not with deciphering sorne underlying meaning already present in a work, but with accounting for the con- straints imposed on its sense-making operations and the conditions of its validity. Deconstructing ideology and established meaning by at- tacking their monolithic status in order to pluralize them were so many forms of a radical historicism that is systematized in Michel Foucault's work, together with an ahistoricism characteristic of the synchronie position. Structuralism was much more than a school, in Barthes's view; it marked a true shift in the evolution of conscious- ness. "Structuralism can be historically defined as the passage from a symbolic consciousness to a paradigmatic consciousness,"20 which becomes apparent in a comparative approach, not on the basis of meanings defined by their substance, but on the basis of their forms. For Barthes, phonology was the science par excellence of this para- digmatic consciousness, the model of models. "It is [phonology] that, throughout Claude Lvi-Strauss's work, defines the structuralist threshold. "21 A Critical Vocation This change in the sixties cannot be reduced simply to a shift among the disciplines in the social sciences; it was also the expression of a pe- riod during which the intellectual, that is to say, the writer, could no longer argue from a critical perspective or revoit in the same way as during the immediate postwar period. The issue was no longer to sub- vert the entire social order. Henceforth, revoIt "is really the whole, the stuff of all our truths, 1 mean what we might calI Western civiliza- tion."22 Barthes's critique, like that of all the structuralists, worked on destabilizing dominant Western values, on making a radical critique of petit-bourgeois ideology, of opinion, and of the doxa. This para- digmatic consciousness or consciousness of paradox, which tried to shake the doxa, had to evaluate and dismantle from within logics and models, modes of being, and modes of appearance of ideological con- structions. Its object was the superego of dominant rationality and its I964: The Semiological 209 connotations, which required a thorough understanding of how lan- guage functions. The angle of attack seemed more effective than simply rejecting past values in the na me of avant-garde literary princip les destined to be very quickly assimilated into the system in place: "Any avant-garde is quite easily and quite quickly co-opted. Particularly in literature. "23 The consumer society that spread du ring the fifties had such a capac- ity for rotating goods that it embraced cultural goods as weIl; never was the move from an avant-garde-that is to say a radical break-to a commercial object so swift. Assimilation provided the mechanism of seH-regulation in this culture and "the windows at Herms and the Galeries Lafayette are surreaI."24 It became increasingly difficult, and virtuaIly illusory, to escape the web of the technical society and the culture of mass consumption in order to express a cry, a revolt, or a refusaI. Doubtless this was one of the reasons that semiology, as a discourse with scientific and critical aspirations, became something of a refuge, and which, for want of being a Rimbaud, a Bataille, or an Artaud, made it possible to disman- de the mechanism of domination from an irrecuperable position of extraterritoriality in the name of scientific positivity. Subverting lan- guage necessarily meant using language itseH and constituted the first step in breaking down the barriers between literary genres: the novel, poetry, criticism. AlI these forms of expression are textual and there- fore from the same analytic grid of paradigmatic consciousness: "1 be- lieve that now we are beginning a revoIt that is more profound th an prior revolts because, perhaps for the first time, this one affects the very instrument of revolt, which is language. "25 ln this sense Barthes saw himself as participating in the writer's enterprise with other means. The obvious tension in him between the writer and the semi- ologist never completely killed his literary aspirations, even when he examined such diverse objects as cuisine or fashion and its language, the technical language of linguistics. In 1964, his program elicited ever-growing enthusiasm. Semiology appeared to be the modern means of literary creation in the second haH of the twentieth century. Twenty-four The Golden Age of FormaI Thinking Closest to the hard sciences and to mathematical language, semiotic structuralism was the most formalized branch of structuralism. It was also the most ambitious. As Aigirdas Julien Greimas, the program's first promoter, understood it, semiotic structuralism was not just a simple offshoot of linguistics, but sought to encompass aU of the sci- ences of man. "From the beginning, 1 have always intended that semi- otics go beyond linguistics, which is only one part of it."l Greimas remained faithful to Saussure's vision in this, believing that he could unify anthropology, semantics, psychoanalysis, and literary criticism under a single banner. For those linguists who gave courses at the Institut Poincar at the Facult des Sciences de Paris, proximity to mathematicians and logi- cians was institutional. Antoine Culioli gave a seminar on formaI lin- guistics beginning in I963. Greimas taught there, as did Bernard Pot- tier, Jean Dubois, and Maurice Gross. Greimas's seminar focused on semantics, which until then had been considered to be extraneous to traditionallinguistics. This was where, little by little Nicolas Ruwet, Oswald Ducrot, Mar- cel Cohen, and then Tzvetan Todorov came together. There was also an important person named Lucien Sebag, who died, unfortunately, during the summer when we had thought of giving a seminar to- gether. We wanted to establish a link between anthropology, seman- tics, and psychoanalysis. Sebag committed suicide and 1 have never forgiven Lacan for that. 2 2IO The Golden Age of Formai Thinking 2IT Greimas's Structural Semantics came out in 1966, the year of the structuralist hits. It grew out of the seminar that he had given at the Institut Poincar from 1963 to I964 and emphasized a general semiotics embracing aH signifying systems. This finally resulted in a certain receptivity of linguistic research to quite different fields. The futile dialogue in which the two masters of French linguistics, Greimas and Martinet, were engaged quite clearly indicated their differences. "1 get lost when 1 read Greimas. Semiology likewise goes in all direc- tions at once."3 Martinet wanted to limit himself to describing how language functions and he set clear boundaries on linguistic research. Greimas responded: "Martinet is a big peasant who knows his own field well. When someone wanted to study music or painting, 1 sent them to Martinet, who told them, 'Study phonetics and come back in a year.' A fairly unappetizing prospect!"4 The Roland Barthes of Elements of Semiology very clearly adopted Greimas's view of general semiotics, even if he was institu- tionally ahead of his Alexandrian master in the Sixth Section of the EPHE, ta which he had Greimas elected in I965, with Lvi-Strauss's help. Once Greimas became a directeur d'tudes and after Smantique structurale came out, semiotics began to gain institution al support in France, thanks once again to Lvi-Strauss, whose work sketching out the structura li st program was more advanced and who was also al- ready better ensconced, with contacts in high places. ln 1966, a research group took shape around Greimas as the semio-linguistic section of the Laboratory of Social Anthropology of the EPHE and Collge de France, which is to say, around Lvi-Strauss and his team of anthropologists. Oswald Ducrot, Grard Genette, Tzvetan Todorov, Julia Kristeva, Christian Metz, Jean-Claude Co- quet, Yves Gentilhomme were all involved. s ln addition to research, there was sorne very high-powered semiotic teaching, based on gen- erallinguistics, mathematics, logic, grammar, and semantics. Structural Semantics: Greimasism Structural semantics "was always the poor cousin of linguistics,"6 if we look at how many hurdles it had to overcome before its specifie object and methods were established, and the fact that it only came on the scene at the end of the nineteenth century. To overcome these handicaps, Greimas anchored semantics on the most rock-solid for- maI grounds possible, which were those of logic and mathematics, 2 l 2 The Golden Age of FormaI Thinking "which linguistics cannot ignore."7 He adopted the model of Saus- sure's most formalist heir, Hjelmslev; "Claude Lvi-Strauss said that before he began writing, he always read three pages of Marx's Eigh- teenth Brumaire. 1 used to read a few pages by Hjelmslev."8 Greimas adopted the mathematical notion of discontinuity, and contrasted two different analytic levels: the object of the study, lan- guage, and the linguistic instruments that constitute a metalinguistics. From a Hjelmslevian point of view, everything takes place in two metalanguages: the one descriptive, with meanings formulated in lan- guage, and the other methodical. This approach implied two new instruments or denominations with respect to Saussure's definitions. Greimas differentiated signifying phemes from the semes of the sig- nified, considering them to belong to different levels. He also re- examined the signifier/signified unit split into two heterogeneous lev- els. "Once the communication has occurred, the junction between signified and signifier is destined to be dissolved if the analysis of one or the other levels of language is to proceed even a little bit."9 The seme becomes the minimal distinctive unit making the construction of lexemes, paralexemes, syntagms, or other elements possible. Another concept that Greimas borrowed from logic, isotopia, re- veals how entire texts belong to homogeneous semantic levels that can be interpreted as structural realities that become visible in language. "These techniques are comparable, for the social sciences, to algebraic formulation in the natural sciences."10 This model seemed to offer the possibility of allowing the social sciences to acquire the same degree of scientificity as the hard sciences. But this meant that structural seman- tics needed to dissociate itself from any humanist perspective and replace intuition with verification. A speaker's intentionality fell by the wayside, dissolved within a subjectless hierarchy of contextual interwea vings. The other implication of structural semantics, which had already been apparent in Saussure but which Greimas made quite clear, was its nonhistoricism. Structural semantics sought to extract an atempo- raI and organizational structural reality from the real, whatever the contextual framework or signified content might be: "We can reason- ably suppose that the achronic organization of contents that we en- counter in areas quite unrelated to each other should have a general scope. Because this model is uninterested in contents ... we must con- sider it to be metalinguistic."l1 Greimas hopedto move beyond the The Golden Age of Forma! 2 contingency the events in human in order ta write a struc- tural history purged of aU traces of empiricism. During the structural- ist phase, his was the most scientistic semiotic project for it went fur- the st in its desire for scientificity made manifest by the onmipresent mathematical terminology-"procedural algorithm," "rules for estab- lishing equivalences," "conversion rules"-and its function was to be a model of rigor. We find this logical and scientific approach in Lvi-Strauss and in Lacan, whose two projects most closely approximated scientific struc- turalism. The recurrent structuralist notion of rupture lay at the heart of semiotics since it established the division between two structures belonging to two different realities, but "how can we go from an im- manent theory of language to an immanent the ory of meaning in gen- eral? How, in other words, can we infer the binarism of meaning from the binarism of signs?"12 Claude Brmond proposed an answer to these fundamental ques- tions,!3 He differentiated between two stages of analysis in Greimas's reading of Propp: the first was inductive based on the model of Mor- phology of the Folktale: "Greimas considered the sequence of func- tions outlined by Propp in order to discern-and his idea has sorne merit -a better-structured system of basic oppositions." 14 Greimas contributed a certain number of useful tools, by distinguishing, for example, between the actors and actants among Propp's characters on the basis of their operationallevel. This let him build a mythical ac- tantial model with six terms, which was more effective than Propp's seven characters. But Greimas did not stop there. He quickly went on to a second stage of deductive abstraction where he argued for the a priori exis- tence of a transcendent princip le that would make it possible to go step by step from this principle to its concrete, textual manifestations. There were two basic ideas here: the semiotic square, which was Greimas's basic unit of meaning, and the ide a of a semiotic generation of meaningful objects. Brmond saw the square as "completely ster- ile," more a "mystical ide a th an a transcendent principle,"15 and nothing justified its extrapolation from Propp's model, which would be the model of models for any text in general, but especially for every possible written and unwritten text. "Ultimately, this simple postulate is like the head of a pin on which the diversity of the entire uni verse is made to rest. "16 2 r 4 The Golden Age of Forma! The semiotic square, a the Aristotelian square of op- posites and oppositions, became an explanatory matrix for an inde fi- ni te number of narrative structures. "This is the most flagrant case of an irrefutable theory, as Popper explains it."17 The semiotic square usually imposed an initial structure on a narrative, whether filmic or textual, letting it land on its feet since anything could be put in the four corners of the square without any verification whatsoever. "The use of the semiotic square has always shocked me a bit. 1 think it is justified at the end of an analysis, but surely not at the beginning."18 With the semiotic square, the empirical world and the referent could be kept at bay so that the kernel of intelligibility, the principal and invisible key of aH signified reality, could be discerned. Meaning was therefore directly derived from a structure that was immanent to it. Paradoxically, the semiotic program that united Propp, Lvi- Strauss's analysis of myths, and Hjelmslev's Prolegomenas, and that presented itself as the most comprehensive semiotic program, disap- pointed its promises. Greimasism quickly seemed to bec orne hermeti- cally locked in an increasingly confidential abstraction. The orthodox believers rapidly dwindled in number as Greimas's theories mobilized the most sophisticated, meticulously logical strategy that produced very disappointing and often tautological conclusions. "1 remember that, as part of the jury, 1 presented the summary of a very thick thesis by a very weIl known student of Greimas, on marriage. The conclusion was that marri age is a binary structure. This is true, in a certain way, but is this a conclusion that requires a thousand pages of analysis?"19 If Greimasism did not have a particularly brilliant destiny, Greimas himself remained one of the major sources of hope for the structuralist enthusiasts of the sixties. For Jean-Claude Coquet, who had met Greimas at the University of Poitiers where they taught together dur- ing his last year there, "Smantique structurale was an absolutely bril- liant book, full of ideas, one of the major works of the period. "20 When Greimas left Poitiers, he also left a student who was work- ing on a diplme d'tudes suprieures ta Jean-Claude Coquet. Franois Rastier was very close ta Greimas, who considered him ta be his spiri- tual son. "Rastier informed me about structural semantics. That was how 1 came ta know Greimas and 1 was fascinated by his intellectuai dexterity and the force of his convictions."21 The kind of linguistics most often practiced at the time eliminated the subject and history. Given this, Greimas seemed ta be the ma st radical, and therefore the The Golden Age of Formai Thinking 2 Il most his success sidelined mile Benveniste's approach to structural linguistics. Hjelmslev's mode!, which Greimas adopted, was in fact based on the production of a text baptized "normalized," or "objectivized." In order to arrive at this pure, scientific object, Greimas eliminated aIl dialogic signs or forms referring to a subject (first and second person pronouns, for example), which meant that he was left with third person canonical enunciations. And for the sake of a uniform present, he also normalized texts by e!iminating all refer- ence to time. The criterion for dissociating anteriority and posteriority became the vague reference to a distant past: "Whence Greimas's in- terest in folktales and mythic narratives, which were easier to work on. "22 But there was a steep price for the quadruple negation of the first pers on pronoun, of the subject, of intersubjective dialogue, and of the here and now with respect to space and time, and Greimas's the- ory rather quickly ran onto the shoals of an impoverished narrative reality, in favor of an ontologized structure. Would semiotics be able to create such a unifying pro gram for the social sciences? Its scientific imperialism was certain but its cohabita- tion with structural anthropology in a single institutionallaboratory was short-lived. Barthes the Semiotician Greimas had a disciple between 1960 and 1964 who already enjoyed significant notoriety: Roland Barthes. This was the period when Barthes repressed his vocatiolll as a writer and used Greimas's theory in order to better approximate a rigorous and scientific discourse. But Barthes was an essentially intuitive thinker, and he needed to rational- ize his feelings; Greimas was the person who seemed to go farthest in this direction. "You can't understand anything about Barthes if you don't understand that even when his thinking appears most abstract, he is really just covering up his affective choices. "23 Saussure's binary mode! fit Barthes like a glove since he thought in dichotomies, and al- ways set a valorized term against a devalorized term: the good and the bad; someone who is attractive and someone who is not; the crivain and the crivant; taste and distaste, and so on. But if Barthes would later give free rein to his feelings, they remained underground in the early sixties when he was articulating the principles of a semiologie al pro gram that were consonant with Greimas's theses. We can also understand Barthes's phase of theorizing and sei en- ZI6 The Golden Age of Formai Thinking tism in terms of a desire for university respectability. Even if he suc- ceeded quite quickly and brilliantly, he never joined the ranks with the traditional diplomas. His quest for recognition generated a veritable work ethic in him, and behind the dilettante that the specialists saw was a deeply ascetic man devoted to work. "He was basically the op- posite of a bohemian and led a typically petit-bourgeois life; he had an absolute need not to be upset by unexpected events. "24 At the begin- ning of the sixties, then, Barthes worked on the topie he would have wanted to have worked on as a thse d'tat had he continued his uni- versity work: fashion. He had tried to find a thesis director and, ac- companied by Greimas, visited Andr Martinet: "1 almost directed The Fashion System as a thesis. 1 gave him my O.K., aIl the while say- ing that this was not linguistics. "25 Given Martinet's relatively un- enthusiastic response, Barthes went to see Lvi-Strauss to ask him to direct his thesis. Greimas again went with him, and waited like an anxious father in a nearby bistro to hear how things had gone. "Barthes came out after half an hour saying that Lvi-Strauss had re- fused. "26 Their disagreement had to do with the limited breadth of the project since, for Lvi-Strauss, Barthes's work only dealt with a writ- ten system of style and not with a general system. Barthes, on the other hand, believed that nothing significant existed beyond the realm of the written. Barthes's hopes of university recognition were dashed, but in 1967, Seuil published the book, the labor of six years from 1957 to 1963. Because it was like a thesis for him, even if it did not have that tag, this book was partieularI, meaningful for Barthes. His spiritual father confided that "we looked at his book together three times and reworked it each time. "27 So this was both theoretically and affectively the expression of a significant period in his relationship with Greimas. The Fashion Sys- tem bears the marks of this relationship and appeared from the outset as a methodical work set on examining spoken-rather than worn- clothes, which was the basis for the divergence with Lvi-Strauss. Barthes essentially worked on the style system as a metalanguage, in Hjelmslevian terms. The transition from real to written clothing, by way of the clothing-image, was made with the use of shifters, an idea Barthes took from Jakobson. Shifters "are used to transpose one structure into another, to go from one code to another code, if you will."28 But Barthes used the idea in a very partieular way since he was not referring to a specific message. He also designated three shifters The Golden Age of Formai Thinking 2I 7 for moving from one code ta another: the principal shifter was the "sewing pattern," the second the "sewing program," and the third is the one that "makes it possible to go from the iconic structure to the spoken structure, from a representation of a piece of clothing to its description. "29 Formalist assumptions of normalizing the functional uses of lan- guage led Barthes to give priority to the written piece of clothing be- cause it was the only one that could give rise to an immanent study free of any practical function: "For these reasons, 1 have decided to examine the verbal structure here. "30 He defined his objects, consist- ing of newspapers from 1958 to 1959, and exhaustively sifted through Elle and Le Jardin des modes. A strictly orthodox Saussurean, Barthes reproduced the language/speech duo by opposing the clothing-image, located on the speech si de and therefore inappropriate for scientific consideration, and the clothing-text, which is on the language side and therefore an object eligible for scientific inquiry. Barthes anchored his analysis in the opposition developed by Hjelmslev: "The problem raised by the coincidence of two semantic systems in a single enunciation was dealt with primarily by Hjelm- slev."31 He adopted the separation between the expressive level (E) and the level of contents (C), brought together by the relation (R); this gives ri se to a multilevel analysis of denotation and connotation, of the language-object and of the metalanguage. Fashion was thus caught up in a process of formalization and therefore of desubstantification, giving Barthes access to the essence of fashion, which appears as a sys- tem of signifiers, a classificatory activity cut off from the signified. "Fashion therefore immediately proceeds to a sort of sacralization of the sign: the signified is separated from its signifier." 32 F ashion func- tioned on the basis of a double postula te. Because it was, on the one hand, a naturalist system, it could be interpreted as a logical system. The popular press practiced a naturalized fashion with an infinite number of fragmented references to a dream world and its utilization, whereas a more "distinguished" press practiced fashion in apurer manner, freed from all ideological underpinnings. At the end of his long study, Barthes made it manifestly clear that the full signified rep- resented the signifier of alienation, and he thereby drew sociological conclusions without falling prey to sociological reductionism. The fashion system translated a semiology characterized by its elaboration 2 r 8 The Golden Age of Formai Thinking of a taxonomy. The novelty, however, was that this taxonomy was made in order ta dissolve the subject in language. Jean-Franois Revel took the work ironically, and used a syllo- gism to illustrate its thesis: a rat nibbles the cheese but the rat is a syl- lable and therefore the syllable nibbles the cheese. "A structuralist rat, nothing impossible about that, of course. But if the rat writes, can he still eat chee se ? It is up to the sociologists to tell us." 33 However, the book was weIl received in general. Raymond Bellour interviewed Barthes in Les Lettres franaises,34 and Julia Kristeva saw the book as a step toward demystifying the science of the sign: "Barthes's work subverts the main current of modern science: thinking the sign. "35 Kristeva applauded Barthes for his radical interrogation of all metaphysics of depths, and for separating signifier and signified in favor of the relationship between signifiers, which was in fact part of Lacan's reading of Saussure when he invoked the signifying chain. Thanks to The Fashion System, an entire generation could imagine that it was possible to undertake similar investigations in other par- ticularly vast fields. If Barthes was able to isolate the vestemes in written/described fashion, why not flush out the gustemes and other distinctive units at allieveis of social practice? In 1967, the response to Barthes's work was spectacular and a veritable collective fervor took hold of his semiological program. But Barthes soon distanced himself from his own pronouncements and ambitions and, leaving Greimas to occupy center semiotic stage, re- turned to his vocation as a writer, which for him was the goal of a structuralism that would have been meaningless had it not subverted scientific language from within. "Structuralism's logical continuation can only be to rejoin literature not as an object of analysis, but as an activity of writing .... It is therefore up to the structuralist to trans- form himself into a writer."36 The need to write as the result of Barthes's methodological exigency in 1967 presupposed another re- naissance, which came to be the very principle of his writing: the plea- sure principle. In an interview with Georges Charbonnier in 1967, Barthes an- swered a question about the book of the year. Would it be a mathe- matical work, given that the public relished formaI thinking to the point that the social sciences would quickly consume themselves? "The final phase is that they question their own language and become, in their turn, writing." 37 Although Barthes did not renounce this liber- 1 The Golden Age of Formal Thinking 2I9 ating aspect of generalized formalization-the triumphant relegation of aH referents to the dustbin of insignificance, the intersection of work and fate in a Mallarman Hne between writing and formaliza- tion-he nonetheless admitted that "literary writing maintains a sort of referential illusion that makes it delicious." 38 By his taste for writ- ing as a figure of the other's desire, an erotics of language based not on reality but on the illusion of the referent, we see that Barthes's writing in I967 was already setting the stage for a radical change that would become apparent in the Barthes of post-May I968. An Ideology of Rigor Hjelmslev inspired the semiotic program in France, but other influ- ences were also at play during the golden age of formaI thinking. There was, for example, a spectacularly successful mathematical epis- temology in France, known for the mathematician Bourbaki. Bour- baki's mathematical structure, however, appeared as an antididactic form occulting the origin in the historical and empirical sense of math- ematical knowledge. "The logic of its presentation and the context of the justification are far more important than the context in which the disco very was made or in which the investigation took place. The entire empirical and tentative aspect of mathematics is systematically eliminated in favor of a purely formalist presentation. "39 This new ap- proach even gave rise to an important teaching reform at the begin- ning of the sixties, called new math; but it was a dis aster and even its author repudiated it. The Bourbaki ideology certainly contributed toward a structural- ist mentality and activity, which Pierre Raymond called an ideology of rigor. Bourbakism made it clear that the splendors of the mathemati- cal edifice were such that even those who might be able to appreciate them were held at arm's length: "Where the links, the concatenation, the imbedding of propositions are given as a sort of subjectless, objec- tive necessity whose internaI weaving is to be analyzed without under- standing the properly historical process of mathematical discovery. "40 The French found this model particularly fascinating, showing how much Louis Hjelmslev, the major linguistic inspiration for the semiotic school in Paris, valorized mathematics as a science. Semiotics was therefore complicitous with Bourbakism in its search for the codes and messages exchanged around points of emission, and in its concern to constantly extend the formalization of communication phenomena. 220 The Golden Age of Formai Thinking The other model in this are a from which structuralism drew its concepts and methods was cybernetics. Cybernetics became increas- ingly productive in the era of mass communication and cast an aura around the structuralist program. Cybernetics offered a potential bridge between math and the social sciences, and provided a frame- work for sorne especially wide-ranging investigations. It was a true interdisciplinary crossroad that addressed notions from algebra, logic, and information theory and game theory. A certain osmosis existed, therefore, between a desire for formal- ization that found the very expression of a split from the referent in mathematical language, and formalist research in the visual arts, music, literature, and architecture, coming from the East. "It was a period when Lacan and Chomsky sold as well as the popular mystery stories written by San Antonio. 1 remember that 1 was living in Puteaux and 1 would go buy my books at the drugstore on the Neuilly bridge. That's where 1 bought Desanti's Mathematical Idealities 41 and Lacan's crits. "42 These formaI models proposed that all boundaries between mathe- matical, logical formalization and the social sciences be effaced. Jean Piaget offered a particularly good example of a will to place psychol- ogy in a continuum using mathematics. With this end in mind, Piaget established a circular diagram of scientific knowledge that ended with a single and interdependent idea of the different sciences. Such a circle made it possible to link mathematics, physics, biology, and psychol- ogy.43 The semioticians were utterly fascinated by logical formaliza- tion, which they adapted to language. The temptation to borrow in this way was strengthened because computer programs were address- ing problems having to do with language, and logicians had the ad- vantage of having come up with almost perfect formalizations in their thinking about linguistic operations. "The temptation was therefore quite strong to try to adapt these logical formalizations to language, but 1 think that it was a sort of capitulation. "44 Although he never denied that formalization and model making were necessary, Oswald Ducrot held that a properly linguistic concep- tualization should be the starting point, but that it should not, for example, be limited to differentiating true from false. If there is a ten- dency in language to construct true propositions and to link them through the reasoning process, other dimensions of language must also be taken into account and that logicians tend to ignore. "A re- The Golden .Age of Formai 222 that Antoine about this a big influence on me. One day, he said, 'truth-I don't know what that iS."'45 Lacan: A Bend in the Road toward Logic In 1965, logic took up where the Saussurean linguistic modelleft off via another discipline, psychoanalysis. Jacques Lacan's text, "La sci- ence et la vrit" showed how much the cole Normale Suprieure and Jacques-Alain Miller had determined the direction in which things would go. Beginning with Gottlob Frege, Miller wanted to un- coyer the concept of structural causality that Althusser emphasized in his reading of Marx, as a basis for applying Lacan's notion of suture. Frege, in his Foundations of Arithmetic (1884), had established mod- ern symbolic logic by criticizing the empirical method. Symbolic lan- guage should be dissociated from aH reference to any conscious sub- iect. "Logic is that which is conceived or constructed outside any intuition; logic is that which is general to the point of belonging to every language such that no language could be conceived without it. "46 We can easily understand Lacan's interest in the work of a logi- cian who excluded the psychological subiect, even if Frege, who initi- ated a philosophy of language, was more appreciated by the Anglo- Saxons th an by the French. According to lisabeth Roudinesco, when Jacques-Alain Miller articulated Frege's concept of the zero and that of its successors with Lacan's theory of the signifier, he recast Lacanian thinking. The conse- quences were political and theoretical: "Theoretically, Lacanian think- ing becomes the model par excellence of the capacity of Freudian thinking to elude the ide aIs of psychology. Politically speaking, this re- casting makes it possible to designate adversaries who are considered to be deviants with respect to a doctrine that represents scientific nor- malization in its aH-powerful singularity. "47 After having used the rise of the social sciences to decenter the subiect with Saussurean linguis- tics, Lacan radicalized his reading of Freud even further in order to avoid becoming the agent of constructing the social sciences, with the attendant risk of reestablishing a humanism of an unalienated subiect. In Kurt G6del's logic, a theorem of incompleteness makes it possi- ble to perceive the idea of truth as eluding complete formalization. "He infers that the experience of the Cartesian doubt marks the sub- iect with a split between knowledge and truth."48 This turning point heralded the transition from a me-theme to a matheme, and is at the 222 The Golden Age of FormaI Thinking origin of many topological manipulations. For some, this formaliza- tion had less to do with clinical psychoanalysis than with its transmis- sion, and was more a didactic concern for rigor and method: "It is clear that Lacan does not use these objects as mathematical objects. They have a purely metaphorical status. "49 For others, the topological turning point was much more important because it made it possible for Lacan to better grasp the structure of the subject: "For him, the subject's structure is topological; he said so." 50 This structure, which had for centuries been represented as com- plete by the figure of the sphere, in fact better approximates the aspher- ical and incompleteness. This view of the subject gave rise to the mul- tiple topological manipulations designed to turn the sphere around in order to finally reach the subject's true structure as fundamentally split within the topology of knots. Notwithstanding their differences, Claude Lvi-Strauss, Aigirdas Julien Greimas, and Jacques Lacan were the most scientific of the structuralists in the mid-sixties, the most radically turned toward the search for a deep, occult structure, whether the metaphor be Lvi- Strauss's enceintes mentales as the structure of structures, Greimas's semiotic square, or the aspherical structure of Lacan's subject. These were the three crowning points of formaI thinking, aIl part of the same adventure seeking to establish the social sciences on the same footing as the natural sciences within the city of science. Twenty-five Great Confrontations Barthes/Picard A Homeric combat that best reveals the issues of the period was waged between Roland Barthes and Raymond Picard. This was an im- portant joust, with the new criticism contesting the old Sorbonne. The pivotaI figure was that classic of classics, Racine, who had become an object of contention and scandaI. Would the venerable Sorbonne aUow itself to be dispossessed of its patrimony in that realm of predilection known as tragedy by those very individuals who could not distinguish between journalistic scrib- bling and national literary treasures? Surely such provocation could not go ignored for francit was outraged. The confrontation occurred in the mid-sixties between two protagonists with different institu- tional ties and statures. Raymond Picard belonged to the venerable Sorbonne and Roland Barthes raised his voice from a modern but marginal institution. The stage was set and aU the elements assembled for the duel, which was cast like sorne great Racinian tragedy of the twentieth century. The important combat deepened the differences be- tween the two camps. Literary history was no longer the same after this, caught in the vise of two languages, each a stranger to the other. The French Book Club published Roland Barthes's Racinian Man in 1960 and an article on Racine came out in the Annales that sum- mer.! Three years later, Seuil published both pieces as On Racine, to- gether with a third piece on the same topic, and it was only then that 223 224 Great Confrontations they received public acclaim. The Sorbonne could accept the fact that the new criticism addressed the new novel, but that it sought to appro- priate the representative of classicism and of tradition in order to ex- periment with the incendiary effects of its analytic grid, its mixture of linguistic methods, psychoanalysis, and anthropology, bordered on scandaI. "If you want to do literary history, you cannot touch the indi- vi dual Racine."2 That Barthes published his article in the Annales already gave a clear idea of how he aligned himself in his approach to literary history, appealing to Lucien Febvre against the tenets of literary positivism. He adopted Febvre's combat against historicizing history, against the domination of events, in order to de fend the necessary dissociation be- tween the history of the literary function and the history of writers of literature. To do so, Barthes raised the same problems that Febvre had sketched out when he expressed the desire to study a writer's context, his ties with his public and, more generally, the elements of a collective mentalit, what Febvre called the mental equipment of a period. "In other words, literary history is only possible if it is sociological, and if it is interested in activities and institutions, and not in individuals."3 Barthes adopted the Annales ide a about an active criticism that does more than assemble and collect documents and archives, asking questions and subjecting the material to new hypotheses. Just as his- tory, for Febvre, was a history problem, Barthes held that a literary critic had to be paradoxical and raise contemporary questions when addressing any literary work, thereby participating in its undefined impact. Barthes read Racine analytically and structurally, therefore, and no longer saw the author as a cult figure, but rather as a field of investigation for validating new methods. The structure of Racinian man was Barthes's object and it was re- vealed through Barthes's careful and attentive dialectic of space, and particularly through a logic of places. The interior spaces of the bed- room, that mythic retreat separated from the antechamber-the scenic site of communication-by a tragic object (the door), the object of transgression, were contrasted with the exterior spaces of death, flight, and events. "In short, in Racinian topography, everything converges on the tragic site, but everything gets mired in it."4 Based on this topo-Iogic, tragic unity took shape not so much in the individual singularity of Racine's characters as in the function defining the hero as enclosed. "He who cannot go out without dying: Great Confrontations 225 his limits are his privilege, his captivity is his distinction. "5 This func- tional, binary opposition separating interior and exterior also made it possible to distinguish between Eros and the Eros event. Eros was a peaceful and sororal love rooted in childhood, whereas the Eros event was sudden, expressing itself violently and without warning, pro duc- ing ravishing effects that provoke a tragic alienation, which, accord- ing to Barthes, was Racine's true subject. "Racinian disorder is essen- tially a sign, which is to say, a signal and a communication."6 A whole dialectic of the logic of places unfolded in this mythic combat of shadows and light in terms of contiguity and hierarchy. The Racinian hero was driven by the need to prove his ability to make a break; his heroism depended on his capacity to do so. His own infi- delity created the hero who, like a creature of God, appeared locked in an inexpiable batde between the Father and his son. Barthes quite con- vincingly demonstrated that Racine substituted the word for praxis, for the offstage event; verbal communication became the source of dis- organization, the very site on which the tragedy unfolded and con- sumed itself. "The fundamental reality of the tragedy is therefore this word-action. Its function is clear: to mediate the Power Relationship. "7 Barthes used Jakobson's binarism as much as Freudian categories, together with a structural synchronic approach, and the Sorbonne's most erudite Racine scholar had a particularly violent reaction to all of this. Raymond Picard, author of The Career of Jean Racine, editor of the Pliade's publication of the complete works of Racine, and great Racine specialist, published his answer in 1965 in the evocatively entided work, New Criticism or New Imposture? Picard focused espe- cially on Barthes's excessive use of psychoanalytic decoding for under- standing Racine's theater and quickly lowered a chaste veil over the heroes whose secret and frustrated sexual passions had been revealed: "We must reread Racine in order to recall that his characters are, after all, quite different from those of D. H. Lawrence .... Barthes has decided to discover an unbridled sexuality." 8 Picard sliced through Barthes's systematization, denounced his avowed inability to speak the Truth about Racine, and therefore refused him the right to say anything whatsoever about an author about whom he had no exper- tise. For Picard, Barthes was "the instrument of a criticism that oper- ates by instinct,"9 that uses a pseudoscientific jargon to make inept and absurd assertions in the name of biological, psychoanalytic, and philosophical knowledge. Picard denounced the tendency toward gen- 226 Great Confrontations eralization, toward taking a single, concrete example for a category of universals in a critical game that confuses everything. For Picard, the mixture of impressionism and dogmatism set to a modernist rhythm of indetermination "makes it possible to say absolutely any stupid thing."lO Picard was not personally attacked by Barthes's study, but he counterattacked nonetheless, as self-appointed spokesman for the Sor- bonne. The institution was irritated by this structuralist agitation and wanted to see Barthes, who had become an idol, pilloried before being rejected. The violence of the polemic against him rather surprised Barthes: "1 was not expecting such an attack from Picard. 1 never at- tacked university criticism, 1 simply set it apart, named it."l1 For Barthes, the assault was provoked by the issue of university exams in literature. New criticism was dangerous because it questioned the ab- solute, intangible nature of the criteria used to establish a comfortable canon of knowledge, which was so certain of its values and methods. He saw the attack against his book as a defense of verifiable knowl- edge measured in terms of eternal truths. A whole generation of structuralists sided with Barthes, of course, and wholeheartedly embraced his cause against the aged Sorbonne. On the human level, we were always on Barthes's side. Today, 1 would not say that Picard was entirely wrong intellectually, but he was entirely wrong when it came ta his aggressivity. Barthes and Greimas were not agrgs and they could not enter the university. Barthes's thesis had been refused. As for the linguists, they had no career options and many of them suffered because of that. They were the victims of a veritable interdiction. French scholars of the time were mostly conservative politically, and governed by univer- sity scruples. 12 Picard's answer showed just how hermetic academic discourse was, and it once again demonstrated its stubborn hermeticism in the face of new issues and questions. Aesthetics professor Olivier Revault d'Allonnes kept score, and in the spirit of reconciliation, told himself that aH the polemicists were right. He did not want to choose between Lucien Goldmann's socio- logical perspective, Charles Mauron's psychoanalytic viewpoint, Ray- mond Picard's biographical approach, and Roland Barthes's struc- turalist outlook. "They are aH right. AH of that exists in Phdre and perhaps that is what makes it a great work. To recaH Adorno's Great Confrontations 227 metaphor, great work can layering. "13 At the time, as Louis- Jean Calvet pointed out, Picard was well received by the media. Jacqueline Piatier wholeheartedly supported him in Le Monde and referred ta "Roland Barthes's surprising interpretations of Racine's tragedies."14 Le Journal de Genve relished Picard's counterattack: "Roland Barthes KO'd in one hundred and fifty pages."15 Barthes suf- fered from these attacks at the time because he could not bear the polemic. He confided to his friend Philippe Rebeyrol: "You know, what 1 write is playful, and if 1 am attacked, there's nothing at all left."16 But the polemical debate, which Picard turned into a public event, boomeranged against the old Sorbonne. Soon, an enthusiastic generation of students would have the op- portunity to contest academic wisdom. Barthes answered Picard in his Criticism and Truth, published in 1966, at the height of the structural- ist paradigm. The book was clamorously heralded by the press, and bore the question "Should Barthes Be Burned?" on the promotional band encircling the coyer. The drama was therefore carried to an ex- treme, and Barthes once again played the role of the virtuous innocent risking being burned at the stake. It was an opportunity to fire up an entire intellectual community around the ambitious program pro- posed in The Elements of Semiology, which thus reached a vast pub- lic. This time, Barthes answered without spa ring the polemical tone. He denounced the fact that within "the literary state, criticism needs to be as restrained as the police."17 Barthes saw Picdrd's criti- cism as an expression of the most traditionalliterary history, clinging to a vague notion of "verisimilar criticism," which stands on its own, and thus has no need ta be supported by evidence. This notion in- cluded references to a critic's objectivity, to his taste, and to the clarity of his argument. Barthes characterized this type of literary history as the old criticism: "These rules are not of our time: the last two come from the classical age, the first from the era of positivism. "18 He also attacked the postulate according ta which the literary critic should limit himself to the literary level. Here, Barthes forayed beyond imma- nentist proclamations in order ta defend content and the external ele- ments that shed sorne light on the general economy of the literary text and required sorne knowledge of history, psychoanalysis, and anthro- pology. Unlike the positivist method, Barthes defined the critical act as an act of writing in the full sense of the work, a work on language. And in sa doing, by bringing the writer and critic together, he weak- 228 Great Confrontations ened the boundaries, limits, and prohibitions that differentiated writ- ing genres. Barthes took a double line of defense against Picard. He invoked the rights of the critic as writer and bearer of meaning, a veritable crea- tor by virtue of his own active reading; this critidwriter represented a more scientific discourse that no longer considered writing as deco- rum, but as a source of truth. The structuralist current supported his argument, with references to Lacan, Jakobson, and Lvi-Strauss. In- fluenced by the work of deconstruction in the social sciences, he pro- posed and made himself the spokesman for a "science of literature," as opposed to a traditional literary history.1 9 A science of the condi- tions of the content rather than of the content itself, which is to say, of its forms. Not surprisingly, Barthes took linguistics as the model for his science: "Its model, obviously, will be linguistics. "20 The author is displaced by the language, which has become the true subject, making the search for a hidden sense and ultimate meaning vain because it assumes an idea of the subject that is, in fact, an absence. "Literature never bespeaks anything other than the subject's absence. "21 In proclaiming the birth of a new historical era based on the unity and truth of writing, Barthes spoke for the ambitions of an entire gen- eration that saw in the explosion of the critical discourse of the social sciences a mode of writing that, properly speaking, rejoined literary creation. He shook up a university discourse that preferred to turn a deaf ear to an increasingly insistent voice. Even after 1966, the distant echoes of these batdes and gambols reverberated, and Ren Pommier's violent remarks clearly revealed the breach that Barthes had success- fully made into academic knowledge-a true robin announcing the spring of 1968.22 Lvi-Strauss/Gurvitch The other notable confrontation of the sixties pitted Lvi-Strauss against a whole area of sociology that was reluctant to be cast in the structural mold, even if it was familiar with the notion of structure. This sociology was gready influenced by the highly colorful personal- ity of Georges Gurvitch. It was another front in the battles of the mo- ment and was essential for Lvi-Strauss, who absolutely needed to persuade sociologists to join him if he hoped to bring aIl the sciences of man together around an anthropology that had become structural. The polemic between Gurvitch and Lvi-Strauss was, therefore, quite Great Confrontations 229 lively because the theoretical and institutional stakes were important; not surprisingly, it crystallized around the notion of structure. Gurvitch had laid out his idea of social structure in 1955, and de- fined it much as Murdock had done, as a phenomenon designating the idea of coherence among social institutions. 23 As a phenomenon, the idea of structure can be compared with or contrasted to other terms. For Gurvitch, social classes had to be distinguished in their structure as well as in their organization, and these social structures became the objects of an ongoing process of destructuring and restructuring. When they are involved in a process, they are also part of a dialectic. For Gurvitch, the social encompassed and extended beyond structure, and was irreducible to it: "It is incomparably richer than [its struc- ture], and its fullness implies the unexpected even more."24 Gurvitch criticized structuralism at once for its reductionism and impoverish- ment of reality and as something static that crushed society's imma- nent movement beneath its weight. Lvi-Strauss's retort was particularly stinging. "By what authority does M. Gurvitch appoint himself as our mentor? And what, in fact, does he know about concrete societies? As a pure theoretician, Gurvitch is interested only in the theoretical aspect of our work. "25 Which should take precedence, the singularity of an event or the per- manence of structure? This debate had recurred in sociology ever since Durkheim and Tarde, and was once again evoked at the heart of the confrontation between Lvi-Strauss and Gurvitch. An article by Gilles Gaston-Granger that was widely cited in the sixties paid consid- erable attention to it. 26 Gilles Gaston-Granger, an epistemologist, defined the alternative apparently opposing a perceptual comprehension of the world and an intellectual conception of the scientific approach, and in this regard he contrasted Gurvitch with Lvi-Strauss. "For Gurvitch, a structure is, in a certain way, a being, where for Lvi-Strauss, it is only a model. "27 Gurvitch refused both mathematical tools and formalization and con- sidered structure to be a phenomenon, whereas for Lvi-Strauss it was a question of a learning tool. Gaston-Granger considered Gurvitch to be an Aristotelian, whereas Lvi-Strauss represented "the party of a mathematics of man."28 Gaston-Granger did, of course, point out the danger of reifying a learning tool and transforming it into the object of knowledge in the social sciences, but the risk was to be taken de- spite the potential danger: "The risk must be run. "29 Gaston-Granger 230 Great Confrontations opted for structuralism even if he maintained a critical distance and criticized Lvi-Strauss for having gone from analytical models to universalizing diagrams, and running the risk of reintroducing a cer- tain ontologization into the instruments of conceptualization. Thirty years have passed since he published his article and Gaston- Granger is freer now th an he was at the time because he did not want to ruffle Gurvitch's sensibilities. Today, he considers that Gurvitch was "infinitely sm aIl next to Lvi-Strauss, and the bearer of a scholastic void."30 As for Lvi-Strauss, Gaston-Granger had only warned him against the danger of considering structures to be more real than real- ity, much like Plato; he nonetheless hoped that a great sociology or structural anthropology would be created and discover the key to a scientific understanding of social man. Today, Gaston-Granger is less optimistic about the results of Lvi-Strauss's program: "1 think that Lvi-Strauss's work did not yield what 1 had hoped it would."31 Gaston-Granger is severe and he does not fully admit how impor- tant Gurvitch was for a whole generation of sociologists and anthro- pologists. Of course, Gurvitch was something of a megalomaniac, whose rather natural vanity made him consider only his own work as worth taking seriously. Roger Establet, who became his assistant, was in fact supposed to have worked on that project: "1 was supposed to give courses on his work."32 His dogmatism was weIl known. "When he said that there were fourteen levels of structural depth, he did not me an thirteen or fifteen and he recalled with no little irony a Durkheim who had only found three." 33 But the hidden side of these dogmatic assertions reveals a touching individual, bludgeoned by history and driven by a consuming passion. Gurvitch lived on the rue Vaneau in the apartment where Marx had lived when he was in France; he was an exile in Paris and bought nothing except books, hoping one day to return to the Soviet Union. The conditions he stipu- lated for his return in his ongoing negotiations with Soviet authorities made him particularly sympathetic. He wanted to be able to speak in Russian to workers as they left the factories, and to be able to work in Russian archives in order to write a history of the Russian Revolu- tion in the place where he had been a commissar of the people. He was, therefore, a sociologist forever cut off from the field in which he would have liked to work. Finally granted permission in 1964 (he had given up on the idea of addressing workers in Russian, on the ad- vice of his wife), Gurvitch died before being able to realize his dream. Great Confrontations 23I During this entire period, Gurvitch was the rather charismatic leader of a network that was more or less reticent about the structural- ist vogue. The coterie included sociologists like Jean Duvignaud and Pierre Ansart, philosophers like Lucien Goldmann and Henri Lefebvre, and anthropologists like Georges Balandier. Most did not want to con- front Lvi-Strauss head-on. The choice was rather between two em- blematic figures of sociology: Raymond Aron and Georges Gurvitch. And yet, even in Gurvitch's group, the influence of structuralism spurred research and determined sorne methodological choices. Lucien Goldmann, of course, was receptive to a structuralism that he qualified as genetic and receptive to history. But structuralism's influence was also palpable among sociologists such as Pierre Ansart even if Gurvitch was directing his thesis. "1 have a very clear memory of the first day 1 heard structuralism discussed. It was a course that Georges Davy had given after having been at Lvi-Strauss's thesis de- fense. He gave an absolutely fascinating discussion on The Elemen- tary Structures of Kinship, which he presented as a unique intellectual possibility."34 And yet, Pierre Ansart, who had to do a complementary thesis on the birth of anarchism-which, moreover, he defended in 1969, after Gurvitch's death-freely elected a structuralist problem- atic. Influenced by Lucien Goldmann, he tried to construct a presenta- tion of the structuration of a thought process about anarchism in its relationships with economic structures, practices, and contemporary worldviews. "For those of us seeking our way, structuralism seemed to offer something extraordinarily productive for our work." 35 Structuralism did have a real influence on this group of left-wing sociologists, but it was the object of heated debate because of its demonstration of the dehumanizing process of our technical civiliza- tion. During a colloquium at Royaumont in 1960, the debate was quite lively; a consensus on criticism led by Gurvitch against struc- turalism brought together in a united front Jeannine Verds-Leroux, Sonya Dayan, Pividal, Tristani, and Claude Lefort. Jean Duvignaud, who was close to Gurvitch, examined the correlation between struc- turalism and the place from which it emanated: "Many people were dragged into this conflict because there was something more than what met the eye. The question was whether or not a society could trans- form itself from within."36 For Duvignaud, the famous epistemological break, which legitimated ideological structuralism so that it could either become official university doctrine or that of the intelligentsia, 232 Great Confrontations reproduced the hiatus between the dominant laws of the technostruc- ture and those of an eventual global change. "1 will therefore say that Lvi-Strauss's thinking has become true, even obvious, since, after hav- ing taken a detour via the natives, it once again found the very struc- tures of the second industrial age."37 Jean Duvignaud suggested the idea that Lvi-Strauss ignored history less because he observed the prevalence of relationships of reproduction, of a cooling of temporal- ity among tropical cultures he called cold, than because of an intuition about the changes under way in the postindustrial civilization at a time when communication was carrying the day over change. A Book Event: The Savage Mind Another great intellectual duel pitted two sacred monsters of the French intelligentsia against one another: Jean-Paul Sartre and Claude Lvi-Strauss. Lvi-Strauss had been attentive when Sartre's Critique of Dialectical Reason was published but had not objected at the time to Sartrean philosophy, not because he had abandoned philosophy, despite his remarks to the contrary, but because he was preparing a severe and highly polemical response on his own anthropological turf. Lvi-Strauss's answer was the final chapter of The Savage Mind, enti- tled "History and Dialectic," which became the masterwork in the history of anthropology. The Savage Mind came out in 1962, as did Totemism Today. Lvi-Strauss not only reacted to Sartre's theses, but he continued to explain how the savage mind operated. He added grist to the demonstration begun in "Race and History," by concen- trating this time on a demonstration of the universality of mental mechanisms beyond differences of content. In this respect, there was an important shift from Lucien Lvy-Bruhl's theses contrasting the prelogical mentality of primitive societies, characterized by the prin- ciple of participation, with the logical mentality of civilizations, gov- erned by a principle of contradiction. Contrary to anthropological tradition, Lvi-Strauss asserted: "The savage mind is logical, in the same sense and the same fashion as ours."38 Long presented as the primitive expression of emotions, the savage mind, here, was perceived in terms of the dimensions of the syn- thetic and analytic goals it assigns itself. The savage mind proceeds just like the Western mind through the paths of understanding, and uses a complete system of extremely varied distinctions and oppositions. There are, however, two distinct but unhierarchized kinds of Great Confrontations 233 minds, distinguishable two strategie levels. The savage mind, on a perceptuallogic and expressing itself in signs rather than in con- cepts, i5 a closed and finite system, governed by a given number of laws. Lvi-Strauss, to be sure, opposed this closed and circular system to open scientific thinking with its different relationship to nature. The savage mind belongs to a kind of thinking that binds words and things together in a relationship of redundancy. It understands the concrete world and is neither spontaneous nor confused, as was long believed. Its terrain of predilection comprised the daily activities in primitive societies, including hunting, gathering, fishing, and so on. "The richness of abstract words is not a monopoly of civilized lan- guages."39 Lvi-Strauss described the confusion of ethnographers when faced with the wealth of knowledge of Indian tribes and their capacity to distinguish, identify, and represent the animal and vege- table worlds in which they lived. The Hopi Indians had distinguished three hundred and fifty kinds of plants and the Navajo Indians more than five hundred. This kind of concrete mind made its classifications in a meticulously careful way so that this knowledge, organized in a complete system of prescriptions and prohibitions, could be useful for everyday life. ln Totemism Today, published the same year, Lvi-Strauss illus- trated the central thesis of The Savage Mind. He showed that until then anthropologists had encountered an apparent aporia because they limited their observations about totemism to similarities between the animal or vegetable world and the human world, whereas the value of totemic classification lay in the structural homology it established be- tween a natural and a social series. "The totemic illusion begins, first of aU, by distorting the semantic field governing the same type of phe- nomena."40 Totemism integrates binary oppositions and its function is to transform whatever might appear to create an obstacle to integra- tion into something positive. Natural species are not selected because they are good to eat but because they are good to think about. 41 An osmosis exists between method and reality, a homology between human thinking and its object. Ethnographie research therefore be- cornes logical construction and can reach the level of anthropology- in other words, the se arch for the fundamental laws of the human mind. Lvi-Strauss diverged here from Malinowski's functionalist inter- pretation, which only examined the naturalist, utilitarian, and affec- 234 Great Confrontations tive dimensions when explaining that the deep interest that primitive societies showed for the animal and vegetable worlds cornes from their primary preoccupation with food. Lvi-Strauss argued that the explanation lay at a deeper level than a simple identity mechanism, namely, the intersection of nature and culture: "Totemism postulates a logical equivalence between a society of natural species and a world of social groups. "42 Structuralism always flourishes, therefore, at the crossroads of nature and culture, upon which its project is built. The Savage Mind was an immediate and spectacular success and helped to make the structuralist program better known beyond an- thropological circles. It was so successful, in fact, that a journalist from France-Soir warned those of her readers who might be tempted to buy the book not to be misled by the reproduction on the cover of the Viola tric%r, called "wild pansy" (pense sauvage). The lovely bouquet of flowers adorning bookstore windows might make poten- tial readers think that the book was about botany, whereas, the jour- nalist warned, this was really a very difficult essay. More seriously, Claude Roy considered Lvi-Strauss's book to be as important as Freud's Psychopath%gy of Everyday Life: "Freud brilliantly demon- strated that our madness obeys a logic that escapes the conscious mind. Claude Lvi-Strauss proposes a profound and new demonstra- tion that shows that the apparent chaos of primitive myths and rituals in fact obeys an order and principles that until now have remained invisible. "43 In a long article in Critique, Edmond Ortigues began by drawing an analogy between the methods of Paul Valry and Lvi-Strauss. Both the poet and the ethnologist shared the same formaI concern: "A like-minded family of minds: the same reticence with respect to his- tory, both equally insistent about defending the sensitivity of the intel- lect against the intelligence of the emotions."44 In his column in Le Monde, Jean Lacroix hailed this strictly scientific work but was some- what skeptical of what he called "the most rigorously atheist philoso- phy of our time."45 For him, this philosophy occasionally resembled a vulgar materialism that sees a reflection of the mind's liberty even in mathematical expression, that is, cellular activity in the cerebral cor- tex, which obeys its own laws. Le Monde gave the event considerable coverage; in addition to Jean Lacroix's article in November 1962, there was Yves Florenne's article of May 1962 and an interview with Lvi-Strauss on July 14 of the same year. Claude Mauriac reviewed Great Confrontations 235 the book in Le Figaro, and Robert Kanters enthusiastically reviewed it in Le Figaro littraire, commenting judiciously that "the sciences of man today are the sources of the art of tomorrow. "46 The structura li st community voiced its approval through Barthes's very favorable review of Lvi-Strauss's two 1962 works. Barthes ap- plauded the substitution of a sociology of signs for a sociology of sym- bols, as well as the introduction of a socio-Iogic that was in keeping with the comprehensive semiological enterprise. Lvi-Strauss's merit was to have extended the field of human freedom to a realm that had escaped it thus far: "Claude Lvi-Strauss invites us to consider a soci- ology of that which is specifically human. It acknowledges that hu- mans have the unlimited power to make things signify. "47 Lvi -Stra uss/Sartre The Savage Mind was one of those rare moments when a book seemed to be a real irreversible event thanks to its capacity to transform our vision of the world and of others. Lvi-Strauss decided to publish his deferred attack on Sartre in this centerpiece of the structuralist pro- gram, a veritable riposte to Critique of Dialectical Reason that was particularly polemical. Sartre's charisma was targeted, along with the status of philosophy as the crown discipline, as well as the privileged position of the philosophy of history, and of historicism, eliminated from the structural perspective. History is nothing more than a narra- tive, condemned to ideography. Lvi-Strauss attacked Sartre's eleva- tion of it as unifying and totalizing: "In Sartre's system, history plays exactly the part of a myth. "48 Experience, events, historical material all belong to myth and Lvi-Strauss could not understand why phi- losophers, and Sartre first among them, insisted on granting history so much importance. He viewed their fascination as something resem- bling the effort to restore a collective temporal continuity, in contra st to the ethnologist's method, which unfolds in spatial discontinuity. For Lvi-Strauss, historical content was wholly illusive and mythi- cal; since a historian chooses a given region or epoch, he can only con- struct local histories, without ever managing to achieve any sort of meaningful comprehensive history: "A truly total history would can- cel itself out-its product would be naught. "49 Thus, no historical to- tality existed, but only a multiplicity of histories untied to a central subject, to man. History can only be partial or incomplete, and there- fore remain partial, in the sense of being "biased."50 This was a for- 236 Great Confrontations mal diatribe against philosophy of history: its "alleged historical conti nuit y is secured only by dint of fraudulent outlines."51 History would only be the last refuge of a transcendental humanism and Lvi- Strauss invited historians to rid themselves of their vision of man as central, and even to give up history. "As we say of certain careers, his- tory may lead to anything, provided you get out of it."52 Instead of history identified with huma nit y, Lvi-Strauss proposed the timelessness of the savage mind, which grasps the world in a renewed synchronic totality. Sartre did not directly respond to this attack, but Pierre Verstraeten analyzed Lvi-Strauss's work in Les Temps modernes in an article entitled "Claude Lvi-Strauss or the temptation of nothingness." Verstraeten argued that "Lvi-Strauss willingly mixes up the realms of semiology and semantics (or linguis- tics) by systematicaUy applying the princip les of semantics to aU of semiology."53 Lvi-Strauss proved the power of the dialectic nega- tively, by discerning how inane historical temporality was for him. Verstraeten therefore criticized Lvi-Strauss by taking his own idea of the imagination just as Lvi-Strauss had dubbed Sartrean philosophy as mythic. In 1962, this underlying battle between the two giants of the period led to Lvi-Strauss's triumph: the structural program took precedence over Sartre as the incarnation of historicism. Ricoeur /Lvi -Stra uss The Savage Mind also stirred another important debate during the same period in the review Esprit. The editorial board immediately felt concerned and chaUenged by Lvi-Strauss's work and as represen- tatives of a philosophy of the subject. Esprit's director, Jean-Marie Domenach had created a philosophical group to study Lvi-Strauss's work over a period of months, in order to publish a special issue on him. There were articles by Jean Cuisenier, Nicolas Ruwet, and oth- ers, that put The Savage Mind into perspective, and the issue ended with a debate between Lvi-Strauss and the team that had worked on his work. Certain of Lvi-Strauss's remarks were edited out of the transcribed debate, such as this one: "My own formula is that of Royer-CoUard: the brain secretes thought the way the liver secretes bile."54 And Lvi-Strauss refused a second round of interviews or de- bate, which many foreign reviews repeatedly requested. Nonetheless, Jean-Marie Domenach was particularly grateful to Lvi-Strauss for having participated in this contradictory confrontation: "1 appreciate Great Confrontations 237 his participation in this debate because 1 greatly admire his inteUectual ability." 55 Paul Ricoeur's article "Hermeneutics and Structuralism" clearly sketched out the two divergent positions. Ricoeur did not reject the scientificity of structuralism's work on the codes operating in lan- guages and myths, but he did contest what he saw as a transgression of limits in the unjustified shift to generalization and systematization. For Ricoeur, the two levels needed to be clearly differentiated. The first was based on linguistic laws and formed an unconscious, non- reflective stratum, a categorical imperative that did not necessarily require reference to a conscious subject. Binary oppositions in phonol- ogy illustrated this level, as did elementary kinship structures-about which, moreover, Ricoeur acknowledged the validity of Lvi-Strauss's analyses: "The structuralist enterprise seems perfectly legitimate to me and removed from any criticism so long as it remains conscious of the conditions of its validity and therefore of its limits." 56 With The Savage Mind, Lvi-Strauss generalized his enterprise, which worked as well in the tropics as it did in more temperate climes and resembled logical thinking. Yet Ricoeur contrasted totemic think- ing to biblical thinking, which reversed the relationship between di- achrony and synchrony. He did not suggest that subjective meaning should replace the objectivity of formalized meaning, but rather some- thing he called the object of the hermeneutic: "Which is to say the di- mensions of meaning that are opened by each of these successive re- turns; the question that is raised becomes the following: do aU of these cultures equally offer as much to reconsider, repeat, and rethink?"57 Ricoeur characterized the transition from structural science to struc- turalist philosophy as "Kantianism without a transcendental subject, indeed, an absolute formalism."58 His hermeneutic took this stage of formaI deciphering into account at the same time as it set a goal of making understanding the other coincide with self-understanding through the mediation of the interpretation of meaning, by a mind that ceaselessly thinks and rethinks itself. Lvi-Strauss repeated and accepted the "Kantianism without a transcendental subject" in his reply to Ricoeur, but although he ac- cepted the terms, he rejected the question of the meaning of meaning: "We cannot at the same time try to understand things from without and from within."59 For Lvi-Strauss, the scientific phase of his work 238 Great Confrontations was the requisite taxonomy of societies, which meant that he could only go forward in those areas that had been sufficiently prepared. The era of great debates had begun, and with it the question of disci- plinary boundaries was raised. Caught up in the game of disciplinary confrontations, many would go from one to another and accumulate analytical tools and areas of competence; interdisciplinarity was on its way to becoming the new religion. In order to be a good structuralist, one had to be a linguist, an anthropologist, and have a bit of psycho- analysis and Marxism. The period was rich and intense; men and con- cepts became mobile, irrespective of boundaries and indifferent to customs agents. These were the forerunners of a structuralism that was more ideological than scientific; this malleability made it possible to acquire powerful positions and shake up the old Sorbonne. Indeed, Michel Foucault's election in November I969 to the Collge de France, and Paul Ricoeur's defeat, can be seen as part of structuralism's pro- pulsive force. As the numbers of encounters and debates increased, different dis- ciplines were forced to redefine their positions. Andr Green did just that for psychoanalysis when he called its practices into question on the basis of the then current opposition between history and struc- ture. 60 Back to back, he dismissed Sartre, who denied a theoretical basis to psychoanalysis, and Lvi-Strauss, whose panlogical position led him to limit his considerations about man to his physical-chemical structure. A defender of the work of Freud, Andr Green demon- strated that history and structure could not be dissociated in psycho- analytic practice: "History is inconceivable outside of repetition, which itself refers to structure; structure, insofar as man is concerned, is not conceivable outside of man's relationship with his genitors, who constitute the symbolic and introduce a temporal-atemporal relation- ship that implies the historical dimension."61 ln this symphony of dis- cord and friction, which produced anathemas and exclusive models, Andr Green's position of a well-tempered structuralism seemed like that of the sage who settles matters at a time of extreme positions when it was a question of pushing things to an extreme. Twenty-six Signifying Chains The Schisrn Between the schism in 1953 and his excommunication in 1963, Jacques Lacan consolidated his positions by anchoring them firmly in the flour- ishing structuralist paradigm. Indeed, this grounding became necessary while negotiations to affiliate the Socit Franaise de Psychanalyse (SFP), which was finally created in 1953, with the International Psychoanalytic Association (IPA) foundered. It quickly became clear that the sine qua non of this affiliation would be the abandonment of Lacanian practice, and the pure and simple exclusion of Lacan himself, who had become the main obstacle to a general reconciliation. Banished, Lacan gathered the faithful around and created the cole Franaise de Psychanalyse in 1964, while another part of the SFP, led by Jean Laplanche, affiliated itself with the IPA in 1963 and became the Association Psychanalytique de France. What was true for Trotskyists was also true for psychoanalysts: the schisms and dissolu- tions became the yeast for the Lacanian movement. The secession of those who had been members of the SFP for ten years, in addition to being the result of the sought-after benediction of the IPA, followed a certain number of disagreements. On the one hand, the practice of short sessions created great con- cern for the numbers of patients filling the waiting rooms. On the other han d, mixing individu al or so-called didactic analyses with teaching also raised a certain worry about the risks of mixing the gen- 239 240 Chaim res. "But above Lacan's unwillingness to give up anything ta do with his practices suddenly revealed their importance .... Sa, what in our (or my) nave eyes had appeared to be secondary was in fact the main issue."l A good many of Lacan's disciples would there- fore go their way within other organizations. Risk of isolation and marginalization became Lacan's major con- cern. Anyone who was not with him was considered to be necessarily against him. But Lacan needed to rise above things in order to give his charisma free rein. Exiled and banned, definitively excluded from his temple, Lecan identified himself quite simply with Spinoza, who had fallen victim to the same excommunication, in two stages: the Kherem of July 27, I656, was the principal excommunication, followed by the Chammata, which forever excluded him from the Jewish community of Amsterdam. 2 ln order to hone the image of the martyr, Lacan left his teaching position at Sainte-Anne Hospital. Lacan was alone at that point, without his refuge of Colombey- les-Deux-glises, but the author of the Rome Report returned as a hero and announced a new undertaking: on June 2I, I964, he estab- lished the cole Franaise de Psychanalyse: "1 establish, as alone as 1 have always been in my relationship to the psychoanalytic cause, the cole Franaise de Psychanalyse." He obtained the protection of Fer- nand Braudel and Louis Althusser and created an outpost at the Sixth Section of the EPHE at the ENS. This institutionallink allowed him to broaden his public considerably and, thanks to the philosophers, he found himself in an important strategic position on the intellectual playing field. Eminently aware of the absolute necessity of developing his public, he bowed to Franois Wahl's insistent request to publish the bulk of his writings, something he had always refused to do. Seuil began publishing in I966. Given Lacan's theoretical politics, he needed to find sorne sup- port. Having failed with Paul Ricoeur,3 he invited Lvi-Strauss to the opening lecture of his seminar in Dussane Hall at the ENS. Lvi- Strauss agreed to come despite very serious reservations about Lacan's style. Lacan therefore managed to transform his failure with regard to the IPA and the weakening of his movement in the wake of the split into a moment of glory symbolized by his teaching at the ENS. For five years, anyone who was anyone among with-it Parisian intellectu- aIs rushed to see and hear the man who became the shaman of mod- ern times. "Rejected by the international psychoanalytic movement, Signifying Chaim 24I Lacan's work came to have a central place in the French adventure of structuralism. "4 The Signifier The trace of structuralism in Lacan's theory of the unconscious is par- ticularly noticeable in the role of the signifier. We have already seen that he adopted 5aussure's notion of the sign in the fifties and modi- fied the respective places of the signified and the signifier in order to valorize the latter. In his seminar on Psychoses (1955-56), Lacan made it clear that the signified was not free from the signifier but slid beneath it until it reached a point at which the patient's meaning be- came more clear, which he called a point de capiton; this is "what makes the signifier stop the otherwise indefinite slippage of significa- tion."S There is therefore no similarity between 5aussure's and Lacan's signifier, even if the 5aussurean signifier "is not only the homonym but also the eponym of the Lacanian signifier. "6 Once it had bec orne inde- pendent from the idea of the signifie d, the notion of the signifier took on even greater importance for Lacan at the beginning of the sixties, when the signified represented the subject for another signifier. "It was on December 6, 1961, exactly, during the seminar on Identification, that Lacan defined the signifier for the first time, by distinguishing it then and from then on quite clearly from the sign. "7 It was not until 1964 and The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis that the signifier really came to occupy the place of the subject for another sig- nifier that it kept from then on. The signifier, the n, occupied the place and site of the subject, who se existence is given as the absent cause for its effects, that is, the signifying chain by which it makes itself intelligible. The subject is not reduced to nothing, but rather ta the status of nonbeing; it is the non- signifying foundation of the significance of signifiers, in other words their very condition of existence. It is the analyst's job to restore the internaI logic of this signifying chain, for no one of the discrete ele- ments can in and of itself represent meaning. A subject for another sig- nifier, the signifier only fulfills its function by constantly being effaced in order to let another signifier take its place. Lacan represented this chain by making 5 bec orne 52, which represents the signifying chain, and 51 the additional signifer that pushes it forward. The subject, however, is nowhere, or in the place of the signifier that it supplants, given that that place is to be nowhere. Transcribed as a slashed $, out 242 Signifying Chains of step with itself, the subject is forever split; it occupies the fourth term of the signifier's structure and is just as eccentric with respect to what is said. This object is represented as the objet petit a [object little 0] (for other).8 Lacan's profound interest in the signifier is thus key and took off in the sixties as a fundamental stake in the structuralist vogue. The context revealed what Jean-David Nasio called the "umbilical" mean- ing of an idea, or the conditions under which an idea is born and evolves. 9 An entire dialectic developed on the basis of this signifying structure, according to a double logic of places and forces, and estab- lished the primacy of the signifier over the signified. The world be- came little more than a fantasy in which things are subordinate to words. Even if Lacan's definition of the signifying chain freely inter- preted Saussure's ideas, it was nonetheless part of a more general structuralist conception that atomized the realms of discourse and in- stituted the order of things on the basis of the order of words. Only the signifier of lack holds the world together, the Thing that Lacan took from Heidegger in order to designate the quadripartite earth, sky, humans, and gods. "Thinging is the nearing of the world,"lO but just as it did in Heidegger, the Thing "bears this fourfoldnesss because it is essentially constituted by a void."ll The thread of the world was thus based on a centrallack, which was the condition of its unity. Objet petit a One of the principal terms of Lacan's signifying structure is the objet petit a. Serge Leclaire considered this to be a major scientific discov- ery: "An invention worthy of the Nobel Prize, a veritable inven- tion."12 The innovation came in two steps. Lacan first referred to the "little other" as a mediating element between the barred subject and the Other, situated in an imaginary function. In the second stage, the little other became the objet petit a, as an object of lack, a metonymic object of desire, a simple signifier of desire cut off from its reference to a desiring subject and from any symbolic reference to an unconscious signifer. Lacan no longer attached the objet petit a to the imaginary, but to the Real as he understood the term, which does not mean reality but that which resists signification. "The Real is what is impossible. " For Lacan, this partial objet petit a was extremely important. He placed it at the level of the function of refuse and gave new meaning to Chains 243 the separation of the fetus, forever separated from the placenta, which is tossed into the trash bin. The libido is thus designated as a multiple chain of desires, trying in vain to substitute themselves for the initial separation. The objet petit a is put "in the place of the refuse of the signifying operation." 13 It has a relationship with all parts of the body that can be linked to the function of refuse, transi- tion, or separation. Objet petit a as an object of desire ever reborn and always lacking became increasingly central to Lacan's thinking and came to incarnate the very object of psychoanalysis: "The object of psychoanalysis ... is nothing other than what 1 have already set forth in the function that the objet petit a plays in it." 14 It is the object of the drive that makes the law of desire, as well as the phantasmatic object, function. "The objet petit a is the negative of the body." 15 Whatever its place in Lacan's framework, the objet petit a cannot be addressed as an isolated object, for it only exists through its articulation with the symbolic and the imaginary by way of the Real. Castration, however, determined the mode of this articulation and made it possible for de- sire to become manifest: "Castration is the law that organizes human desire like a partial truth,"16 ma king it possible to enter into the order of the Law, linked to the Name of the Father, in other words to a fig- ure that can be dissociated between that of the real father and the symbolic father. ln this respect, Lacan reversed Freud's vision of the Law as a pro- hibition: the Law was positive, the law of desire. In the early sixties, when he taught principally through lectures, Lacan favored writing, as did Jacques Derrida later, and identified the signifier with the letter (The Pur/oined Letter), completely in tune with Saussure. "The Thing becomes word, says Lacan, in the sense of motus: it is both speech and silence, which takes your breath away and overwhelms speech."1? ln analytic practice, the objet petit a has become a fundamental to01 for certain analysts. "The objet petit a is useful. Analysts even say that, depending on the object, this or that drive can be deduced. It makes it possible to get des ire going once again and to avoid despair."18 Lacan said of this objet petit a that it had to become the corner- stone of psychoanalysis rather the corner stone of rejection. Even if he established the rules of a science while remaining fundamentally pes- simistic about it, the object on which his science was based was syn- onymous with an unrecoverable loss; the objet petit a set the signify- ing chain going. So Lacan laid out the rules for investigating the 244 Signifying Chains signifying chain but held out no illusions about the analyst's ability to find what had been forever lost. An analysis is not just a positivist ef- fort of memory; in place of the lost object there is an entire "construc- tion made of signifiers, but what organizes them? The object as if it were 10st."19 For Serge Leclaire, the partial object is the necessary counterweight, by virtue of what it evokes as impermanent in order to escape the pure Signifier, to a Symbolic purged of its Imaginary dimen- sion. This was one of Lacan's fundamentallessons and had the virtue of preventing any dogmatic closed-mindedness. "AlI the analysts who have really contributed something interesting have spoken about ob- jects. Whether it be Freud, of course, or Melanie Klein, Winnicott, or Lacan."20 Lacan broached the question of meaning through the idea of sig- nifying sequences. Interpretation always cornes after the fact and is deferred with respect to what has been said. This temporal difference makes recourse to the objet petit a necessary as a substitute for de- taching meaning in the relationship between the signifier and signified. We might even wonder if Derrida did not simply borrow this objet petit a for his notion of diffrance, so central to his work on decon- struction. For Lacan, the objet petit a became something like the means of recuperating the eliminated of the signified in the signifying chain. "It is the loss of this objet petit a as an object that provokes de- sire and as an object of desire per se that both makes the subject speak and is that about which he will speak, while always eluding him. "21 The analyst is therefore glad to be able to keep his patient's attention riveted to these objets petit a. Yet even those analysts who were quite deeply affected by Lacan's teaching do not attribute the same importance to this objet petit a. "1 don't do anything at aH with the objet petit a. "22 Andr Green is clearly the most critical on this essential issue. In 1966, he published an article in Les Cahiers pour l'analyse on the objet petit a in which he clarified Lacan's perspective on it as well as that of Jacques-Alain Miller on the relationship between (a) and the suture, based on Frege. This was the period when Green, while still a member of the Socit Psychanalytique de Paris (SPP) and of the IPA, was fascinated by Lacan's work: "The love 1 felt for Lacan lasted seven years. "23 Andr Green is the current director of the SPP and has therefore had an en- tirely fascinating and receptive career, given how deeply he was af- fected by Lacan's teaching, even though he maintained his theoretical ''''''lifvinp- Chains 245 and distance. His position changed and he became in- creasingly critical of Lacanian positions for theoretical reasons. "As time went on, 1 was less and less in agreement with him, but he fected me quite profoundly."24 Green began going to Lacan's seminar in 1961 and was at the same time interested in Winnicott, whom he had discovered at the Ed- inburgh conference in July of that year. Although he was conceptually interested in the objet petit a at the time, today he is quite critical about this aspect of Lacan's thinking: "1 don't think that psycho- analytic theory can be satisfied with a the ory about partial objects. By eliminating the so-called total object, the Other capital 0 is once again necessary and this Other is nothing other than God."25 Green was interested in Lacan's Augustinian sources and particularly in Saint Augustine as read by Pascal in his Writings on Grace, doubly infused with religion and mathematical formalism. 26 He also saw this double polarization in Lacan, who gave his spiritual forebears, and not the church, which he criticized, a chance to renew themselves. "The struc- tural approach (the question of the Filioque) should come first and it alone makes it possible to have an exact idea of the function of im- ages. Here De Trinitate is just like a theoretical work which we can take as a model. "27 Lacan's rereading of Freud referred to a pure Sig- nifier that can be read through the lens of religion. In the place of Freud's castration anxiety, Lacan gave castration an ontological status derived from the Name of the Father, together with the trinitary order of the Subject-Real/SymboliclImaginary-giving a Christian cast to his reading. Indeed, Lacan was quite familiar with the Bible and, inso- far as the Great Other is concerne d, its position with respect to the drive chain remains undetermined, a pure extraterritorial Signifier, the veritable equivalent of the soul: "Lacan reverses Freud's appreciation of Goethe in Totem and Taboo: 'In the beginning was the action.' He admitted that he preferred a formula taken from Saint John: 'In the beginning was the language.' "28 Other readings are possible. Alain Juranville, for example, also recognized the figure of God in the pure Signifier, not a religious God but the God of absolute reason. However, the Thing's location outside the world as an incarnated Signifer refers back to fullness as God's jouissance, beyond the world's closure in Saint Augustine. Lacan's po- sition of radical if dialectical idealism was confirmed when he posited the world as fantasy or when he referred to its unity as an initiallack 246 Signifying Chains or to a causal chasm. The Signifier-master was everywhere and no- where; it escaped the worldly world and at the same time could be located within it. Like God, it was only a Name, albeit an essential Name because it was the condition of being in this world insofar as castration, as a symbolic operation, must be endured. AlI of Lacan's efforts to decontextualize and to eliminate the organic dimension of Freudian theory and to take refuge in linguistics, and then in topology, as so many intellectual and formalizable means of approaching the question, can therefore be seen as so many secular efforts to achieve a rule, a Law made by a regular member of the clergy who had attained salvation after having blocked ail the other roads that did not lead to the Big Other. Reading Lacan this way could explain why so many Jesuits, and not the least among them Michel de Certeau or Franois Roustang, as weil as Catholics like Franoise Dolto, joined in the Lacanian adven- ture. "1 see in Lacan a new encounter with that whole Catholic, post- Tridentine, theological intelligence, in the sense of an awakening re- garding the question of the Trinity,"29 remarked Jean-Marie Benoist, a philosopher who shared this feeling with Philippe Sollers. Both con- sidered that Lacan had made a post-Tridentine opening possible, that of baroque thinking. Many Christians thus followed Lacan, "believ- ing that they were working for God, until the moment they realized that Lacan was only working for himself."3o This religious dimension was carefully occulted during the struc- turalist period when the issues were science, theory, and formaliza- tion. And yet, specialists of the history of religion attended the semi- nars. Bernard Sichre, for example, did not believe that Lacan was trying to give a Catholic reading of Freud, but that he was, in fact, the only one to believe that, at the risk of going mad or suffering the re- turn of the repressed in its most fanatical and frightening forms, the religious question was unavoidable. And this at a time when the major concern was to wring the neck of Western metaphysics. "This is not to say that psychoanalysis should be religious. But to ask why one of the la st important works of Freud was, precisely, Moses and Monothe- ism. "31 On this point, both Freud and Lacan attributed to religion a centuries-old function of effectively mediating between forbidden sex- ual reality, and they wondered whether this discourse had the same place in contemporary society. Yet, Lacan confronted a total symbolic where nothing had replaced the mediating role of religion. Neither a SHY,o,tVlnU Chains 247 political nor a scientific discourse cau replace the dominant fictions that organize social and Lacan therefore assigned this role ta psychoanalysis, this lucid placeholder, "ideally, because psycho- analysis cannot be a religion." 32 Affect The signifying chain effectively eliminated the insignificant dimension of affect. This was another of the points on which Andr Green criti- cized Lacan. In I960, at Bonneval, he heard Jean Laplanche and Serge Leclaire on the unconscious and he shared Laplanche's reservations about the linguistic conception of the unconscious. At the same time, and with respect to affect, Lacan announced at Royaumont that "in the Freudian field, in spite of the words themselves, consciousness is a feature as Inadequate to ground the unconscious in its negation (that unconscious dates from Saint Thomas) as the affect is unsuited to play the role of the protopathic subject, since it is a service that has no holder."33 So Jean-Bernard Pontalis asked Andr Green to write on af- fect for Les Temps modernes; his article was published in I961. Green took up the question more broadly in a work published in I970:34 "For me, Lacan gives an anti-Freudian version of the unconscious."35 For Andr Green, the richness of Freudian the ory was based on the heterogeneity of the signifier. Freud did not consider the signifier ta be an array of internally homogeneous, interchangeable terms such as one finds in language, but a series of levels of different materials. Green insisted on distinguishing, as Freud did, between the mate rial of the psychic representations of drives (endosomatic stimulation) and the preconscious (the representation of things with the representation of words that corresponds to them). The clearly distinct levels may not always translate from one to the other. "The proof is that there are psychosomatic problems that do not have representations."36 And yet, according to Green, with Lacan we return to a Platonic concep- tion linking things to a linguistic essence. Where Freud saw hetero- geneity, Lacan saw homogeneity and went so far as to introduce intel- lectuals to a clean unconscious. However, according to Green, the analyst's work is to account for complexity. Eliminating affect in favor of a purified Signifier explains why Saussure was considered to be the dawn of modern consciousness on this point. In order to establish the scientificity of linguistics, Saussure was also obliged to eliminate the referent, speech, the individual, and the diachrony. There was a 248 Signifying Chains price to be paid for the birth of modern linguistics; ma king the mean- ing of language less vital was the parallel to be drawn with Lacanian psychoanalysis. Lacan used the Saussure an rift to negate affect and to leave on the sidelines other possible linguistic sources that took affect more into account: Saussure's disciple Charles Bally, for example.37 In structural linguistics as in Lacanian psychoanalysis, affect was forced to the sidelines by an ever-increasing formalism. A sense of mastery could be maintained as long as the field was limited and homogeneous. And yet, "affect is something over which we really have no control; it is evanescent, diffuse, slippery, full of disorder and noise. That is why it seems fundamental to me."38 In his Studies on Hysteria, Freud emphasized the need to get to the affective origin of trauma tic memories. Serge Viderman used the metaphor of the crystal ball so dear to the structuralists and considered psychoanalysis to be doser to the smoke than to the crystal ball. Negating affect, the barred objet petit a could simply be the result of an essential aspect of analy- sis that Lacan needed to use but that he also wanted to guard against, even going so far as to repress it: transference. Lacan was so concerned with formalizing and purifying the ana- lytic situation that he reduced transference as much as he could, for it created the most aberrant sentiments, and difficult to rationalize. He banished the term "countertransference" by placing it in the category of the analyst's desire. "He refused to let us talk about or use the term." 39 Freud's relative laconism on the subject became a pretext that made it easier for Lacan to purge the term. Was it also in order to guard against his personal tendencies toward an overflowing affectivity, working out his theoretical justification after the fact in order to con- tain his own affective drives? But although transference was to be con- tained in an analysis, Lacan recommended it in the teaching of psycho- analysis. The first yearbook of the cole Freudienne made it quite dear that teaching psychoanalysis succeeded only when transference oper- ated. But it changed at this point to become a vector of knowledge free of all sentiments, referring back to "the subject who is supposed to know." The Lacanian subject was disincarnated, and the familiar struc- turalist theme of the negated individual once again made its presence felt. "The Lacanian operation is double, which is to say perfectiy con- tradictory. On the one hand, it has to maintain subjectivity, ... and on the other, to empty this subjectivity of all incarnation, humanization, affectivity, and so on, in order to turn it into a mathematical object. "40 Signifying Chains 249 Jean Clavreul believed Andr Green's criticism of affect to be un- founded. Of course, Lacan always refused to take any pleasure in the delights of intersubjectivity where one hates or loves oneself, but this did not mean that he was indifferent to affect, since he never stopped speaking about love, hate, and love-ha te, and he even devoted an en- tire seminar to anxiety. "But what Lacan showed us was this kind of dependency of affect with respect to the game of signifiers. "41 Serge Leclaire also remained unconvinced by Andr Green's cri- tique of Lacan for eliminating affect, which he found too imprecise and to which he preferred the ide a of economy or of drive-inspired movement: "1 remember a debate with Green in which 1 had proposed sorne other formulations, saying that one is affected to a job or re- ceives ones affectation, but to make it a corner stone, no. "42 And yet, Lacan used affect in the transference that he promoted among his disciples. He did not hesitate to mix genres in this context, for whatever he learned through a personal analysis was immediately reinjected into the organizational circuit of power and knowledge in the name of the imperative of didactic transmission. Reacting against this tendency, "the French Psychoanalytic Association is the only asso- ciation in the world in which there are no didacts, in which analysis is considered a personal issue. "43 The key institutions Lacan created were interesting for the way they lent dynamism to analytic know-how, rather than letting it slug- gishly coagulate into a dogma. Analytic work became a source of re- newal and debate. The conventions of transmission, supervision, and multiplication of cartels were so many tools and points of observa- tion. "1 have said of la passe [transmission] that it was a site for ob- serving the transferential situation. "44 There were two types of cartels: work groups with at least three and no more than five people, with ei- ther an additional person (the "extra one") or the "plus one," so that each of the individuals in turn became the "plus one" onto which the transference was made without the presence of any additional person. Above aH, this made it possible to pursue unfinished analytic work and to sweep away illusions, but the unconscious returned in another swing of the pendulum. For Claude Dumzil, Lacan pointed out a dif- ficult path, the only possible one, which required that the toys used along the way be destroyed; but this was the only way to keep the pos- sibilities of analytic research open. Twenty-seven Mythology's Earth Is Round Lacan placed the signifying chain at the level of the unconscious; Lvi- Strauss situated it in the constant reutilization of myths. This recycling made it possible to understand the meaning of mythology thraugh the matrix whose transformations resemble the unconscious operations of condensation and displacement. Lvi-Strauss saw mythic structure as the product of a veritable syntax of transformations. In the tetralogy he devoted to myths, Mythologiques, he pursued his argument, which diverges from the dominant symbolist theory of the early twentieth century, symbolist theory, which viewed the mythic story as an object eut off from its environment and which tried to raot out the occult meaning of each term of the mythic tale. Lvi-Strauss also tried to get beyond functionalism, and particularly Malinowski, who tried to take account of the social function of myths in their specifie context. In- stead, he integrated the study of myths into a symbolic system, but emphasized the ide a of system, structure, and construction by cutting the myth into minimal units, which he called mythemes, and which he arranged into paradigms. He essentially attempted to decode mythic discourse internally and, unlike the functionalists, he studied each myth independently of the conditions of its communication and func- tion. By studying the full range of myths, he hoped to find their com- mon structure. Myths must be understood by juxtaposing their differences and variations, an approach that would be consonant with Vladimir 25 Earth Is Round 25 l ProPP's 1928 suggestions. Comparing mythic analysis to Penelope's tabors, Lvi-Strauss intimated that the work of decoding was infinite, whereas the conclusions to be drawn were relative: "As happens in the case of the optical microscope which cannot reveal the ultimate struc- ture of matter to the observer, we can only choose between various de- grees of enlargement. "1 The My th as a Mode of Derealization Lvi-Strauss did not believe that myths were the best material for working out a comparison between infrastructure and the uncon- scious psyche, but that they could provide a key to the constants of the human mind since they, more than any other object, escaped external determinism and social constraints. Seen this way, myths, even more than kinship structures, provided a propitious terrain for study and were a better means of reaching the structures of the human mind: "They make it possible to discover certain operational modes of the human mind which have remained so constant over the centuries and are so widespread over immense geographical distances, that we can assume them to be fundamental."2 Their meaning would be the prod- uct of a signifying chain, and, in the manner of Lacan's concept of the unconscious, the signified, while not exclu de d, slips beneath this chain. The environment was not really negated in this signifying system, but could play a local role in the communication of the mythological mes- sage, and which operated internally in its resistance to reality: "The syntax of mythology is absolutely free within the confines of its own rules. Ir is inevitably affected by the geographical and technological substructure."3 Beyond the diversity of the societies that spawned them, myths could be taken as a group, a mode of derealization, an uninterrupted flow of representations to be examined in their internaI variations, "in the author's fascination with myths which, in the last resort, all say the same thing."4 They referred to a double unit y: unit y of the system in which they were integrated and unit y of the message to which they referred, expressed by the relationship of the message to itself and to another message, thereby doubling the emphasis. Myth's Signifying Chain Lvi-Strauss started working on Amerindian mythologies relatively early on. In 19 SI, he began teaching in the Fifth Section, where the theme was religious sciences, at the cole Pratique des Hautes tudes 252 Mythology's Earth Is Round (EPHE) and his first seminar was entitled the Visit of Souls. "My ideas on mythology took shape at the cole [Pratique] des Hautes tudes."5 In his I955 article "The structural study of myths,"6 he laid out the methodological principles according to which the constituent units of myth are not isolated relations but bundles of relations whose combi- nation produces meaning: "We have reorganized our myth according to a time referent of a new nature ... a two-dimensional time referent whieh is simultaneously diachronic and synchronic."7 Anthropology was no longer to seek an ultimate meaning or the essence of myth in an invariant, but should defiue each myth by the accumulation of its versions as constituent parts of the signifying chain that alone is capable of substituting a beginning of interpreta- tive order to initial chaos. Repetition revealed the myth's structure and was a function of one or many codes disclosing the mythic sub- stance of the message. The Savage Mind, published in I962, was a prelude or general in- troduction to the later tetralogy. In this early work, Lvi-Strauss pre- sented the mythie mind as being as structured as the scientific mind and every bit as able to think in terms of analogies and generaliza- tions. He attacked Jung's theory of archetypes and the notion of the collective unconscious, and laid out his own ambition of sketching the construction of a "theory of superstructures,"8 based on juxtaposing many explanatory systems and on reintroducing the individual myth, as a single element in a process of general transformation, into the sig- nifying chain of other myths. One element was therefore substituted for another in the signifying mythological chain and internaI shifts within the mythic system became necessary. In this way, he adopted the binary oppositions between marked or unmarked terms, a notion borrowed from phonology, and above aIl the notion that meaning re- sults from position, so many analytic tools borrowed from linguistics and applied to myth. More than ever, linguistics became the heuristic mode!. The anthropologist's work, therefore, must consist in "organizing aIl the known variants of a myth into a set."9 Repetition acquired a special status since it was essential for revealing the very structure of the myth in its synchronic and diachronie dimension. "Mythieal thought is therefore a kind of intellectual bricolage,"lO continually re- cuperating the de bris of events. Lvi-Strauss attacked the quest for ul- timate origins because he considered the object of the analysis to be to define each individual by the ensemble its versions. He fore opened up a limitless and indefinite quest for the primitive mind, who se lively imagination organized material in new ways, inverting or substituting ideas integrated into increasingly complex combinations. Social reality, however, dropped out of the anthropologist's pur- view in this game of slipping beneath the signifying chain in which dis- tinctive oppositions take their place within the structure and establish the structura lit y of the signifying chain. References to the ecosystem or to social organization only made sense once they were integrated into the signifying chain, which, by definition, was constructed at a re- move from referential reality, which is always held at sorne distance. Saussure had excluded the subject, similarly eliminated from this scientific perspective. "The subject is an epistemological obstacle"l1 for Lvi-Strauss. There was no place for a "cogito"-"Myths are anonymous"12-and Lvi-Strauss pursued his enterprise of decenter- ing a subject dominated by the mythological universe that speaks in him but unbeknownst to him. Man is only a pertinent level of analysis insofar as he reveals the organic constraints inherent in his mode of thought: "The problem therefore is to define and categorize these enceintes mentales."13 Although he addressed other objects of study, Lvi-Strauss had in fact pursued the same goals since his work on kin- ship. His oeuvre was coherent, straddling the borderline between na- ture and culture and bent on establishing the natural bases of culture (and making it possible to transform anthropology into a science of nature freed from the reins of a philosophy that, at each step along the way, was being repudiated and treated as an object of derision and of repeated polemics). The My th of Reference Having established the bases of his method, Lvi-Strauss really began his study of the vast field of Amerindian myths in 1964, with The Raw and the Cooked. He opened with the Bird-nester's aria, a myth of the Bororo of central Brazil, which became his myth of reference and the basis for the study of 187 myths belonging to about twenty tribes, which together constituted a series that answered the question of the origin of cooked food, of cuisine. A son, guilty of incest with his mother, is sent by his father to con- front the souls of the dead. The son accomplishes his task with the help of a good grandmother and various animais. Furious that his 254 Earth 1s Round plans had been foiled, the father invites son ta come with him to capture the macaws that nest on the face of a cliff. The two men arrive at the foot of the rock; the father erects a long pole and orders his son ta climb it. When the son had barely reached the place where the nests were perche d, the father knocked the pole down, leaving his son to the vultures. The birds devour the son's buttocks, after which they save him. Once back in the village, the son takes revenge by transforming himself into a stag and rushing at the father so furiously that he im- pales him on his antlers. He then gallops toward a lake and drops his victim into it; all that remains of the grues orne feast are the bare bones at the bottom of the lake and the lungs, which float to the surface in the form of aquatic plants. The son also takes revenge on his father's wives, including his own mother. Decoding: Culinary Mediation Lvi-Strauss's method resembled Freud's interpretation of dreams, iso- lating each sequence of the myth and comparing it to other sequences in other myths. And yet, an anthropologist's questions differ funda- mentally from those of an analyst: the interpretation focused less on the son's incest than on the oppositions between sensorial qualities, based on their binary organization. The Bororo were apparently not interested in guilty incest in this myth or in the veritable guilty party or the perpetrator of the incest, who appears as the hero of the myth; the y were interested in the father who wanted to take revenge on his son and who was mortally punished. The object of the myth, accord- ing to Lvi-Strauss, lay not in what it recounted explicitly but in the explanation of the origin of cooked food-even though this theme was apparently missing-because cooking is the mediating operation par excellence between heaven and earth and between nature and cul- ture. Myths about the origins of fire bespeak a double binary opposi- tion between the raw and the cooked and between the pristine and the corrupted. The link between raw and cooked has to do with culture, whereas the link between the raw and the rotten has to do with na- ture. Fire is an essential mediator for the beginning of cooking and works in two ways. It unites sun and earth and saves man from what is rotten, but it also eliminates the risks of a situation that would lead to a burned world. The basic rule of Lvi-Straussian interpretation was to focus on the myth's internaI organization and to arrive at para- digmatic sets based on different mythemes. In order to reveal the Earth 15 Round 25S meaning this a deeper rationality had to be brought to bear, drawn from the se arch for permuting sets, articula- tions of sign systems manifested in a long mythic series; whence the long comparative quest to establish a meaningful series. Taking as starting points observable, empirical categories such as the cooked, the raw, the humid, the rotten, and the burned, Lvi- Strauss restored conceptual tools and abstract ideas, behind his ethno- graphie observations, which elucidated the way primitive societies think. Although he took ethnographie observation quite seriously, Lvi-Strauss nonetheless considered theory to be most important. Discernible qualities of mythic discourse have a logical existence that reiterates the five senses in five fundamental codes. The mythic mind was structured like a language in a way that recalled Lacan's defini- tion of the unconscious: "By ta king its raw material from nature, mythic thought proceeds in the same way as language which chooses phonemes from among the natural sounds."14 The Infra- and the Supraculinary ln From Honey to Ashes, the second volume of his Mythologiques, Lvi-Strauss moved from the oppositions between material qualities to oppositions between full and empty, container and contained, inter- naI and external. The analysis became more complex as the less obvi- ous myths were discussed, for while they said the same thing, they me- andered and took more detours on their way to saying it. These myths reflected a new dimension of a culture's transition to society: from the paleolithic economy to a neolithic economy, from the hunter-gatherer society to an agrarian society. Lvi-Strauss explored the same realm of cooking with honey and tobacco, but in a roundabout way, for they appear, "each in their different ways, culinary paradoxes."15 The Indi- ans considered honey to be a ready-made food, a given of nature, ma king it a natural infraculinary object. The symbol of a descent to- ward nature, honey could be good but it could also be poisonous. Ambiguous, therefore, it engendered risks illustrated by the "girl who was crazy about honey" myth with its reference to the seduction of the natural order over human culture and the danger of its dissolution in the natural order. Unlike honey, tobacco is a supraculinary product, whose function is to restore the relationship between the natural and cultural orders that honey can undo. As the smoke rises sinuously, tobacco restores what honey undid by rising toward culture. Lvi- 2)6 Earth 15 Round Strauss made a second shift in his distinction between a of immediately obvious images and a new category of the imagination that came iuto play and required an image that symbolism did not offer: "We see aH the important mythic scenes backwards, a little as if we had ta decipher the subject of a tapestry from the interwoven threads which we see on the back."16 Human life had ta find its precarious balance somewhere between the two perils of a natureless culture and a cultureless nature, each of which posed the threat of famine. Setting the nature/culture relation- ship, initially considered as a fact and then as the arder of things in The Elementary Structures of Kinship, into a dialectical relationship was here perceived as a myth culture needed in order ta create itself with and against nature. "1 have changed rather a lot since then through the influence of the progress made in animal psychology and the tendency ta make ideas of a cultural nature intervene in the sci- ences of nature."17 The nature/culture opposition shifted; from an im- manent property of reality, it became an antinomy belonging to the human mind. "Opposition is not objective; it is men who need to for- mulate it. "18 The ethnographic context was no more than a frame, the beginning of a reflection that had to free itself from the popular cus- toms, beliefs, and rituals whence myth arises, in order to reach a higher level of abstraction so that "the context of each myth consists more and more of other myths. "19 Honey and tobacco, unlike the sta- tic ideas of the raw and the cooked, represent dynamic imbalances: they are temporal rather than spatial oppositions. The Culinary Moral With his third volume, The Origin of Table Manners, Lvi-Strauss cast his net more widely than the geographical zone that until then had been limited ta South America; he now included North American 1ndians in an even more complex comparative study of myths that studied the opposition between the different ways according to which the terms were used, whether together or separately. Culinary media- tion continued to be the general focus, but in this volume morality made its appearance as a new and central object. After the material and formallevels, this was the third level involved in describing what was now a logic of propositions. The ordered world is also a threatened world; it suffices to dis- place the boundaries or transgress the safe distances. Every infraction Mythology's Earth Is Round 257 can crea te disturbances in any universe, be it natural or cultural; ap- propriate customs therefore play a regulatory role. Lvi-Strauss con- trasted the ethics of the West, where individuals respect hygiene in or der to protect themselves, and the et hic of societies called primitive, where hygiene is respected so that others are not victims of one's own impurity. The "savage," unlike the "civilized man," shows a greater humility toward the order of the world. After the origins of cooking and its derivations, therefore, Lvi-Strauss addressed the different ways of preparing and eating dishes. Each stage along the way iIlus- trates the fact that "culture is not defined as a realm but as an opera- tion, one that makes of Nature a veritable universe .... This operation is a mediation that is both separated and united."20 Nature was therefore constantly acculturated and culture, conversely, naturalized; mythic thinking operated in both directions in this instance. The Tetralogy The Naked Man came out in 1971, the fourth and last volume of the remarkable tetralogy and the end of a seven-year-Iong effort. The press applauded the event. Le Monde published a complete dossier in- cluding an interview with Lvi-Strauss by Raymond Bellour, articles by Hlne Cixous ("Le regard d'un crivain"), by historians Marcel Dtienne and Jean-Pierre Vernant ("Eurydice, la femme-abeille"), and by the linguist-musicologist Nicolas Ruwet ("Qui a hrit?"), as weIl as an article by Catherine Backs-Clment. Even television viewers could watch what Le Figaro called a "seri- ous Sunday": Lvi-Strauss was the gue st speaker. He decided to show off the Laboratory of Social Anthropology he had created, showing viewers bits of the fieldwork of Franois Zonabend, Pierre Clastres, Maurice Godelier, and Franoise Izard. The Naked Man as weIl as the entire Mythologiques were unanimously hailed, and Lvi-Strauss thus joined Wagner in the register of the social sciences. The fourth volume at first seemed out of joint with the first three, for it was no longer a question of cooking or of culinary metaphors. But in fact the four volumes were linked by a profound unit y, and it was clear for Lvi-Strauss from the outset that if the first term of the Mythologiques was raw, the la st would be nude, for at the end of this mythological journey, he found the equivalent of the Boraro myth of reference. Moreover, "if the transition from nature to culture, for the Indians of tropical America, is symbolized by the transition from the raw to the cooked, for the Indians of North America, this transition is symbolized by the invention of clothing, ornaments, costumes, and, beyond aH this, by the invention of commercial exchanges. "21 The South American hero reduced to the state of nature-or to the state of rawness-had his parallel in the North American hero reduced to the state of nudity. The Naked Man revisited the determinisms of the economic infra- structure and the tetralogy reached its apex: "This rounds off my analyses of a vast system, the invariant elements of which can consis- tently be represented in the form of a conflict between the earth and the sky for the possession of fire. "22 The decisive and founding ele- ment was therefore a mortal hero's capture of fire from the heavens, willingly or not. The earth oven appears as effectuating the double conquest of fire and of earth by the culinary art of cooking. A verita- ble pivot of these mythic tales, the earth oven plays the role of a for- maI pattern. "Consequently, at this stage, the image of the earth oven as a supreme manifestation of culinary art ... marks the transition from the state of nature to the constitution of society. "23 In the finale of The Naked Man, which was like a contrapuntal re- sponse to the overture of the first volume, Lvi-Strauss reminded the reader of the methodological necessity of effacing the subject in order to reach mythic structure. And, by attacking the subject, he once again took up the polemic he had never really ceased waging against the pre- tensions of philosophie discourse. Lvi-Strauss answered those critics who accused him of dessicating and impoverishing the human uni- verse with his formaI reductions of messages shaped by the societies he studied: However, for too long now philosophy has succeeded in locking the social sciences inside a closed circle by not allowing them to envisage any other object of study for the consciousness than consciousness itself. . . . what structura li sm tries to accomplish in the wake of Rousseau, Marx, Durkheim, Saussure and Freud, is to reveal to con- sciousness an abject ather than itself; and therefore, to put it in the same position with regard to human phenomena as that of the nat- ural and physical sciences, and which, as they have demonstrated, alone allows knowledge to develop.24 This criticism also sought to achieve the status of a natural science able to discern the conditions governing the operations of the human mind through anthropology, among other things. The internaI tension Earth 15 Round 259 between nature and culture was reiterated in Lv-Strauss's own course, between his own ambition to read the intangible laws of the neuronal nature of the human brain and his undying desire to be a creator who had chosen the social sciences as a realm of study in which to create something artistic. This tension is palpable in the very composition of Mythologiques, conceived on the basis of Wagner's tetralogy.25 The Raw and the Cooked dealt with the origins of cooking and once again repeated the theme of the genesis of the world, of the Law, and of Das Rheingold. The Origin of Table Manners corresponded to Die Walkre in its treatment of kinship and of incest and how to avoid it. From Honey to Ashes corresponded to Siegfried as an acculturation of savagery. The Naked Man, of course, corresponded to Die Gotterdammerung, a return to origins after the disappearance of the system constructed to reach the finale. The musical analogy is present from the definition of the project to study myths in "La structure des mythes," where Lvi-Strauss compared the mythological object to a musical score that should be read vertically and horizontally. The Raw and the Cooked was dedicated to music and took the figure of a fugue. The musical reference was even more explicit in The Naked Man: "1 have tried to construct with meanings a composition comparable to those that music crea tes with sounds. "26 Music and mythology in Lvi-Strauss mirrored one other, from the invention of the fugue whose composition was reflected in the myth. "With the death of myth, music becomes mythical in the same way as works of art."27 And yet, the scientific if not scientistic per- spective of the program of structural anthropology was constantly repeated with greater optimism about its powers of analysis: "struc- turalism offers the social sciences an epistemological mode! incompa- rably more powerful than those they previously had at their dis- posaI. "28 Philosophy was the obvious target for it had always given priority to the subject, "that unbearably spoilt child who has occupied the philosophical scene for too long now."29 Naturalist Structuralism If Lvi-Strauss rediscovered man, it was as human nature. In The Naked Man, he used his research on vision and on the cerebral cortex, which demonstrated that the data of perception are repeated as binary oppositions. Binarism, therefore, became not simply an externallogi- 260 M",'h"il",,,,,'o Earth Is Round cal apparatus slapped on reality, but a reproduction of corporal oper- ations, "and if it constitutes an immediate property of our nervous and cerebral organization, we should not be surprised that it also sup- plies the best common denominator for making human experiences coincide that might seem superficiaIly ta be utterly different."30 Lvi-Strauss hoped to awaken on Judgment Day to find himself among the natural sciences. But the price for such an accession would be the elimination of aIl narrative content from the signifying chain of myths and, like phonemes, the reduction of mythemes to oppositional values. Scientific conque st would then be based on compatability or incompatability but it led Lvi-Strauss to a "logical formalism"31 that contributed to setting mythemes into relationship with each other within a myth. Formalism established the syntagmatic link and the su- perposition of mythemes taken from different myths, which constitute paradigmatic groups. The mind reiterated nature because it was na- ture; their complete isomorphism blurred the tradition al lines of de- marcation between these two orders of reality. In this respect, we can talk about Lvi-Strauss's radical materialism. Indeed, he remarked that if he were asked about the signifier to which the signifying chains ultimately lead, "the only reply to emerge from this study is that myths signify the mind that evolves them by making use of the world of which it is itself a part. "32 Causality was clearly at work in these mythological links, but it was neuronal and implied, by definition, that the semantic content of mythological propositions be kept at a complete distance from their social referent. Not that this referent was absent from Mythologiques, of course, because these volumes include aIl the available ethno- graphic information that Lvi-Strauss had, but it was only as per- tinent as a simple decor, the basic material that was used without determining the mode of thinking. Because the logical constraints governing mythic utterance could only be seized at the grammatical level, this was the only pertinent level for mythic necessity, and the only possible means of reaching the enceintes mentales. Through the symptom that it represented, grammar revealed that which it avoided saying. A myth's truth consists "in logical relations which are devoid of content or, more precisely, whose invariant properties exhaust their operative value."33 Lvi-Strauss could thus avoid the specular relationship between social reality and myths. He escaped-and he was right to do so-the mechanisms of reflective thought; but he re- Mythology's Earth Is Round 26I placed them with an internaI mythological logic obeying only neu- ronal constraints. The necessary autonomy of culture from society was pushed to the limits of its logic, until it became entirely independent. The phono- logical model became the theoretical basis for extracting social con- tent, for favoring the code over the message. "The proposition accord- ing to which the elements that form the myth lack independent meaning follows from the application of phonological methods to myths. In fact, the absence of meaning is a characteristic of pho- nemes."34 His analogy between mythology and music lent support to Lvi-Strauss's ambition to have a theory that is constructed, detached from an object. The result was a fascinating monument-Lvi- Strauss's work itself-but its cost was the loss or abandonment of the principles of any hermeneutic perspective. Logical reductionism re- quired eliminating affect from the signifying chain, just as it had for Lacan. Thus, the sexuality of Amerindian societies was put to every- thing except sensual ends. It answered a "dialectic of opening and shutting,"35 and therefore opened onto a desexualized world where sexuality was everywhere. The parallels between Lvi-Strauss's and Lacan's structural procedures were once again clear, and made patent by Lacan's similar affirmation that "sexual relationships do not exist." The subject was negated, an insubstantial site, delivered up to the anonymous thinking unfolding within it. This mind could be bet- ter understood so long as the subject "dissolve, like a spider, in the threads of its structural web."36 A Machine That Abolishes Time History is the other important omission in the Mythologiques. Lvi- Strauss saw a particular relationship between myths and temporality. Mythology and music, "indeed, are instruments for the obliteration of time."37 The object Lvi-Strauss chose to use in his polemical demon- stration with philosophers was designed to unseat the priority, which he considered exorbitant, that they gave to historicity. And yet history was not absent much and we have already seen that Lvi-Strauss criti- cized functionalism for ignoring it, but it belonged to the realm of contingency. History's place was "the place that rightfully belongs to that irre- ducible contingency .... To be valid, any investigation which is en- tirely aimed at elucidating structures must begin by submitting to the 262 Mythology's Earth Is Round powerful inanity of events."38 Clio was repressed, the first step in a scientific procedure; the dichotomies Lvi-Strauss established between necessity and contingency, nature and culture, form and content, all align structure and science, the event and contingency. Relegating his- toricity in this way did not belong to cold societies alone: Lvi-Strauss saw the "Greek miracle" (the transition from mythic to philosophical thinking) as a simple historical occurrence that meant nothing more than that it happened there and could just as weU have taken place elsewhere since no necessity made it inevitable. At the end of his mythological adventure, Lvi-Strauss radicalized his position. The temporal order that myths reveal was not only time rediscovered, like sorne Proustian experience, it was "abolished."39 "If taken to its logi- cal conclusion, the analysis of myths reaches a point where history cancels itself out."40 We once again find that importance ascribed to presence that so characterized the structural paradigm, but this is a present that stretches out and dissolving past and future in a temporality nailed to the ground, static, a mind that refutes historical teleology as much as the ide a of fleeing time in a reconciled present. Lvi-Strauss borrowed this ide a of "man liberated from the temporal order" from Marcel Proust. 41 Both this liberation and refutation of history led him to the point of "reinstalling a philosophy of presence."42 This presence was nothing other than the presence of nature that had forced out history, presence of the mind and of the universal genotypes that functioned like a binary machine; aU of this a reinstatement in the living and pres- ent material of the human mind. The Dusk of Men The end of history sounds a crepuscular note in the finale of The Naked Man. At the culmination of this great work elucidating the mythological universe, the reader perceives the historical pessimism that, from the beginning of the undertaking, has inhabited Lvi- Strauss. Everything that had been so inteUigently studied becomes nothing more than the ephemeral flowering of a world fated to meet its end, its ineluctable death. Mythologiques ends with the dusk of men, and echoes Wagner. These myths let the complex edifice appear as it "slowly expands to its full extent, then crumbles and fades away in the distance, as if it had never existed. "43 Time unfolds in the very logic of its disappearance, inscribing its Earth 1s Round 263 own abolition in a dusky Lvi-Strauss his initial con- ception of an anthropology as entropy: "The lyrism of death is the most beautiful, but also the most fearsome. "44 Having been revealed to itself at the price of a very complex conceptual unfolding, structure has no message to communicate to us other than that we must die: "This gigantic effort has therefore met its vain limits: it opens on NOTHING, which is the last ward, and not accidentally so, of this sumptuous 'finale.' "45 The polemic with philosophers, and with Sartre in particular, and the teasing and distant tone Lvi-Strauss sounded with respect to philosophy in general, should not, however, lead us to imagine that philosophy was absent in him. Lvi-Strauss never stopped thinking of structuralism not only as a scientific method or a new sensibility that occasionally finds echoes in literary, pictarial, and musical creation, but also as a philosophy of the end of history, henceforth foreclosed. According to Jean-Marie Domenach, Lvi-Strauss "contributes to the destruction by killing, with his knowledge, this cultural vivacity, life, and vigor. The murder- ous side of this philosophy is atrocious .... Rather than finishing with hope or a renaissance, he ends by what 1 had called a requiem or a de profundis. The only thing that remains is to let writing sink into entropy. "46 A sign of the degradation of the ideologies that inspired it, struc- turalism was the oudine of a totalizing ideology in the making, an ex- pression of synthetic thinking as well as its destruction in a vertiginous and deathly spiral. Twenty-eight Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism Lvi-Strauss, and numerous anthropologists after him, traveled all over the American continent using the structural grid in or der to bet- ter grasp the unconscious dimension of the social practices of native populations. Those who turned their sights toward Africa held the structural paradigm at a greater distance because it did not adequately describe societies that had been colonized. Not only did researchers need to work on populations larger th an those small Indian communi- ties that had escaped genocide, but the interweaving of beliefs and local cu st oms together with colonial institutions also led to phenom- ena of acculturation that made it rather difficult to reduce African so- cial organization to binary oppositions; geographically, the area to which the structural paradigm could be applied was therefore rather limited. But there were structuralist Africanist anthropologists, and at the risk of being quite reductive, we might imagine a binary opposi- tion between Lvi-Straussian Americanists and Africanist disciples of Georges Balandier. Georges Balandier: Africanism Georges Balandier trained a whole generation of ethnologists as Africanists. He had been trained in ethnology by Michel Leiris, who became his model, and belonged to the small circle of sociologists in- cluding Jean Duvignaud and Roger Bastide who met on the rue Vaneau at Georges Gurvitch's place. Balandier's conception of doing Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism 265 sociology in was informed by his militant anticolonialism and his work quite naturally addressed the political dimension of life. A victim of structuralism, Balandier paid quite dearly for his criricism of the dominant paradigm of the sixties. "1 paid for it at the Collge de France. Claude Lvi-Strauss did aIl he could to find candidates who were the equivalent of what 1 could propose."1 And yet, Balandier and Lvi-Strauss had been close friends for six or seven years, until Lvi-Strauss was elected to the Collge de France. Despite their different methodologies and fields, they had had com- mon activities. Both were involved, for ex ample, in the International Council for Social Sciences, affiliated with UNESCO after 1954, and of which Lvi-Strauss was secretary-general and Georges Balandier the head of a research office. Their falling out was apparently due to a bad pun that reached Lvi-Strauss and for which he was unforgiving. "Everything degenerated because of a trivial incident, a sort of gossipy story."2 What should not have been an definitive rupture took on the tone of a polemic as early as 1962 with a vigorous critique of Georges Balandier's inconsistency in the organization of his propositions. 3 The rift was never repaired; beyond the peripeteias and the ruffling of sen- sibilities, it symbolized two divergent points of view. Georges Balandier was, in fact, deeply marked by postwar existen- tialism. A member of the Resistance during the Second World War, he had been associated with Michel Leiris and the Muse de l'Homme, and Leiris had introduced him to Sartre's entourage at Les Temps modernes. Balandier was not involved, however, in the great postwar debates because he left to do anthropology in black Africa in 1946. In Dakar, he became the editor in chief of Prsence africaine and actively participated in decolonialization in Africa, during which he became "an active agent close to certain African leaders."4 What struck Balandier first when he went to Africa was poverty. He quickly looked to politics as a means of emancipation and came to believe that politics took precedence; he diverged from the structural- ists. Balandier participated in history in the making and saw Lopold Sdar Senghor, Skou Tour, Houphout-Boigny, and Nkrumah prac- tically on a daily basis. He discovered the figure of the other, of alter- ity, and of negritude as a culture that was different and was to be rec- ognized as such, but at the same time, he immediately felt that he was participating in a moment in history that was coming to a boil not only because of growing hostility to the colonial framework and the 266 Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism desire for political emancipation, but also because of the historical de- mand of these peoples aspiring to reestablish links with their own pre- colonial history. Africa was changing profoundly. Since the Bandung Conference on Asian and African nonaUiance, the continent was rising up and the confrontations were increasing even as populations were growing poorer and shantytowns were spreading. Parties and unions were emerging in a world that until then had been organized by clans. The society Georges Balandier was discovering was therefore the very op- posite of a society frozen in time: "1 can in no way accept the ide a that in these societies myth shapes everything and history is absent, in the name of a notion in which everything is a system of relations and codes, with a logic of possible permutations that enables the society to maintain an equilibrium."5 To the contrary, Balandier discovered the movement and productivity of chaos, the indissociability of synchrony and diachrony. "1 am learning that societies are not produced, they produce themselves; none escapes history even if history is made dif- ferently and even if there are multiple histories."6 Once he was back in France, Balandier joined the Sixth Section of the EPHE, where, in 1954, he set up a program on sociological studies in black Africa. He also became a member of the cabinet of the secre- tary of state, Henri Longchambon, in Mends-France's government, where he was responsible for the social sciences. In 1961, Jean Hyp- polite asked him to teach a seminar at the cole Normale Suprieure at the rue d'Ulm, which he did until 1966. "Everything was bathing in structuralism, which had borne many things along with it in its course."7 It was in this sanctuary of triumphant structuralism during the sixties that Balandier successfully attracted sorne geographers, historians, philosophers, and students of literature to anthropology, among them Jean-Nol Jeanneney, Rgis Debray, Emmanuel Terray, and Marc Aug. A whole generation that had protested against the Aigerian war was drawn to Georges Balandier, whose charisma was linked to his ability to fit his theoretical practice and the disturbances of history and to avoid the ivory tower isolation of a scientific laboratory. He gave his first class at the Sorbonne in the faU of 1962. "The African- ism about which 1 lectured didn't concede anything to the structuralist mode."8 ln 1967, he published Political Anthropology9 and his analy- sis looked beyond the classical vision of power as the simple manage- Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism 267 ment of repressive to include the imaginary and the symbolic. In this respect, his work in Africa was consonant with Marc Bloch's The Thaumaturge Kings, where the analysis focused on the trans- formed body of the king incarnating political power. Balandier em- phasized politics and history, which structura li sm had largely ignored. Indeed, having taken shape at a remove from things political, French structural anthropology had a particular blind spot for politics. Ba- landier therefore read the work of Anglo-Saxon Africanists starting in 1945: Meyer Fortes, John Middleton, Siegfried-Frederick Nadel, Michael-Garfield Smith, David Apter, J. Beattie. He adopted Edmund Leach's criticisms of applying the structuralist approach to the study of political systems. In his work on the political organization of the Kachin, Edmund Leach had noticed an oscillation between the aristocratic and democratic poles that required constant variation and fine-tuning of the sociopolitical structure. "The rigorous- ness of many structuralist analyses is superficial and deceptive,"lO be- cause they are based on unreal situations of equilibrium. Although Ba- landier's thinking diverged from Lvi-Strauss's, he nonetheless agreed with Lvi-Strauss's criticism of Western ethnocentrism and its tendency to define politics in such a limited way that it was reduced to little more than an apparatus of the state. As early as 1940, Meyer Fortes and Ed- ward Evans-Pritchard had established a dichotomy between stateless segmentary systems and state systems, the former among the Nuer of the Sudan, and the latter among the Tallensi of Ghana. Il But Balandier went even further in attacking a typology based solely on the princip le of coercion. Instead, he proposed a synthetic approach to politics that included social stratification and kinship laws. He rejected the structuralist postulate of isolating variables in order to study their inner logic, preferring a total approach mixing the real, the imaginary, and the symbolic in a dynamic equilibrium that was, by definition, unstable. This perspective accorded a place and an importance to such notions as open strategies, thereby giving its au- thors some latitude in their choices; it could include the relationship between kinship and power through the interplay of marriage al- liances conceived of as so many pieces of the political network. Balandier took issue with anthropology's assertion that politics began where kinship ended. Such an approach let historical problema- tizing into the picture: "Anthropology, political sociology, and history have been led to coalesce their efforts."12 It became possible to dia- 268 Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism logue with historians. This dialogue occurred in 1968, when a sion show called the Lundis de l'histoire presented Balandier's work and Balandier, along with Jacques Le Goff and Pierre Vidal-Naquet. Balandier's synthetic and diachronie approach in fact resembled the work of both of these medievalists, in which certain sources, like the epics, de scribe wars among pretenders to the crown as so many politi- cal issues. Balandier's definition of politics was therefore quite broad. "Politics as a means of ensuring the government of men must be dis- tinguished from politics as a strategie me ans that men use. We too often tend to mix up these two levels."13 The Heirs of Balandier and Lvi-Strauss It would be pointless to try to compare the respective impact and in- fluence of Lvi-Strauss and Balandier. Clearly, the structuralist vogue carried Lvi-Strauss to his glory and left Balandier in the shadows, relatively speaking. And yet, historie al injustice has to be rectified, for Balandier's influence was as important as it was on occasion mis- understood. Balandier launched quite a number of studies and careers and if Lvi-Strauss had his progeny, many of Balandier's, and particu- larly the Africanists among them, consider themselves to have a dou- ble paternity. Marc Aug, the current president of the EHESS, was one such ex- ample. In 1960, while preparing his agrgation in literature at the cole Normale Suprieure and unsure about the direction to take since he was attracted equally to philosophy and literature, he was going to both Lvi-Strauss's and Balandier's classes. He thought that ethnology might offer a middle road that could reconcile his taste for writing and his desire for a more speculative form of thinking. The op- portunity presented itself, thanks to Balandier, to enter the ORSTOM, and in 1965 Aug left for the Ivory Coast. "It was my friend Pierre Bonnaf who suggested that 1 go and see Balandier, who was very attentive, and seductive because of his unusual background. "14 Aug received his training as an Africanist in Balandier's seminar but he did not sense a significant opposition between Balandier's perspective and Lvi-Straussian structuralism. "It's true that in those years, a critique of Lvi-Strauss was taking shape in Balandier's seminars, but 1 was too much of a novice to attach any fundamental importance to it."15 ln the Ivory Coast, Marc Aug's sensibilities to colonialism and neocolonialism, which had profoundly affected the lagoon popula- Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism 269 tians of the Alladian, were sharpened. In this respect, was doser ta Balandier in cansidering history had a certain place in equa- tion, but his first object of study placed him more in Lvi-Strauss's camp since he was working on a monograph trying to recover the logic of kinship ties among the Alladian. His first concern, upon arriv- ing in Africa, was to look for kinship rules. This would have reminded even the most myopie that transformation sys- tems do indeed exist .... There are many variants, but they are ail based on the common models of reference for occupying space, in the modes of residing in that space, and in the way power is trans- mitted. The West has the most purely lineal societies without any central authority, and, at the other end of the spectrum, a sovereign ruled at the head of an autonomous political power; ail the inter- mediary systems can be found between the rwO. 16 But his thinking quickly evolved and he worked increasingly on power and on the ties between politics and religion, themes that were doser to Balandier's work, although he never questioned the contribution of structuralism. Dan Sperber, similarly, was trained by both Balandier and Lvi- Strauss and went from Balandier to Lvi-Strauss. A third-world mili- tant who translated one of the earliest of Nelson Mandela's texts in 1963, Sperber turned to anthropology as a complementary science that would help him better understand the cultural dimension of polit- ical problems in the third world. "1 was therefore first at Balandier's seminars at a time when the structuralists, or Lvi-Strauss, were no longer part of my thinking." 17 He finished his Licence in 1962, and then signed up with Balandier to do his troisime cycle. 18 Dan Sperber left for England in 1963 to work with Rodney Need- ham, who initiated him, in fact, to structuralism. "Needham, on the one hand, and the empirical atmosphere in England, on the other, gen- erated a very lively interest in structuralism." 19 Dan Sperber gave many presentations in Britain in which he defended and explained structura li sm. l remember a talk l gave in a college at Oxford in which l defended the structuralism of the moment when General de Gaulle had re- fused to let the English into the Common Market. One of the profes- sors said then, "Sperber does intellectually what de Gaulle did to us politically." At the time, l seemed to be defending something rather exotic and not altogether trusrworthy.20 270 Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism It was only upon his return to France in 1965 that Dan Sperber, who had joined the CNRS, started going to Lvi-Strauss's seminars on a regular basis. Today, he says that anthropology interested him at the time because of Lvi-Strauss, "not in the sense of simply being in agreement with him or sharing his convictions, but because thanks to him it was possible to raise general questions in a scientific way. "21 Africanism Resists Structuralism But many Africanists remained skeptical about structuralism. Claude Meillassoux, for example, had a very particular background that sug- gested once again how much the choice to be a professional anthro- pologist resulted from chance and opportunity more than any clear- eut university trajectory. Meillassoux was an untraditional Africanist whose training and activities were quite eccentric with respect to the profession of ethnology. After studying law and political science, he left for the University of Michigan's School of Business in 1948. Upon his return, he ran his family's textile business in Roubaix, in the north of France, but he found administration unsatisfying and left again for the United States, recruited by the commissariat la productivit. Back in France once again, he became the intermediary between American experts and French businesses. In the early fifties, Meillas- soux became a militant in the new, independent left and joined the CAGI (Centre d'Action de la Gauche Indpendante [Center for action by the independent left]), along with Claude Bourdet, Pierre Naville, and Daniel Gurin. He was looking for a job and Balandier needed someone to inventory the works by British functionalists on black Africa. "That was how 1 did my ethnology classes. 1 had an office on the Avenue Ina. 1 wrote my index cards and had endless discussions with Georges Balandier. "22 Having been trained, after having taken Balandier's courses, Meillassoux joined a research project in the Ivory Coast in 1956 where he was to be responsible for the economic aspect of things. ln the sixties, after a seminar on trade and markets in West Africa organized by the Institutional African Institute (lAI), Meillassoux organized an international colloquium to which he invited, among others, Emmanuel Terray, Michel Izard, and Marc Piot. The collo- quium was supposed to take place in the Ivory Coast but Terray was persona non grata there and Meillassoux, who did not want to give in to the government's orders, held it in Sierra Leone. After this, Michel Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism 27 l Izard suggested that Meillassoux give an unofficial seminar on Africa that would be called the Meillassoux seminar. By its very existence, it demonstrated that even theoretical splits could take second stage to more empirical considerations about ethnographic material collected through fieldwork. However, in keeping with Balandier's perspective, Meillassoux always remained very critical of structuralism as it tri- umphed in anthropology: "Primitive 60cieties were used for all pur- poses and structuralism used them as material to push its ideas on the way the mind structures the rest, whereas this is, in a word, the way computers think. Binary thinking is bureaucratic thinking. "23 ln Meillassoux's view, Lvi-Straussian structuralism worked by analogy. For want of being able to construct its own problematic, Lvi-Strauss used different sciences, one after the other, to support his theses, and his disciples were always tripping over these trying to keep up with their master's frenetic movement, which was always one step ahead of them. "1 went to Lvi-Strauss's courses at the Collge de France. He was a king who opened a door; the moment it seemed that the philosophers' stone had been found, he shut the do or again and took up another subject in the next seminar. Still, it was fascinating because he came up with intellectually stimulating comparisons and combinations. "24 Jean Duvignaud was also disappointed by the structuralist model in North Africa because it did not account for the complexity and changes in the kinship systems there: "My work in Chebika, in Tunisia, led me to take my distance from structuralism. "25 His work of four years was published in 1968.26 Bertucelli used it as the basis for a very beautiful film called Ramparts of ClayP Lvi-Strauss's review L'Homme criticized Duvignaud for having abandoned kinship struc- tures, but it was not for not having tried to apply the analytic categories that Lvi-Strauss had developed. Duvignaud had not been able to apply them successfuUy. Close to the group of Gurvitchian sociologists and to Balandier, he was also very critical of the ambitions of the structuralist paradigm, which he considered to be a renewal of the Comtian posi- tivist legacy, which culminated "in a sort of ontology of the visible."28 The structuralist a priori met functionalism in its presupposition of a positivity of social coherence and through its holistic view of the social realm: "It is not at aU clear that contestations, deviations, forms of sub- version, revoIt, eccentricities, atypicality, and figures of anomie can be integrated into the whole and are in the service of the whole. "29 272 Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism ln the center of Chebika, Jean Duvignaud discovered a place that corresponded to no logic or rule, an empty zone where people wan- dered and waited; it challenged aIl reductionism and stymied the self- enclosed structural grid. The phenomenological perspective remained valid, according to Duvignaud, in its desire to define consciousness as the consciousness of something, recalling the hidden dimension of life behind formaI logic. Without refuting the validity of sorne points of the structuralist method, Duvignaud suggested that this epistemology should include that part of collective experience that resists any par- ticular determinism. Structura li sm Regains Africa There was, therefore, an implicit spatial division of labor. When Michel Izard joined the CNRS and the Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale 30 in 1963, he was more of an exception as an Africanist. Africanism was represented by Balandier on the one hand, and on the other by the sector of studies of systems of thought in black Africa established in the wake of Marcel Griaule by Germaine Dieterlin and taken up again by Michel Cartry. But structuralism's success was such that in 1968 the situation changed and Africanism managed to pene- trate Lvi-Strauss's Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, "which must be tied to the entrance of Tarditz, who was probably the first Africanist close to Lvi-Strauss."31 Including Africanists in the laboratory meant that Africa and structuralism were not incompatible, as a certain geopolitics of research might have suggested. The fact that today an Africanist, Franoise Hritier-Aug, heads the laboratory is quite sig- nificant in this respect. There are many homes in the African house, and for Jean Pouillon, who was also an Mricanist in the lineage of Lvi-Strauss, "Balandier's Africa is not at aIl the one 1 know."32 More- over, the fact that many Marxist Africanist anthropologists, among them Emmanuel Terray and Maurice Godelier, were interested in struc- turalism would increase this current's influence throughout the sixties. It is not at aIl clear that Africa defined the limits of structuralism, but it certainly suggested an analysis that was more attuned to politi- cal phenomena and to acknowledging social dynamics and history, perspectives that remained marginal if not repressed, in the structural- ist current. Twenty-nine Reviews One measure of the exceptional intellectual activity of the period was the vitality, number, and influence of the new reviews, which provided both a place for a special sociability and the perfect framework for valorizing the strength of the structuralist paradigm. These inter- disciplinary reviews could circumvent traditional institutions, and provide a forum for exchange from which concentric circles of influ- ence spread outward. A review's inherent structural flexibility, its capacity to respond quickly to the most recent theoretical debates and battles, as well as to reflect the conceptual progress in thinking about these problems, en- abled the various reviews to augment the structuralist successes well be- fore these made the daily or weekly press. Those that were to transform readers in the social sciences into crowds of enthusiastic structuralists addressed a public of disciplinary specialists, or touted themselves as the embodiment of interdisciplinarity, or finally, were linked with a par- ticular political ideology, which felt troubled by the structuralist phe- nomenon and invited a debate with its representatives. We have already mentioned the mst issue of Lacan's review, La Psychanalyse, which came out in 1956 and carried the famous Rome Report, a text by Heidegger, and an important article by mile Benveniste on the func- tion of language in Freud's understanding of the unconscious. The publication of philosophical and linguistic theses in a psycho- analytic review clearly indicated the intentions of the Socit Franaise 273 274 Reviews de Psychanalyse: "If dwells in language, it must be receptive ta dialogue. Psychoanalytic receptivity to the human sciences is a gesture that puts an end ta psychoanalysis's long-held position of extraterritoriality. "1 La Psychanalyse therefore had no in- tention of strictly limiting itself either to a well-established Freudian- ism or ta the internaI debates of the analytic corporation, but rather planned to present itself as an organ of structural modernity able to renovate Freudian thinking based on a dialogue with the other social sciences. We have also mentioned Lvi-Strauss's creation of L'Homme in 1961. Although L'Homme presented itself as a French anthropology journal, it sought a broader public than that of the professional milieu; its editorial board included Pierre Gourou, a geographer, and mile Benveniste, the most popular and respected linguist of the period. Langages Linguistics was the pilot science for the structuralist renewal of the sixties. Although only one review-Le Franais moderne-was founded between 1928 and 1958, during the decade from 1959 to 1969, no fewer than seven new linguistics reviews were created. They repre- sented the culmination of the energetic work and thinking in linguis- tics going on in a number of areas in the discipline. In 1966, the year of the structura li st consecration, Andr Mar- tinet created La Linguistique 2 and Larousse began its own linguistics review, Langages.3 The editorial board of Langages included sorne of the most illustrious names in modern linguistics and the team that worked on the review was drawn primarily from the meetings, semi- nars, and colloquiums in Besanon. Aigirdas Julien Greimas, a veri- table flag-bearer of structural thinking, conceived the project and proposed a thematic formula for the review whereby one or two spe- cialists in the are a being addressed would guest-edit each issue. Work sessions took place at his home and the project bore fruit thanks to Jean Dubois at Larousse. Martinet's review was aimed at professional linguists, but Lan- gages had other ambitions. From the outset, the structuralist method was supposed to reach the vast field of the social sciences, bring into contact, contrast, and unify the networks of research in the various disciplines. The first issue announced the very princip les of linguistics as a pilot science. "The study of language is fundamental for the hu- manities, for philosophers, psychoanalysts, and people in literature, Reviews 275 and this exigency calls for broad information-this study encompasses all signifying systems. "4 This very broad notion of an en- compassing semiological project indu ding linguistics as a subconti- nent corresponded exacdy to the program defined by Roland Barthes in 1964. Barthes was, in fact, the anonymous author of this opening of the first issue of the review. "It was really a very new type of 'lin- guistic' review .... It set linguistics in the broad cultural arena, an idea that had taken hold of Paris in 1966." 5 The project was ambitious and sound, it relied on groups that had been working for a number of years in this direction, and it was receptive to different areas of think- ing in their relationship with language-Nicolas Ruwet was working on music and language, Oswald Ducrot on logic, Henry Hcaen on medicine, Roland Barthes on literature, and Maurice Gross on artifi- cial intelligence. The mood was euphoric during the planning stages but the first issue led to a serious conflict because several schools were already dis- puting the paternity of modern thinking about language. Todorov was in charge of this inaugural issue bearing on "research in semantics," which gave considerable importance to Chomsky's theses. Greimas was so angered ("He [Todorov] produced an American issue")6 that he resigned from the editorial board. The rupture would not be over- come. Jean Dubois and Nicolas Ruwet would adopt increasingly Chomskyan positions; with Greimas gone, Barthes wanted to avoid getting involved in the dispute and, "as a result, sought one thing and one thing only, to escape."7 In the grips of a veritable implosion, the editorial board of Langages stopped meeting and it fell to Jean Dubois, who had sorne editorial power at Larousse, to continue. This episode notwithstanding, Dubois was able to begin a collection called "Langages at Larousse." At the high point of the structuralist vogue, it sold as many as five thousand copies, a sign of success that was aIl the more remarkable given the technical nature of linguistic discourse. Communications Communications was a major instrument for disseminating struc- turalist ideas. Born in 1961 at the Centre d'tudes et de Communica- tion de Masse (CECMAS) in the Sixth Section of the EPHE, which had been created in January 1960 at Georges Friedmann's initiative, Communications was a veritable symbiosis between sociology and semiology. The tide expressed the major concern of the moment: de ci- 276 Reviews phering the meaning of messages transmitted by the technology of in- formation dissemination: press, radio, television, advertising, aIl the media, whose importance was growing considerably at the time. It was thus a matter of investigating modernity in which "technical civi- lization and mass culture are organically linked .... The contents, the substance pass, but the form, the being, and consequently, the mean- ing of the thing remains."8 Georges Friedmann edited the review and the members of his edi- torial board had diverse relationships with structuralism. 9 Communi- cations published two programmatic issues-number 4 in I964 and number 8 in I966-prepared by a group around Roland Barthes. These were real syntheses of structuralist ambitions: number 4 in- cluded Barthes's "Les lments de smiologie," and number 8, in par- ticular, was devoted to the structural analysis of a rcit that came to be seen as a manifesto of the French structuralist school.lO Tel Quel Tel Quel was founded in I960, at Seuil, and quickly became the ex- pression of structuralism's syncretic ambition. ll It did not emanate from any particular discipline among the humanities and as such reflected the profound concern for synthesis during this period. Launched by writers and targeting an avant-garde intellectuai audi- ence, Tel Quel had been in the offing since I958. "Franois Wahl had said that it would be the Parnassus of Napolon III, this new Napolon III embodied by General de Gaulle inI958."12 On the cover of the first issue, Tel Quel took up a phrase by Nietz- sche: "1 want the world and 1 want it as it is [tel quel], and 1 still want it and want it forever."13 This liminary declaration denoted an essen- tially literary intention, placing poetry "at the mind's acme."14 The whole group had an essentially literary goal, but the word "science" set off the quote on the cover because the project sought to appropri- ate aIl avant-garde and modernist forms in the social sciences in order to advance a new kind of writing. During the sixties, structuralism embodied scientific modernity, whence a very encompassing subtitle: " Literature/Philosophy/Science/Politics. " But the goal remained liter- ary: "This periodic and contemporary political activity was always carried out in the name of literary creation, by writers."15 The objec- tive, therefore, was to influence literary creation and change the mode of writing by using the contributions of structuralism to support the Reviews 277 new Tel was interdisciplinary from the start, a place where discussion and exchange were given priority, where the only princip le was to reflect the avant-garde. The cornerstone of the project was rhetoric, a particular realm of knowledge made popular by structuralism. Tel Quel took as its adversary classicalliterary history of the nine- teenth and twentieth centuries: "To set ourselves apart from the reign- ing idea of literature in France in the postwar period, which was a lit- erature of psychologie al restoration." 16 In this sense, the inteIlectual communion was unambiguous between the structuralist paradigm, which attacked the notions of the conscious mind, the subject, a mas- tery of history, and Tel Quel, which had recourse to the social sciences in or der to destroy the idea of a harmonious and positivist literary his- tory. The review was a crossroads and at the same time a surprising and curious mix of Lacan-Althusser-Barthesianism, so much so that it was often considered to be the organ of an imaginary structuralist international; in the sixties, Marcelin Pleynet, as the review's director, was invited to write an article on structuralism by a medical journal. The privileged position enjoyed by the unconscious and by formaI structures was a time bomb that would eventuaIly explode psycholo- gism: "The best way to say that psychologism in literature was fin- ished was to be interested in psychoanalysis."17 The strength of Tel Quel was to remain inde pendent of aIl parties and institutions and to be without any particular disciplinary loyalty. The logic of the editorial board was to stay in the avant-garde, but in- sofar as the avant-garde always runs the risk of being recuperated, in- geste d, and digested by the system-"Run, comrade, the old world is behind you" -what resulted was a conception that was most often terrorist and that amounted to flattening the adversary (in general, the one that was closest at hand), and imagining that there was always a conspiracy brewing. Tel Quel gave free rein to a veritable terrorized terrorism, which Marcelin Pleynet summed up by saying, "It was al- ways a matter of avoiding being surrounded."18 And, curiously enough, even though it was born in 1960, Tel Quel had nothing to say about Aigeria until it became the hard core of one of the most pro-Chinese positions in France. The review's history is punctuated by extremely brutal ruptures, each of which resulted in the expulsion of valuable members of the editorial board. "In truth, the history of Tel Quel is not a history of 278 Reviews exclusions of the exclusion of individuals, which made it possible ta include much broader fields of investigation. "19 Sollers was respon- sible for the first overtures, thanks to his position in support of the New Novel, which led to Thibaudeau and Ricardou joining the board. The second overture was to include poetics, with the intro- duction of Denis Roche and Marcelin Pleynet, who became secretary in 1962, replacing Jean-Edern Hallier, whose break would come in 1971, at a time when Maoism was triumphant, as "the failure of an attempt from the right to take over the review. "20 During the period from 1962 to 1967, baptized a posteriori as the review's "formalist era," Tel Quel was strongly influenced by the rising wave of structuralism. 21 Barthes, who had formed a strong friendship with Philippe Sollers and Julia Kristeva, became closer to the editorial board and to the review, "which provoked a break be- tween people like Genette, Todorov, and me, on the one hand, and Tel Quel, on the other."22 For Barthes, the Tel Quel group was seductive; it incarnated modernity, and his friendship with Sollers and Kristeva was reinforced by their common publisher, Seuil, which published both Barthes and the review. It was under the "Tel Quel" imprint that Barthes's Critique et vrit came out in 1966, and at that point, Barthes remarked that "the review Tel Quel is a critical enterprise for me."23 Jacques Derrida was also close to the review, which he sup- ported and which published his texts. Lacanian discourse was very much in evidence in articles by Sollers and Kristeva, who were faithful auditors of Lacan's seminars. Althusser's influence was palpable in Tel Quel's rereading of Marx, particularly in the dialogue it undertook with the French Communist Party as of 1967, with La Nouvelle Critique. 50 were the pro-Chinese, pro-Cultural Revolution positions the review took, which hailed from an orthodox Althusserian perspective. Jean-Pierre Faye, who had joined the editorial board in 1963, left when its members became Maoists, and his departure was a crisis punctuated with insults. If the important breaks in the history of Tel Quel took place because of arguments about particular political positions, these remained sec- ondary ta a fundamentally literary goal. The Communist Thaw For the French Communist Party press, on the other hand, literature came after the application of the official party line. Not that this pre- Reviews 279 cluded the article by someone from the outside in order ta broaden the party's audience by attracting an intellectual readership. During these years of peaceful coexistence and of the beginning of de- Stalinization, Les Lettres franaises, the PCF literary weekly run by Louis Aragon and Pierre Daix, began to print articles of the avant- garde and of formalist thinking in order to break out of the socialist realist mold. "tes Lettres franaises and a certain avant-garde of the PCF were the tir st to make it possible for the literary avant-garde, the university, and structuralism to meet prior to 1968."24 Jean-Pierre Faye, for example, was a member of the Tel Quel group who regularly contributed to Les Lettres franaises, and he so successfully convinced the journal's board to take an interest in for- malism that he was asked to publish an interview with Roman Jakob- son. "1 became quite close friends with Jakobson. As soon as he came to Paris, he got in touch with me."25 La Nouvelle Critique was the second PCF review that was open to debate. Created in December 1948 as an organ for theoretical struggle to be waged after the creation of the Cominform, this weekly publica- tion for PCF intellectuals was the tool for a veritable normalization in the hands of its editorial director, Jean Kanapa. This was the Stalinist period, the period of the two sciences (bourgeois and proletarian), of Zhdanovism and of Lysenkoism. This kind of review would have ig- nored the structuralist challenge had it not been for the meeting in March 1966 of the central committee of Argenteuil, and then of the Eighteenth Congress of Levallois in January 1967. The result was a new position with respect to intellectuals. A "logic of receptivity replaced a politics of the besieged fortress."26 Thanks to the new formula of 1967, La Nouvelle Critique therefore enjoyed relative autonomy with respect to the PCF leadership, and it acted as a headhunter in the social sci- ences. This quest for new alliances especially led the PCF intellectuals to valorize a history informed by the social sciences, and, as a result, An- toine Casanova organized a collective discussion in the review. He pub- li shed a number of articles on this theme that were reprinted in a 1974 anthology entitled Aujourd'hui l'histoire. Here, alongside articles by Communist historians, were others by Andr Leroi-Gourhan, Jacques Le Goff, Jacques Bergue, Georges Duby, and Pierre Francastel. As of 1967, La Nouvelle Critique thus became a place of debate, receptivity to modernity, and therefore to an encounter with struc- turalism. Of course, this PCF review never adopted structuralist 280 Reviews theses, but it did discuss and comment on them. Even before the turning point, La Nouvelle Critique had opened its pages ta certain positions and fundamental debates. It was there that Althusser pub- lished his famous 1964 article "Freud et Lacan," in which he had opened Marxist thinking to psychoanalysis and to Lacanian think- ing.27 These pages had also held debates on the relationship between humanism and Marxism in 1965-66. After Maspero' publication of Althusser's new reading of Marx, the debates in La Nouvelle Critique corresponded to the need to "decide, first of aIl, on whether to assimi- late Marxism to a philosophical humanism, as Garaudy and Schaff asserted, or to assert its antihumanist and theoretical aspect, as Al- thusser maintained."28 In 1967, the new La Nouvelle Critique was invited by Tel Quel to join an enterprise of intellectuai modernization. The PCF review en- thusiastically accepted the offer, considering that its work was "of a high literary and scientific level," so much so that the Communists claimed that they were ready to learn from the Tel Quel writers, whose "work greatly merits our sympathy and can teach us quite a bit."29 This was a time of dialogue, but the PCF did not adopt aIl of the structura li st theses. In 1967, La Nouvelle Critique published four arti- cles attacking structuralism, without directly attacking Althusser, who was a member of the party.3 0 Pierre Vilar and Jeannette Colombel criti- cized Michel Foucault's The Order of Things for ignoring history; Georges Mounin criticized the broad and flabby dissemination of the linguistic model, and Lucien Sve argued for a scientific humanism against the Althusserian theoretical antihumanism. 31 La Nouvelle Cri- tique did not adopt the paradigm, but it it did help to disseminate and discuss it, and this strategy attracted a certain number of intellectuais such as Catherine Backs-Clment, Christine Buci-Glucksmann, and lisabeth Roudinesco to the PCF, which they perceived as a place where debate was possible. This turn in the relationship between the PCF and intellectuais was the result of a certain international thaw, but, as the party leadership saw it, it was also necessary because of the competition from the political and cultural activity of students, who would later reject it and establish their own theoretical development. The Maoist Pole The cole Normale Suprieure on the rue d'Ulm in Paris was a sanc- tuary of protest, and Louis Althusser was its figurehead. Sorne disci- Reviews 28I pIes of the caman of the philosophy agrgation began the marxistes-lninistes in late I965. Distributed by the Union of Com- muni st Students, the CML bore this remark by Lenin in an epigraph: "Marx's the ory is all-powerful because it is true." They were success- fuI: the first printing of a thousand copies immediately sold out. However issue 8 created a serious crisis. Robert Linhart, a hard-line Maoist, an Althusserian, and a philosopher who specialized in econ- orny, blocked it because he no longer recognized the review's mission of placing political struggle at the fore front when the issue was com- pletely devoted to the power of literature and included articles by Aragon, Jorge Luis Borges, and Witold Gombrowicz. Linhart accused Jacques-Alain Miller of "only looking for an academic career, a bour- geois position of authority. "32 The year 1966 at Ulm saw a double break: Jacques-Alain Miller and his group established an epistemologi- cal circle that would publish Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, and a second break would affect the Union of Communist Students in November 1966, when its "pro-Chinese" wing was dissolved and had to form its own organization, the Union of Young Marxist-Leninist Communists (UJCML). With issue 9-10 of the Cahiers marxistes-lninistes, Do- minique Lecourt became editor in chief, and references to Althusser became increasingly obvious. Issue II was entirely devoted to his work with, in particular, the publication of excerpts from Matria- lisme historique et matrialisme dialectique. As of issue I4, which was devoted to the Chine se Great Proletar- ian Cultural Revolution, the Cahiers marxistes-lninistes became the theoretical and political organ of the Young Communists Marxist- Leninist. The break with the PCF was consummated; the party was considered revisionist, according to the Chine se line. And yet Al- thusser, who remained a member of the PCF, nonetheless gave his blessing to his students by publishing an article in this issue on the Cultural Revolution, but without signing his name. Paradoxical as it might appear, given the distance between the respective positions of the exaltation of Maoist China on the one hand, and structuralism on the other, an entire generation of students was politically and theoreti- caUy fascinated by this symbiosis. The editor in chief of the Cahiers marxistes-lninistes, Dominique Lecourt, embodied this double commitment. He had been accepted at the ENS in 1965 as a HeUenist but had converted to philosophy. A militant against the war in Aigeria at the beginning of the sixties, 282 Reviews within the UNEF (National Union of French Students) Lecourt was seduced by Althusser's positions. In 1966, along with four others, he founded the UJCML. "There was something in the themes of the Cul- tural Revolution that echoed a certain number of Althusser's posi- tions." 33 Theoretical concerns were an essential vector of Dominique Lecourt's political combat; as early as 1967, he regularly went to Georges Canguilhem's seminar. Canguilhem "played an absolutely decisive role in my thinking."34 Lacan was at Ulm, and Lecourt did not miss the show even if the Maoist militants were "rather over- whelmed by the relatively irreconcilable atmosphere of our proletar- ian ideals." 35 These young ENS students wanted to find the same scientific rigor in their interpretation of Marx as Lvi-Strauss had found in the savage mind. But theoretical combat, like political combat, had to be on- going, and this was what a certain number of Althusserians, including Dominique Lecourt and Robert Linhart, found unacceptable in issue 8 of the Cahiers marxistes-lninistes. Jacques-Alain Miller, Franois Rgnault, and Jean-Claude Milner, who were in charge of the issue, appeared to be totally esoteric, and there was a split after awful ses- sions that probably lasted until three in the morning. We talked about the epistemological split and the Signifier. 1 remember espe- cially one big meeting where Robert Linhart was talking with Jean- Claude Milner about the Signifier and unsignified of the Signifier for hours in order to know how it was materialistic. These discussions had a certain appeal.3 6 Out of this break finally came the review by the young generation of Althusserians, Les Cahiers pour r analyse, which we might consider to be an Althussero-Lacanian review. It took a position of a combative structuralism as a totalizing philosophy, and its sources included Al- thusser, Lacan, Foucault, and Lvi-Strauss. The offspring of Althusser and Lacan were here. The editorial board included Alain Grosrichard, Jacques-Alain Miller, Jean-Claude Milner, and Franois Rgnault, all of whom were members of Lacan's psychoanalytic association, the cole Freudienne de Paris. From 1966 to 1969, Les Cahiers pour l'analyse was engaged in an epistemological investigation into the scientificity of psychoanalysis, linguistics, and logic in order to construct the science, conceived as a theory of discourse or philosophy of the concept. Georges Canguil- hem's remark opened the collective reflection on one of the issues: Reviews 283 To work on a concept is to vary the ways in which can be ex- tended, to understand and generalize it by incorporating certain exception al traits, to export it beyond its original context, to take it as a model or, converse!y, to seek a mode! for it-in short, to pro- gressive!y confer transformations upon it that are regulated by the function of a formY Les Cahiers pour l'analyse in the sacred ENS on the rue d'Ulm was the most symptomatic emanation of the structuralist fervor of the sixties, in its unbounded, ambitions in its most radical scientistic experiments, in its most elitist appearance as an avant-garde/popular dialectic that claimed to speak in the na me of the world proletariat, and which it used to legitimate the most terrorist and terrifying of the- oretical practices. Was it a caricature, a Ubuesque parody, or was this a serious en- ter prise that took the baton from the first structuralist period? Doubt- less both, and it was this unharmonious mixture that inspired an en- tire generation of philosophers. Thirty Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? In the sixties, the challenge of the social sciences was taken up by philosophers, who would reappropriate the structuralist program and thereby maintain their domination of the intellectual field, avoiding the marginalization experienced by the classical humanities. The cole Normale Suprieure was a sanctuary of intellectuallegitimacy and an essential institution, for through it and its goal of transmission, struc- turalism could circumvent and disdain the traditional universities (even if the ENS was in the process of losing its unique stature as the institution responsible for shaping future leaders of the nation to the cole Nationale d'Administration [ENA]). ENS students were part of a double structure, depending on whether they were at the rue d'Ulm or at the school in the suburb of Saint-Cloud. At Saint-Cloud they could take courses with Jean- Toussaint Desanti, who encouraged his students to convert to the new disciplines, counseling them to be trained in one of the social sciences even if it might mean eventually giving up philosophy. Conversely, Louis Althusser constructed a theory in which philosophy. played a central role, and he incited his students to test the validity of the dif- ferent social sciences on the basis of a philosophy of the concept. Al- thusser, like Desanti, included the structuralist paradigm in his strat- egy, but this meant speaking in the name of philosophy, whereas for Desanti it meant more of a reconversion. Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? 285 Saint-Cloud Jean-Toussaint Desanti has a place in the phenomenologicalline. An heir to Merleau-Ponty, who had him read Husserl as early as 1938, Desanti joined the PCF after the war. "It was the experience of politi- cal struggle that led me toward Marx and his successors."l He had en- tered the ENS on the rue d'Ulm in 1935, where he met Jean Cavaills, an important meeting for Desanti, who elected mathematics as a privi- leged philosophical object, and engaged essentially in work on episte- mology. He concluded that philosophy was not an autonomous and founding discourse, but a second discourse. "In order to do philoso- phy seriously, we have to get to the heart of positivities-these are Desanti's words."2 The confliet in the sixties between these two philosophers was latent. Althusser was increasingly committed to Marxism-Leninism, while Desanti was disengaging himself, having broken with the PCF in 1958. Nonetheless, Desanti had helped the agrgation students at Ulm, including Althusser, to take the examination, and had even had Althusser get his PCF card after he had passed it: "1 was the one who had him join the Party ... alas!"3 Desanti regretted having led Al- thusser into what he considered, as early as the end of the fifties, to be a dead end. He considered Althusser's work to be a true philosophical undertaking of complexifying Marxism, but that only had the effect of "slowing things down because this very elaborate enterprise of maintaining Marxism-Leninism is not at all adapted to the problems of our period. Who, aside from the Albanians, is a Leninist today?"4 Desanti combined structuralism and phenomenology in his search for mathematical idealities. He was not, however, trying to escape either the world or experience: "They are the form of an exigency that makes it possible for us to understand the productivity of this sort of object, ideal objects." 5 They are rooted in an are a that is sym- bolizable from the outset and belong neither to the intelligible nor to the material world, but lie somewhere between the two. In his re- search on mathematical objects, Desanti used the contribution made, since the mid-nineteenth century, by the baring of structures and, since the beginning of the twentieth century, the contributions of the Bourbaki group, which had made it possible to construct symboli- cally defined problematic objects. "It is a poor structure from which extremely powerful theorems can be obtained that enables us to mas- 286 Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? ter chains of properties among fields of objects that are differentiated from the outset."6 In this respect, Desanti was driven by a desire to lay bare the structure, form, and unity. His theoretical project of establishing sig- nificant connections using the principles of closure and the rules of transition is related to the structuralist project. However, he did not give up on meaning-giving acts or on his eidetic quest for an area where meaning is preconstituted and therefore to be reactivated. He basically remained a phenomenologist. The necessity of having to link conducts to the determination of a underlying structure once again poses the question of the subject. The subject is not abolished because if it signifies nothing, there is no structure. Where experience is missing, there is no structure. Struc- ture is that which shapes itself, is made and one wants to make, and this relationship must be understood. That is the problem we are facing today.? Sylvain Auroux, an epistemologist in linguistics and a disciple of Desanti, chose a path reflecting the relationship of his teacher's work to philosophy and science. In 1967, he was accepted into khgne, and took courses with Desanti, who initiated him into structuralism. "Structuralism was the anticulture and we bathed in it."8 He entered the ENS in Saint-Cloud, passed the agrgation, did his doctorate in philosophy, taught high school for a while, and then entered the CNRS in the sciences of language. In so doing, he fulfilled the advice that Desanti had given him to get involved in a specifie discipline, lin- guistics, and to become a research director at the CNRS and work with other linguists. "People like me always saw Althusser as an ideol- ogy maker .... He had managed this feat of giving a Platonic version of Marxism."9 Rather than constructing an epistemology outside of and critical of science, Desanti therefore encouraged epistemological work on sciences from within, which is what Sylvain Auroux later accom- plished. "As Desanti said at the time, to be a philosopher of mathe- maties is to place one self within mathematics. "10 Sylvain Auroux's conversion to linguistics did not indicate, however, that students at Saint-Cloud should abandon philosophy, particularly since Martial Guroult was giving a very strict history of philosophical texts there at the same time. Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? 287 Ulm At Ulm, Louis Althusser was the tutelary figure for the new genera- tion. He became an agrg in philosophy in 1948, was the philosophy caman responsible for preparing ENS students specifically for the agrgation examinations. Althusser, more th an Desanti, considered that philosophy had a role to play vis--vis the modern social sciences, as a the ory of theoretical practices able to evaluate the scientific val id- ity of different disciplines in order to test the truth. Philosophy, for Al- thusser, should main tain its traditional role as the que en of disciplines, even if its discourse should change and address new problems. During the sixties, Althusser and his disciples played a central role in dissemi- nating structuralism because they could me et the challenge of the so- cial sciences, which prided themselves on their rigor and as the bearers of a certain modernity, by shepherding them into the traditional mold of a totalizing philosophical discourse as the bearer of truth. Ulm therefore became the epicenter of a structuralist ideology, a very French symptom of the importance of the humanities in the uni- versity program. From this point of view, it was the ideal place for launching a counteroffensive against the aged Sorbonne. The very ex- pression of excellence, the ENS incarnated the double advantage of traditional scholarly legitimacy and the most advanced modernism. "1 remember quite clearly that university philosophy inspired tremen- dous weariness; it was a mixture of humanism and spiritualism," re- calls Jacques Bouveresse, who had been a student at Ulm. 11 The ap- pearance of what was called, at the time, the "good" social sciences came as a breath of fresh air, a real intellectualliberation. The remedy was not, however, to appropriate all the social sciences: there were the good ones (psychoanalysis, anthropology, and linguistics, the trio comprising the structuralist paradigm) and the bad ones (the tradi- tional social sciences of psychology and sociology, the empirical sci- ences of basic classification), which were looked down upon with the greatest disdain. The philosophers tried a takeover in the se three innovative sci- ences. "The scientists who were involved accepted this, as is often the case, because philosophy, even if it is disdained, has the advantage of being able to conquer a broader public than the one scientists can ever hope to reach." 12 By renewing its problematic, philosophy could thus socialize the social sciences, which had the advantage of using a read- 288 Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? able, rigorous, and formalizable discourse. The operation was so suc- cessful that philosophers refrained from carrying it out in the name of philosophy, which many at the time considered dead; instead, they substituted the word theory, as, for example, in the imprint by that name inaugurated at Maspero, and whose director was none other than Louis Althusser. It was not a matter of becoming an anthropologist, a linguist, or a psychoanalyst, however, but of using the rigor of these disciplines to demonstrate their scientism in the name of a theory that was superior to these specific theoretical practices. This was an effort at internaI sub- version as much as of appropriation undertaken in favor of philoso- phers. Such an operation required a certain stealth, and that, according to Jacques Bouveresse, imposed a heavy price: "It was a time when one had the impression that agame was being played without any rules. You could say anything, without any rule for argumentation once a certain number of dogmatic presuppositions were accepted."13 MarxatUlm The first innovation made by the caman at Ulm was to enshrine Marx among the holy of holies by including his works in the ENS, the insti- tutional bastion for training the nation's prestigious elite. In I960, Althusser published Feuerbach's Philosophical Manifestos,14 and in I96I he began giving his seminar on the "young Marx," in response to student demand. "The book on Montesquieu came out in I959, and his first texts on overdetermination and on the young Marx came out in I960. We asked him to give a seminar on the young Marx at the ENS."15 Students at Althusser's seminar included Pierre Macherey, Roger Establet, Michel Pcheux, Franois Rgnault, tienne Balibar, Christ- ian Baudelot, Rgis Debray, Yves Duroux, and Jacques Rancire. For them, reading Marx like Aristotle or Plato was completely surprising at the time, even if the literaI method of textual explanation continued to use well-known canons. If Althusser's disciplines expressed their enthusiasm about this "overwhelming originality,"16 they also had po- litical reasons to fight Garaudy since they had broken with the PCF leadership. This political dimension was fundamental for a generation that protested against the war in Aigeria, and their feeling of commu- nion was cemented by the intense sociability that prevailed among the boarders at the ENS. "It was a militant community. When Althusser Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? 289 published his 6rst articles on the young Marx, we said to ourselves, "Here is a rigorous Marxist we can respect. "17 Again emphasizing the intensity of the social life within the school, a common theoretical undertaking began to take shape while preparing the agrgation ex- amination. This was how "we decided that we would help one an- other for the agrgation." 18 Althusser spent 1962-63 lecturing on the origins of structuralist thinking: Lvi-Strauss, Montesquieu, and Foucault. Jacques-Alain Miller talked about the archaeology of knowledge in Descartes; Pierre Macherey addressed the origins of language. Jacques Rancire, tienne Balibar, Jean-Claude Milner, and Michel Tort also participated in this seminar. 19 ln 1964, Althusser changed his orientation and the seminar under- took a collective reading of Capital. "AlI that happened without ever giving a thought to the possibility of a publication. It was a free and disinterested activity. "20 And yet, this work, which was supposed to have been limited to a strictly confidential circle, was published by Maspero as Reading Capital and had remarkable repercussions. In 19 6 5, we were in an unbelievable situation; we had become famous overnight without having tried. . . . It was a time when the exam readers for the agrgation found our names quoted in the students' exam papers as if we were important contemporary philosophers. We were immediately famous, and remained so through 1968, and 1 can assure you that we paid for it dearly.21 This work and its publication quite obviously had major political implications beyond the university, particularly in the confrontations occurring inside the PCF where, since 1963, Althusserian positions had come un der sharp criticism from Garaudy. Ulm thus became a double instrument contesting the traditional university structure and the PCF leadership. Just as the linguists who were confronted with classical literary history had used structuralism, so here too it was used to prote st the leading authorities, whose imprecision was de- nounced in the name of scientific rigor. A symbiosis took hold of the different disciplines at Ulm, the temple of structuralist ideas. Michel Pcheux had acquired a solid linguistic background and many took Georges Canguilhem's courses and were therefore involved with epis- temology. Everyone was familiar with Lvi-Strauss's work. "1 had 290 Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? been interested in Lvi-Strauss somewhat in reaction to the norm im- posed by the Certificat de morale et sociologie. There was a counter- culture side to it."22 Althusser added a revisited Marx to this struc- turalist paradigm, and a return to Marx joined the ranks of the "returns to" Saussure and Freud. He had the excited feeling of finally being able to achieve a philosophical synthesis that could account for the different forms of contemporary rationality, beyond the social SCIences. In a confused way, Althusser was adopting the structuralist orien- tation while maintaining a critical distance in the name of Marxism. An internaI tension existed from the outset in the concepts that were advanced, making it possible to understand why Althusser later spoke about a "flirtation" with structuralism that had gone too far. At the time, it was a question of using the momentum, the propulsion, the scientistic side of a rather optimistic linguistic positivism that thought it could interpret aIl reaches of knowledge with a total semiology, starting from a simple phonological model. But Althusser and the AI- thusserians, in line with Nietzsche via Canguilhem, were at the same time critical of those who believed themselves able to create such a metalanguage. This ambivalent captation made it possible to coast along on the crest of a structuralist wave, using those themes that brought disciplines and viewpoints together, while at the same time deconstructing them from within. "The somewhat enormous opposi- tions like subjectlstructure or the notion of a subjectless trial took on such importance because they served to mask the conceptual ambigu- ity within which we were operating. "23 During these first years of working out their theory, the Althusser- ians leaned, however, toward scientism. The changes in political ori- entation that they hoped to see on the part of the PCF leadership were to be guided by science: "Science had to be placed in the driver's seat, as was said at the time."24 The ambient climate of scientism empha- sized further the enthusiasm of a whole generation that believed it was possible to synthesize modern rationality and philosophical prob- lematization, and that lived it as an emancipation. Jacques Rancire was a student at the ENS in 1960, and he was immediately seduced by "the intellectual dynamism that was generated around Althusser,"25 whereas until then, philosophy had been limited to Husserl and Hei- degger. When he got to the ENS, "the generation that was taking the agrgation were aH old-guard Heideggerians. "26 This was the last year Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? 291 during which Jean Beaufret, a disciple of Heidegger, was giving his course. The Althusserian new guard was receptive to new fields of knowledge, ta broadening philosophical culture sa that it took new objects into consideration, and to bringing about a radical break with everything that was based in any way on dassical psychology. "For my generation, this corresponded to a kind of liberation from univer- sity culture. "27 If structural linguists attacked literary history limited to the au- thor and the work, and anthropologists and psychoanalysts circum- vented models of consciousness, Althusserian philosophers also sought to joyfully bury humanism like the pitiful remnants of a bygone era of triumphant bourgeois thinking. Man was the object of a dismissal; he should surrender his arms and soul and submit ta the various logics that condition him and of which he is only a miserable speck. By virtue of its challenge of the validity and the very existence of the sub- ject, the Althusserian enterprise was utterly harmonious with the en- tire structura li st movement. Lacan Shores Up the Breach A powerful ally in this effort against huma ni sm and psychologism penetrated the sanctuary on the rue d'Ulm in 1963, at the invitation of Althusser: Jacques Lacan. Lacan too was at war, but his war was being waged within a different institution-psychoanalysis. Banned from the institution, he was also exduded from the psychoanalytic ap- paratus (the International Psychoanalytic Association). Lacan and Al- thusser were to become a team that was as curious as it was fascinat- ing for a generation that would become, in part, Althussero-Lacanian. Jacques-Alain Miller, the former director of the cole de la Cause Freudienne, daims to have read Lacan at Althusser's urging,28 when he was giving his seminar on the foundations of psychoanalysis in 1963-64, but which was essentially focused on Lacan. As we have seen, many Althusserians were to go from Marx to Freud and from Althusser to Lacan; Les Cahiers pour l'analyse was essentially the ex- pression of this Ulmian Lacanianism, which evolved from Althusseri- anism. The Althusserians were split among themselves; there were those who remained strictly loyal to their master and who would re- main in philosophy, such as tienne Balibar, Pierre Macherey, and Jacques Rancire, and there were those who converted to psycho- analysis, choosing to exercise a particular discipline in a practical way. 292 Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? Philosophy had once again lost a good part of its forces to a new, conquering social science. A whole Althussero-Lacanian current iden- tified with a position known as antirevisionist: at one and the same time opposed to the Soviet and PCF revis ion of Marx and to the revi- sion of Freud by the official heirs of the IPA. The symbiosis between these two currents was at once theoretical and strategie and led to a reliance on solid dogma and sacred texts. In the mid-sixties, the crowds of Chinese waving the little red book on Tiananmen Square would represent for them the hope for an end to the old world. Their leader Mao Tse-tung quickly became the harbinger of a new China, saluting the birth of a new world. Mao Tse-tung thought, Lacan thought, Althusser thought-all united aga in st ego thought. But by the end of the sixties, the Molotov cocktail was poised to welcome the radicalization of young French students. Thirty-one The Althusserian Explosion Neither God, nor Caesar, nor the tribune-yet Louis Althusser seemed to many to be the supreme savior of Marxism. His was a difficult undertaking, a veritable wager that amounted to setting Marxism at the center of contemporary rationality but disengaging it from praxis and from the Hegelian dialectic so as to get beyond the current Stalin- ist vulgate based on mechanistic economism. To carry out this shift, Althusser used structura li sm; he presented Marxism as the only form of thinking that could manage a global synthe sis of knowledge and set itself at the center of the structural paradigm. The price therefore im- plied getting on the structuralist bandwagon by setting aside experi- ence, its psychological dimension, models of consciousness, and the dialectic of alienation. Setting the referent on the sidelines took the form of an "epistemological break," resembling Bachelard's models of rupture. It differentiated the ideological on the one hand, from a sci- ence incarnated by historical materialism on the other. AlI the sciences were thus to be questioned on the basis of the foundations of scientific rationality and the philosophy of dialectical materialism in order to free them from their ideological setting. Based on the model of the ar- bitrariness of the sign with respect to the referent, science was to "sat- isfy purely internaI exigencies," 1 and the cri te ri on of truth was there- fore not to dep11d on a possible falsifiability of propositions. Untethering Marxism from its own historical destiny in the early sixties provided a means of saving it from rapid decomposition by 293 294 The Althusserian tX1JlOS:lOn placing it at center of science. It was one response ta need ta abandon an official, dogma-bound, post-Stalinist Marxism with an onerous past. Althusser made it possible to camplexify Marxism, to cross its adventure with that of social sciences that were in full swing, and to up the ante by presenting the theory of theoretical practices as the discourse of discourses. Louis Althusser offered the exciting chal- lenge to a militant generation that had cut its teeth in anticolonial combats of resuscitating a scientific Marxism freed of the scoria of the regimes that had ruled in the na me of Marxism. From Jesus to Marx Louis Althusser was born on October I6, I9I8, in Birmandreis, AIge- ria. In I939 he entered the ENS, and from I940 to I945 he was a pris- oner of war in Stalag XA in Schleswig-Holstein, where he corresponded with Ren Michaud, who initiated him into Marxism. He continued his preparation for the agrgation. after the Liberation; he was twenty- seven. Agrg in I948, he joined the French Communist Party at the same time, and decided to stay at the ENS on the rue d'Ulm, where he became the caman, the person responsible for helping to prepare stu- dents for the agrgation. At the same time, he began working on a thse d'tat with Jean Hippolyte and Vladimir Janklvitch, "The Poli- tics and Philosophy of Eighteenth-Century France." And yet, at the beginning, Althusser was a practicing Catholic, a member of Action Catholique, and confirmed in his religious convic- tions by his khgne teacher in Lyons from I937 to I939, Jean Guit- ton. According to Guitton, although Althusser had returned from the war transformed, he nonetheless remained fundamentally true to his des ire for a religious absolute, which he in fact displaced onto Marx- ism. The friendship between the two never waned, des pite the distance between their respective positions and Jean Guitton's experiences of contestation at the Sorbonne, where he held a chair in the history of philosophy: "You taught me to enter a relationship with an idea, with two, to combine them, oppose the m, unite them, dissociate them, to flip them like flapjacks, and to serve them up in an edible dish."2 From I945 to I948, Althusser had been attracted both to the PCF and to a small group of Catholics from Lyons founded by Maurice Montuclard and headquartered in Paris. Althusser's fascination with religion and mystical purity lasted until the drama of I980 when he asked his friend John Guitton to in- The Althusserian Explosion 295 tervene in his ta me et Jean-Paul II. Althusser \Vas granted a meeting with Cardinal Garrone, and Guitton, who had met the Holy Pather, was given ta understand that his request \Vas granted. How- ever, Althusser murdered his wife Hlne shortly thereafter and the project was aborted. A great reader of Pascal, Althusser was fiHed with the disquiet of a tragic mysticism and the unsolvable character of contradiction. Having abandoned Christianity, however, he displaced his que st for an absolute onto a purified Marxism, a crystaHine phi- losophy that could counterbalance religious faith and get beyond metaphysics by substituting a total, exclusive, and rigorous science for it. "In his bedroom, 1 saw the works of Lenin next ta those of Teresa of Avila. Regarding Althusser, 1 wondered about a problem that had always haunted me-the problem of change. Had Althusser changed in the secret and profound recesses of his being?"3 It was fashionable ta ontologize structure during the sixties, and it enabled Althusser ta shift the system of causality in use in the Marxist vulgate. Until then, explanations had been limited ta a simple mono- causal notion of reflection. Everything had ta derive from economics, and superstructures were therefore considered ta be simple transla- tions of the infrastructure. Breaking with this purely mechanical view offered the double advantage of complexifying the system by sub- stituting a structural causality for a simple relationship of cause and effect in which the structure determines what dominates. However, as Vincent Descombes explains, Althusser's analytic model also made it possible ta save the Soviet economic model, still considered consonant with the socialist model and dissociated from any objectionable and autonomous political and ideological reality. Althusser could there- fore make an even further-reaching critique of Stalinism than that of the official critique of the personality cult, but at a lesser cast because it saved the socialist base of the system in the name of the relative autonomy of the forces of production. Althusser quickly grasped the utility of structuralism for a Marxism in need of renewal and contin- ued ta regard the Soviet Union as a socialist country. "The structural- ist doctrine was almost worked out at the ENS under Althusser,"4 and it was represented by his disciples in Les Cahiers pour l'analyse. Until then, structura li sm had advanced within specific disciplines: anthropology for Lvi-Strauss, psychoanalysis for Lacan, linguistics for Greimas. With Althusser, it became possible ta broaden horizons ta include a structuralist philosophy that presented itself as such, and 296 The Althusserian Explosion as the expression of the end of philosophy, the possibility of reaching beyond philosophy in the name of theory. Moreover, Althusser's con- ception of a separation between science and ideology coincided with and quickened the rapidly genei"alizing division between the techno- structure and the workers. The Althusserians "gave significant com- fort to the split between the learned elite and the ordinary mortals, which, they implemented in their reviews and in their Maoist move- ment, which were hierarchized into groups with their relays and their grassroots committees: an organization that reflected that of French administration."5 The project therefore took its place as part of the project of unifying the thinking that was going on about the social sciences, under the vigilant supervision of the philosophers. "There really was ah attempt to construct a single problematic of the social sciences. "6 Strategie Planning There was also another-political-Iogic guiding Althusser's interven- tion in challenging the validity of the official PCF positions. As we have seen, between March I96S and February I966, La Nouvelle Cri- tique became the locus of an important debate between Communist intellectuals about the relationship between Marxism and humanism. An important confrontation took place between Roger a partisan of a Marxist humanism, and Althusser, who argued for a the- oretical antihumanism. "This controversy ... appeared to us very concretely to raise the essential question of the theoretical status of historical materialism."7 Jorge Semprun opened the argumenfagainst the Althusserian position by separating Marxist thinking, which is dialectical, from Althusserian thinking, which operates in terms of breaks. Using Marx's I843 Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Law, he showed that even the young Marx had never had an abstract notion of man, and that on the contrary, even as early as I843, he defined man as an entirely social being. Michel Simon insisted on the disso- ciability of Marxism and humanism, even if he agreed with the AI- thusserian criticism of the use of the notion of alienation outside of the vague realm of ideology. He was careful to distinguish clearly between the abstract and universalizing humanism of the rising bourgeoisie and Marxist positions, but "humanism designates some- thing that, in its deepest recesses, is essential for Marxism."8 Pierre Macherey defended the hard line of Althusser's positions and pro- The Althusserian Explosion 297 posed a position of rupture in place the discourse of that was being outlined by certain party ideologues: "There is a break between the approaches of Semprun and Althusser."9 He rejected any possible dialogue between two discourses that did not grant equal im- portance to the concepts being used. Using the same terminology was misleading because it addressed opposing ideas. The same was true for the term "praxis," which for Semprun referred to a real object, whereas for Althusser it referred to a theoretical object. Michel Verret also enthusiastically embraced Althusser's position: "Althusser em- phasizes in a remarkable way that this huma ni sm can only follow the theoretical destiny of alienation. "10 Roger Garaudy had been warning against Althusser's sabotage of the young Marx since 1963, but his arguments were strongly contested by many party intellectuals. But the philosophers' meeting that took place in January 1966 at Choisy, without Althusser, made it possible to consolidate the team of ideologues who were part of the leadership around Garaudy: Lucien Sve, Guy Besse, Gilbert Mury, Pierre Boc- cara, Jean Texier. Each, at different levels, expressed disagreement with Althusser's positions. On this occasion, Garaudy strenuously at- tacked Althusser's notion of science, which he characterized as "out- dated," "naive, scholastic, and mystical," as well as his "bloodless doctrinariness. "11 A Marxist heretic in the eyes of the Communist Party apparatus, Althusser was isolated, and his isolation makes it easier to understand his strategie interest in suturing his positions to those of the structural- ist wave, which had the enthusiastic support of intellectuals during the mid-sixties. Althusser offered the advantage of defending a "Cartesian Marxism made up of dear and distinct ideas,"12 which made intellec- tuaIs proud to be Communists. A return to Marx and to his funda- mental texts made possible by a purely theoretical and exegetical ap- proach helped to attenuate the guilt feelings of being a Communist after the incontrovertible evidence of Stalin's crimes. "Althusser's work really represented a breath of fresh air."13 The context was fa- vorable for Althusser's theses because the PCF had been trying to es- tablish a new relationship with intellectuals since the end of the fifties in order to abandon Stalinism bit by bit. Receptive to new forms of artistic expression and to the different avant-gardes, the party was breaking with socialist realism; in its openness to new theoretical exi- genes, it was casting off the Lysenkoist delirium of the pasto As earIy 298 The Althusserian LAl"V'lVU as I959, Maurice Thorez announced the creation of a Center for Marxist Research and Study (CERM), which Roger Garaudy was to head up. The PCF was looking for a way to compensate for the losses it suffered from the trauma of I956, by resuming the interrupted dia- logue with intellectuals. Althusser arrived at a propitious moment, the culmination of a process that had begun with the decade and that gave intellectuals a special place in defining the new post-Stalinist line. But his theses went unadopted by the PCF central committee that met in March I966 and that concluded, in fact, that "Marxism is the human- ism of our time."14 Once the Garaudy line had triumphed, Althusser's work was care- fully filtered by the party leadership and his texts disappeared from the shelves of the cole Centrale des Cadres. This defeat was largely offset, however, by the tremendous dissemination of his work from the very place where Althusser would once aga in resume his theoreti- cal efforts: the ENS on the rue d'Ulm. From Ulm, he could oppose the party leadership with a Marxist discourse fertilized by structuralism and worthy of the ranks of modern rationality. Michel Pcheux had been a disciple of Althusser in I965-66, and the philosophy professor of Roger-Pol Droit, who, along with Guy Lardreau, Christian Jambet, and many others, was stimulated by Althussero-Lacanism, which seemed to incarnate the philosophy of the concept. Today, Roger-Pol Droit looks back on his training and his early philosophical years as a period defined by grids: grids in the sense of a conceptual frame- work of elucidation. We had the feeling that if we could just find the right overlay we would see what was invisible without the grid. The structure depended on this: it belonged to what was apparent in what we did not see, in the rainbow diversity of reality. And at the same time, theses are grids in the cellular sense of the word. 15 The Althusserians had succeeded in ma king epistemology fash- ionable. It was a time when the epistemology of everything was being undertaken, such that one could say that it was no longer philosophy that was being done, but science. The situation was aIl the more para- doxical in that epistemology, by its hermetic discourse and the degree of expertise required in different fields, was generally limited to small circles: "1 even saw Derrida once answer a question put to him about whether what he was doing was science say no, it was not, but that it The Althusserian Explosion 299 could become that." 16 This was the scientistic context of Althusser's project, which also responded to the desires of a new generation that did not want to bear the burden of Stalinist crimes and hungered for an absolute. A11 of this made possible a paradoxical bringing together of an often mad political voluntarism-a desperate activism-and the notion of a subjectless process that resembled a mystical commitment: Just as for ail religious persons, the subject tears itself from itself in arder to become the agent of a process. l was raised by the Jesuits. It was clear that we were ripping ourselves from ourselves, and were no longer subjects before the great Subject that was the Process; this is how we saved our souls. It was completely feasible to reconcile these thingsY Althusser became a rallying point for an entire generation. For those who wanted to leave academicisms behind, he was a standard-bearer, an anchor: "1 was a student from I95 5 to I960 and Althusser brought us a kind of illumination. It was extraordinarily stimulating."18 The Return ta Marx Maspero published two books in I965 that were immediately and spectacularly successful and became the major references of the pe- riod: For Marx, a collection of articles by Althusser published in the "Thorie" collection, which sold thirty-two thousand copies; and Reading Capital, a collective work including, in addition to Al- thusser's pieces, contributions by Jacques Rancire, Pierre Macherey, tienne Balibar, and Roger Establet. Maspero had been created in I9 59, and we might wonder if Louis Althusser deliberately chose this house or if he came to it after having been rejected by the ditions So- ciales. According to Guy Besse, on the one han d, Althusser did not want to commit the whole of the party to his positions, which would have been the case had his book come out at the ditions Sociales, and, on the other hand, his concern for efficiency would have led him to choose Maspero because its distribution network enabled him to reach a much broader public than simply that of the PCE But it would seem that behind Althusser's attitude, which was at once daring and fearful, lay the party leadership's major roadblocks. "In I979, Al- . thusser told me that he had only published at Maspero after having been turned down elsewhere." 19 50 the Althusserians had achieved a "return to" Marx himself, a 300 The Althusserian Explosion Marx extracted from the commenta ries and from the exegeses that had been made of his work up to then and that had blocked any direct knowledge of his positions. The act of reading Marx was the first of the shifts the Althusserians accomplished, and in so doing they fully participated in the structural paradigm by favoring the discursive realm and the internaI logic of a self-enclosed system. Of course, AI- thusser's perspective was not linguistic, but he was part of this auton- omization of the discursive sphere that must be approached on the basis of a new theory of Reading, inaugurated by Marx himself, ig- nored by the vulgate, and reactivated by Althusser. This new practice of reading was baptized "symptomatic read- ing," using an adjective directly borrowed from psychoanalysis and from Lacan in particular, and which bespoke the more essential character of that which is invisible and refers to a lack or an absence. Althusser distinguished between two different modes in Marx's read- ing of classical political economists. First, he read the discours es of Ricardo, Smith, and so on, within his own categories of thinking in order to understand their lacunae and to establish their differences, thereby demonstrating what his predecessors had missed. This first reading allowed for "an inventory of possible agreements and differ- ences."20 But behind this was a more essential reading, beyond the ob- served inadequacies, lacunae, and silences. This second reading let Marx see where classical political economy had been blind even with its eyes open. He made patently clear those assertions his predecessors had left unproblematized and unquestioned. Marx thus made answers appear where questions had not even been asked, in a purely intra- textual play. "The not-seeing is then included within the seeing; it is a form of seeing, therefore, in a necessary relationship with seeing. "21 Just as an individual neurosis can be expressed by a certain number of symptoms without any obvious or direct correspondence to their cause, so too political economy could see or take into consideration what it does. There were two advantages to this kind of reading. On the one hand, it demonstrated a certain sensitivity to the need for linguistic rigor by seeking the key to the problem within the text itself, by prob- lematizing the text and its internallogic; and, on the other hand, it of- fered a method that, similar to Freudian analysis, considered that the most essential reality is the least obvious. Althusser's reading was situ- ated neither in the absence of the discourse nor in what it makes ex- The Althusserian Explosion 301 but in that gray area the latent manifest discourses, which anly a particular kind of Iistening or reading can bring ta light. If the error concerns seeing, sight depends on structural conditions, the conditions of discourse, the range of possibilities of what is said and what is unsaid. This shift borrowed as much from Michel Foucault as from Lacan: "Althusser did nothing more th an reemphasize the ideas of Foucault,and Lacan again."22 The model of making a dialectic of visible and invisible space carne from Foucault's Madness and Civilization, which Althusser invoked at the beginning of Reading Capital, not only with regard to the relationship of the interiority of shadows, darkness, and light, but also with respect to the attention paid to those apparently heterogeneous conditions that organize branches of knowledge into disciplinary units: "Terms that recall sorne very remarkable passages of Michel Foucault's preface to his Madness and Civilization. "23 The Epistemological Break Althusser also borrowed Bachelard's idea of an epistemological rup- ture, but he made it more radical by adopting the term "break" in order to emphasize its trenchant quality. He took his analytical model for reading Marx from scientific epistemology. Bachelard applied this notion notably to physics, and more precisely to quantum mechanics, to express the distance separating scientific knowledge and perceptual understanding. Althusser extended the idea, broadening it into a general concept that applied to the history of any of the sciences, making it clear that the discontinuities on which any particular scientific edifice was built needed to be discerned. In his concern to present Marx as the bearer of a new science, Althusser saw a radical split between a young Marx still mired in Hegelian idealism, and a mature, scientific Marx. Yet, "Bachelard never would have spoken about a split between a science and a prior philosophical construction."24 According to Althusser, Marx reached a scientific level at the point when he managed to rid himself of the ideological and philosophicallegacy with which he was imbued. Althusser even laid out the phases of the process and very precisely designated l 84 5 as the moment of the caesura that permitted Marx to bec orne scientific. Everything before l 84 5 is the work of the young Marx, a Marx before he was Marx. The young Marx is therefore marked by the Feuerbachian theses 302 The Althusserian Explosion of alienation, of generic man. This was the period of a rationalist, lib- eral, humanist Marx doser to Kant and to Fichte than to Hegel. "The first works suppose a Kantian-Fichtean kind of problematic,:'25 fr. tered around the figure of a man destined to his freedom and who must restore his lost essence in the thread of a history that alienates him. He must resolve the contradiction of his alienated rationality, in- carnated by astate that remains deaf to the demands of freedom. De- spite himself, this man realizes his essence through the alienated prod- ucts of his labor and he must complete this realization by once again taking possession of this alienated essence in order to become trans- parent to himself, a total man finally realized at the end of History. This reversaI came directiy out of Feuerbach: "The fundamentals of the philosophical problematic are Feuerbachian."26 According to Althusser, Marx rejected the notion of founding history and politics on an essence of man in I845, when he adopted a scientific theory of history based on entirely new explanatory con- cepts such as social formation, the forces of relation- ship,s onf4lIoduction, and so on. At that point, he elimlnated the philosophical categories of the subject, essence, and alienation and made a radical critique of humanism, which was considered to be part of the mystifying ideology of the ruling class. This was the ma- ture Marx of the period between I845 and I857, and his evolution made the great scientific work of his matur years possible, for Capi- tal is a veritable science of the modes of production, and therefore of human history. This fundamental break in Marx's work was perceptible thanks to the shift from praxis to epistemology. Thanks to Capital, Marx broke definitively with ideology and his work thus cam to make a sci- entific contribution the equal of Newton's Principia. "We know that a pure science exists only if it is ceaselessly refined .... This purification and this liberation are acquired only at the cost of a constant struggle against ideology itself. "27 Whereas until then Marx's work had been considered to be a return to the Hegelian dialectic from a materialist perspective, Althusser made a term-by-term comparison of Hegel's and Marx's dialectics; Marx did not simply stand Hegelian idealism back on its feet, he constructed a theory whose structure was in aH ways different, even if the terminology of the negation and the identity of opposites, and of getting beyond contradiction, suggested certain similarities in procedure. "It is absolutely impossible to maintain the The Alrhusserian Explosion 303 fiction of the reversaI, even in its apparent rigor. Because, in truth, even as Marx reversed them, he did not maintain the terms of the Hegelian model of society. "28 This discontinuity between Hegel and Marx let Althusser break with the Stalinist ecbnomist vulgate, which was satisfied with substitut- ing the economic sphere as an essence for Hegel's political-ideological essence. But this criticism of the mechanisms of Marxist thought was made in the name of the construction of a pure and decontextualized theory, which, as such, made it possible to achieve the status of a sci- ence. Dialectical materialism, for Althusser, was the theory that estab- lished the scientificity of historical materialism, and it had to be pre- served from the ideological contamination that constantly threatened it. "We see that it can no longer finally be a matter of reversaI. Because we do not get a science when we overthrow an ideology."29 Historical materialism was therefore the science of the scientificity of sciences. And a historian can only find perplexing this obvious sci- entism that runs through Althusser, even when he is, like Pierre Vilar, deeply committed to the construction of a Marxist history. "There is a progression in Marx's thinking that absolutely do es not occur around a break. 1 completely disagree with such an idea, which in fact belongs to Foucault's work. "30 Althusser certainly wanted to escape the Stalinist vulgate, which had a tendency to see everything as a reflection of economic relation- ships, by making a purified scientific field autonomous. In this regard, he produced a veritable renewal of Marxist thought. But by offering a system that was closed in on itself, Althusser precipitated the crisis. This sounded the death knell for a certain Marxism because, after coming full circle, things went around in circles. If Marxism is alive, it is not because it is satisfied with exhuming scientific concepts. This dimension contributed to a certain decline of Marxism, which, para- doxically, it had wanted to save. How can you construct a Marxism that is fundamentally a reflection on history with a profoundly ahis- torical method. 31 If Althusser finally sawed off the branch he was sitting on, he did nonetheless inspire a momentary second wind in Marxist thinking and comforted a whole current of modernist intellectuals in se arch of a radical break that was as much theoretical and institutional as it was poiiticai. 34 The Althusserian Explosion A Structured Totality Rather than the mechanistic vulgate of the theory of reflection, Al- thusser proposed a structured totality in which meaning was a function of the position of each of the e l e m e n T S ~ of the mode of production. He could therefore acknowledge the specifie efficacy of the superstructure, which was dominant in certain cases, and in aIl cases in a relationship of relative autonomy with respect to the infrastructure. By unhooking the superstructure from the ideological-political sphere, Althusser could save the socialist base of the Soviet Union because its relative autonomy "could explain quite simply, in the ory, that the socialist infrastructure could, for the most part, evolve without being harmed during this period of errors affecting the superstructure."32 As they said at the time, you don't throw out the baby with the bathwater, and although one could legitimately speak about Stalinist crimes and of a savage repression against the masses by those in power, it was not yet possible to talk about exploitation and the failure of a system that remained fundamentaIly and miraculously preserved at the level of its infrastructure, safe in the face of a bureaucratie degeneration affect- ing only the highest reaches of Soviet society. To Hegel's ideological- political totality, Althusser opposed the complex, structured totality of Marxism, which, depending on the historie al moment, was hier- archized differently in terms of the respective places of ideology and politics, for example, in the mode of production, even if economics was always determinant in the final analysis. With Althusser, structure became plural, transforming a single temporality into multiple temporalities. "There is no general history, but only specifie structures of historicity." 33 Thus there were unly dif- ferential temporalities, with each one autonomous in its relationship to the whole: "The specificity of each of these times and of each of these histories-in other words, their relative autonomy and indepen- dence-is based on a certain type of articulation within the whole."34 Althusser participated in the deconstruction of history, and in so doing he was part of the structural paradigm, not by denying historic- ity but by breaking it into heterogeneous units. To his way of think- ing, the structured whole was dehistoricized anq decontextualized in the same way that, in order to achieve the status of a science, that which is ideological had to be detached. Knowledge (Generality III) is only possible through the mediation of a body of concepts (Generali- The Althusserian Explosion 305 ties II) that work on an empirical prime matter 1). Snch an approach assimilated the object of analysis of Marxism ta the abjects of the physical and chemical sciences and implied a total decentering of the subject. "This meant mixing up experimental sciences with what are caUed the social sciences." 35 Structural Causality ln general, structuralism tried to avoid simple causal systems, and in this respect Althusser's work was consonant with structuralism. Leav- ing the the ory of reflection behind, he proposed to combine what was internaI to the structure of the mode of production. And yet he did not abandon the search for a causal system, which was indispensable for establishing the scientific character of his theory, but defined a new de- termination, which he caUed structural causality or metonymic causal- ity: "1 believe that when it is understood as the concept of the efficacy of an absent cause, this concept is admirably weU suited for designat- ing the absence as structure in the effects under consideration."36 This concept of the efficacy of an absence, a structure defined as the absent cause of its effects, reaching beyond each of its elements in the same way that the signifier goes beyond the signified, belonged ta the aspherical structure that defined the Subject for Lacan, con- structed on the basis of a lack, of the loss of the first Signifier. This dialectic around a void is found in Lacan and in Althusser, and the princip le of explanation, which is of course unfalsifiable, can accom- modate any kind of situation like an open sesame. Here, the purifica- tion of Marxism reached the highest degree of a metaphysics that "also makes sacrifices to a hidden God in the name of the struggle against theology."37 This structuralist philosophy, which endows itself with aU the appeal of scientificity in order to renew Marxism or Freudian thinking, also ontologized structure with idea of structural causality. It becomes a fact that "structures are deep causes and the observable phenomena of simple surface effects; ... these structures therefore have an ambiguous status."38 They are, in fact, occult enti- ties insufficiently substantial to act since, as structures, they are only pure relations; but, moreover, they are too solid to be structures in Lvi-Strauss's sense of the term, and thus make it possible to account for observable phenomena in terms of causalities. L ~ c a n is everywhere in Althusser's work and the strong current of Althussero-Lacanianism at the rue d'Ulm was based on a theoretical 306 The Althusserian matrix that made a symbiosis of the two possible: from the sympto- matic reading via the structural causality, which is absent from its ef- fects, to overdetermination, another fundamental conceptual tool that Althusser imported from psychoanalysis. "1 did not forge this con- cept. As 1 have indicated, 1 borrowed it from two existing disciplines: linguistics and psychoanalysis. "39 This notion was central, pro vi ding the Marxist contradiction with its specificity and making it possible to account for the structural total- ity, the transition from structure to another in a concrete social formation. Along with overdetermination, Althusser borrowed other Freudian concepts as weIl, such as condensation and transference, which make their way into Marxism. This intrusion let Althusser mul- tiply the contradiction, if not to dissolve it. It "corroded ... the com- fortable arrangements of the logos of contradiction. "40 Theoretical Antihumanism and Antihistoricism The appetite for Althusser's theses also corresponded to a moment in which the conception of the Subject was taking off from the theoreti- cal horizon. The structuralist program had already managed to re- duce, dethrone, and split the Subject, and generally make it insignifi- cant; with Althusser, Marx took his place alongside those who, on the basis of the social sciences, were carrying out and developing this de- centering of man in every way. "In a strict relationship ta theory, we can and should speak openly of Marx's theoretical antihumanism."41 The notion of man loses aIl meaning as it is reduced to little more than a philosophical myth, a contemporary ideological category of the ri se of the bourgeoisie. Reading Capital in a theoretical antihumanist per- spective would set in place essentially structural categories; these were Lacanian in Althusser and Lvi-Straussian for tienne Balibar. "In Reading Capital, 1 had somewhat imitated a certain number of models for constructing concepts that, although they wete not ta ken from Lvi-Strauss, made it possible to discover, surprisingly, a comparative method in Marx's texts. There are aspects of Marx that are structural- ist before structuralism. "42 Balibar in fact made an essential contribution in the collective an- thology Reading Capital, in which he studied the fundamental con- cepts of historical materialism. He elucidated Marx's theses on the basis of a theoretical apparatus in which the methodological presup- positions of Lvi-Straussian structuralism became readily apparent. The Althusserian L,X1JiU"UH 37 l'vlarxist notions were reconstructed from purely formaI determina- tions, as they are in the phonological model, and evolved according to a system of purely spatial pertinent differences that exduded material nature, the concrete substance of the objects in question. Just as for kinship structures, empirical descriptions of observable reality counted less th an defining the mode of production as "the differential determi- nation of forms, and defining a 'mode' as a system of forms that repre- sents a state of variation. "43 Setting the referent aside therefore lent an essentially formaI aspect to the approach, making it possible to daim a greater latitude for applying it to aIl possible cases. "This combina- tion-practically mathematical- ... will incite us to speak about a perfectly unexpected structuralism here. "44 In a pure interp!ay com- bining forms and pertinent differences, tienne Balibar did, never- theless, agree that economics played the fundamental role, that of determining the relationship of relationships, that of the structural causality. This theoretical elaboration made a science of the modes of production possible because it could achieve a high degree of abstrac- tion and generalization and at the same time make use of a system of pertinent causality. In such a science, the Subject shone by its im- pertinence; indeed, it is sim ply impossible to find, an exquisite corpse cast out with the ideological bathwater: "Men only appear in the the- ory as supports for the relationships implied in the structure, and the forms of their individuality only appear as the determined effects of the structure. "45 The structural paradigm lends sorne support to this decentering, which also daims a philosophical heritage in Spinoza and his definition of attributes, which function like pertinent characteris- tics within the mode of production in Marx. A subjectless process, therefore, according to the Althusserians, shapes the course of history. Not only the Subject, but aIl historicist notions of history went unrecognized for their potential perversion of the sought-after theo- retical scientificity: "The fall of science in history here is only the indi- cation of a theoretical faIl."46 Althusserian antihistoricism evolved over a number of stages, induding the de composition of temporalities and the construction of a totality articulated around pertinent rela- tionships within a general theory. But this totality in fact became im- mobilized without recognizing structure in the same way that Lvi- Strauss's cold societies were immobilized, without recognizing what was going on in their internaI contradictions or in the potential for 308 The Althusserian Explosion getting beyond them. By metonymy, the state of t r u ~ t u r e was substi- tuted for the cadaver of the subject, which had disappeared along with its historicity. Since this atrophied and frozen structure had to be at- tached to something, Althusser anchored it with the status he gave the notion of ideology, which served as a pivot much as the symbolic did for Lacan or Lvi-Strauss. Althusser used it as an invariant, atemporal category, like the Freudian unconscious, and therefore had free rein to complexify the kind of purely instrumental relationship used in the Marxist vulgate's view of the dominant ideology as a simple instru- ment of the ruling class. A Subject of Substitution: Ideology Althusser elevated ideology to the level of a relatively autonomous veritable function making it mechanically irreducible to what und er- _ lay it. But setting ideology at a distance also meant its hypertrophy as a transhistoric structure invoked in order to construct theory. By in- duction, then, the efflcacy of the ideologicalled to the creation of sub- jects absolutely subjected to the place to which they were assigned, like so many mystified objects of occult forces represented by a new subject of history: ideology. This was the period when everything was ideology: feelings, be- havior ... Nothing escaped the critique of ideology, which became a totalizing category within which an impotent individual operated. The only escape from what could have been a vicious circle in a closed sys- tem, the only way of getting out of this labyrinth, was, for Althusser, through the epistemological break, the sole thread that made the ad- vent of science possible. Marxism, as a theory of theoretical practices and as the ideologi- cal detergent in the name of science, allowed for an entire generation to reconcile its political commitment with a truly scientific exigency that, in its purity, resembled a metaphysical desire for an absolute. We can readily understand how such a thinking machin could attract those avidly in se arch of critical arms. Thirty-two Marxism's Second Wind This new Althusserian reading represented a youthful cure for Marx- ism and rid it of its tragic cast. Everyone used the mature Marx to turn him into the harbinger of the scientificity of his discipline, as the remarkable sales of the very theoretical For Marx attested. Moreover, the totalizing conception of Althusserian thought gave each discipline the feeling that it was an active participant in a common adventure. Marx became the intersection of aIl research, a veritable common de- nominator in the social sciences. In philosophy, Althusser received the exemplary and completely unexpected support of Alain Badiou, a brilliant philosopher who was close to Sartre, who thus once more lost one of his disciples, carried away by the structural wave. Badiou published an enthusiastic article on the (new) beginning of dialectical materialism in Critique. 1 "This article was very favorable and everyone was quite surprised by such a reversal."2 Alain Badiou was pleased with the harmony generated by the new Althusserian theses and by the political context. He discerned three types of Marxism: a fundamental Marxism based exclusively on the young Marx of the Manuscripts of I844, a totalitarian Marxism based on dialecticallaws, and, ta king Althusserian thinking as its real- ization, an analogical Marxism for which Capital is a privileged ob- ject and that "uses Marxist ideas in such a way as to undo their orga- nization. He in fact considered the relationship between the base and the superstructure ... as pure isomorphs."3 After the publication of 39 3IO Marxism's Second Wind his article, Badiou was invited by Althusser's work group to partici- pate in a philosophy course for scientists that was to be held at the ENS during the academic year 1967-68. Lecturing to an enormous crowd, Badiou presented his ideas of the mode!. This symbiotic synergy between political commitment, epistemo- logical reflection, and a new approach to Marxism carried beyond the Latin Quarter to most French university campuses. In Aix-en-Provence, Jolle Proust, who was about twerity at the time and working in epis- temology with Gilles Gaston-Granger, discovered For Marx with a passion and discussed its new theses in her work group. "We were completely convinced. We felt that we were discovering the theoretical possibilities linked to political positions and inseparable from struc- \ turalism that seemed to offer the key for interpreting a range of differ- ent fields. What was fascinating was that it worked in linguistics, so we aIl did sorne linguistics."4 Such a return to Marx's work and to the internaI construction of his texts cannot but recall the principles of Martial Guroult's method. For a whole generation of philosophers, this kind of reading meant the possibility of breaking with a form of teaching that tended to water down the specificity of philosophical problematization itself and to analyse purely doxographic influences. Althusserian structural Marx- ism laid the foundations for a new era in philosophy, but aIl the fields of knowledge experienced a serious jolt in 1965. Althusser's model, which made use of the structuralist vogue, became in its turn, the launching pad for other efforts to transform the human sciences. Althusserism in Linguistics Michel Pcheux, a friend and disciple of Althusser, thought that the best way to do philosophy in the sixties was to do it in the social sci- ences. In this regard, he was somewhat of an exception among the ENS disciplines. Appointed to a CNRS social psychology laboratory at the Sorbonne, under Pags, he belonged to a discipline that, at the time, had the reputation of being the worst of horrors in the eyes of Althusserians. As a student of Althusser and Canguilhem, he was something like the Trojan horse of psychologism. In 1966, Pcheux met Michel Simon and Paul Henry, two researchers from another social science laboratory in the Sixth Section of the EPHE, under the direction of Serge Moscovici. The three of'them together worked on a critique from within of the classical forms of the social sciences. "We Marxism's Second Wind 1 l had become sort an informaI te am and we worked together practi- cally aIl week long. " 5 Michel Simon had been a technician in the laboratory and later became a researcher, while Paul Henry, who had been trained as a , mathematician, was interested in ethnology. He had gone to see Lvi- Strauss in 1962, just after having fini shed his Licence in mathematics, to discuss his interest in taking up ethnology. Henry had found Lvi- Strauss appealing because of his use of mathematical models and his will to construct an encompassing communication theory. Lvi- Strauss advised Henry to do linguistics and to get a certificate in eth- nology. When Henry entered the social psychology laboratory, he, like Pcheux, had a critical perspective. He was surprised by the use of mathematics and the proliferation of equations without any concep- tuaI constructions, and his research projects were increasingly ori- ented toward linguistics, toward the structures of language and the notions of what is implicit or presupposed. These placed him at the heart of the structura li st problem. "We were interested in structural- ism because it was a way of critiquing social psychology, and particu- lady by the notion of the subject."6 Led by Pcheux, this little work group tried to apply Althusser's theses to linguistics. Many others worked on this as weIl, particulady at Nanterre: Rgine Robin, Denise Maldidier, Franoise Gadet, Clau- dine Normand. Michel Pcheux initially pub li shed two articles in Les Cahiers pour l'analyse under the pseudonym of Thomas Herbert, first in 1966 and aga in in 1968.7 This theoretical work was part of the dou- ble return to Marx that Althusser had undertaken and the return to Freud carried out by Lacan, and was to be used as a framework for the publication of a book that became a methodological manifesto. Pcheux's Automatic Discourse Analysis, published in 1969,8 served as a bridge to Althusser's thinking, making it accessible to linguists. Pcheux also argued for the notion of a break in the process of estab- lishing a science, and he took the example of technical practices that only later became scientific practices, such as stills or scales. Scales were long used for commercial transactions before Galileo used them as an object for the theory of physics. "This process is exactly what Pcheux called the 'methodical reproduction' of the object of a science."9 For Pcheux, this second stage was the true realization of science; he was convinced that the human sciences were merely ideologies and that philosophically based criticisms of them were useless. He hoped 3 I2 Marxism's Second Wind to transform them from within by providing truly scientific instru- ments adapted to their specifie field. However, the proximity between this ideology belonging to the social sciences and political practice in its ability to reproduce social relationships made it necessary to give priority to discourse, the specifie instrument of political power. This hidden tie between political practice and the social sciences needed to be examined. "Pcheux totally rejected any idea of a language reduced to an instrument for communicating meanings that exist or could be defined independently of it. "10 The orientation that Pcheux gave dis- course analysis took its place within the Althusserian notion of ideol- ogy, transformed into a veritable subject of discourse, a universal ele- ment of historical existence. His goal was to make the link between language and ideology explicit. He "placed himself between what we might call the subject of language and the subject of ideology,"l1 at - the core of the problem of a structuralized Marxism. Althusserian Thinking in Anthropology Alain Badiou's conversion to Althusserianism brought with it another. The anthropologist Emmanuel Terray had also been rather a Sartrean early on and a great admirer of Critique of Dialectic Reason. Later, Terray would transform anthropology from a Marxist-structuralist perspective. He had taken courses with Althusser at the ENS but had left Ulm in I96I, just before Althusser began teaching Marx. When Althusser's theses were published, Terray was in the Ivory Coast doing fieldwork, and it was his friend, Alain Badiou, who kept him current. "1 read For Marx and Reading Capital then with great interest and excitement."12 Althusser's article "Contradiction and Overdetermina- tion" in For Marx seemed the most fundamental to him because it made it possible to tear Marxism away from questions of origins and metaphysics in order to make it an instrument of scientific analysis. But what would influence Terray's anthropological perspective more than anything was tienne Balibar's article "The Fundamental Con- cepts of Historical Materialism," in Reading Capital. Terray later tested the validity of the concepts of mode of produc- tion, relation of production, forces of production, and their articula- tions while doing his fieldwork. "Reading this text, 1 wrote the second part of my book, Marxism and Prirrtitive Societies. 13 This was a rereading of Claude Meillassoux's work using the conceptual grid that tienne Balibar had proposed."14 Before pub1ishing his book, Terray Marxism's Second Wind 3 I3 sent the manuscript to Althusser, who not only considered it ta be per- - tinent but immediately understood how much it would affect the work being done in anthropology. From then on, Terray was included in the circle of Althusserians. An ethnologist and friend of Terray, Marc_Aug, was also work- ing in the Ivory Coast at the time, and he also joined the Althusserian vogue. "Althusser was enormously influential because he appeared to be a liberator, a model of nuance with respect to the Marxist vul- gate."15 ln his monograph on the Alladians, Aug had also tested the pertinence of the Althusserian model, but only in notes,16 although today he recognizes his discomfort in this exercise of ma king a theo- retical projection of a reality ill adapted to his reading grid at the time: "It did not correspond to what 1 was looking at empirically, which is to say, people who wondered about death, illness, and the beyond. "17 This manner of questioning was therefore quite eccentric with regard ta the instruments being used in Althusser's form of struc- tural Marxism, even if there was a real change in anthropological re- ceptivity ta an entirely new manner of thinking about social and eco- nomic fields. Althusserianism in Economics Althusserian thinking also made inroads in economics. Under AI- thusser's direct influence, Suzanne de Brunoff published Money in Marx,18 a book that was contemporaneous with Reading Capital. But it was especially Charles Bettelheim's work that was spectacularly influential at the tme. Bettelheim took Althusserian categories of contradiction between the relations and forces of production in order to demonstrate-and in this he distinguished his work from that of Althusser-the reestablishment of the capitalist mode of production in the Soviet Union. Using the invariant of the separation between pro- ducers and owners of the means of production-the basis of business organization in the Soviet economy-he deduced the domination of capitalism in social organization. Taking a structural Marxist perspec- tive, meaning became positional, defined by the polarity between the proletarian and the bureaucrat, who, like the capitalist, finds himself on the other side of the structure. Bettelheim's work was also interest- ing because it reduced the dominance the Marxist vulgate attributed to the forces of production and underscored, tu the contrary, the prin- cipal role played by social relationships in the very organization of 3I4 Marxism's Second Wind production. 19 Bettelheim and Balibar agreed on this point to consider the level of the productive forces also as a relation of production. Bet- telheim questioned the neutrality of the productive forces, a thesis that Robert Linhart later took up in his study on the inherent contractions in the development of Soviet socialism in Lenin, Peasants, and Taylor. 20 Linhart demonstrated the opposition between the construction of a socialist reality and the application that Lenin, as early as 1918, wanted to make of Taylor's model, which involved a clear division be- tween a technocratie leadership and the workers. This application of Taylorism overwhelmed the technical division of work at the same time as it tore the workers' own knowledge out of their hands in order to transfer it to a bureaucratized management. And yet, because the Althusserian theses were so intensely theo- . retical, it was impossible for them to make a decisive and immediate incursion into economic territory, although economists would be deeply jolted by Althusser's ideas after the shock wave of the May 1968 movement. Althusser Introduces Lacan It is also to Althusser's credit that psychoanalysis came to the fore of French intellectuallife, thanks to his 1964 article "Freud and Lacan," which came out at the same time that Lacan relocated his seminar to the ENS on the rue d'Ulm. 21 Althusser's position made it possible to open Marxism up to Freudian thinking and to put an end to the sepa- ration imposed by the Stalinist rejection of psychoanalysis. With Al- thusser, the return to Freud took the form of a recourse to Lacan, for both were engaged in a similar enterprise of epistemological elucida- tion and ideological critique and both were waging a war against hu- manism and psychologism in the name of science. This similarity was also apparent in their renewal of a particular kind of reading of the basic works of Marx and Freud. "The return to Freud was not a return ta the birth of Freud but to the mature Freud. "22 What Althusser appreciated in the Lacanian ap- proach was that Lacan saw a break in Freud's work that resembled the one he perceived in Marx's work: "Lacan's first words are to say that by virtue of his principles, Freud founded a science."23 But a sci- ence needs it own object; it cannot be constructed as a simple art of accommodating leftovers. After Freud's discoverr of this specifie ob- ject, the unconscious, Lacan, according to Althusser, taok a step for- Marxism's Second Wind I5 ward in constituting psychoanalysis as a science by considering that the transition from a biological to a social existence was to be in- scribed in the register of the Law of Order, which is to say, language. According to Althusser, Lacan's contribution lay in the priority he ac- corded the symbolic over the imaginary: "Lacan made clear this cru- cial point: the se two moments are governed, domina te d, and marked bya single Law, that of the symbolic. "24 Shifting the ego out of the center and subordinating it to an order eluding consciousness recalls Althusser's reading of Marx wherein history is a subjectless process. In this way, an Althussero-Lacanism could explode and make Marx and Freud the great thinking machine of the sixties. A renewed Marxism received its second wind, fanned even further by the aftermath of May 1968. Thirty-three I9 66 Annum mira bile (1): A Watershed Year for Structuralism Everything started falling apart as of 1966. A friend had talked to me about The Order of Things and 1 made the mistake of opening it .... 1 dropped Stendhal, Mandelstam, and Rimbaud, the way one fine day you stop smoking Gitanes, in order to read the authors that Foucault was discussing-Freud, Saussure, and Ricardo. 1 was in- fected. The fever did not stop and 1 loved this infection. 1 did not want to get better. 1 was proud of my knowledge, like a louse on the pope's head. 1 was talking about philosophy. 1 called myself a struc- turalist, but 1 was not going around shouting my head off since 1 was still uncertain; the slightest jolt would have shaken me. 1 spent my nights teaching myself the principles of linguistics and 1 was quite happy .... 1 was gorging myself on syntagms and morphemes .... If 1 happened to have any discussions with a humanist, 1 wiped him out with an epistemic blow. . . . 1 spoke the names Derrida or Propp in an emotional and almost ttembling voice, preferably during autumn evenings, like an old soldier caressing the flags he has wrested from his enemy .... Jakobson was my tropics and my equator, mile Ben- veniste my Guadeloupe, and the proairetic code my Club Med. 1 thought of Hjelmslev like a steppe .... It seems to me that 1 was not the only one to have gotten lost in these detours.! Twenty years later, Gilles Lapouge describes the real Saturday night fever of the sixties for a structuralism that had reached its zenith. AlI the energy of the social sciences converged at that point to irradiate the perspective of research and publication around the struc- turalist paradigm. The year 1966 was the "central reference point .... At least in Paris, we could say it was that year when lots of things got p6 A Watershed Year for Structuralism JI7 mixed together, and it was probably a decisive year for the most spe- cialized research areas."2 The year I966 can be consecrated as the structuralist year; if we can talk about the descendants of I848 or of I968, we have to include those descendants of I966, who were just as turbulent. "1 am a child of I966."3 Publishing in the Kingdom of Structure The activity in publishing houses in I966 gave a clear idea of the veri- table structuralist explosion going on everywhere that year and it, appeared to be a real seismic jolt. The number of major works was impressive: Roland Barthes published Critique et vrit at Seuil, his fa- mous reaction to Picard's attack, and about which Renaud Matignon wrote in L'Express: "This is the Dreyfus Affair of the world of letters. It too had a Picard, whose name was even written the same way, and his 'J'accuse' has just been published."4 For Matignon, Barthes's work holds a place in the history of critical thought equal to the one ac- corded the Declaration of the Rights of Man in social history. There was no real French civil war to decide whether Barthes or Picard was right, but the .intellectual world found itself very much divided that year along those lines. Greimas published his Structural Semantics at Larousse that year. "Thanks to D ~ b o i s , my semantics has become structural in big red let- ters. He told me, 'You will sell a thousand more copies if you add the word structuraL'" 5 Adding the adjective "structuralist" was a good sales pitch in the mid-sixties. Everyone was affecte d, including the "trainer of the French soccer team, who declared that he was going to reorganize the team according to structuralist principles."6 Franois Wahl, Roland Barthes's close friend and editor at Seuil, managed to persuade Lacan to publish his writings in an anthology: "The crits were published because of me, to tell you the truth. 1 found myself de facto in a central role, speaking purely in a topo- graphical sense."7 This enormous nine hundred-page volume, written in a baroque and hermetic style, consecrated Lacan as the "French Freud" in I966. When the reviews starting coming out, 5,000 copies had already been sold and Seuil quickly had to reprint the crits. They continue to sell well: 36,000 volumes had been sold by I984. In I970 the two-volume paperback was published and it broke all records for this kind of book, selling 94,000 copies of the fust volume and 65,000 copies of the second volume. 3I8 A Watershed Year for Structuralism Still at Seuil, in the Tel Quel collection, Tzvetan Todorov made the work of the Russian formalists known to a French public with his Theory of Literature, with a preface by Roman Jakobson. Grard Genette published Figures in the same collection. The real event of the year, however, was Michel Foucault's The arder of Things. Its success was unprecedented: the book was out of print within days. "Foucault is selling like hotcakes: 800 copies of The arder of Things in five days, during the last week of July (9,000 copies in all)."8 Published in April of 1966, The arder of Things sold 20,000 copies during that year al one; in 1987, it sold 103,000 copies. 9 Given the difficulty of the work, this was entirely exceptional. Thanks ta Foucault's work, Pierre Nora, who had just joined Gal- limard, began the Library of the Human Sciences collection in 1965: 1 was profoundly convinced that there was a movement taking place in what we called the sciences of man. Different disciplines were be- ginning to converge around a common set of problems based on the fact that when men speak they say things they are not necessarily re- sponsible for, and end up doing things they did not necessarily want to do, that forces they are not conscious of course through them and dominate them. . . . Moreover, a second movement was going through the research being done: this was a sociopolitical content, which gave this knowledge a potentially subversive value.1 At the same time and in the same collection, along with Michel Fou- cault Pierre Nora brought out lias Canetti's Mass and Power,11 and Genevive Calame-Griaule's Ethnology and Language. 12 mile Ben- veniste's General Linguistics also became the great reference work of the moment and brought its author out of his isolation at the Collge de France. Pierre Nora did not, however, want to limit himself ta being a simple spokesman for structuralism. He was taking Raymond Aron's seminar at the time and asked Aron ta prepare a book that would come out in 1967, The Stages of Sociological Thinking. 13 And yet, the fact that he was director of Gallimard's social sciences publications in 1966 made him, despite himself, structuralism's standard-bearer. He tried, unsuccessfully, ta draw Lvi-Strauss into his circle: "When 1 got ta Gallimard, 1 went ta see him ta try and bring him along. For rea- sons that are not important here, he did not want to come to Galli- mard."14 ln 1966, Payot decided to publish Georges Dumzil's An- cient Roman Religion,15 which was originally ta have come out at a A Watershed Year for Structuralism I9 German publishing house. Pierre Nora immediately understood how important it was to publish a work by Dumzil in the structuralist fever of the time and went to see him. "Pierre Nora intervened. He made me. 1 am a creation of Gallimard." 16 Even if certain houses, such as Seuil or Gallimard, appeared to be the spearheads of the structuralist publishing enterprise, others also participated in the explosion of 1966. ditions de Minuit published Pierre Bourdieu and Alain Darbel's Love of ArtY ditions Franois Maspero, which had stunned everyone in 1965 with Reading Capital and For Marx, published For a Theory of Literary Production 18 by Pierre Machery, an Althusserian. Presses Universitaires de France reprinted Georges Canguilhem's thesis, Normal and Pathological,19 which had initially come out in 1943. Nor were historians silent in this rising tide of structure. The Annales school also published a certain number of major works during this same year of 1996, includ- ing Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie's The Peasants of Languedoc,20 pub- lished at the cole Pratique des Hautes tudes (SEVPEN), and Pierre Goubert's Louis XIV and Twenty Million Frenchmen,21 published by Fayard. The master of the Annales school, Fernand Braudel, took ad- vantage of this infatuation with the long haul and structures to have Armand Colin republish his The Mediterranean and the Mediter- ranean World at the Time of Philip II.22 The year 1966 was one during which the apprentice structuralist reader had to read constantly. Every day brought another work to the harvest; a number of reprints came out that were also considered ab- solutely indispensable reading for a good structuralist. Gilles Gaston- Granger's FormaI Thinking and the Human Sciences 23 (Aubier, 1960) was an example. "When 1 got to the Sorbonne in 1965-66, 1 asked people two or three years older what 1 should read. Everyone told me that 1 had to read that book, which was being quoted everywhere."24 The same was true for Jean Rousset's Form and Meaning 25 (Corti, 1962), which was essential for an entire generation, and in which the author proposed to analyze the production of meaning within texts based on their internaI formaI structure. Reviews in the Kingdom of Structure The year 1966 was also one of intense structuralist activity in reviews. Hundreds were created. The first issue of Langages came out in March 1966 and presented the scientific study of language as an es- )20 A Watershed Year for Structuraism sential dimension of culture. This project focused on the interfacing of various disciplines interested in problems of language. Similarly, Les Cahiers pour l'analyse was published by the Cercle d'pistemologie de l'cole Normale Suprieure in early 1966, and the Note to the Reader, signed by Jacques-Alain Miller for the editorial board, clearly expressed its ambition to construct a theory of discourse for aIl the sciences of analysis: logic, linguistics, and psychoanalysis. The first issue focused on truth and included Lacan's famous text "La science et la vrit," which was reprinted in the crits published by SeuiL Issue 3 of Les Cahiers pour l'analyse came out in 1966, and in it Lacan clearly placed himself within the structuralist movement, in an answer he gave to philosophy students: "Psychoanalysis as a science will be structuralist to the point of acknowledging a rejection of the subject in science. "26 Analytic discourse should therefore be used to construct a the ory of science. Communications 8: An Ambitious Pro gram But the major review-event was issue 8 of Communications, devoted to the structural analysis of the rcit, which included articles by the semiology luminaries of the day: Roland Barthes, Aigirdas Julien Greimas, Claude Brmond, Umberto Eco, Jules Gritti, Violette Morin, Christian Metz, Tzvetan Todorov, and Grard Genette. Communica- tions 8 was not just a simple issue, it was a pro gram. Barthes wrote an introduction to the structural analysis of the rcit and designated linguistics as the founding model for "dechronologizing" and "relogi- fying" narrative within a structural .logic. Greimas located the struc- turalist enterprise at the intersection between semantics and a Lvi- Straussian analysis of myth. His contribution, written as an homage to Lvi-Strauss, was supposed to complement to the anthropologists work in its constitution of elements for a the ory of interpretation for mythic narrative: "The recent progress in mythological research, thanks especially to the work of Claude Lvi-Strauss, includes a con- siderable number of materials and elements of reflection that belong to semantic theory. "27 Greimas put himself on Lvi-Strauss's turf and addressed the Bororo myth of reference, which had been the basis for the first volume of Mythologiques, The Raw and the Cooked. But he shifted the perspective, and, rather than arguing that narrative was the unit y of the mythological universe, he considered that universe from A Watershed Year for Structuralism 32I the angle of narrative unit y in order to explain the descriptive proc- esses at work in it. This Hjelmslevian approach to the material that Lvi-Strauss had studied in order to understand immanent structures did not sit particu- lady well with Lvi-Strauss, who did not feel he needed a lesson in rigor, even when it was given by a semantician like Greimas. Shortly thereafter, Lvi-Strauss dismissed the team of semioticians headed by Greimas, which he was housing in his social anthropology laboratory at the Collge de France. He could not continue to keep a team under his roof that thought it did things better than he did by creating a syn- thesis between his own paradigmatic approach and Propp's syntag- matie analysis. "Greimas did not understand that the two things were completely different. "28 He paid a heavy price for his lack of under- standing. Lvi-Strauss's structures were not, in fact, narrative struc- tures. He did not study the linear, syntagmatie links of a myth whose constitutive elements of a -paradigmatic structure were picked here and there: "Mythic structure is something completely external to nar- rative form and is altogether of capital importance. "29 Vladimir Prpp's work on folktales provided the other important model of narrative analysis. Morphology of the Folktale appeared in Russian in I928 and became the great inspiration for the structuralist method, especially after it came out in France in I965 at Seuil. It was translated into English in I958 and had attracted Lvi-Strauss's atten- tion as eady as I960.30 Lvi-Strauss explained Propp's method in his article and was enthusiastic about what he called its prophetic quality, but critical of the distinction Propp drew between folktales and myth. For Lvi-Strauss, the folktale was the degraded, weakened version of the first myth, and the fact that it lent itself to the most diverse permu- tations made it less appropriate than the myth for structuralist analy- sis. But Lvi-Strauss especially criticized Propp's formalist vigor, and contrasted it with the structuralist method: "Formalism destroys the object. Propp ends up discovering that there is, in fact, only one folk- tale."31 Lvi-Strauss took issue with formalism because it ignored the complementarity between signifier and signified that Saussure had pointed out, and he essentially criticized Propp for his method, al- though he did acknowledge and emphasize the importance of Propp's work, which became one of the matrices of thinking in the context of literary semiology. Propp responded in the Preface to the Italian edition of his book, 322 A Watershed Year for Structuralism which came out in 1966. "Morphology of the Folktale and Theory and History of Folklore were two parts or two terms of an important work."32 In fact, Lvi-Strauss did not consider that the morphology of the folktale was presented as the prelude to a historical study that is its inevitable complement. This second work, published in the Soviet Union in 1946, was carefully ignored in France,33 Gallimard pub- lished it only in 1983, a clear sign of how, in the sixties, a historical approach was carefully overlooked. Claude Brmond had already based his study on the narrative message using Propp's method in issue 4 of Communications in 1964, and in 1966 he again used Propp's work to define the logic of possible narratives. 1 fust had Madame Jakobson's translation of Vladimir Propp and indeed found that it was very interesting insofar as it implied a shift in the mechanics of narrative and of characters toward functions. 50 1 began to think about this approach without ever considering that what 1 was doing fit into the structuralist project. There are narrative structures, of course, but they do not represent more than simple logical constraints or ways of creating the drama of the story. For me, you do not need to look for anything more.3 4 In his 1966 text, Claude Brmond sketched out a typology of elemen- tary narrative forms that corresponded to universal categories of human behavior, and from this he constructed a possible classification of narrative types around a basic referential structure that then under- goes a process whereby it is made more complicated or adapted to this or that spatial or temporal situation. Umberto Eco's piece clearly revealed one of the ambitions of structuralism to decipher everything rather than limiting the corpus of the great literary works to the usual canons. Eco chose Ian Fleming's popular 007 James Bond series. Casino Royale, the first volume in the series, which came out in 1953, served as the unvarying matrix for aIl the later books. Eco was interested in James Bond's sustained popular- ity, and instead of giving the general analysis and valorizing its ideo- logical aspects, he demonstrated that the series was, above aIl, rhetori- cal. Fleming's world is Manichaean because of its convenience in the art of persuading the reader. "Fleming is not reactionary because he uses a Russian or a Jew as a bad guy; he is reactionary because he uses formulas."35 Eco shifted the reactionary label generally attached to A Watershcd Year for Structuralism 323 Fleming in arder ta describe the fable, a genre in which inherent dog- matism leads to inevitably reactionary forms of formulaic thinking. For his part, Todorov used the work of the Russian formalists to create categories of literary narration within the framework of some- thing that was no longer a literary study, but a study of literariness, not a direct reading of works but of the possibilities of the literary dis- course that made the works possible. "This is how literary studies can become a science of literature."36 Grard Genette investigated the boundaries of narrative using Aristotelian and Platonic definitions of how these boundaries operate in the work of such contemporary writers as Philippe Sollers or Jean Thibaudeau who experimented with and proclaimed the end of repre- sentation, and announced perhaps the definitive end of the age of rep- resentation. Taken together, these contributions provided an immense scaffolding for literary research, which would be used to contextualize the dominant discourse of classicalliterary history with a vengeance, fueled by the apparent collectivity of the project and its promise of constructing a truly new science. Les Temps modernes When Sartre's Les Temps mOdernes devoted a special issue to struc- turalism, its sweeping success was consolidatedY Jean Pouillon wrote the Introduction, beginning with the incontrovertible fact that struc- turalism was in vogue: "Fashion is exasperating in that by criticizing one is also yielding to it."38 For Pouillon, the phenomenon expressed two important ideas: totality and interdependence, or the search for relations between different terms, not in spite of, but in light of, their differences. Structuralism was therefore a matter of "looking for the relations that give a positional value to the terms that they bring to- gether in an organized set."39 Marc Barbut wrote about the meaning of the term "structure" in mathematics, and recalled Lvi-Strauss's use of the analogy of a system of four classes in his analysis of the Kariera kinship system. Greimas contributedan analysis of the relationship between "structure and history" in order to emphasize that the Saussurean di- chotomy between diachrony and synchrony lacked pertinence, and he contrasted Hjelmslev's notion of structure as an achronic mechanism. He also responded to the criticism of structuralism's ahistoricism and recalled Fernand Braudel's three temporalities of structure, moment, 324 A Watershed Year for Structuralism and event to salute-without in any way agreeing with the use to which it was put-the beginning of a reflection on the problem as weil as historians' effort to integrate structure. "Such a view, unfortu- nately, does not stand up to dose examination .... First of all, we do not see how to sustain the argument according to which that which lasts longer is more essential than that which does not la st long. "40 According to Greimas, everything, for a structuralist, is located at the level of a metalinguistic model, and in this context, the historical di- mension is relegated to the role of "background."41 Maurice Godelier reiterated the pertinence of the link between Marx and structuralism. Marx "presages the modern structuralist current,"42 and he is therefore understood, thanks to Lvi-Strauss's work, as the true precursor of the structuralist paradigm because he made it possible to dissociate visible social relationships from their underlying logic. Not only did he prefer structural analysis to histori- cism, but he finally furthered the contradiction by locating it in "two structures that were irreducible to one another: the forces of produc- tion and relation of production. "43 Pierre Bourdieu laid out the bases of a sociology of intellectual thought and of artistic creation that, he argued, should encompass more than the traditional opposition be- tween internaI and external aesthetics by using a rigorous structural method: "The intellectual realm enjoys a relative autonomy, which justifies the methodological independence of the structural method when it considers this realm to be a system ordered by its own laws."44 Althia Althia published its special issue on structuralism in February 1966. It included an article by Maurice Godelier on contradiction, and an article by Lvi-Strauss on scientific criteria in the social sciences and the humanities. Kostas Axelos contributed an article on Lucien Sebag's attempt to reconcile Marxism and structuralism, and Georges Lapssade wrote a piece on Hegel. Roland Barthes presented struc- turalism as the possibility of "defetishizing the old-or concurrent- knowledge. "45 Esprit Esprit had devoted an issue in 1963 to Lvi-Strauss's thesis and in De- cember 1966, the review organized a conference whose proceedings A Watershed Year for Structuralism 325 were published in in a speciai issue on structuralism. 46 Esprit invited its readers ta ponder this rather complete panorama. Jean-Marie Domenach viewed the structura li st phenomenon as an en- terprise that destabilized the terms by which philosophy had operated until then, particularly in its view of consciousness. He raised the question of how the challenge of those on the left to the foundations of the established system can be reconciled with their political stuggle, for if men are moved by a system that cons trains them and cannot assure sorne autonomous consciousness, in the name of what can they continue to protest? The complexities and contradictions of the structuralist phenomenon explained its attraction. "Structuralism has two faces: one expresses the epistemological sufficiency of our period and the other expresses the anxiety of an absence, the tides of darkness. "47 But Esprit remained reticent and cri tic al of the notion of the death of man and his dissolution in the structures surrounding him. On the one hand, Mikel Dufrenne placed the neopositivism in vogue in a France that was belatedly dise ove ring Anglo-Saxon logical positivism, and interpreting it in its ciwn way, on the same plane as antihuman- ism. "Contemporary philosophy cries: hands off of man!"48 On the other hand, Paul Ricoeur recogaized that the structural triumph was costly; scientificity was accompanied by two major exclusions: the act of speaking-Saussure's elimination of speech in his study of lan- guage-and history. And without repeating the wanderings of either mentalism or psychologism, he suggested moving beyond this ampu- tation; thus, "reflecting on language would me an considering the unity of that which Saussure untethered, the unit y of language and of speech."49 Sartre Breaks His Silence Jean-Paul Sartre was mute in the face of this unbridled passion for structura lis m, alone in his silence as each successful publication weakened the bases of his existentialist philosophy a bit more. In 1966, Foucault, at the height of his glory, shelved Sartre along with nineteenth-century philosophers. This was too much for Sartre, who decided to break his silence and wage war, on the occasion of a special issue of L'Arc that was devoted to him. 50 Bernard Pingaud wrote the Introduction, in which he reviewed the radical changes that had taken place over the previous fifteen years, during which time philosophy 326 A Watershed Year for Structuralism had been supplanted by the social sciences: "We no longer speak about consciousness or the subject, but rather about rules, codes, and systems. We no longer say that man makes sense, but that meaning cornes to man. We are no longer existentialists, but structuralists." 51 Sartre responded to Pingaud's questions, and the polemical tone of his remarks reflected his anger as well as the difficulty of his position. On the great success of Michel Foucault's The Order of Things, Sartre re- marked that "the success of his book proves that people were expect- ing it. However, truly original thinking is never expected. Foucault brought what people needed: an eclectic synthesis in which Robbe- Grillet, structuralism, linguistics, Lacan, and Tel Quel are each used in turn to demonstrate the impossibility of historical thinking. But what was being targeted behind the attack on history, of course, was Marx- ism. The issue was the creation of a new ideology, the la st barrier that the bourgeoisie can still erect against Marx." 52 Following this somewhat reductionist assault, Sartre pondered his remarks, and clarified: he did not totally reject the structuralist method, so long as it remained mindful of its limits. If, for Sartre, the mind could not be reduced to language, it remained a fundamental part of his philosophy and corresponded to a constitutive part of the practico-inert. Even if Lvi-Strauss's work found grace in Sartre's eyes, he still answered the polemic against him that Lvi-Strauss opened in The Savage Mind, by considering that "structuralism as Lvi-Strauss conceives and practices it has significantly contributed to history's cur- rent fall from grace."53 For Sartre, Lacan fully belongs to structural- ism insofar as his decentering of the subject is linked to the same dis- crediting of history: "If there is no longer any praxis, there cannot be any subject. What do Lacan and the psychoanalysts who come after him tell us? That man does not think, he is thought, just as for certain linguists he is spoken."54 He nonetheless recognized Lacan's debt to Freud, for the status accorded the subject in Freud was already am- biguous, and the psychoanalytic cure in principle presupposed that patients let themselves be acted upon by abandoning themselves to free association. Althusser also came under attack for his ahistoricism because he privileged the concept of atemporality at the cost of his- toricity, without fully understanding "the permanent contradiction between the structure of the practico-inert and man, who turns out to be conditioned by it." 55 Finally, Sartre attributed this tremendous development and energy A Watershed Year for Structuralism 3 of social sciences ara und the structura li st paradigm ta an Ameri- ean import, an ideologieal adaptation of a technocratie civilization in which philosophy has no place: "You see what is happening in the United States: philosophy has been replaced by the social sciences."56 During the same year that President Johnson sent B-S2s to bomb North Vietnam on a daily basis, we can ap)feciate the extent to which Sartre's evaluation could be insulting to the structura li st musketeers. In fact, this affair created a scandaI because Sartre's viewpoint on the successive attacks on his philosophy since the early sixties was ardently solicited. Le Figaro littraire dramatized the gravit y of the situation, brandishing on its coyer: "Lacan Judges Sartre." Lacan an- swered ironically in an interview, and relativized Sartre's position: "1 don't consider myself at aIl with respect to him." 57 Lacan simply re- fused to credit any notion of a homogeneous structuralist group: "Who is going to believe that we are working together?"58 It was not an issue of plotting, of course, but of an intellectual debate, and Jean- Franois Revel, who had virulently criticized structuralist theses in his articles in L'Express, titled his report on the dossier on Sartre in L'Arc: "Sartre on the Ballot." He recalled "King Lear, repudiated and de- spoiled by his daughters,"59 and to the Sartrean analogy of the corre- spondence between the ri se of a technostructure and the success of an antihistorical and negative doctrine of the subject, he added the politi- cal parallel between a Gaullism in which the French citizen is spoken when his role is limited to listening to General de Gaulle incarnate the voice of France during his famous press conferences. Structuralism Crosses the Atlantic The year 1966 also saw a number of important colloquiums and sym- posia. The chteau at Cerisy remained a sanctuary for intellectual ac- tivity; in 1966 it was the site of a colloquium on the topic "Current Paths of Criticism." Plon published the proceedings two years later. 6o In September 1966, on the shores of Lake Leman in Geneva, a francophone philosophy congress was organized on language, and the discussions focused on presentations by mile Benveniste and Mirca Eliade. Others, beyond the confines of Europe, were also beginning to be touched by the fever of French structuralism. In October 1966, un der the auspices of the Humanities Center at Johns Hopkins Uni- versity, an important structuralist ceremony unfolded. This was the first structuralist crossing of the Atlantic to reach the New World. 328 A Watershed Year for Structuralism Americans, having quite correctly perceived the multidisciplinarity of the phenomenon of critical thinking in France, invited the representa- tives of the different sciences of man: 61 Lucien Goldmann and Georges Poulet in sociological literary criticism, Roland Barthes, Tzvetan Todorov, and Nicolas Ruwet in literary semiology, Jacques Derrida in philosophy for his work on Saussure and Lvi-Strauss, published in Critique at the end of 1965,62 Jean-Pierre Vernant for his historical anthropology of ancient Greece, and Jacques Lacan for his structural- ist rereading of Freud. The symposium was published several years later in the United States. 63 Roland Barthes was quite clearly singled out as one of the stars of the effervescence in French intellectuallife. He spoke about the repres- sion of rhetoric in the nineteenth century and how its replacement by positivism had long separated the paths of literary theory and the theory of language. Within this framework, he outlined the historical roots of the rise of interest in a reflection upon language and the new interfacing between literature and linguistics, which he called semio- critical, based on writing as a system of signs in a relationship of ob- jectivation. He recalled the new frontiers to be conquered in the ex- ploration of language using the modern symbiosis that structuralism had achieved between linguistics, psychoanalysis, and literature. Jean-Pierre Vernant addressed Greek tragedy by demonstrating that tragedy cannot be interpreted unless its context is understood, but not in the classical sense of the term: "What 1 calI context is not something that is outside the text, but that underlies the text. As we read and decipher the text itseH, we realize that its semantic fields force us to consider elements that are outside the tragedy and that give meaning to it."64 Vernant insisted on the necessity of starting with the internaI, hermetic structure of the text, but also on the need to bring to light aIl the verbal, semantic, and ideological play that makes the specifie effects of tragic discourse possible. Vernant met Lacan for the first time in Baltimore. It was a meeting that was not to be repeated, even if shortly thereafter, while Vernant was vacationing on Belle-Ile, he was surprised to see three Lacanian messengers arrive and explain that he absolutely had to attend the master's seminar. "They were explaining to me that 1 was doing the same thing as Lacan was doing without knowing it-which proved that 1 needed a good psychoanalysis. 1 told them that it was a little late, but they insisted that Lacan was very interested in my work and A Watershed Year for Structuralism ]2.9 that he it qui te attentively."65 who se discourse was ready difficult to understand in his native tongue, insisted on speaking English in Baltimore, despite the fact he did not speak it fluently, mak- ing his talk even more hermetic. Still, he appeared as the great guru of structuralism. Thirty-four 19 66 Annum mirabile (II): Foucault Sells like Hotcakes The publishing event of the year and the summer blockbuster was, without any doubt, Michel Foucault's The Order of Things. Sartre had said that the book was predictable, but neither Foucault nor Pierre Nora, his editor, had foreseen anything like what happened. The first printing of 3,500 copies, which had come out in April, quickly sold out, and 5,000 copies were reprinted in June, 3,000 in July, and 3,500 in September. Michel Foucault was borne along by the structuralist tide and his work came to embody the philos op hic al syn- thesis of the new thinking that had been developing for fifteen years. If the author later put sorne distance between himself and the structural- ist tag, which he considered insulting, in 1966 he considered himself to be at the heart of the phenomenon: "Structuralism is not a new method; it is the awakened and troubled consciousness of modern thought."l Pierre Dumayet invited Foucault to appear on an important tele- vision literary show of the period, Books for Everyone, where he spoke in the name of the founders of a collective rupture in which he, to- gether with Lvi-Strauss and Dumzil, considered that Sartre "still be- longed to the nineteenth century because his entire enterprise tries to make man adequate to his own meaning."2 Foucault's remarks em- phasized his consonance with the new ambitions of structura li sm. He claimed that philosophy had been dissipated in other activities of the mind: "We are coming to an age that is perhaps one of pure thinking, 33 Foucault Sells like Hotcakes 33 T of thinking in deed, and disciplines as abstract and general as linguis- tics or as fundamental as logic, or even more, literature since Joyce, are activities of the mind. They do not replace philosophy, but are the very unfolding of what philosophy was in the past."3 Foucault defined his archaeology of the social sciences (the book was originally to be subtitled An Archaeology of Structuralism) as the expression of the will to make our culture appear in a position of strangeness similar to the way we perceive the Nambikwara de- scribed by Lvi-Strauss. It was not at all a question of tracing the con- tinuous and logical lines along which thinking had unfolded, but rather of discerning the discontinuities that made our own cultural past appear as fundamentally other and foreign to us, thanks to this restored perspective. "This is the ethnological situation that 1 wanted ta reconstitute."4 Moreover, Foucault attacked any effort to identify with the purely ephemeral figure of man, a figure at once recent and destined to quickly disappear. God was dead, and man was destined to follow him, nudged along by the very sciences whose legitimacy is based on his existence: "Paradoxically, the development of the social sciences invites us to witness the disappearance of man rather than his apotheosis." 5 The epoch was clearly fascinated by the death of man, and many were ready to join the funeral procession. The successive negations of the subject in Saussurean linguistics in structural anthropology and Lacanian psychoanalysis found in Foucault someone who could re- install the figure at the very core of Western cultural history, but as an absence, a lack around which the epistemes unfold. The Foucault Effect Foucault's reception was a flamboyant event. Jean Lacroix saluted his work as "one of the most important of our time,"6 and Robert Kanters dubbed it "an impressive work" in Le Figaro'? Franois Chatelet, in La Quinzaine littraire, considered the book to be a philosophical event that revolutionized thinking. Reading Foucault's work would lead to the birth of "a radically new perception of the past of Western culture and a more lucid notion of the confusion of its present."8 In L'Express, Madeleine Chapsal evocatively entided her three-page article "The Greatest Revolution since Existentialism,"9 and Gilles Deleuze wrote a three-page review in Le Nouvel Observa- teur: "Foucault's idea: the sciences of man were not created when man 332 Foucault Sells like Hotcakes took himself as an object of representation, nor even when he discov- ered his own history-to the contrary, they were created when he de- historicized himself. "10 Foucault was of course very much in demand to explain this death of man that the press quite generously attributed to him alone. In answer to a question about when he stopped believing in meaning, asked during an interview given by La Quinzaine littraire, Foucault answered: "The breaking point came on the day when Lvi-Strauss for societies and Lacan for the unconscious showed us that meaning was probably only one sort of surface effect, a shimmering, a froth, and that what profoundly coursed through us, what existed before us, what maintained us in time and space, was the system."ll Raymond Bellour strongly supported Foucault's theses, whereas his party, the PCF, was clearly less enthusiastic. But Bellour enjoyed a certain auton- orny in Les Lettres franaises, where he interviewed Foucault. Bellour considered Foucault to be the initiator of a true revolution in the his- tory of ideas when he restored the logical totality of the ideas of a pe- riod and when he relegated to the dustbin of history what had been considered until then to be the bible in this field, the famous "Hazard" and his Crisis of European Consciousness. 12 Bellour quite lucidly dis- cerned the writer beneath the philosopher, and appreciated the daz- zling style: "This era will have seen the birth of a new kind of writer, under the guise of the decipherers of meaning."13 In aIl of his numerous interviews and lectures during I966, Fou- cault continued to shelve Sartre alongside nineteenth-century philoso- phers and to firmly place himself alongside Lvi-Strauss, Dumzil, Lacan, and Althusser-the writers and researchers who embodied the modernity of the twentieth century. Which fully justified Didier ri- bon's remark: "It seems clear that Foucault considers himself to be a full member of the structuralist galaxy,"14 even if it was a very special structuralism based not on the existence of structures, but a "struc- turalism without structures,"15 leading Franois Ewald to say that Foucault was never a structuralist and that his project was to combat the idea of structure and therefore of structuralism. For Ewald, Fou- cault's whole enterprise was to make politics possible, whence his hos- tility to the very ide a of structure: "Structure is one of the forms of the important historical subject, of the grand identity running through history, whereas Foucault quite clearly explained that that is what he wanted to destroy."16 This internaI tension, as yet unfelt by Foucault Foucault Sells like Hotcakes 333 in I966, arose his ambiguous position as a philosopher who placed himself at the center of the social sciences in order to subvert them from within. But, far from challenging the structuralist phenom- enon, his position was reinforced by structuralism, even if Foucault disagreed with the scientism that the others in the movement sought to legitimate their discipline. Transitory and Ephemeral Man Above aU, The Order of Things was an heir to Georges Canguilhem's work. Foucault also argued that scientific history should be based on discontinuities and on the Nietzschean deconstruction of established disciplines. His radical rejection of humanism bespoke the Nietz- sc he an base. Man, as an active, conscious subject of his history, dis- appeared. His recent return and discovery presaged his proximate end. His centra lit y in Western thinking was merely an illusion, dis si- pated by studying the many different kinds of conditioning that he un- derwent through history. Decentered, man becomes relegated to the periphery of things, un der the influence of many forces, such that he disappears in the froth of time: "Man is probably no more th an a kind of rift in the order of things .... It is comforting, however, and a source of profound relief, to think that man is only a recent invention, a figure not yet two centuries old, a new wrinkle in our knowledge." 17 Foucault undertook to historicize the manner in which the illusion known as man took shape, born only in the nineteenth century. For the Greeks, what existed were the gods, nature, and the cosmos; there was no room for a conception of a responsible subject. For Plato, the fault could be attributable to an error in judgment or to ignorance rather than to individual responsibility. Similarly, there was no room for man in the classical episteme. Neither Renaissance huma ni sm nor the rationalism of the classics could conceive of him-there had to be a rift in the configuration of knowledge for man to corne to have a central place there. Western cul- ture conferred a central role on man, who appears as the king of crea- tion, the absolute referent of aU things. This fetishization is particu- larly clear in philosophy, where the Cartesian ego introduced the subject as substance, the container of truths, reversing the ancient and medieval scholastic problematic of error and guilt. "Subordination is reversed, and it is error that becomes relative to fault: to make an error ... is to openly assert, by means of the free and infinite will, the 334 Foucault Sells like Hotcakes meaningful contents of understanding that remain confused."18 And yet, as Foucault, following Freud, commented, this man has experi- enced many serious narcissistic wounds in the history of Western thought. Copernicus, discovering that the earth was not at the center of the universe, revolutionized thinking and set back the primitive sovereignty of man. Later, Darwin, discovering the proximity between man and simian, reduced man to the phase of an episode in a biologi- cal time that he does not comprehend and that leaves him behind. Finally, Freud discovered that man cannot know himself alone, that he is not fully conscious, and that his behavior is determined by an un- conscious to which he has no access, yet which makes his words and actions comprehensible. Man therefore found himself progressively dispossessed of his at- tributes, but he reappropriated these breaks in the realm of knowledge in order to forge so many instruments with which to reassert his dom- ination. In the nineteenth century, he appeared as a starkly palpable, perceptible object, at the confluence of three forms of knowledge: Propp's philological apparatus, Smith and Ricardo's political econ- orny, and Lamarck and Cuvier's biology. The singular figure of a liv- ing, speaking, and laboring subject appeared at that point, the prod- uct of this triple knowledge and the holder of a central place among these new sciences, their necessary figure and common signifier. He could then be restored to his sovereignty over nature. Astronomy made physics possible, biology made medicine possible, the uncon- scious made psychoanalysis possible. But, for Foucault, this recent sovereignty was necessarily illusory and short-lived. On the heels of Freud, who had discovered the unconscious dimension of individual behavlor, and of Lvi-Strauss, who sought to explore the unconscious of collective social practices, Foucault set off in se arch of the uncon- scious of the sciences where we believe our conscious minds dwell. Such was the Copernican revolution he wanted to realize in order to demystify humanism, which for him was the important perversion of contemporary times: "Humanism is the Middle Ages of the modern era."19 Foucault saw the philosopher's main role as removing the epis- temological obstacle of the privilege granted to the cogito, or to the subject as consciousness and substance. He fully theorized the consti- tution of a true philosophical base bringing together the different semiotics oriented around the text and subjecting man to a network dissolving him despite himself: "Let us be done with this old phi- Foucault Sells like Hotcakes 33 losopheme of human nature, this abstract man."20 This was Fou- cault's perspective, and it corresponded with Lvi-Strauss's evocation of the fleeting figure of man: "The world began without man and it will end without him."21 Moreover, Foucault paid homage to Lvi- Strauss when, through ethnology, he made it possible to dilute man by successively undoing all his efforts at positivity. Ethnology and psychoanalysis ho Id privileged positions in our modern knowledge, Foucault remarked. "One may say of both of them what Lvi-Strauss said about ethnology: that they dissolve man."22 This obituary might appear paradoxical at a time when the social sciences were exploding, but Foucault conceived psychoanalysis and ethnology to be "countersciences,"23 and their valorization was con- sistent with the structuralist paradigm, which portrayed them as the main keys to modern understanding. In this respect, the structural revolution was "the guardian of man's absence. "24 Multiple and Discontinuous Temporalities Decentering or dissolving man created another temporal and historical relationship in which time became plural and immobile. External con- ditions that determine human practices were also observed differently. Will the history of man ever be more than a sort of modulation com- mon to changes in the of life (climate, soil fertility, meth- ods of agriculture, exploitation of wealth), to transformations in the economy (and, consequently, of -society and institutions) and ta the succession of forms and usages of language? But in that case, man is not himself historie al: since time cornes ta him from somewhere other than himself. 25 Man thus endures multiple temporalities that escape him, and in which he can be no more than a mere object of these pure external events. Consciousness became the dead horizon of the mind. The un- thought was not to be sought in the depths of the human mind; it was the Other for man, within him and outside of him, next to him, irre- ducible to him, fleeing "in an unavoidable duality."26 Man was articu- lated on the already-begun of life, of work, and of language, and thus he found to be closed the paths leading to what would be his origins and his beginning. Modernity, for Foucault, lay in this recognition of the impotent and inherently illusory theology of the man of the Cartesian cogito. Having removed the hero and cultural fetish from the pedestal upon 336 Foucault Sells like Hotcakes which our culture had placed him, Foucault took on historicism. Fou- cauldian history is no longer a description of evolution, a notion bor- rowed from biology, nor a tracing of progress, a moral-ethical notion, but rather an analysis of the many transformations at work, a tracing of discontinuities, like so many instant snapshots. This deconstruction resembled a Cubist enterprise, exploding history into a dehumanized constellation. Temporal unit y became little more than a fiction obey- ing no necessity. Indeed, reversing historical continuity was the neces- sary corollary to the decentered subject. "The human being no longer has any history: or rather, since he speaks, works, and lives, he finds himself interwoven in his own being with histories that are neither subordinate to him nor homogeneous with him .... the man who ap- pears at the beginning of the nineteenth century is 'dehistoricized."'27 Self-consciousness dissolved in the discourse-object and in the multi- pli city of different histories. Foucault proceeded to deconstruct history in the manner of Cu- bism, breaking it up into a dehumanized constellation. Temporal unit y was now nothing more than a fiction; it obeyed no necessity. History belonged to the sole register of the aleatory, to contingency, as it did for Lvi-Strauss, both unavoidable and meaningless. And yet, unlike Lvi-Straussian structuralism, Foucault did not elude historic- ity. He even considered it to be a privileged zone for analysis, the per- fect site for his archaeological investigation, but in order to point out the discontinuities vexing it, beginning with the important fractures juxtaposing coherent synchronie slices. Epistemes Foucault located two important discontinuities in the episteme of Western culture: that of the classical period in the mid-seventeenth century, and that of the nineteenth century, which inaugurated the modern era. Areas as diverse as language, political economy, and biol- ogy gave indices that, if correctly read, revealed these alterations in the order of knowledge. At every stage, Foucault separated what be- longed to the realm of the conceivable from what did not. "The his- tory of knowledge can be written only on the basis of what was con- temporaneous with it."28 The discontinuities that Foucault indicated, insofar as any form of evolutionism was eliminated, became so many enigmatic figures. These were true rents in the fabric, and it was enough to localize them and discern their modalities without asking Foucault Sells Iike Hotcakes 337 how they emerged. lndeed, how events came to occur remained fun- damentaHy enigmatic in Foucault's work. "Such a task implies the calling into question of everything that pertains ta time, everything that has formed within it, everything that resides within its mobile ele- ment, in such a way as to make visible that rent, devoid of chronology and history, from which time issued. "29 Discontinuity appeared in its specificity, irreducible to a system of causality because it was eut off from its roots, an ethereal figure that emerged from the morning fog of the creation of the world. Foucault's approach radically broke with any se arch for origins or for any system of causality. He substituted a polymorphism that made it impossible to restore a historie al dialectic. The Order of Things, his archaeology of the social sciences, sought to explain how this new configuration of knowledge emerged, based on a method that was the most structuralist form that Foucault's thinking took and that led from one episteme to another, from one discursive tissue to another in an unfolding in which words led to other words. The synchronie di- mension of this eminently structuralist approach of valorizing the au- tonomous discursive realm over the referent made it possible to locate the significant coherence between discourses that do not immediately appear to share anything except simultaneity. "He showed me the a u ~ dacity of the inteBectual comparison between biology, astronomy, and physics .... Contemporary sociology today does not have this expan- sive power." 30 Foucault's episteme, however, raised the most questions. Not only the unresolved question of understanding how to proceed from one episteme to another, but also the question put to Foucault himself: on the basis of which episteme does he speak? This idea, omnipresent in I966 in The Order of Things, was so contested that it disappeared from Foucault's later work. His archaeology sought the fault lines, the significant ruptures in the continental plates of knowledge: "What 1 am attempting to bring to light is the epistemological field, the epis- teme in which knowledge, envisaged apart from aB criteria having ref- erence to its rational value or to its objective forms, grounds its posi- tivity and therefore manifests a history." 31 The Representation of the Represented The first configuration of knowledge that Foucault addressed was the episteme of the Renaissance until the sixteenth century. Knowledge at 338 Foucault Sells like Hotcakes the time was based on the same, on repetition, on the representation of what is represented. The basis of knowledge in Western culture was similitude. The relationship of the idea to its object was doubled: "The universe was folded in on itself."32 Many procedures of simili- tude existed in this episteme: the proximity of site, simple reflection, analogy, and the interplay of sympathies-aH could assimilate very diverse things to a fundamental identity. The sixteenth century super- imposed semiology and hermeneutics in a form of knowledge that was complete, with unlimited similitude or reference to resemblance, but at the same time reduced because it was constructed as a simple addition: "Sixteenth-century knowledge condemned itself to never knowing anything but the same thing."33 Nature was merely a figure reflecting the cosmos; erudition and divination belonged to the same hermeneutc. This episteme would shift in the sixteenth century because of a rent affecting the old kinship between words and things, the site from whch man could be born to himself and become a particular object of knowledge. The change was figured by Don Quixote's que st, his attempt to read the world in order to demonstrate the truth of books. He pitted himself against the nonconcordance be- tween signs and reality, against the perfect discord that brought his utopia up short. Nonetheless, this tilter against windmills stubbornly persisted in his desire to decode the world through its dated grid, and his adventure became doubly significant as it unveiled the birth of a new configuration of knowledge and the historicity of language. Don Quixote's experience of words and things and the inadequacy of his form of knowledge could lead to madness in its indifference to dif- ferences: "Words wander off on their own, without content, without resemblance to fiH their emptiness; they are no longer the marks of things."34 With the new episteme of the classical seventeenth century and Cartesian rationalism, the analogical hierarchy gave way to critical analysis. Resemblances became comparative. "Western reason is en- tering the age of judgement."35 A general science, a theory of signs, became possible in the classical episteme by using a mathesis for sim- ple structures for which algebra was the universal method, and a sys- tem of classification for complex natures. A general grammar was born with this critical order: "The basic task of classical discourse is to give names to things, and with this name, to name their being."36 A Foucault Sells like Hotcakes 339 science of language arose out of this new distance between words and things. Similarly, natural history, inseparable from language, was barn. Divided into three classes-mineraI, vegetable, and animal- natural history did not yet cleave the living from the nonliving. The classical episteme was also characterized by the birth of the analysis of wealth, which resembled the analysis of natural history and general grammar. Whereas ec-onomic conceptions of the Renaissance made monetary signs correspond in quantity and weight of the metal elected as the standard of exchange, things changed during the seventeenth century. Exchange became the basis for the birth of mercantilism. Gold became precious because it was a form of money, and not the re- verse, as had been believed in the sixteenth century. Money took its value from its pure sign function. The Episteme of Modernity At the end of the eighteenth century and at the beginning of the nine- teenth, this episteme was once again shattered. Our modern episteme was born of the same disjunction that forced aH of Western thinking to shift. The new sciences that appeared in the nineteenth century con- structed their objects in a realm removed from observation. Life, work, and language became so many "transcendents." The analysis of wealth was supplanted by political economy. Adam Smith embodied the first important shift: what circula tes as things could be referred to work. "From Smith onward, the time of economics is no longer to be cyclical time of alternating impoverishment and wealth ... but the time of capital and production."37 Ricardo completed this advent of political economy by ensuring that, at the heart of economic thinking, work determined value, not as a sign but as a product. A similar revolution took place in natural history and made the birth of biology possible. Jussieu and Lamarck no longer defined char- acteristics on the basis of the observable but on an internai princip le of organization that determines function; this implied a transversal cut within the organism' to see the vital organs below the superficial organs. Biology became possible, and Cuvier used the discovery to as- sert the primacy of function over organ. In the realm of language, an epistemological revolution took place with the appearance of philology. No longer limited to its rep- resentational function, the word now belonged to a decisive gram- matical whole. "The language is then defined by the number of its 340 Foucault Sells like Hotcakes units and by aH the possible combinations can be established tween them in discourse; so that it is a question of an agglomeration of atoms." 38 The Era of Relativism The succession of epistemes up to our own era, this historicization of knowledge and of man-a figure that only became possible in the la st epistemological configuration-Ied to a historie al relativism for Fou- cault, similar to that of Lvi-Strauss. Just as there is no inferiority or anteriority between primitive and modern societies, there is no truth to be sought in the different stages that constitute knowlege. There are only historically distinguishable discourses: "Since the human being has become historical through and through, none of the contents ana- lyzed by the human sciences can remain stable in itself or escape the movement of History."39 The foundations of contemporary knowl- edge, represented by disciplines that are themselves structures used in verifiable scientific practices, are only temporary, transitory configura- tions. Paradoxically, this absolute relativism that completely histori- cizes knowledge is turned against the historical approach in favor of a fundamentally spatial conception, a purely synchronic epistemologi- cal space that must separate inside from out, but that turns its back on duration, and therefore on history. Foucault invited us to turn an eye on temporality that was as cold as the one the ethnologist turns on primitive societies. The misunder- standing with historians arose from the fact that Foucault took no re- ality or historical referent into consideration, but only considered the internaI modulations of the discursive realm. The level of discourse was the only one he saw in this nominalist approach, which cons id- ered the word to be something practically physical, like a thing, and replaced the thing. Discourse and documents were no longer to be considered documents, but monuments: "The text is a historical ob- ject like the trunk of a tree. "40 His approach led him to valorize the internaI coherence of successive epistemes and to ignore the processes of transformation and mediation. Diachrony and discontinuities re- mained, therefore, fundamentially enigmatic. The Order of Things was written during Foucault's most struc- turalist phase. This was the period when the sciences of sign systems tlourished and during which, behind the description of the succession of different epistemes since the classical period, he discerned the re- Foucault Sells like Hotcakes 34I pressed each these stages of Western culture, modes or order, their historical a prioris and hierarchies. Just as Lvi-Strauss perceived the unconscious of social practices in primitive societies, Foucault deciphered the unconscious foundations constituting West- ern knowledge, thereby prolonging the Kantian effort to "shake us out of our anthropological slumber. "41 In order to escape from this anthropological space and from fi- nite analysis at the empirical transcendentallevel, Foucault conferred a special status on three different disciplines at the end of his book. Psychoanalysis reconsidered and corrected by Lacan, ethnology, re- vised by Lvi-Strauss, and history, reconsidered and deconstructed by Nietzsche. The Order of Things closed, therefore, on the episteme of structuralism, which offered itself as the realization of modern consciousness. One noteworthy absence in this pro gram was entirely consonant with the structura li st moment: Marx was relegated to the episteme of the nineteenth century. At the deepest level of Western knowledge, Marxism introduced no real discontinuity; it found its place without difficulty, as a full, quite comfortable and, goodness knows, satisfying form for a time (its own), within an epistemological arrangement that welcomed it gladly (since it was this arrangement that was in fact making room for it) .... Marxism exists in nineteenth-century thought like a fish in water: that is, it is unable to breathe anywhere else. 42 There was an important break between the position of Foucault, who tried to diverge from the Marxist model as much as from the phenom- enological model, and that of the Althusserians, who were trying to give Marx a second wind. They wer clearly divided and their diver- gence was such that they provoked a major rupture in the history of science. Foucault had to justify his position because the Althusserian group of the ENS epistemological circle considered it a provocation. Later, he rectified things with The Archae%gy of Know/edge. "When he wrote The Order of Things, he was unaware of Althusser's reading of Marx, whereas in The Archae%gy of Know/edge he speaks of a Marx revisited by Althusser."43 Foucault's position in 1966 was wholly in line with the ambient structuralist theorizing. By speaking of the primacy of pure reason and of the representation of the struc- tures of experience articulated on the constitution of epistemological objects, he gave it a philosophical answer. 342 Foucault Sells like Hotcakes Thanks ta this, Foucault appeared as the potential spearhead aH the structuralists united in their battle aga in st the philosophy of meaning, against huma ni sm and phenomenology, by raising again the question of the relevance of philosophy, as Kant had done, and con- sidering it in its critical and demystifying capacity. Thirty-five 19 66 Annum mira bile (III): Julia Cornes to Paris When the twenty-four-year-old Julia Kristeva arrived in Paris in a snowstorm just before Christmas 1965 with only five dollars in her pocket, this young Bulgarian woman never imagined that she would bec orne the Egeria of structuralism. Indeed, the structuralist period was, along with everything else, an encounter between a daring cul- tural adventure and a talented woman. It was a propitious moment. Kristeva's arrivaI in France near the beginning of 1966 plunged her into a veritable cultural whirlpool that would rivet her with the pas- sion of a foreigner eut off from her native Bulgaria. Circumstances would lead her into the eye of the cyclone. The French were inter- ested in and responsive to the Russian formalist texts that Todorov was publishing, and in the political and literary events unfolding in Eastern Europe at a time when East-West relations were thawing. This was the context in which Kristeva was awarded a French gov- ernment scholarship by General de Gaulle and began to work on what seemed to be the very expression of modernity in France at the time: the New Novel. She began writing her thesis with Lucien Gold- mann, but very quickly direct contact with semiological thinking, then in full flower, led her to deconstruct her subject of study in order to work on narrative and on the constitution of the novel as a genre. From that point on, she was a full-fledged participant in the intellec- tuaI fervor of the day. 343 344 Julia Cornes ta Paris A Taste for Formalism Krsteva attended Barthes's seminar at the Hautes tudes and also went to Lvi-Strauss's Laboratory for Social Anthropology, which housed a section on semio-linguistics. She met Philippe Sollers there. "1 will always see her as she appeared to me then, very charming. There was something quite striking about her, her grace, her sensu al- ity, this union between grace and physical beauty and her capacity for reflection. From this point of view, she is unique in history."l Their union sealed Kristeva's intellectual place within Tel Quel, the most active and provocative group in 1966, which placed her at the center of the who's who of Parisian intellectuals. She met her com- patriot Todorov, became friends with Benveniste, discovered Lacan, thanks to Sollers, and went to his seminar. Sympathetic to the PCF or at least to its intellectual fringe (La Nouvelle Critique, Les Lettres franaises), she argued for Marxist positions and, after sorne months, became the spokesperson for structuralism's pretentions to generaliza- tion, a surprising mixture of semio-Marxo-Freudian thinking that embodied the intellectual avant-garde's desire to revolutionize the world ... through writing. Ir was a foreigner who was to best express this ambition, the most Parisian foreigner in the capital. Philippe Sollers, whom Kristeva would marry in 1967, was interested in liter- ary semiology at the time. In 1966 he wrote up a presentation that he had given on Mallarm on November 25, 1965, in Barthes's seminar in which he proclaimed Mallarm to be the great initiator of the cur- rent rapprochement between literature and literary theory: "For Mal- larm, literature and science are henceforth in close communication. "2 Tel Quel's entire project was part of the Mallarman legacy: an experimentation with literature beyond genres and limits, literature as the expression of self-consciousness in death, a veritable suicide after which language claims its rights and reaches beyond the limits of the subjectivity of the author's consciousness. Mallarm was attuned to rhetoric and to philosophy, and invited semiological reflection ail the more so since Le Livre crire sets the impossible as its horizon. Only scintillating fragments remain, glittering in a foreclosed future that, according to Mallarm, "is never more than the flash of that which should have happened before or near the beginning."3 Mallarm opened a vast program of formai thinking, that of a literai revolution, of a return to rhetoric, of a return of the East, of the "return to," and Julia Cornes to Paris 345 the arrivai from the East of a certain Julia Kristeva. According ta Jean Dubois, "this taste for formalism is the expression of a profound tendency that pre dates even structuralism. As a young agrg, 1 was interested in formaI structures, and if 1 was a good Greek and Latin grammarian, it was because the se are formaI structures."4 A Toast to Literature The excitement of I966 quickly affected Julia Kristeva, but her status of foreigner gave her a certain lucidity that enabled her rather quickly ta point out the two important aporias of the structuralist paradigm: history and the subject. Mikhail Bakhtin's work was particularly use- fuI for her in this. The year I966 was indeed a special one for literary thinking. Althusserian thinking had even appropriated literature, which Pierre Macherey considered as an abject of production in For a Theory of Literary Production.5 Macherey examined the new figure of the literary cri tic, who, during the structuralist era, had stopped being a second skin and had become practically a writer: "The critic is an analyst."6 The critic's task comprises the deciphering and reconstruc- tion of meaning; it is no longer restricted to the role of simply restor- ing the meaning that had been deposited in a literary work. Although Macherey did not adhere to the principles of the general formalism of the period, and even saw "a Platonic reminiscence"7 in them that led to derealizing things, he was in favor of reading literature as Althusser and his group read Marx. It was not a matter of looking for the philosophers' stone hidden behind the text, but of saying what the text says without saying it: "A true analysis ... should encounter something that is never said, an initial unsaid."8 Literature, decidedly, was in its heyday, the center of a major theoretical wager during the year of Barthes's response to Picard in Critique et vrit. Grard Genette, however, argued for a more subtle position, apparently preferring a peaceful coexistence based on a com- plementary division of labor between hermeneutics on the one hand, and structuralism on the other. There would thus be a division of the literary field between a literature capable of being experienced by the critical consciousness of hermeneutics, and another distant and rather indecipherable literature that became the privileged object of structural analysis: "The relationship that brought together struc- turalism and hermeneutics could be one of complementarity rather than a mechanical separation or exclusion."9 Genette clearly defined 346 Julia Cornes to Paris the reversaI taking place at the time by identifying the shift from a temporal to a spatial determinism. The new structural sensibility was essentially characterized by its rejection of historicity and its with- drawal into a slack present whose shape needed only to be outlined: "Each unit is defined in terms of relationship and no longer in terms of filiation." 10 Like Pierre Macherey, Grard Genette was particularly critical of the way the psychologism that held sway in classicalliterary history took an individualist approach, paying exclusive attention to works and authors at the expense of the networks of literary produc- tion and those of reading. "The conditions of its communication are produced at the same time as the book ... ; what makes the book also makes its readers."ll When crits came out that year, it provoked many conversions to a Lacanized Freudian thinking. Gennie Lemoine, one of the members of the Esprit team who had been with the review since 1946, left it to join Lacan's school in 1966. Antoinette Fouques was writing her the- sis with Barthes on the avant-garde at the time and she converted to psychoanalysis as soon as she read the crits. "1 could almost say that 1 knew Lacan before Freud. "12 At the end of the crits, Lacan repub- lished an essential article that had already come out in January 1966 in the first issue of Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, "Science Truth." ln it he rejected the fashionable notion of "human sciences" because it recalled for him the state of servitude that Georges Canguilhem had already pointed out with respect to psychology. But the repugnance with which the "human sciences" inspired Lacan evaporated once they became invested and metamorphosed by structuralism to imply a new notion of the subject. "The subject is, shall we say, internally excluded from its object."13 During this structural year, and despite a move toward logic that had begun in 1964, Lacan still leaned heavily on Lvi-Strauss: "The loyalty that Claude Lvi- Strauss's work displays with regard to this structuralism will only be considered in our thesis to limit us for the moment to its periphery."14 Shortly after, Lacan evoked the "Lvi-Straussian graph" to explode the subject. Descartes's famous ego would have had no other existence than one of denotation. According to lisabeth Roudinesco, in 1966 Lacan was still suffering from insufficient recognition, which would explain his search for support, whether from Lvi-Strauss or from Foucault, whose Birth of the Clinic he mentioned in the crits,15 without falling into what he would later qualify as the "structuralist banquet." Julia Cornes to Paris 347 Julia Kristeva therefore traversed a Paris jolted structuralism, the sanctuary of exchanges among those who enthusiastically shared the impression of belonging to a new world of the concept, beyond the notion of substance and disciplinary deep-rootedness, in the sole abyssal vertigo of the infinite game of relationships and their com- binations, shaking boundaries and settling in as close as possible to the limits, on the threshold of the ever-receding and ev er-inaccessible realm of the possible. The Solitary Path of Maurice Godelier Freud and Marx were the two important tutelary figures in question. Lacan's reading and his return to Freud became absolutely fundamen- tal for the indispensable renovation of Freud's work, in the same way that Althusser's reading of Marx was a return and a revision of the master. But there were also sorne hybrid cases, and Maurice Godelier was one of these. Godelier sought a way to reconcile two approaches that might seem antagonistic at the outset, for he tried to create a syn- thesis between Lvi-Strauss and Marx in order to return to Marx. And his effort was every bit as much a renewal and just as structural as the efforts of Lacan and Althusser. ln 1966, Maspero published Godelier's Rationality and Irra- tionality in Economy,16 but the second part of his work was a group of articles that had appeared between 1960 and 1965 in La Pense and conomie et politique, which is to say prior ta Althusser's reread- ing of Marx. Godelier distinguished between Marx's hypothetic- deductive and dialectical methods. He had not awaited Althusser's re- turn to Marx; his solitary undertaking was part of an oeuvre that displays a certain solidarity with Lvi-Strauss's structural anthropol- ogy. "1 reread Capital alone at a time when no one was interested in rereading it."1? Having come from an agrgation in philosophy, Gode- lier had studied economics for three years and tried to create an eco- nomic anthropology that would make it possible to undertake a com- parative theoretical study of different economic systems over time and in space, based on a widely accepted definition of political economy that would include aIl dimensions of social life. "There is no eco- nomic rationality in itself nor any definitive form or mode! of economic rationality."18 Of course, in the context of the sixties, it was surprising that no common activities were ever undertaken by Althusserians and Gode- 348 Julia Cornes to Paris lier, given the great proximity in their points of view. Godelier, how- ever, did go ta the rue d'Ulm one Sunday morning to the initial meet- ing of an important collective research program led by Althusser. "A monstrous operation unfolded there before our very eyes. There was Althusser, the sacred interpreter of the sacred work, assigning tasks to everyone. Badiou was supposed to take care of the Marxist theory of mathematics, Macherey was to take care of the Marxist theory of literature ... "19 According to Emmanuel Terray, Godelier had an un- favorable reaction to the group because he was suspected of seeking an impossible compromise between Marx and Lvi-Strauss. If ideas circulated quickly in I966, and if aU roads led to struc- turalism, it was not easy ta discern who held center stage, a poten- tiaUy hegemonic position in this cultural cauldron. The positions were dear and the risk of faUing into the pot relatively high. The game had to be subtle. No, clearly, a structuralist Paris was an impossible wager. Part III A Hexagonal Pever Thirty-six The Postmodern Hour Sounds Imperceptibly, over the course of the twentieth century in the West, a new relationship with temporality was ta king hold. At the same time, European domination and its role as a model for the rest of huma nit y were on the wane. At the beginning of the century in Vienna, at the heart of the old, decadent Hapsburg empire, a new ahistorical culture was bursting forth. 1 The First World War had decisively redrawn the old economic maps in favor of the non-European powers. Europe underwent a crisis of consciousness as it realized that the uninterrupted linear evolution- ism of its own historicity had been broken when it had been obliged to pass the baton of modernity to the young American power. In 1920, Spengler's Decline of the West relegated Europe to its proper provin- cial place, a Europe that was beginning to experience the unstable foundations of nineteenth-century evolutionism. Heirs to the Lumires and the Aufklarung, the social sciences were enjoying their belle epoque, progressing toward the age of per- fection and of reason triumphant. The tenants of immobilism or of change had all concurred on a general shape of the future of progress, whether Saint-Simon, Spencer, Comte, or Marx. August Comte saw outlined against the horizon of humanity a theological state, suc- ceeded by a metaphysical state, and finally a positive state. For Karl Marx, the transition from slavery to serfdom to capitalism culminated with socialism. These certainties about constructing the future in a 3F 352 The Postmodern Hour Sounds progressive perspective would founder in the face of the tragic reality of a twentieth century that, in 1920, had not yet run out of surprises for Eurocentrism. The Second World War and the Holocaust further traumatized a West that had scarcely dressed its wounds when it saw its leading po- sition in the world challenged by whole continents shaking off the colonial yoke. A denuded Europe problematized its dramatic past against a background of increasingly radical pessimism. And at each new jolt, Europe mourned the very idea of a future of rupture. A Futureless Present A dilated present made the pa st present. A new kind of relationship to historicity developed; the present was no longer the anticipation of the future but the arena for a possible recycling of the pasto "When the difference of the future is no longer to be sought in the present, we suddenly discover it coming from behind, backwards."2 Only when the question was no longer the search for something in the past that made another construction of the future possible could the relation- ship between past and present be relaxed, when the future was screwed shut, weighed down in a present equilibrium condemned to infinitely repeat itself. The taste for novelty, the publicity picture of our daily life, made it possible to further dilute every possible future alterity.3 Having rejected all historical teleology and all meaning given to the history of humanity, the distant enticements of the "world that we have lost," of the Middle Ages magnified as the site of alterity linked to the search for the roots of identity, could be rediscovered. A new, ethnological consciousness was needed to replace histori- cal consciousness as this decentering of European culture and meta- physical deconstruction unfolded. The West was beginning to exam- ine its nether side, the ways in which the unconscious made itself palpably present by its very absence. Freud had discovered the laws of the unconscious underlying our society and Durkheim had deciphered the unconscious of our collective practices. Postmodernity therefore was built around this quest for underlying mechanisms and targeted the deconstruction of the humanism that Michel Foucault had charac- terized as medieval, using this triumphant epistemological revolution of the sixties in order to glorify it: "Structuralism is not a new method, it is the awakened and troubled consciousness of modern thought."4 The Postmodern Hour Sounds 353 Reason Loses Its Charm A fundamental pessimism, a sort of negative theology, was nourished by the provincialization of Western reason and realization of the irre- ducible logic of resistance of other logics, and of cultural plurality. "Those who were disappointed by Western reason"5 countered the optimistic belief in rationality by falling into a sort of nihilism or reflection on limits made at the intersection between sense and non- sense. It was a complex situation confusing personal idiosyncrasies born of disillusionment and rejection but still bearing the marks of its contesta tory beginnings. Theorizing man's incapacity to master his collective or personal history, underscoring his incompleteness, the defunct pavane of Western reason also heralded a more rigorous ef- fort whose lucidity was greater than that of Western reason itself. This is what was clearly at work in Lvi-$trauss's exhuming of primitive societies, what gave Lacan a capacity to care for his patients, what allowed Foucault to work on prisoners, the forgotten, and the re- pressed. The ruse of reason worked at its own decentering. The relationships between the structuralist paradigm and the dis- illusionment of the period are therefore complicated, not a mirror re- flection of each other, but rather the scientific mind developed au- tonomously with regard to the context. To argue for their equality would be "like saying that Einstein's relativity is a disillusionment based on the idea that everything is relative."6 And yet another piece must be added to this context of ambient disenchantment preceding the explosion of structuralism, which is the exhaustion of the evolu- tionist, phenomenological, functionalist paradigms and the se arch for an epistemological renewal. The law of evolution itself was seen to be comprised of successive ruptures and models and programs surpassed, conveying a veritable histary of theoretical failures. In the same way that the West was discovering a nonlinear history, the social sciences were no longer thinking of themselves as successive accumulations of layers of sedimentation. The Ideology of Suspicion The twentieth century is the century of ruptures, breaks, and radical shifts. It has led to a fundamental pessimism with respect to history and ta the onset of the postmodern era. We would agree with Jean- Franois Lyotard, who dates the rupture of Western evolutionism in 354 The Postmodern Hour Sounds 1943/ the year of the final solution, a radical plunge into horror. No one could henceforth ignore Dachau and Auschwitz, said Adorno. Technological modernity became a steamroller, a planetary death ma- chine enmeshed in an ideology of suspicion. In addition to which, the reality of the totalitarian system behind the Iron Curtain was laid bare as the underside of the ostensible model. Beyond reason, implacable ruses muzzled the hopes of creating a better world and this obser- vation of a necessary discontinuity: "We must start from the begin- ning."8 It was no longer possible to naively exalt the continuous progress of freedom and human lucidity, nor to sustain the humanist vision according to which man is the perfectible master of his destiny, marching directly toward perfection. In place of that rosy future stood the approach of partial changes whose limits and possibilities needed definition. From Budapest to Alexandria by way of Aigiers, 1956 witnessed a procession of disillusionments. In France, songs of Liberation were silenced and a certain collective hope dimmed. Only the voice of the master who ended aIl hope sounded and resounded as he awaited the moment in 1958 when he could calI for a new national leader, this general who presented himself as the incarnation of the "incarna- tion." The fifties were to deal a new hand to French intellectuals. "After 1956 ... we were no longer obliged to hope for anything."9 Not that the decade was more propitious for bringing forth posi- tive changes. If, during the space of a springtime in 1968, the inter- national movement had infected French society, the year ended with the Soviet boot crushing another spring, the Prague Spring. A new wave of intellectuals was to fully feel the brunt of this new jolt. "1 was in New Guinea in 1968, and 1 cried when 1 heard that the Russians had invaded Czechoslovakia .... We saw how legitimacy was estab- lished with tanks rather than with democracy; it was all over." 10 Revo- lutionary hopes, exposed to the forces of oppression, took on a mythological cast for an entire generation, reduced to a fantasy and repressed like a nineteenth-century myth. These important experi- ences of limits invoked by the intellectuals were irreversibly eroded in Western society, which no longer thought of itself as belonging to what Lvi-Strauss called a warm history, but rather seemed to borrow from primitive societies, in order to favor a cold relationship to an im- paled and immobile temporality .. The Postmodern Hour Sounds .3 5 5 The Death of Evolutionism Revolutionary eschatology dissolved with the resistances, blockages, and inertia of our society. In the same way that political will and com- mitment were discredited, a similar theoretical discredit tainted aIl things historical. The structuralist paradigm would be constructed and flourish from this negation of historicity and quest for origins, from the genesis of the reflection on temporal rhythms. It would freeze movement, cool off history, and anthropologize it when "the natives become the indigents." Il Western fascination with the unchanging lifestyle of the Nambik- wara that Lvi-Strauss had resurrected in a certain way, a West break- ing with its historicity, revealed the beginning of the postmodern pe- riod. The very ide a of progress as a unifying phenomenon underwent a form of disinfection. Pluralized, progress was no longer perceived as the driving force of social evolution. And without refuting certain ad- vances, these were no longer part of a total problematization of soci- ety. This deconstruction lay behind a true intellectuai revolution inau- gurated by structuralism, particularly through anthropology and the idea of the equivalence of the human species. This was a fundamental shift from Lvy-Bruhl to Lvi-Strauss. It demonstrated that, beyond the tropics with their plurality of lifestyles and thinking, aIl human societies were the complete and hierarchy-free expression of human- ity. This aspect of the structura li st revolution remains, ane! it gave a new perception of the world in which aIl forms of social organization were considered equal, abolishing distinctions between inferior and superior or befores and afters. Thanks to structuralism, the idea of progress lost significant luster. "In order for there to be a notion of progress, there had to be primates at the beginning .... This was acquired thanks to structuralism, something we no longer realize be- cause we do not see the transition clearly. It is a given; it has become something obvious."12 Granted, it was easy to go from re!ativity to re!ativism, but whatever the position, perceiving the Other as a partial manifestation of the human Univers al meant abandoning the histori- cal vision of nineteenth-century evolutionism. The human sciences re- placed the consciousness of a mode! Europe poised at the vanguard of human progress with a critical consciousness that dethroned the Sub- ject and History, and that turned consciousness upon itself, or rather, upon its nether side, its repressed. This egalitarian notion burst forth 356 The Postmodern Hour Sounds during postwar period, and with decolonization it was here to stay. Ir was a completely new idea that recleflned the geopolitical points of the globe. The perception of humanity became eccentric as a result for the Western inteIlectual; no longer read from within, iden- tity was projected into an external space. This inflection of perspective required a dialectical relationship between spaces, and that the an- thropologist's glasses be trained on the universe of the Other. Temporality Slides into Spatiality There had clearly been a radical break with the Enlightenment and the belief in continuous progress as Condorcet had imagined it.1 3 Western man had been at the center of the conception of knowledge and judg- ment before his anthropocentric viewpoint was decentered. The seeds of this revolution had been planted at the end of the nineteenth cen- tury by new structures of scientiflc thought, pictorial perspective, and writing, aIl of which favored discontinuity and deconstruction. From the arbitrariness of the Saussurean sign to the new mathematical and physical models to quantum the ory to the Impressionists' dislocation of classical perspective, foIlowed by that of the Cubists, a new vision of the world imposed discontinuity: the referent was held at bay. Western reason was being gnawed at from within and tending toward plurality as of the late nineteenth century, no longer con- ceived of as a reflection, but rather as a discontinuous succession of different structures. Psychoanalysis emphasized this phenomenon by demonstrating the discontinuity between the unconscious and the conscious requiring the presence of a third element in the analytic context. An inflnite unfolding of epistemes replaced the unitary view of evolutionism. The shifting ideas between the nineteenth and twentieth centuries further accentuated these changes. Nineteenth-century European his- toricism had seen human history as a liberation from the laws of na- ture, whereas the twentieth century once again took its distance from history in order to retether itself to nature, perceived as "a regulatory ideal in the para dise to be rediscovered."14 The batdes waged by man in the name of the noble values of freedom and equality were thus considered doubtful, incomplete, and most often destined to failure. Historical consciousness was repressed by a planetary, topo- graphical consciousness. Temporality shifted into spatiality. Being re- moved from the natural order gave way to a se arch for unvarying The Postmodern Hour Sounds 357 logics born of the nature/culture joining. The prospect of a foreclosed future generated a quest for an immutable human nature with evident constants-Lv-Strauss's enceintes mentales, ecosystems, the longue dure, structures, the extension of the notion of geographicity-and the natural paradigm took its revenge. "Today we see how the de- sacralization of history leads to a resacralization of nature by com- municating vases." 15 The ruptures were tragic and provoked a need for and a return to cultural, ethnie, and natural constants for protection. This approach sought even more to protect against history, to be free by clinging to an identity that anchors rather than constructs history from a signify- ing diachronie logic. Those uncertain moments of history, the cult of the past, the restorations occulting superficial ruptures transformed man as the subject of his history into an object of history that he could not understand. The relationship between men, as a result, is "sub- jected to a zoological status." 16 Western society underwent a number of changes during the inter- war years that further upset the relationship between past, present, and future. The future was reduced by computerized programming to little more than a projected reproduction of the present, but it was im- possible to think a different future. The end of terri tories and the be- ginning of a society beyond national soil contributed to the state of temporal weightiness, a cooled relationship to temporality. "What we called the acceleration of history fifty years ago . . . has become the crushing of history."17 Similarly, this atemporal relationship became fragmented into myriad uncorrelated objects, a segmentation of par- tial and disarticulated knowledge, a disaggregation of the general field of understanding, and the gutting of any real contents. This socio- economic mulch would particularly nurture a structurallogic, symp- tomatic reading, logicism or formalism that would find its coherence elsewhere than in the world of flat realia. Sorne, like Henri Lefebvre, saw a direct link between structural- ism's success and the implantation of a technocratie society. In his view, structuralism played the role of an ideology legitimating a social caste, the technostructure of the new indus trial state, the justification of its location at the highest levels of authority, and the theorization of the elimination of history. Structuralism would thus be the harbinger of the end of history for a middle class that had managed to reach a posi- tion of domination. An ideology of constraint and of the weight of the 358 The Postmodern Hour Sounds structural on human liberty reduced to common property, it reflected the consumerism in which the citizen would cede his or her place to the consumer. The social universe and the representation of the world that it engendered were thus magnificently connected with the mortification of the European left, which, in the sixties, averted its gaze from history and from notions of progress. Structuralism therefore answered a so- cial need; it crystallized a particular historical situation in which shift- ing attention toward the figure of the "savage" no longer responded to a need for exoticism but to the desperate search for the truth of hu- manity in a universe where the future seemed to be foreclosed. As early as 1967, Franois Furet had seen that the intellectual mi- lieu of the Marxist left was the most receptive to the structuralist vogue.t 8 According to Furet, this milieu had an inverted relationship whereby it could express nostalgia for a Marxism that was being abandoned little by little to the rhythm of revelations about the gulag, and, thanks to structuralism, find sorne compensation for the same determinist ambition to universalize and totalize, but without the bur- den of history. According to this hypothesis, structuralism would ex- press a very specific historical moment, an intersection characterized by political immobility and the consolidation of systems. The death knell had sounded for progress; the structuralist fervor led to a calling into question of dialectical thought. Philosophers con- tributed new readings that were to cast doubts on the Hegelian foun- dations of their analyses. In their place, a symptomatic reading made it possible to perceive an epistemological break between the "young Marx," who is still Hegelian, and the "mature Marx," scientifically mature, a structuralist before his time. "A nondialectical culture is in the process of taking shape."19 At the same time, Franois Chtelet w;as reducing the dialectic to rhetoric and Gilles Deleuze was an- nouncing "an ebb of dialectical thinking in favor of structuralism."20 Today we customarily say that the ebb of ideologies has made it possi- ble for a hundred structuralist flowers to bloom. In the same way that the limits of praxis resulted in man's decentering, an immantentist reading of the social sciences saw the sources of scientific rigor in the decentering of human practices. Repetition Compulsion Posthistory brought a new relationship with a dilated present that ap- pears as ahistorical, an eternal recycling of different configurations of The Postmodern Hour Sounds 359 the pasto This present offered a hermetic horizon, for it could only re- pro duce itself in the dominant presentism. The fashion for commemo- ration clearly illustrated this new re1ationship with historicity. Mem- ory repressed history, which was no longer the search for origins in or der to generate future possibilities, but the simple reminder of the universe of signs of the past living in an immutable present. Signs that referred to each other and whose only referents were those sites of memory, so many traces left in the space of a past, perceived some- where over the horizon of an impassable split. We experience "the end of what we were as an affirmation: the adequation of history and memory."21 These sites of memory kept their symbolic value and in- vited an archivistic relationship to the pasto They were not revisited so as to be reconstructed, but were simply considered as the remains of a repressed past that had disappeared. A radical discontinuity separated the memory of an ever-indefinable past, invisible as reality except for its multiple material signs, from a slack present that recycles, commemorates, and remembers. The rela- tionship to temporality was thus split and memory became memories, fractured for want of a breakwater constituting a full, collective mem- ory. History flowed back into the moment, thanks to the unification of lifestyles and mentalits when there were no longer any true events, but only a profusion of "news." The present plunged its roots into the past through a purely museographical relationship, without concern- ing itself with the oudines of a definition of the future. It thus destabi- lized the very function of historical discourse as the connection be- tween past and present. Postmodernism established a re1ationship to history resembling that of a senile individual who can do little more than collect souve- nirs, remaining forever cut off from all possibility of a future project. Structuralism's success therefore corresponded to a general phenome- non of civilization and should be ascribed as much to the establishment of a technocratic society and to the birth of Herbert Marcuse's one- dimensional man as to the reification of man reduced to his con- sumerism. In this respect, and without being reducible to that, humanity was the ideology of nonideologies, the end of revolutionary ideologies, of colonial ideologies, and of Christian ideologies. But in the sixties this aspect was the unsaid, the unconscious of profound changes that only bec orne evident in the eighties. This process of pacification, this end of meaningful breaks, closed the present in on itself; what came to domi- 360 The Postmodern Hour Sounds nate was the feeling of satisfaction, of marking time, of a society where "the new is greeted like the oId, where innovation has become banal. "22 Discourses of Legitimation in Cri sis Both a fundamental pessimism critical of the illusions of reason and a des ire to deconstruct everything that presented itself as total coher- ence, categorical imperative, and natural order subjected to the de- compostion of a radical critique, spurred the retreat of history and the crisis of discourses of legitimation that characterize postmodernity. The very notion of reality was caIled into question. Since everything that touched these categories elicited only disillusionment, reality was repressed into meaninglessness. Structuralism was, in this respect, one stage in the process of deconstruction, by its faculty of derealization. Public space was imperceptibly transformed into a space of advertise- ment in the era of the simulacrum, at the same time as aIl the poles of reference were vanishing, so many spatiotemporal frameworks for the values we had believed to be eternal and univers al. Paul Virilio saw in philosophy's search for the hidden face an echo of an aesthetic of disappearance in which the reality effect supplants reality. Every metanarrative is in crisis in the postindustrial or post- modern society because of a generalized skepticism. According to Jean-Franois Lyotard, this transition to a new economy of discourse occurred at the end of the fifties in Europe when "reconstruction" was coming to an end. 23 With modern technologies of communication and the informatiza- tion of society, knowledge shifted and became the inseparable face of the power of the deciders, the programmers, who little by little rele- gated the old traditional political class to a lesser role. In this context, the question of legitimation deviated and provoked a crisis of the major narratives. "The 'crisis' of scientific knowledge ... represents, rather, an internaI erosion of the legitimacy principle of knowledge."24 De- constructing the One, the metadiscourses, yielded to a proliferation of multiple discourses unassigned to any single subject, simple language games, a seamless fabric. The humanist perspective dissolved and was replaced by a performative stake, a "legitimation by the fact."25 A Crepuscular Vision Structuralism responded to this crisis of legitimation discours es by re- ducing human ambitions to something of only provincial proportions, The Postmodern Hour Sounds 36I simple participants without any particular privileges, living beings on the planet, subjected to a history that no longer belongs ta them, at the geologicallevel. Lvi-Strauss was the most eminent representative of this fundamental pessimism, of this retreat of man. One of the most critical observers of the evolution of Western modernity, he contrasted it with a profound skepticism and pessimism that placed him in the long line of conservative thinkers stretching from Edmund Burke to Philippe Aris. "1 would gladly accept the reproach of pessimism, on the condition that the adjective 'serene' is added. "26 This jaded view was further underscored by Lvi-Strauss's own position as an anthropologist who watched his field disappear be- neath his very feet with the staggering blows of an often forced ac- culturation. At the beginning of the nineteenth century there were two hundred and fifty thousand natives in Australia, but in the mid- twentieth century there were only fort y thousand survivors of hunger and illness. Between 1900 and 1950, ninety tribes disappeared in Brazil. These disappearances from the specific ethnological field forced the ethnologist to consider his own society, to which he could certainly apply his methods of analysis, but based on the uniformity of modernity that imposed its laws. Lvi-Strauss therefore observed an atmosphere of something that was ebbing. After the dusk of the gods, it was the turn for humans: "The day is coming when the last of the cultures we call primitive will have disappeared from the face of the earth."27 At the end of his four volumes on myths, a disabused Lvi-Strauss concluded with an involution of the resources of the universe/nature/home combination, which ended "before collapsing in upon themselves and vanishing, through the self-evidence of their own decay. "28 As early as 1955, Lvi-Strauss had warned the West of the disas- ters, of the underside of its euphoria in the thirty glorious years. With Tristes Tropiques, he was offering to make primitive societies live aga in, to remove them from the mire beneath "our garbage" flung in the face of humanity, the concrete that takes root everywhere like dan- delions, the pauperization of the sIums, deforestation. This is a sad score ca rd of a conquering, lesson-giving civilization, a civilization of death behind the hypocrite face of adventure and of encounter with the Other. Lvi-Strauss's structural anthropology attacked the Lu- mires and their pretension to a univers al message. In a similar fashion, and on a speculative rather than an ethno- 362 The Postmodern Hour Sounds graphie level, Foucault expressed this same desire to shake up universal- ism. "1 dream of the intellectual who destroys facts and universals. "29 The Richness of a Clos ure Whether defined by Lvi-Strauss or by Foucault or by aIl of new struc- turalist thinking, and despite its tremendous diversity, this new prob- lematization took root in this retreat of history characteristic of post- modernity, in this pessimism that was not only serene but productive. For want of a historical perspective, once having destabilized the sta- tus of man and taken its distance from the reality of the real, struc- turalism preferred closed systems in which methods with a scientific vocation sought refuge, an inaccessible place, repressed and removed from consciousness. An increasingly complex social reality and an in- ability to identify any unifying logic favored this withdrawal into the search for a unit y in the hidden face of reality. Revealed meaning fell into insignificance. It was no longer part of the closed field of this uni- verse of signs that, removed from the referent, referred back and forth among themselves in the absence of any material causality. The truth of the closed system could no longer be sought by sorne hermeneutic whose starting point was revealed meaning, but it was to be under- stood in the relationships and interrelationships between signs within their specifie and limited structure, and the interplay that it defined be- tween the signs. This web of relationships excluded historical contingency just as it excluded the free play of initiative. If structurallinguistics provided the preferred model of approach, there was nonetheless sorne resemblance between the cybernetic approach, which decenters the finalist and an- thropocentric perspective in order to give precedence to the processes of self-regulation, a combination of a physics of relationships, the games and replays of the same and the other, decentered humanity that only held an illusory place. "We must break this network of appear- ances that we caU man with aIl our might. "30 At the moment when the social sciences seemed fascinated by the cybernetlc model, the human variable in its psychological and historical components lacked consis- tency and was replaced by a rigorous method that sought to reach a level of efficacy equal to that being practiced in the hard sciences. The closed system that became necessary would paya heavy price for set- ting the real world at a distance. And yet, it would be remarkably ef- fective in the receptivity it would inaugurate in the field of knowledge. The Postmodern Hour Sounds 363 In its quest for the unconscious dimension of social practices, structuralism would open the universe of signs of the symbolic, of col- lective representations, and of customs and rituals in their internal logic, and from the nonexplicit strata find the traces of human activity. Acceding to the se new objects and pluralizing them would help shat- ter systems of causality: "The structural method has made it possible to triumph over causalisms or simplistic determinisms."31 The unify- ing coherence of social history faded as weil, sinking into the quick- sands of the unifying and plural structural combinatory, a dialectical game of the same and of the other inaugurating the new era of a posthistory. Thirty-seven Nietzschean -Heideggerian Roots One philosopher was intensely aware of the impasses of history at the heart of a nineteenth century in which Western history reigned tri- umphant, and that was Nietzsche. He clearly understood that the thinking of the moment was preparing the advent of the despotic state. German unit y was realized, but at the price of a militarized and aggressive Prussia. Nietzsche's Untimely Meditations (1873-74) ad- dressed the dangers of history, by which he meant two different defini- tions of the term: historicity (Geschichte), and the understanding of historical change. Nietzsche theorized the suicide of Western history and the death of Homo historicus. Instead of the theodicy leading to the creation of the col de st "of cold monsters," the state, he put forth an argument in favor of multiple, local, and present values, a return to sources in a Europe bastardized by successive racial mixtures and whose universalizing message had been deformed by the radical exit from historicity. During the same period, Darwin was demonstrating the simian origins of the human species. Anthropocentric perspective and metaphysical thinking were thus both being rut to the test by sci- entific discoveries. Nietzsche's nihilistic discourse could flower and challenge the out- look of the triumphant Lumires like a narcissistic wound following on the heels of the Copernican-Galilean revelation that the earth was not at the center of the universe, and rock Western metaphysics. The evolution of reason would thuslead to its other side, to a realization Nietzschean-Heideggerian Roots 365 of the non-sense, the even the relativization of the figure of man. Nietzsche dispatched history as well as the dialectic of reason. Later, Heidegger renewed the Nietzschean legacy in his radical critique of modernity. His thinking was rooted in Oswald Spengler's Decline of the West, a depiction that Heidegger, aHected by the trauma of the First World War and the ensuing debade in the Weimar Republic of the twenties, pushed to its paroxysm. He plotted the tra- jectory of the Forgetting of Being, of a constant repression underlying the prevalence of being. Man no longer had access to the revelation of truth insofar as each manifestation of truth "is at the same time in it- self a dissimulation."l ln this view of things, history was nothing more than the sad unfolding of reason, mystified since the original crack. The theme of the eternal return found its echo in the Heideggerian no- tion of a perennis philosophy, a veritable remake of the same based on the question of why there is Being rather than nothing. The answer was that there was no answer. As a philosophy of impotence, this phi- losophy signaled our incapacity to answer without reappropriating the "Scriptures and the Holy Roman and Apostolic Church, which does not, however, me an that Heidegger was a believer."2 Both of these philosophies, moved by a profound pessimism, sought to establish the end of philosophy. "It looks as though every- thing is becoming chaotic, the old becoming lost to us, the new prov- ing useless and growing ever feebler."3 For Nietzsche, the faculty of reason that made it possible to decenter man still nourished his illu- sion of omnipotence, salving the wounds it inflicted each time a bit more. Similarly, the Forgetting of Being was further accentuated by the development of modernity and the generalization of technicity. The Anti-Lumires These two thinkers presented themselves as anti-Lumires. Nietzsche denounced the brutal violence of the Lumires philosophy that culmi- nated in the French Revolution. In his eyes, any brutal change or revo- lutionary break could only elicit a vision of barbarism: "It is not Voltaire's moderate nature ... but Rousseau's passionate follies and half-lies that called for the optimistic spirit of the Revolution against which 1 cry: 'crasez l'infme.'''4 Here Nietzsche defended the moder- ate and progressive philosophers against those radical philosophers who worked toward the fulfillment of the Revolution. But Nietzsche's work, like that of Heidegger, was essentially a radical critique of the 366 Nietzchean-Heideggerian Roots Lumires. Both attacked a certain notion of historicity as a bearer of progress, for if history has any meaning at aU, it is that we are inex- orably moving toward a decline. The conscious mind is encumbered by history and must free itself in order to judge the present. "He sends the dialectic of reason packing."5 Underlying the Lumires' claims of universality, Nietzsche saw the immanent and hidden roots of the wiU to power. Becoming was meaningless, or rather an apprenticeship in the tragedy of the world, which is its very essence. "History resides in us like camouflaged theology."6 Meaninglessness clearly led man to impotence, to a nihilism assumed by an aristocratic and powerful elite making any illusion of human action moot. The human spirit of ratio- nalization was perceived as continuous with religious spirit; substitut- ing reason for God would have been equaUy illusory. The effort at human mastery was therefore absurdo For Nietzsche, humanity began its decline with the beginning of Greek thought, and Socrates, who appeared in Ecce Homo, was the very symptom of decadence. Instincts and Dionysian hubris are con- trasted to Socrates' ethic, which would later be embodied by religious morality in order to repress and suffocate vital drives. The entire his- tory of civilization therefore unfolds according to an internallogic of castrating reason and a mystifying morality. Philosophy must discover the creative drive shrouded beneath the mask of civilization. Nietz- sche favored forgetting in order to be rid of the illusory and mystifica- tion: "Thus it is possible to live almost without memory, and to live happily moreover, as the animal demonstrates, but it is altogether im- possible to live at aU without forgetting."7 Filled with a fundamental pessimism and hostility to historicity, Nietzsche also nourished a vis- ceral hatred of the masses and of revolution. Nietzsche described his thoughts in his correspondence with a German officer during the I870 siege of Paris. He considered war to be a useful test of virility, but the awful spectacle of the Paris Com- mune, the "slaves'" revoIt, and their breaking of rules frightened him. General insurrections lead straight to "barbarism" he wrote in I87I-73 in his preparatory notes for an essay on the future of teach- ing establishments. Those dispensers of earthly happiness, the social- ists of the late nineteenth century, could only perfect the metaphysical cast of mind at work in aU of Western history and therefore make it veer toward decadence and catastrophe. But laying bare the illusions of the metaphysical era also revealed an unprepared and weak indi- Nietzschean-Heideggerian Roots 367 vidual in the grips of the ephemeral, a striking contra st to the false happiness of the metaphysical ages. Whence the temptation to be borne toward the construction of a better future, a future that is al- ways part of a comforting illusion: "That better future which one wishes for mankind must necessarily be in sorne respects a worse fu- ture for it is folly to believe that a new higher stage of mankind will write in itself aIl the excellences of earlier stages." 8 Socialism was Nietzsche's true enemy: "Socialism is the fanciful younger brother of the almost expired despotism who se heir it wants to be."9 "The poison of this disease which is presently contaminating the masses with increasing speed as a socialist scabies of the heart."lO Since history at the close of the nineteenth century seemed to guaran- tee the irresistible success of the socialist movement, history needed to be eliminated in order to better destroy the dangers threatening the West and was thus assimilated at once to a mystification, to deca- dence, to a smell of rot, and to a paralyzing straitjacket. In the middle of a historicist century, Nietzsche was a radical partisan of the dissolu- tion of the category of the new, the thinker of the end of history. Nietzsche was therefore a precursor of the triumphant post- modernity of the mid-twentieth century. He was already sketching out the deconstruction of the unified, total framework of historical move- ment, which yielded to the immobility of a slack present in which histories undergo a process of atomization and multiplication when they are only constructed on an individual basis: "Nietzsche and Heidegger . . . laid the necessary foundations for constructing an image of existence in response to the new conditions of nonhistoricity or, better yet, of posthistoricity." 11 The Forgetting of Being In the I930S, Heidegger took up Nietzsche's critique of modernity in his lectures. Heidegger, like Nietzsche, saw history as little more than the unfolding of a slow decline whose roots harken back to the Greeks in the constant Forgetting of Being. In his 1957 The Princip le of Reason, Heidegger critiqued two forms of historical thinking. He qualified the first as the metaphysics of history, which imagines that freedom operates in historical evolution, metaphysical insofar as it presupposes man at the center of the historical process-a belief that Heidegger clearly considered to be an illusion, a metaphysics of sub- jectivity. In the second place, he attacked Hegelianism as a teleology in 368 Nietzchean-Heideggerian Roots which reason slowly revealed itself to itself through history, as simply another form of metaphysics that subjects history to the principle of reason, a variation that also reintroduced the Subject into a central position-not because this subject mastered a process that more often than not victimized him by its ruses, but because he could come to understand its significance. However, man modeled meaning on the structure of his own human reason rather than that of Being, which remained confined within Forgetting. In place of these approaches, which Heidegger characterized as metaphysical, he proposed the history of Being, a history without a history, the simple unfolding of that which is presented through its successive images, meaningless, without either filiation or periodiza- tion. To conceive of history, he used the metaphor of a trunkless, root- less rose bush flowering in the springtime. A profusion of buds de- scribed shattered history, with neither a subject to infuse the historical unfolding with meaning nor an underlying, occult subject whose traces would have to be sought. In Being and Time (I927), the temporality of Being was placed alongside that of a progressive decline leading to an apocalpyse, in which, as we know, Heidegger participated. Degradation is structural in human history: "Belonging to the very being of Dasein, degrada- tion is an existential."12 From his rectorate speech to his interview in Der Speigel, Heidegger never stopped reiterating his Cassandra-like warning against the decline (Verfall) in which the West was inexorably becoming mired: "The spiritual force of the West eludes us and its edi- fice trembles, the dead appearance of culture crumbles."13 To this in- volution, Heidegger contrasted the strength of rootedness, tradition, and country; they must be so many breakwaters of resistance against the technicity of the modern world that carries away the totality of being with which the being-there of Being is dissolved. If the history of Western civilization is the history of a progressive forgetting of Being, the twentieth century is the culmination of this amnesia. For Jrgen Habermas, Heidegger's critique of modernity, technic- ity, and mass civilization was unoriginal because it simply appropri- ated the repertory of received ideas of the genration's conservative mandarins. Habermas situated the drift leading Heideggerian theory to embrace National Socialism in what was, in I933, a new invest- ment in the categories of fundamental ontology. Until that point, Da- sein had designated the being toward death in its singularity, whereas Nietzschean-Heideggerian Roots 369 after 1933 it took on a collective sense the reunited population. Heidegger also diverged from the path of triumphant reason and chose the sinuous path of an obscure world that "willlead nowhere." A conception of wandering ta come nearer the paths leading to the realm of origins and of logos. This theme of wandering found no earthly culmination; these pilgrimages of the hum an "shepherd of Being" could only evoke a complete theological variation. "This ex- plained how theologians were the first to adopt Being and Time."14 Heidegger radically detached Being from empirical reality in the same way that he realized the end of history. Antihumanism If structuralism was fortified by this antihistoricism, Nietzsche and Heidegger radically critiqued humanism, in which the figure of man disappeared like so many grains of sand beneath the waves. At the beginning, there was the fracture Nietzsche created with the death of God, which destabilized the notion of an identifiable, definable human mastery and subject of history. He denounced the deification of man that replaced religion at the time of the Lumires and that con- tinued throughout the nineteenth century. If God was dead, no immutable human nature could exist as an aeterna veritas or measure of all things, and this relativism led Nietz- sche to a radical nihilism. Moral judgment became impossible; on what basis could a norm be constructed? "When virtue has slept, she will get up more refreshed. "15 Ethical judgment supposed a freedom of action and a level of responsibility that man does not possess. Under such circumstances, individual judgment in any given situation became the sole criterion for action, the rest little more than the basis for subjugating the subject. "The complete unaccountability of man for his actions and his nature is the bitterest draught the man of knowledge has to swallow if he has been accustomed to seeing in ac- ceptability and dut y the patent of his humanity."16 Nietzsche attacked humanism as a doctrine that assigned man the central role of subject as a full being, as the seat of the proof of self-consciousness. Here, Nietzsche translated the impossibility of relying on any transcendental foundation whatsoever, given the death of God. Heidegger took Nietzsche's critique of huma ni sm further. Man was fundamentally dispossessed of any mastery since his reality could only forever appear to him as something veiled. "The question: who is 370 Nietzchean-Heideggerian Roots man? can only be raised in the questioning of Being." 17 This question- ing led to indetermination and inaccessibility, except that here, man is the trace, the communion, the witness. The effectiveness of Heideg- ger's critique lay in emphasizing the fact that man's definition in no way gave him the capacity to free himseH from the codes enclosing him in contingent definitions and in particular determinations. Ek- sistence preceded being and determined man's initial nothingness, and his vocation of universality. Heidegger represented a major break from the vision of man as mas ter and owner of nature. Later, Sartre would say, "If man, such as existentialism conceives him, is undefinable, it is because he is, first, nothing."18 From this point on, the problem was posed and would give rise to two different interpretations of whether existentialism could be a humanism, as Sartre claimed, or if, as Heidegger believed, it leads to an antihumanism. ln 1946, Heidegger sent his Letter on Humanism to Jean Beaufret in which he clarified his the sis by cleaving the humanist interpretation of his thinking. Ek-sistence was not given to man like the Cartesian cogito, which is only a rationalist hyperbole to be reversed by the for- mula "1 am, therefore 1 think." Man was in an inextricable alienation: "Man, exiled from the truth of Being, goes in circles around himseH like a rational animal. "19 Rather than assuming its position as the shepherd of Being, being in the world has been lost in being. In the twentieth century, this is translated by a universal technologization and generalization of mod- ernity, the Ge-Stell, the setting into place of technology. As Heidegger saw it, man's fate was independent of himseH; he was not autonomous in his subjective faculties and could only be attentive to the voice of Being. In this regard, the philosopher and the poet were presented as those who succeeded in being most proximate to this being-there of Being, most often presented as an abyss. Being points to the human condition as being-toward-death, the first root from which the world of the mind arose. It thus displaced the point of view of the Cartesian cogito or of psychologism. No longer there where consciousness masters itseH, Being was to be found in the cogito's conditions of existence. Whence Heidegger's criticism of Sartre's effort to determine the conditions of the cogito. This archaeol- ogy revealed man to be inexorably decentered and subjected to a his- tory of which he is no longer the subject, but rather its object or its toy. Nietzschean-Heideggerian Roots 37 l The Primacy of Language In this que st for the beginnings of the thinkable, Nietzsche and Hei- degger both thought that language and its laws played a particularly important role. Language had lost its original purety because it had been diverted by the functionality of being. The philosophical or po- etic que st sought to complement this lack in or der to rediscover the meaning of the lost logos. Because being masked the conditions of its reality, Heidegger favored using linguistic interpretation as the privi- leged medium of the history of Being. "Heidegger gives the phenome- nological method the sense of an ontological hermeneutic."20 Language th us became the important object of study in a Heideg- gerian perspective. This clearly showed the fundamental roots of structuralism's generalization of the linguistic model to the entire range of the social sciences. Heidegger's influence was fruitful, but it was constructed at a distance from anything having to do with being. Moreover, his influence went unfelt for Charles Sanders Peirce's prag- matics as well as for the linguistic philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein or of John L. Austin. For Heidegger, who was unfamiliar with the work being done in pragmatics, man did not speak, language spoke, while man was spo- ken. Consequently, his approach was nominalist and fetishized the discursive since language differentiated hum ans from the vegetable and animal realms, a distinction and a burden. Similarly, Nietzsche's critique of metaphysics also decentered the cogito from language pre- sented in its "natural" rhetoric. Metaphoric and metonymic processes found a critique of unattainable truth, in place of which they offered the infinite interpretative labyrinth who se only value lay in the relativ- ity of their site of enunciation. "Rather has the world become 'infinite' for us aIl over aga in, inasmuch as we cannot reject the possibility that it may include infinite interpretations. "21 This new area of interpreta- tion had to avoid metaphysics, which was little more than an exagger- ated que st for a genesis and origins in order to establish a conti nuit y and causality around the unity of the subject. Nietzsche favored a de- constructive genealogy of the subject so as to decipher the conditions of belief systems based on what they occult or repress. This decon- struction aimed at unearthing the originary inscription of a primitive truth, which preceded its formulation; it sought every absolute that was supposed to bear the human being. 372 Nietzchean-Heideggerian Roots The Genealogical Program Nietzsche, like Heidegger, privileged language as disenfranchised from aIl subjection to the imperative of truth. "With his aphorisms, Nietz- sche establishes the return in force of censored and repressed e1e- ments, and puts them in perspective."22 This Nietzschean genealogy had to take another approach to temporality and to the re1ationship to truth. Presented as the point-by-point antithesis of the Platonic ap- proach, Nietzsche argued for the destructive use of reality rather than reminiscence/recognition, for the derealizing and dissociative use of identities against tradition, and for the destruction of truth in place of history-knowledge. "Genealogy is history as a concerted carnival."23 Access to truths thus became doubly inaccessible. On the one han d, truths were no more than c10uds of metaphors, metonymies, and an- thropomorphisms that we believe to be stable, simple exchange values whose use value has been forgotten. On the other hand, the fiction of the cogito became the targeted site of the illusion: "There is no one who is innocent enough to still raise the question of the subject 'l'as Descartes did, as the condition of 'think."'24 For Nietzsche, the cogito was the mode1 of metaphysical pronouncements and the hypostasis of the fictive subject whose polysemism he analyzed. The genealogy valorized the territory of the sign, which was to be retraced as an unveiling of a unitary, metaphysical discourse. The meaning was unsheathed behind the ever-denied textual opacity. Hav- ing deconstructed the carnival masks, it was necessary to reconstruct the unbroken signifying chains of successive interpretations; these chains are no longer proposed as continuo us, but on the contrary per- ceived as discontinuity, as symptoms, or as lacks. The genealogical ap- proach favored the underbelly of what is spoken, the hidden face of the signifieds. It defined a game of dis placement in order to disinvest and de-implicate the metaphysical content of the stratified layers of the signs. The genealogy sought to restore the conditions of discourse more than its contents. Both Nietzsche and Heidegger made this shift toward the discursive. The Nietzsche-Heidegger Program Once Again Heidegger's quest for logos and Nietzsche's genealogy converge here, and both nourished structuralist thinking. The critique of ethnocen- trism and of Eurocentrism intensified during the fifties and sixties with 1"< Roots 373 the structuralist vogue, which adopred Nietzschean-Heideggerian critical paradigm on its own; but behind the continuaI unfolding of triumphant reason lurked the image of the madman, of the savage, and of the child as so many repressed figures allowing reason to reign. Lvi-Strauss rehabilitated the savage mind; Jean Piaget looked at childhood no longer as the negative of adulthood, but understood as a specifie age; Foucault rediscovered the long drift of madness before its internment; as for Lacan, he truly pulverized the Subject, demonstrat- ing, contrary to the Cartesian cogito, that "1 think there where 1 am not, therefore 1 am there where 1 do.not think." In Thinking 68, Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut systematized the in- te11ectual structure of the sixties, even if they were mistaken in cor- relating May I968 and this inte11ectual cast of mind. 25 The major thrusts of Nietzschean-Heideggerian thinking are here: the theme of the end of philosophy, which Derrida developed in order to free think- ing from its captivity. He favored the writing of a pure trace, a mind "that does not mean anything," pure meaning freed from the signi- fied. Also present are the paradigm of the genealogy, or the problema- tization, of the external conditions of production of discourse, rather than the examination of their contents. And there is the idea of truth as the sole means of verifying the adequation between a discourse and its content, an idea that, along with the referent, which is radically cast to the sidelines, loses any foundation. Fina11y, we witness the his- toricization of categories and the end of any reference to a universal. To this systematization, elucidated by Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, must be added the disappearance of the name of the author and the meaning of his existence. The author is erased behind the laws of lan- guage, of which he is nothing more than one pole performing a com- position that does not belong to him. We once again find an attack on the subject and on the enunciation of discourse, and it led to a new de- finition of the literary text and of the work of the cri tic, who must shift his gaze from the author to the text as a closed system. Certainly, these shifts are atwork between Nietzschean-Heideggerian thinking and structuralism. Thus, Heidegger's antihumanism and that of structuralism, even if one may be heir to the other, are not rea11y of the same nature. The structuralist point of view refers huma ni sm to an episteme of the past and therefore finds a compe11ing epistemologi- cal justification, whereas Heideggerian antihumanism remains meta- physical in nature. "He hypostasizes Being to a11 dimensions of his- 374 Nietzchean-Heideggerian Roots tory."26 He produced a philosophy that, more than a conception of the end of history, was a conception of metahistory whose core was Being, a perspective that was not at aU shared by structuralism in its diverse manifestations. Foucault: "1 Am Simply Nietzschean" Foucault's ties to Nietzsche are obvious and overt: "1 am simply Nietz- schean."27 Foucault wrote within a Nietzschean scope and even used the same metaphor of an erased figure of man at the end of The Order of Things; he deconstructed the subject in the same way as Nietzsche had and substituted the project of a genealogy: "Everything is already interpretation. "28 Like Nietzsche, Foucault scoured the lower depths and exhumed what history had forgotten, deciphering the advance of a disciplinary society lying behind the progress of the Lumires, oc- culted by the predominance of a liberating legal-political discourse. Madness was repressed in this way by the very development of Reason, of a Western culture that was vacillating in the mid-twentieth century. Foucault was a brilliant student of Nietzschean thinking, and adopted the dissolution of the figure of man, perceived as a simple fleeting pas- sage between two modes of being of language: "More than the death of God, ... what Nietzsche's thinking presages is the end of his mur- derer, the explosion of the face of man. "29 And from this death of men, he also concluded the primacy of philology and of an examina- tion of discourse, already heralded by Nietzsche and readdressed by Mallarm. Hermeneutics became semiology when it infinitely interpreted in- terpretation, the sign having broken its moorings with the original sig- nified. Humanism had been erected on false foundations of lack and inexistence and was a form of consolation; the principal issue then be- came knowing why and under what conditions man conceives some- thing that will forever be situated outside of him. For Foucault, Nietzsche represented the first uprooting of anthro- pology, whose collapse indicated "the imminent death of man."30 Nietz- sche's genealogy also inspired work rooted in the historical present rather than in an impossible search for origins, so Foucault did not try to understand the continuities that proclaim by bespeaking our world, but rather pointed out the discontinuities, the shifting of the epistemes. Historical knowledge had to its credit the fact that it problematized, that it broke the constants and the consolatory game of recognition. NlItzs,ch,;an-!it;ldt;gg,en,m Roots 375" During the course of archaeology, Foucault was to pay particular attention to archives, to the document understood as a monument that let him retrace the fault Hnes and point out the singu- larity of events freed from any teleological finality. The fact that Fou- cault carried on a dialogue with historians, more often than not shot through with mutual incomprehension, and even went so far as to work with historians such as Michelle Perrot and Arlette Farge, that he was, during the last months of his life counseled by Paul Veyne, is not at aIl fortuitous but corresponded to Foucault's genealogical ap- proach. "The genealogist needs history in order to conjure away the chimera of the origin."31 Highlighting heterogeneity, deconstructing history, and working toward giving the myriad of lost events a sense by making them once again into events-such are the orientations of a Foucault who transported Nietzscheism onto historical terrain. To a lesser degree, we can also perceive Nietzsche's influence on Lvi-Strauss's work. Jean Duvignaud sees this particularly in Tristes Tropiques and in the "finale" of The Naked Man, where Lvi-Strauss's general vision bathes in a profound aestheticism that harks back to Nietzsche: "Aesthetics always emerges as soon as history is elimi- nated."32 Thus, structuralism's circula rit y in Lvi-Strauss, based on which myths refer to each other in a magnificent construction of logic, would refer to Nietzsche's eternal return. Citing Reason Heidegger's influence is even more obvious and widespread for the various components of structuralism. Foucault declared that "Heideg- ger was always the essential philosopher for me."33 Unlike Nietzsche, who was a constant reference, Heidegger's influence on Foucault was implicit, although Foucault quickly became familiar with the work of the German philosopher. Foucault's friend Maurice Pinguet de scribes his first encounter at Ulm with the young Michel Foucault, whom he heard intelligently holding forth in his metallic voice with sorne im- passioned friends about notions of Dasein and being-for-death. 34 Nothing more ordinary for a young ENS student in 1950, when Hei- deggerianism was the koine of every philosopher. But Heidegger is present in the work itself of Michel Foucault. In speaking of Kant in The Order of Things, Foucault employed the typically Heideggerian expression of the "analytics of finitude," according to which man discovers that he is "always already" in the N!etzcI1CaJt1-Hleldeggen21l1 Roots work and that it is therefore vain to look for "Removed fmm aH origins, he s already there."35 We also find Heidegger in Madness and Civilization, where "the entire theme of reason that only bec ornes reason by exclusion is typically Heideggerian." 36 The Archae%gy of Knowledge is an implicit debate with Heidegger's Letter on Human- ism. Similarly, the way of seeing a disciplinary society unfold behind the society of the Lumires in Discipline and Punish corresponds to Heidegger's inspection of reason and points to a fundamentally pes- simistic vision of the fate of Western society. Of course, the lessons to be drawn from this diagnosis went unassimilated; very few simi- larities exist in terms of praxis between commitment in the sense of the resistance to power as Foucault understood it and Heidegger's "commitment" ! ln Lvi-Strauss's case, Heidegger's influence was neither direct nor acknowledged, as it was for Foucault. And yet it is no less diffuse and present in Lvi-Strauss's profound skepticism with regard to moder- nit y, in his critique of global technologization, and in his denunciation of its destructive-and potentially genocidal-character. Questioning planetary homogenization and the suppression of differences is also part of the same sensibility. Lacan and Heidegger Heidegger's influence on Lacan was also quite clear. As lisabeth Roudinesco has pointed out, Lacan was fascinated by Heidegger's style, as indeed was the entire French postwar intelligentsia. The first meeting between the two took place in 1950, but it was above aIl thanks to Heidegger's French disciple, Jean Beaufret, who began an analysis with Lacan in 1946, that Lacan came to know Heidegger via the patient on his couch who became the very source of the diffu- sion of Heidegger in France. Indeed, Lacan and Jean Beaufret struck up a friendship, which made it easier for Heidegger's language to take mot. Lacan's first reference to Heidegger dates precisely from this pe- riod. In September 1946, at the Bonneval colloquium, Lacan gave his presentation "Regarding Psychic Causality." The allusion made it clear that Lacan had read Plato and the Doctrine of Truth, which Heideg- ger had pub li shed in 1941-42.37 Later, Lacan visited Heidegger in Freiburg. 38 Shortly thereafter, he translated the article entitled "Logos," submitted it to Heidegger, and then published it in the first issue of his Nietzschean-Heideggerian Raots 377 review La Psychanalyse in 1953. Lacan paid a resonant hornage to Heidegger on this occasion: "With respect to the presence here of Monsieur Heidegger, for aU those who know where the highest rnedi- tation in the world takes place, this presence alone guarantees that there is, at the very least, a manner of reading Freud that does not bear witness to a mind as cheap as one patent loyalist to phenomenol- ogy claims it to be."39 Despite his enthusiasm, Lacan did not translate more than four- fifths of the text, and he amputated the end in which Heidegger saw poetic writing as a means of escaping the drama of hum an existence. For Lacan, neither escape nor saivation were possible; he perceived no glimmering of Being. lisabeth Roudinesco tells of Heidegger's first trip to France, which, in that August of 1955, looked quite pic- turesque. He came to participate in the interviews at Cerisy-la-Salle organized by Jean Beaufret and Kostas Axelos. Lacan organized a small meeting at Guitrancourt in honor of the illustrious guest. Heidegger stayed at the Prvt, then visited the cathedral at Chartres. Lacan drove as fast as he ran his sessions. Sitting in the front seat, Heidegger did not budge or show any signs of nervous- ness, but his wife kept asking Lacan to drive more slowly. Sylvia ex- plained her worries to Lacan, but to no avail: the master drove faster and faster. On the way back, Heidegger remained silent and his wife's protests got louder, while Lacan kept his foot down on the accelerator. The trip came to an end and everyone went home. 40 Their relationship could have been warmer, obviously, but what counted was the conceptual borrowing beyond any direct communi- cation, which was made difficult by the fact that Heidegger considered that there was only one true language-German-which Lacan was able to translate but could not speak. Lacan took up Heidegger's notion of ek-sistence, the ide a that man is separated from any form of essence, and took inspiration from the distancing of Being with respect to being. Each time Lacan quoted Heidegger, it was to use the notion of ek-sistence as weIl as being-for- death. The Lacanian idea that a reallife is not a real life but a sym- bolic life "is an idea that is everywhere in Heidegger. It is even essen- tial to his philosophy. "41 Heidegger's influence on Lacan's paradigms is easily deciphered. Not only does one find there the fundamental pessirnism of Heidegger, man's decentering, the deconstruction of the subject that is split and letzchean-I-ielaeg;gerlan Roots forever inaccessible ta the long path of 1055, of the Forgetting of Being starting with the structuring experience of the Mirror Stage, but one can aiso find borrowings from Heidegger's vocabulary. Every- thing having ta do with the relationship to Truth, to authenticity, to full and empty speech stems from a Heideggerian approach trans- posed onto psychoanalytic terrain. AlI the commentary on Greek philosophy, on althia, is common to both. In Lacan's "Seminar on the Purloined Letter," the letter's circula rit y recalls the structuralist model and is, at the same time, supported by a whole Heideggerian concern for a site in which truth is unveiled, which is the very site of the letter, a site where it is not in its place. Thus Lacan, in the early fifties, was truly fascinated with Heidegger, a fascination that went unreciprocated, for Heidegger was always indifferent to Lacan's work. It is therefore impossible to agree that "Lacan was never a Heidegger- ian, "42 and to reduce what he borrowed to a simple matter of vocabu- lary, even if it is true that with respect to the problem of science, their positions were opposed. For what is most essential-that is, Heideg- ger's proposaI of a philosophy as a common language for aIl the social sciences-there is a legacy that goes much further than Lacan and Lacanian thought. Jacques Derrida and Heidegger Heidegger's influence was dearer on Jacques Derrida, despite what he has said since the "Farfas affair."43 Derrida considered the epithet "Heideggerian," to be dumsy and he rejected it. At the same time, he daimed that Lvi-Strauss, Althusser, and Foucault were never in- fluenced by Heidegger!44 And to support his thesis about the total absence of Heideggerian influence in France, Derrida recounted an anecdote going back to I967-68. Driving with Foucault one day, he asked why he never spoke about Heidegger. Foucault answered that it was both too important and too difficult, that Heidegger was beyond his grasp. But if we limit ourselves to Derrida's texts, Heidegger's omnipres- ence is not only obvious but explicit: "Nothing that 1 have tried to do would have been possible without the opening of Heideggerian ques- tions, ... without the attention to what Heidegger calls the difference between Being and being, the ontic-ontological difference such as it remains unthought in a certain fashion by philosophy."45 Of course Derrida did not servilely adopt or daim Heidegger's thinking as his Nietzschean-Heideggerian Roots 379 own, for his deconstruction also attacked the very knots of this think- ing and, as with Lacan, sought to radicalize its theses. For Derrida, the Ereignis, man as shepherd of Being, were vestiges in Heidegger of the debris of a humanism to be deconstructed. Der- rida's starting point, however, still remained the privilege Heidegger granted language as the medium of Being, and the transition from a philosophy of consciousness to one of language. Commentary held a similar fascination for Derrida. While participating in the general orientation of structuralism, he distinguished himself by criticizing in turn Claude Lvi-Strauss in On Grammatology, Michel Foucault in Writing and Differance, and Jacques Lacan in The Truth Factor. 46 We will return to his criticisms, which introduce us to the main echos of French Nietzschean-Heideggerianism, which adopted structuralism as its emblem in order to deploy the particularly diverse research po- tentialities in the entire field of knowledge of the social sciences. Thirty-eight Growing Pains To understand structuralism's success, we must do more than broadly paint its historical context and identify the philosophical positions to which the movement was heir. We must also describe the state and shape of the social sciences themselves during the period. For, con- trary to what much reductive thinking might imply, the history of each discipline was generally independent of the others and to the history leading to its creation. As Gilles Gaston-Granger put it, the life of con- cepts at this level is autonomous. We can shed sorne light on the social conditions surrounding the appearance and transformation of a com- mon theory like structuralism if we consider the interdisciplinary rub- bing of shoulders among researchers and teachers, and more generally in the intellectual world. The Intense Socialization of the Social Sciences This period of flourishing structuralist activity was also one during which the social sciences, and particularly those fighting for their place in the sun, were exp an ding in a spectacular way. These new so- cial sciences were in search of their legitimacy, but they also needed to win over a growing intellectual audience of the fifties and sixties. Their identity was forged around a rupture so that they could circum- vent established, traditional positions. The structuralist break pre- sented itself as a scientific revolution drawing numerous disciplines under its banner, and this intense socialization helped win the day. 3 80 Growing Pains 38 l The profoundly scientific and ideological aspects of the movement during this period cannot therefore be ignored, nor can the ideological aspects of its history, for this much-sought socialization led to an ideologization of structuralism's scientific discourse. The structural method does not sum up the history of structuralism. Indeed, we might even raise the question of whether "scientific revolutions are not, in fact, this intense socialization." 1 ln this respect, no science is protected against ideologization or socialization. As we know, physical observation implied purely ideo- logical issues during the time of Copernicus and Galileo; the transition from a geocentric vision of the universe to a heliocentric one gener- ated theological conflicts. Paul Rivet understood the necessity of so- cialization for the institutional success of French ethnology in its early years. Born during a period when colonial thinking had left its mark on this science, ethnology was steeped in ideology. Rivet saw that he could use the situation and reverse it to radically change the percep- tion of cultural and social alterity, and he deliberately used ethnology as an ideological weapon and a major element in the intellectual de- bates of the thirties, thereby facilitating its institutionalization. Eth- nology underwent a certain metamorphosis. From a conditioned disci- pline, it became a conditioning discipline, bearing with it an ethics and a policy of antiracism. Intense socialization and ideologization therefore corresponded to a mode of being in these newly armed sciences. Conceptually forceful, however, they were nonetheless disarmed on the level of institutional legitimacy. What was true for ethnology during the thirties was even more dramatically so for the sciences of the sign during the fifties and sixties, for they could profit from the support of the media, which was playing an increasing role in the intellectual field. The media were in fact taking over the debates of the sixties and placing the issues in the public arena. One could even hear the famous PicardJBarthes duel described as a new Dreyfus Affair. Sorne cons id- ered that the only tangible reality of structuralism was in fact this media hype and that once the media noise was eliminated, "struc- turalism no longer exists."2 ln the same way that the divergences and contradictions counted more among Descartes, Spinoza, Pascal, or Hobbes, the similarities among the structuralists stemmed from their contemporaneity, but their differences were more pertinent. Behind the facade of homogeneity, the conflicts and polemics that exercised 382 Growing Pains aIl the researchers were particularly lively. But media amplification was sought out of a concern for making the phenomenon better known, for recognition, and in a quest for intellectuallegitimacy. Maurice Godelier embodied another attempt at dissociating a form of thinking opposing science and ideology,3 by virtue of his radi- cal distip.ction between the structural method, based on pertinent, rig- orous, scientific analyses of kinship ties and mythic structures, for ex- ample, and structuralism, which belonged more to the realm of the ideological, to general speculative declarations about humanity, soci- ety, and the progress of thought. These were completely different for Godelier, even if researchers combined method and an ideological dimension. "My argument is that the structural analysis of myths, Claude Lvi-Strauss's method, does not at aIl imply his structuralism; he is the one who defined his method, not because his method is lim- ited but because he wanted to define it for other reasons."4 Science, ideology, socialization, mediatization-structuralism was aIl of these at once, like an entangled skein of yarn whose untangling depends on contextualizing certain moments, currents, issues, and their stakes. Philosophers Respond to the Challenge of the Social Sciences The taste for structuralism therefore corresponded to an intense so- cialization of the social sciences and to an explosion such that these became part of a veritable policy of development from the fifties onward. In 1958, for example, a new sociology Licence was created thanks to Raymond Aron's influence: sociology had made consider- able progress in establishing itself institutionally. More generally, those actors in the social sciences in full swing "did not look to philosophers' recognition; on the contrary, they sought to differentiate themselves ostentatiously."s We can appreciate structuralism's success in this respect as a response from philosophers to the challenge raised by the social sciences, which for the most part had come from the same philosophical house. Philosophers were shaken up by the com- petition from disciplines with more scientific and pragmatic ambitions and that were able to articulate concepts and fieldwork. They reacted by appropriating the program in order to consolidate and strengthen their position on the intellectual playing field. Philosophy witnessed the waning of two programs. Sartrean Growing Pains 383 existentialism, articulated around notion a tran- scendental, omnipotent, and completely abstract subject from which everything and aH meaning proceeded, was in complete disarray in the sixties and ran up on the shoals of history against which it had foundered: "One of the last models of the idealism of the French uni- versity."6 Structuralism, by virtue of the immobility of structures and the decentering, if not the extinction, of the subject, offered the means for reacting radically to those philosophers who wanted to mark their distance from this idealism. Sartre had inaugurated a new style of phi- losophy as a stake in a public debate, and this strongly contributed to his popularity during the postwar years and during the decade of the fifties. But he was the first victim of this new mode of relationship with a public that would elude him and be drawn to the structuralists, who turned against him the same weapons he had used to win pre- eminence for his philosophy. The economic situation, the end of the war in Aigeria, the dis engagement from political commitment, and a general disillusionment all contributed to the creation of a new style of intellectual. Sartre no longer incarnated this intellectual and he be- came the expia tory victim of the dtente. The second pro gram on the wane was phenomenology, from which the structuralists also dissociated themselves. Of course struc- turalism did adopt sorne phenomenologie al approaches-for exam- pIe, the priority of structures and of the search for meaning-so much so in fact that Jean Viet, the author of the first thesis on structuralism, saw phenomenology as a specifie tendency of structuralism.7 And yet, phenomenology remained a philosophy of consciousness and basically sought to describe phenomena. For Jacques Derrida, phenomenology remained enclosed in the "closure of representation," by maintaining the princip le of the subject: "Deconstructions replaced descriptions."8 The notion of deconstruction, which would orient aU of structuralist thinking, was first introduced by Derrida when he translated Heideg- ger's Destruktion, a term with neither negative nor positive connota- tions. "Deconstruction seeks to propose a theory of philosophical dis- course. Such a pro gram is manifestly critical."9 Born of the prote st against phenomenology, philosophical struc- turalism carried the critical paradigm to its zenith. It used phenome- nology as a way of opening up or rai ding the legacy of the field of in- vestigation of the social sciences. Most structuralists were trained 384 Growing Pains philosophers: Claude Lvi-Strauss, Pierre Bourdieu, Jacques Lacan, Louis Althusser, Jacques Derrida, Jean-Pierre Vernant. And yet, in search of something else, they had aIl broken with the traditional phi- losophy taught at the university. This was a philosophical generation intensely aware of the challenges of the social sciences and it broke with traditional university rhetoric. But in order to do so, it had to circumvent the traditional, legitimized institutional structures and di- rectly address the intelligentsia. This meant choosing new philosophi- cal objects with a specifically relevant and contemporary orientation, by articulating thinking with the social realm and institutions and ac- quiring a praxeological value. Moreover, for these philosophers, structuralism helped renew a discourse that had become more scientific and that offered them a de- fense against the social sciences. Pierre Bourdieu baptized this the "logy-effect,"lO when he observed the success of archaeology, gram- matology, and semiology. "Logy" evoked the scientific aspirations of speculative structuralism, which borrowed as much from mathemati- callogic as it did from linguistics in order to establish itself as a schol- arly pole in the history of science. Foucault described this fauIt line, which he emphasized and which transcended aIl other forms of opposi- tion: "This is what separates a philosophy of experience, meaning, and the subject from a philosophy of knowledge, rationality, and the con- cept. On the one hand, there is the line of Sartre and Merleau-Ponty, and on the other, of Cavaills, Bachelard, Koyr, and Canguilhem."l1 The social sciences appropriated a whole series of questions, and even the privilege of reflection of a philosophical nature. The philo- sophical avant-garde thus spearheaded a successful counteroffensive under the structuralist banner. Philosophy-open, renewed, carried along by its growing public-would emerge revitalized by the contest and markedly stronger by its growing batallion of teachers: the num- ber of high-school philosophy jobs rose from 905 in I960 to I,3 II in I965 and I,673 in I970.12 The number of postsecondary teaching jobs rose from I24 in I963 to 267 in I967. The gurus of structuralism wanted to assimilate the social sci- ences. They nonetheless criticized their model of positivity and crossed swords with them. Structuralist philosophers increased their virulent attacks on the scientistic pretensions of the social sciences: Lacan against psychology, Althusser against history, and Foucault against the methods of classification in the social sciences. A veritable Growing Pains 385 barrage flre was opened up against the ostensible imposture of the social sciences and their scientiflc certitudes. The structuralists un- leashed an epistemological critique against them, fueled by the work of Gaston Bachelard and Georges Canguilhem. tienne Balibar described this successful turn quite well. The so- cial sciences, purifled by the structuralist critique, sought their positiv- ity in the models and concepts that philosophers had developed. "Thus the text 1 contributed to Reading Capital (1965) seduced an- thropologists and a few historians because 1 was constructing a con- cept of the mode of production and they found it operational." 13 Structuralism could maintain the primacy of this renovated philoso- phy-based on a "formula of compromise"14 between a redeflnition that added a dimension of dynamism, which was critical of humanism and led to radical rupture, and the preservation of the elevated status of the philosophical discipline, despite the frequent reference to the end of philosophy that seemed to mask the phenomenon-by privileg- ing an essentially conceptual and theoretical disco ur se and by casting the borders and divisions among the rising social sciences into sorne degree of uncertainty and confusion. As Louis Pinto pointed out, this was the concern that made Foucault's use of the term "archaeology" able to satisfy the double requirement of proposing a historical dis- course about the social sciences, but that would make it possible to consider them philosophically, which is to say, differendy and better than they could conceive themselves on their own. 15 ln this respect, the philosophical avant-garde fully responded to the challenge of the social sciences and even favored their expansion during the sixties. At the same time, it preserved philosophy's presti- gious place as the "crowning discipline" among the disciplines. Phi- losophy remained at the zenith of the high-school curriculum, and particularly in the institutions where the national elite was shaped: khgne and the coles Normales Suprieures. Philosophy withstood the offensive rather well. Witness the assurance with that Louis Al- thusser rejected the "so-called social sciences" as an anathema that "cannot be explained without referring to their weakened institu- tional (and often intellectual) state in the flfties." 16 The batde of the humanities with respect to the social sciences at this level reiterated the joust between the ENS and the ENA in shaping the national elite, between a classical elite and the new, technocratic elite. 386 Growing Pains Emancipation from History Structuralism did not limit itself to attacking academic philosophy. It also attacked history, that other ancient and well-ensconced canonical discipline certai.n of its positions and methods. This destablization not only of the university discipline but of historicity in general was another characteristic trait of structuralism. War was declared against histori- cism, the historical context, the search for origins, diachrony, teleology and the argument made in favor of permanent invariables, synchrony, and the hermetic text. The Annales school took up the challenge. In 1958, Fernand Braudel favored the longue dure and temporal triparti- tion as the common language of aIl the social sciences under history's baton. At the end of the sixties, the third generation of the Annales de- constructed a fractured and anthropologized history,17 Structuralist lit- erary criticism or semiology began to define itself by repudiating his- tory. Of course it had to cut itself off from traditional, academic literary history of the man and the work, but in its concern for formalization, semiology went quite far in negating any historical elucidation, and thus cut itself off from any psychological or historical referent. Historians, including those who were most open to dialogue with the other social sciences, could not help but feel challenged by struc- turalism. They reacted by attending to the study of socioeconomic structures, cycles, and repeated phenomena, which had already been part of their own program. But they could not calI themselves struc- turalists for the antinomy would have been too marked. There was therefore a profound desire for emancipation with respect to history, pushed to the absurd negation of any historical foundation. Michelle Perrot, a professor at Paris VII who was at the very summit of mod- ernism in history, gave a seminar at the time with colleagues in litera- ture who turned the seminar into a dead end. Perrot thought that she was taking a step toward interdisciplinary progress, but the attacks against aIl reference to any kind of historical context whatsoever gave her "the feeling of being completely out of date." Indeed, for those partisans of new literary criticism, "the very word 'context' made them jump-it was spurned. We had to stay with the closed text, which made conversation very difficult. "18 Antiacademicism This determination to have it out with the canonized disciplines- traditional philosophy, history, psychology-was part of a larger con- Growing Pains 387 text of antiacademic revoit. This was the means for the philo- sophical avant-garde or for the young sciences of the sign to make a place for themselves within the institution. For most of the adherents of structuralism, their status was in fact precarious. Innovation came essentially from those institutions considered marginal at the time, such as the Sixth Section of the EPHE, or even the Collge de France. While considered the high point of intellectual legitimation, these institutions were nonetheless at the margins of the university, the principal teaching and research structure. The paths of the structuralists were, in this respect, significant be- cause they essentially took place outside the university. This was true for Lvi-Strauss among others, as he freely admitted: "It was therefore an active university career whose most striking characteristic is doubt- less that it always took place outside the university per se."19 The same was true for Barthes, Greimas, Althusser, Dumzil, Todorov, and Lacan. Considering the courses given at the Sorbonne in 1967, one notices with no small surprise that the linguistics courses were given by linguistics professors who, with the exception of Andr Martinet, were entirely different from those who are well known today. "In 1967, there was not even any linguistics department at the Sorbonne, but only a simple Institut de Linguistique .... When 1 was a high- school teacher doing my thesis in linguistics, 1 was planning to be un- employed since what 1 was doing was absolutely useless. "20 The weight of tradition and the recalcitrant conservatism of the venerable Sorbonne kept the French university system closed to new influences. Its immobility in turn helped to fan the revolt and the necessary rupture. In order to make a place for themselves, the sci- ences of the sign had to get beyond the institution and find massive and effective support. Structuralism made it possible to federate the avant-gardes of different disciplines and to transform the revolt into a revolution. This was the context in which references to Nietzsche, Marx, and Saussure became operational as true arms of an antiacademic critique of those partisans of a university and mandarin orthodoxy. The struc- turalists in fact adopted an older program in order to make it relevant and current. They were determined to bring areas that obeyed specifie rationalities into the realm of the sciences of man, an idea that went back to Auguste Comte. Structuralism's other main paradigm held that the objective rela- 388 Growing Pains tionships between isolated elements are important rather than any particular elements without the interference of consciousness, the idea of a lag between behavior and consciousness; this view of things had already been clearly proclaimed by Durkheimians and Hegelians. What was new.was that a program rather than its contents became a reality, as well as the speed with which this program was applied and produced tangible scientific results. Linguistics: A Common Program Structurallinguistics provided a method and a common language for bringing about a scientific renewal of the social sciences. Linguistics appeared as the model for a whole series of sciences lacking in formal- ism, and it penetrated ever more deeply into anthropology, literary criticism, and psychoanalysis and profoundly changed the mode of philosophical questioning. And yet, a certain number of social sci- ences remained essentially removed from this dramatic change, or were simply only marginally affected by the debate; it did not shake their fundamental positivism. Psychology at this point was developing systems of modeling and scientific structures free of metaphysical problems, and the situation in economics was essentially the same. Linguistic contagion had affected disciplines in precarious institu- tional positions or those in search of an identity because of the inter- naI contradictions between pretensions to scientific positivity and a link with the political arena, as was the case with sociology. Finally, there were those disciplines, like literary studies or philosophy, that were fully caught up in a quarrel between the ancients and the mod- ems. These circumstances contributed to the weakening of discipli- nary boundaries and structuralism appeared as the unifying project: "At the end of the sixties, it appeared necessary to unify the diverse at- tempts at renewing the human sciences into a single current or even into a single discipline that was more general than linguistics. "21 Roland Barthes and Umberto Eco expressed the temptation even more clearly by agreeing to propose a general semiology that could confed- erate the human sciences around the study of the sign. Modemization was therefore joined with interdisciplinarity. It was necessary to violate the sacrosanct boundaries so that the linguistic model could penetrate the entire field of the social sciences. From the moment when everything has to do with language and we are aH made of language in a world that is language, "everything becomes inter- Growing Pains 89 convertible, everything. This interdisciplinarity, which put the brakes on Humboldt's mode! of a university in which each discipline had its place within strict limits, created a veritable taste for aU the variants of formalism, for knowl- edge that was immanent to itself. The password of the period was communication. Beyond the review of the same name, the term con- veyed this multidisciplinary euphoria. A Unitary Science Just after the war, Lvi-Strauss was the first to formulate this unifying program in the social sciences. Of course his constellation gravitated around social anthropology, which he represented, the sole discipline deemed capable of carrying out this totalizing undertaking. For Lvi- Strauss, anthropology's particular vocation came from its ability to position itself at the crossroads between the natural sciences and the social sciences. Consequently, anthropology "does not abandon the hope of one day awakening among the natural sciences, at the hour of the Last Judgment."23 To construct his anthropology, Lvi-Strauss drew inspiration and a certain number of logical-mathematical models or operational tech- niques from the natural and exact sciences. He aspired to erase the frontier between the natural sciences and the social sciences thanks to scientific rigor. Encouraged by his fruitful meeting during the war in the United States with Jakobson, Lvi-Strauss gave the linguistic model a certain pride of place in his anthropological approach. In his search for invariants, in his paradigmatic and syntagmatic deconstruc- tions, he adopted the lessons of Jakobson's phonology: binary opposi- tions, differential divergence, and so on. Linguistics, thanks to Jakob- son, further enriched a particularly rich area of knowledge. If, thanks to the priority given to language and to deciphering signs, Lvi-Strauss oriented anthropology toward culture, the aspiration of unity was by no means left along the wayside. His quest for enceintes mentales also implied biology, a discipline that was absolutely fundamental in struc- tural anthropology even if it was not truly exploited. Structural analy- sis found that "its model is already present in the body, 1 have already mentioned . . . the exhaustive research that has been done on the mechanism of visu al perception in various animais. "24 "Instead of opposing ide al and real, abstract and concrete, 'emic' and 'etic,' one will recognize that the immediate data of perception cannot be re- 390 Growing Pains duced to any of these terms but lies betwixt and between: that is, already encoded by the sense organs as weIl as by the brain, in the manner of a text."25 In aspiring to a totality, Lvi-Strauss was adopting Marcel Mauss's goal o ~ constructing a "total social fact." He therefore sought to embrace the full scientific arena and finally to make structural an- thropology the science of man, a discipline federating those sciences on the basis of logico-mathematical models, strengthened by the con- tribution of phonology and by a boundless realm of investigation that took in, in a single glance and over the face of the planet, societies without history or writing. The anthropologist could therefore reach the unconscious dimen- sion of social practices and could restore the complex combinations of rules operating in aIl human societies. We can understand how such aspirations could vex aIl those sciences that take man as their primary object, and how it provoked a number of reactions from other disci- plines--competition from sorne and support to the dynamic conqueror from others, in order to win sorne degree of legitimacy for themselves. Defined this way, the goal was equivalent to the difficulty anthropol- ogy had encountered early on in positioning itself institutionally: Newly established sciences find difficulty in inserting themselves into traditional structures. It can never be sufficiently emphasized that an- thropology is by far the youngest of these young sciences (the social sciences) and that the general solutions appropriate to its eiders have what is, for it, an already traditional aspect. It has, as it were, its feet planted on the natural sciences, its back resting against the humanis- tic sciences and its eyes directed toward the social sciences. 26 If anthropology did not manage to dig out the human sciences entirely on its own, structuralism took up the relay. It was in fact the common paradigm, for want of being a common school, for a whole series of disciplines aIl working toward the same end of establishing a total unified science. A French Phenomenon The structuralist blaze was essentially a French phenomenon that radiated outward from France. The Anglo-Saxon world grouped the many works that made the structuralist moment famous under the general category of French Criticism. Why, more than elsewhere, was France a better soil in which structuralism could take root and flour- Growing Pains 39I We can suggest a few answers. First of aH, the weight the hu- manities in France blocked the social sciences within the French uni- versity, contrary to the situation in American universities, where they were triumphing. The philosophical avant-garde in France reacted to the growth of the social sciences by appropriating the structuralist pro gram, making it possible for the renovated humanities to triumph in the quarrel between tradition and modernity. What's more, the joust between the partisans of tradition and those of modernism was also a typically French phenomenon, which merely replayed the de- bates of the early century between the "new" and the "ancient" Sor- bonne. The weight of the humanities also enabled the French intel- lectual to speak in the name of humanity and to be engaged as a spokesperson in a context that did not call on a specific expertise. Another tradition existed that went back largely to the eighteenth century, but that was expanded during the nineteenth century with the Dreyfus Affair, and incarnated during the twentieth century by Jean- Paul Sartre. Even if structura li sm took its distance from Sartre and the figure of the committed intellectual, it would amply use the practice of circumventing structures in or der to directly address and persuade the readers and the public of its theses and short-circuit its peers. Con- versely, in the United States, the university professor is evaluated in dollars and "has no particular right to speak in the na me of human- ity. "27 Similiarly in Germany, few university professors were involved in a media network where it was possible to make a breakthrough, as was the case in Canada for Marshall McLuhan, although the univer- sity made him pay for it dearly. In France, the university grip on its own autonomy was weaken- ing because there were other possibilities of institutional consecration. Underlying the theoretical debates were issues of power represented by the new ambitions of the young social sciences facing the mo- nopoly of the traditional humanities. We once aga in find the specifi- cally French situation of a highly centralized and routinized university, an old Napoleonic legacy, unchanged during the fifties and sixties. The weight of the humanities is also revealed by the central position of an institution like the cole Normale Suprieure on the rue d'Ulm in elaborating the structural paradigm; where the major reviews of the period-Les Cahiers pour l'analyse and the Cahiers marxistes- lninistes-were created and produced there. And Althusser, Derrida, and Lacan were at Ulm. 392 Growing Pains Another given of the that went beyond the university was the relationship between French intellectuals and the history of their own country. Suddenly they became aware, in a decolonized and paci- fied France, that they no longer lived in the country that had presented itself as the gui9ing light of huma nit y since 1789- France was no longer a great power but sim ply a mode st part of a plural Europe. As Franois Furet saw so clearly, the French intellectual, "despite the Gaullist rhetoric, no longer has the feeling of making human history. That France, the one that is expelled from history, accepts all the more easily the expulsion of history."28 Jean Duvignaud confirmed this. He saw the French specificity of the success of structuralism as "a flight from history. "29 Coming together in France and speaking among themselves gave intellectuals the need to fortify an ideology able to create a reassuring cohesion and new aspirations. "There we have the search for an order, practically in the chivalrous, initiative meaning of the word." 30 This would contribute to the radical destabilization of history and thus to the success of structuralism on French soil. In addition, and conversely, there was an element that pointed to the preeminence of the antimodern spiritualist tradition among French intellectuals, a tra- dition strengthened by the dominance of philosophy constructed, if not against science, then at least removed from it and subordinating it, "which amounts to this incredible thing where we see Althusser giving lessons in scientificity to scientists. "31 Marcel Gauchet found in the in- tellectual community's expression of antimodernism the old opposi- tion between the spirit and industry, between art and the horrors of a civilization of the masses, an old, recurrent theme of French intellec- tuaI history. Thomas Pavel offered other views on why France was the favored land for structuralism. He explained the phenomenon through the in- ternaI logic of the development of epistemology in France. The taste for structuralism, he claimed, resulted from France's considerable tar- diness with respect to its European neighbors. France remained so re- moved from the debates on language of the early twentieth century and unaware of the Vienna school (Rudolf Carnap, Otto Neurath, Herbert Feigl, Karl Popper) in the thirties that at the moment when this school went into exile because of the rise of Nazism, the diaspora found refuge in the Anglo-Saxon countries, essentially the United States. France's epistemological removal was clear and even further Growing Pains 393 underscored by the tact that it was ignored as a possible place refuge. "The work of Claude Lvi-Strauss, of the early Barthes, and of Lacan in part represented a deferred-and aH the more visible- explosion in France of the hidden debate on language and the episte- mology of knowledge. "32 After Lvi-Strauss, who had assimilated linguistics as a model for building structural anthropology, the avant- garde philosophers, eut off from the analytic current, also hurried to adopt the linguistic model, but without any epistemological pre- caution, by appropriating a Saussurean linguistics that was already outmoded by the advances of analytical philosophy. The intensity of Parisian life that made it possible to short-circuit the tradition al university and institution al networks also assured a swift diffusion of the structuralist paradigm on the French cultural market. Its adherents were transformed into media stars, the new gurus of a public that had broadened thanks to the spectacular rise in the number of students in letters and social sciences during the sixties. It was thus beneath the tricolor flag of France, and of France alone, that structuralism would flourish and fascinate other countries. But it was always a specifically French product that we indulged in because of our need for exoticism. Appendix: List of Interviewees (Parisian universities are listed as Paris 1 through Paris X.) Marc Abls, anthropologist, researcher at the Laboratoire d'Anthro- pologie Sociale, EHESS. Alfred Adler, anthropologist, researcher at the Laboratoire d'Anthro- pologie Sociale, EHESS. Michel Aglietta, economist, professor of economy at Paris X. Jean Allouch, psychoanalyst, director of the journal Littoral. Pierre Ansart, sociology professor at Paris VIL Michel Arriv, linguistics professor at Paris X. Marc Aug, anthropologist, director of studies at the EHESS, presi- dent of the EHESS. Sylvain Auroux, philosopher and linguist, director of research at the CNRS. Kostas Axelos, philosopher, former editor in chief of the journal Argu- ments, teaches at the Sorbonne. Georges Balandier, anthropologist, professor at the Sorbonne, director of studies at the EHESS. tienne Balibar, philosopher, lecturer at Paris 1. Henri Bartoli, economist, professor at Paris 1. Michel Beaud, economist, professor at Paris VIII. Daniel Becquemont, anthropologist and professor of English at the Universit de Lille. 395 396 Appendix: List ofInterviewees Jean-Marie Benoist, philosopher, assistant director to the History of Modern Civilization chair at the Collge de France, deceased in I990. Alain Boissinot, literature professor, teaches advanced classes at Louis- le-Grand High School. Raymond Boudon, sociologist, professor at Paris IV, director of the Groupe d'tudes des Mthodes de l'Analyse Sociologique (GEMAS). Jacques Bouveresse, philosopher, professor at Paris 1. Claude Brmond, linguist, director of studies at the EHESS. Hubert Brochier, economist, professor at Paris 1. Louis-Jean Calvet, linguist, professor at the Sorbonne. Jean-Claude Chevalier, linguist, professor at Paris VII, general director of the journal Langue franaise. Jean Clavreul, psychoanalyst. Claude Cont, psychoanalyst, former head of the clinic at the Paris Medical School. Jean-Claude Coquet, linguist, professor at Paris VIII. Maria Daraki, historian, professor at Paris VIII. Jean-Toussaint Desanti, philosopher, taught at Paris 1 and at the cole Normale Suprieure in Saint-Cloud. Philippe Descola, anthropologist, associate director of the Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale. Vincent Descombes, philosopher, professor atJohns Hopkins University. Jean-Marie Domenach, philosopher, former director of the journal Es- prit, founder of the CREA. Jol Dor, psychoanalyst, director of the journal Esquisses psychanaly- tiques, professor at Paris VII. Daniel Dory, geographer, researcher at the CNRS and at Paris 1. Roger-Pol Droit, philosopher, editorialist at Le Monde. Jean Dubois, linguist, professor at Paris X, on the editorial board of the journal Langages. Georges Duby, historian, professor at the Collge de France. Oswald Ducrot, linguist, director of studies at the EHESS. Claude Dumzil, psychoanalyst. Jean Duvignaud, sociologist, professor at Paris VII. Roger Establet, sociologist, member of the CERCOM (EHESS). Franois Ewald, philosopher, president of the Association for the Michel Foucault Center. ' f ' f " ~ U U ' A . List of Interviewees 3 9 Arlette Farge, director of research at the EHESS. Jean-Pierre philosopher, linguist, professor at the Universit Phi- losophique Europenne. Pierre Fougeyrollas, sociology professor at Paris VII. Franoise Gadet, linguistics professor at Paris X. Gilles Gaston-Granger, philosopher, professor at the Collge de France. Marcel Gauchet, historian, editor in chief of the journal Le Dbat. Grard Genette, linguist, semiologist, director of studies at the EHESS. Jean-Christophe Goddard, philosopher, professor for Hautes tudes Commerciales prepara tory courses. Maurice Godelier, anthropologist, scientific director at the CNRS, di- rector of studies at the EHESS. Wladimir Granoff, psychoanalyst, head physician at the medical- psychology center in Nanterre. Andr Green, psychoanalyst, former head of the Institut de Psych- analyse in Paris. Aigirdas Julien Greimas, linguist, honorary director of studies at the EHESS. Marc Guillaume, economist, professor at the Universit Paris-Dauphine, lecturer at the cole Polytechnique, director of the journal IRIS. Claude Hagge, linguist, professor at the Collge de France. Philippe Hamon, linguist, professor at Paris III. Andr-Georges Haudricourt, anthropologist and linguist. Louis Hay, literature professor, researcher at the CNRS. Paul Henry, linguist, researcher at the CNRS. Franoise Hritier-Aug, anthropologist, professor at the Collge de France, head of the Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale. Jacques Hoarau, philosopher, professor at the Centre de Formation des Professeurs in Molignon. Michel Izard, anthropologist, director of research at the CNRS, co- direct or of the journal Gradhiva. Jean-Luc Jamard, anthropologist, researcher at the CNRS. Jean Jamin, anthropologist, researcher at the ethnology laboratory of the Muse de l'Homme, codirector of the journal Gradhiva. Julia Kristeva, linguist, professor at Paris VII. Bernard Laks, linguist, researcher at the CNRS. Jrme Lallement, economist, lecturer at Paris 1. Jean Laplanche, psychoanalyst, professor at Paris VII, director of the journal Psychanalyse l'Universit. 398 Appendix: List of Interviewees Francine Le Bret, philosopher, professor at Jacques Prvert High School in Boulougne-Billancourt. Serge Leclaire, psychoanalyst. Dominique Lecourt, philosophy professor at Paris VII. Henri Lefebvre, philosopher, former professor in the Universities of Strasbourg, Nanterre, and Paris VIII. Pierre Legendre, philosopher, professor at Paris 1. Gennie Lemoine, psychoanalyst. Claude Lvi-Strauss, anthropologist, professor at the Collge de France. Jacques Lvy, geographer, researcher at the CNRS, codirector of the journal Espaces-Temps. Alain Lipietz, economist, associate researcher at the CNRS and at the CEPREMAP. Ren Lourau, sociology professor at Paris VIII. Pierre Macherey, philosopher, lecturer at Paris 1. Ren Major, psychoanalyst, teaches at the Collge International de Philosophie, director of Cahiers Confrontations. Serge Martin, philosopher, professor at Pontoise High School. Andr Martinet, linguist, emeritus professor at the Universit Ren Descartes, and in the Fourth Section of the EPHE. Claude Meillassoux, anthropologist, director of research at the CNRS. Charles Melman, psychoanalyst, director of the journal Discours psychanalytique. Grard Mendel, psychoanalyst, former intern at the Hpital Psychia- trique de la Seine. Henri Mitterand, linguist, professor at the new Sorbonne. Juan-David Nasio, psychoanalyst, leads the Sminaire de Psychanalyse de Paris. Andr Nicola, economist, professor at Paris X. Pierre Nora, historian, director of studies at the EHESS, director of the journal Le Dbat, editor at Gallimard. Claudine Normand, linguist, professor at Paris X. Bertrand Ogilvie, philosopher, professor at the cole Normale at Cergy-Pontoise (as of I992, cole Normale schools, which are teacher-training institutions, have become the Institut Universi- taire de la Formation des Matres). Michelle Perrot, historian, professor at Paris VII. Marcelin Pleynet, writer, former secretary of the journal Tel Quel. Appendix: List of Interviewees 399 Jean Pouillon, philosopher and anthropologist, researcher at the Lab- oratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, EHESS. Jolle Proust, philosopher, research group on cognition, CNRS. Jacques Rancire, philosopher, teacher at Paris VIII. Alain Renaut, philosopher, professor at the Universit de Caen, founder of the Collge de Philosophie. Olivier Revault d'Allonnes, philosopher, professor at Paris 1. lisabeth Roudinesco, writer and psychoanalyst. Nicolas Ruwet, linguist, professor at Paris VIII. Moustafa Safouan, psychoanalyst. Georges-Elia Sarfati, linguist, teacher at Paris III. Bernard Sichre, philosopher, professor at the Universit de Caen, for- mer member of the team of Tel Quel. Dan Sperber, anthropologist, researcher at the CNRS. Joseph Sumpf, sociologist and linguist, professor at Paris VIII. Emmanuel Terray, anthropologist, director of studies at the EHESS. Tzvetan Todorov, linguist, semiologist, researcher at the CNRS. Alain Touraine, sociologist, director of research at the EHESS. Paul Valadier, philosopher, former editor in chief of the journal tudes, professor at the Centre Svres in Paris. Jean-Pierre Vernant, classicist, honorary professor at the Collge de France. Marc Vernet, semiologist of cinema, professor at Paris III. Serge Viderman, psychoanalyst, medical doctor. Pierre Vilar, historian, honorary professor at the Sorbonne. Franois Wahl, philosopher, editor at Seuil. Marina Yaguello, linguistics professor at Paris VII. Notes One. The Eclipse of a Star: Jean-Paul Sartre 1. Khgne, preceded by hypokhgne (from the Latin for lazy), are the two arduous years of prepara tory courses following but taking place in a high schoo\. These are pri- marily humanities courses designed for selected students hoping to pass the entrance exams to the cole Normale Suprieure (ENS).-Trans. 2. Pascal Ory and Jean-Franois Sirinelli, Les Intellectuels en France, de l'affaire Dreyfus nos jours, p. 166. 3. Billancourt is a southwestern, largely working-class Parisian suburb where the Renault factories were located. For Sartre, it was important that the working class not imagine that it was being forgotten or ignored.-Trans. 4. Les Temps modernes, no. 89 (April 1953), "Le marxisme de Sartre," by Claude Lefort; "Rponse Claude Lefort," by Jean-Paul Sartre. 5. Annie Cohen-Solal, Sartre, p. 447. 6. Rgis Debray, Le Nouvel Observateur, April 21, 1980. 7. Normal Schools were established by the Third Republic to train teachers for the newly instituted secular schools. Normal Superior was reserved for the elite students, se- lected, as they are today, by arduous competitive examination. Students are admitted for four years of subsidized training, in exchange for which they are assigned to teach in French high schools. The ENS on the rue d'Ulm, located in the Parisian Latin Quarter, was reserved for men (the women's branch is located in Saint-Cloud, a southwestern suburb of Paris) and renowned for the intellectual quality of its teachers and students.-Trans. 8. The tide of agrg was created in 1808 when the imperial university was orga- nized. At the time, it designated an associate high-school professor. An examination, ag- gregating several parts, was established in 1821 and was designed to recruit professors for high schools. It was only in 1883 that women were admitted to the agrgation exam. There are currendy twelve subject matters in which one can be agrg.-Trans. 9. Jean Pouillon, interview with the author. 10. Les Temps modernes, no. 126 (July 1956); reprinted in Jean Pouillon, Ftiches sans ftichisme, 1975. 11. Pouillon, Ftiches sans ftichisme, p. 301. 4 0r 402 Notes ta Chapter Twa 12. Ibid., p. }07. 13. Ibid., p. 312. 14. The cole Pratique des Hautes tudes was created Victor Duruy during the Second Empire, as a rather experimental research institution that was not a diploma- granting institution. A number of sections were created according to themes. The Fifth Section was that of Religious Sciences and was created by Lvi-Strauss. The section that is most important for the history of structura li sm was the Sixth Section with its theme of the social or human sciences. The first section president was the representative of the Annales, Lucien Febvre. The Sixth Section of the cole Pratique became the cole des Hautes tudes en Sciences Sociales (EHESSJ in I977, at a time during which this institu- tion, which was marginal until that point, was allowed to grant recognized diplomas. At this point, the margins converged toward the center, the Sorbonne.-Trans. 15. Jean Pouillon, Sminaire de Michel Izard, Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, November 24, I988. 16. Jean Pouillon, interview with the author. 17. Pouillon, quoted by Cohen-Solal, Sartre, p. 502. 18. Pouillon, Sminaire de Michel Izard, Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, Feb- ruary 9, I989 19. Ibid. 20. Georges Balandier, interview with the author. 21. Georges Dumzil, Entretiens avec Didier ribon, p. 204. 22. Ibid., p. 208. 23. Claude Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. 2I9. Two. The Birth of a Hero: Claude Lvi-Strauss 1. Claude Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. l 5. 2. Ibid., p. I9. 3. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Le Monde, interview with Jean-Marie Benoist, January 2I, I979 4. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Tristes Tropiques, p. I8. S. Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. 47. 6. Ibid., p. 64. 7. Ibid., p. 8I. 8. Francine Le Bret, interview with the author. 9. Raymond Boudon, interview with the author. 10. Ibid. 11. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Le Regard loign; translated as The View from Afar, p. I03. 12. mile Durkheim, "La prohibition de l'inceste," L'Anne sociologique, vol. I, I848. 13. Lvi-Strauss, Tristes Tropiques, p. 57. 14. Ibid. 15. Claude Lvi-Strauss, La Pense sauvage, p. I55; translated as The Savage Mind. 16. The forerunner of the French Socialist Party. 17. Philippe Descola, interview with the author. 18. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, p. I4. 19. A. R. Radcliffe-Brown, "The Study of Kinship Systems," Journal of the Royal Anthropology Institute (I94IJ: p. I7. 20. Lvi-Strauss, Tristes Tropiques, p. 59. 21. Robert H. Lowie, "Exogamy and the Classificatory Systems of Relationship," American Anthropologist, vol. I7 (April-June I9 I 5 J. 22. Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. 58. 23. Jean Jamin, interview with the author. Notes ta Chapter Four 403 24. Claude Lvi-Strauss, structurale en et en anthropologie," Ward, vol. l, no. 2 (1945): pp. 1-21; reprinted as "Linguistique et anthropologie," Supplement ta the International Journal of American Linguistics, vol. I9, no. 2 (April I953); reprinted as "Linguistics and Anthropology" in Structural Anthropology. Three. Where Nature and Culture Meet: Incest 1. Claude Lvi-Strauss, La Vie familiale et sociale des Indiens Nambikwara (Paris: Socit des Amricanistes, I948); The Elementary Structures of Kinship, preface ta the first edition, p. xxiii. 2. Marc Aug, interview with the author. 3. Olivier Revault d'Allonnes, interview with the author. 4. Emmanuel Terray, interview with the author. 5. Lvi-Strauss, The Elementary Structures of Kinship, preface ta the first edi- tion, p. ix. 6. Dan Sperber, Qu'est-ce que le structuralisme? Le structuralisme en anthropolo- gie, p. 26. 7. Lvi-Strauss, The Elementary Structures of Kinship, p. 30. 8. Ibid., p. I4. 9. Jean-Marie Benoist, La Rvolution structurale, p. II2. 10. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, pp. 3I-32. 11. Claude Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. 63. 12. Lvi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, p. 32. 13. Roman Jakobson, Six leons sur le son et le sens (Paris: Minuit, I976), preface by Claude Lvi-Strauss; reprinted in Le Regard loign, "Les leons de la linguistique" (Paris: Plon, I983). 14. Nicolai Trubetzkoy, "La phonologie actuelle," Psychologie du langage (Paris: I933), p. 243; quoted by Lvi-Strauss in Structural Anthropology, p. 3I n. 8. 15. Yvan Simonis, Lvi-Strauss ou la passion de l'inceste, p. I9. 16. Lvi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, p. 68. 17. Ibid., p. 82. 18. Ibid., p. 46. 19. Ibid., p. 62. 20. Jean Pouillon, interview with the author. 21. Raymond Boudon, interview with the author. 22. Jean Pouillon, interview with the author. 23. Simone de Beauvoir, Les Temps modernes (November I949): p. 943. 24. Ibid., p. 949. 25. Claude Lefort, 'Tchange et la lutte des hommes," Les Temps modernes (Febru- ary I951). 26. Jean Pouillon, "l}uvre de Claude Lvi-Strauss," Les Temps modernes, no. I26 (July I9 56); reprinted in Jean Pouillon, Ftiches sans ftichisme, p. 310. Four. Ask for the Program: The Mauss 1. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Introduction l'uvre de Marcel Mauss," in Marcel Mauss, Sociologie et anthropologie, I968 (I950); translated as Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss. 2. Claude Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. I03. 3. Aigirdas Julien Greimas, interview with the author. 4. Jean Jamin, interview with the author. 404 Notes to Chapter Six 5. Ibid. 6. Robert Hertz, Mlanges de sociologie religieuse et folklore, I928. 7. Jean Jamin, interview with the author. [The Collge de Sociologie was founded around 1933 by Georges Bataille and Roger Caillois to train sociologists. The major in- fluences in the school's orientation included surrealists, Hegelianism through Kojve's work, Freud, and work being done in anthropology.-Trans.) 8. Lvi-Strauss, "Introduction l'uvre de Marcel Mauss"; Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss, p. 3. 9. Ibid., p. 10. 10. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Le sorcier et sa magie," Les Temps modernes, no. 41 (March 1949). 11. Marcel Mauss, "Essai sur le don. Forme et raison de l'change dans les socits archaques," in Anne sociologique, 1921; translated as The Gift. 12. Lvi-Strauss, Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss, p. 26. 13. Ibid., p. 8. 14. Ibid., p. 34. 15. Ibid., pp. 35-36. 16. Ibid., p. 37. 17. Vincent Descombes, Le Mme et l'autre, p. 121. 18. Claude Lvi-Strauss, The Elementary Structures of Kinship, p. 51. 19. Ibid., p. 485. 20. Ibid., p. 481. 21. Vincent Descombes, interview with the author. 22. Lvi-Strauss, Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss, p. 53. 23. Claude Lefort, "L'change et la lutte des hommes," Les Temps modernes (Febru- ary 1951); reprinted in Claude Lefort, Les Formes de l'histoire, p. 17. 24. Lvi-Strauss, Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss, p. 35. Pive. Georges Dumzil: An Independent 1. The Acadmie Franaise was founded in 1635 by Cardinal Richelieu under Louis XIII to bring together the wise men of the country. Forty members, known as "immortals," were and continue to be e1ected by their peers to continue the work of writing and revising a dictionary of the French language.-Trans. 2. Georges Dumzil, Mythe et pope, Introduction. 3. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Dumzil et les sciences humaines," France-Culture, Octo- ber 2, 1978. 4. Georges Dumzil, Entretiens avec Didier ribon, p. 64. 5. Franz Bopp, Systme de conjugaison de la langue sanscrite, compar celui des langues grecque, latine, persane et germanique (1816); translated as Analytical Com- parison of the Sanskrit, Greek, Latin, and Teutonic Languages Showing the Original Identity of Their Grammatical Structure (1974). 6. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Rponse Dumzil reu l'Acadmie Franaise," Le Monde, July 15, 1979. 7. Dumzil, Entretiens avec Didier ribon, p. 174. 8. Claude Hagge, Le Monde, October 14, 1986. Six. The Phenomenological Bridge 1. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, La Structure du comportement; Phnomnologie de la perception. Notes to Chapter Seven 45 2. Vincent Descombes, interview with the author. 3. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, "Sur la phnomnologie du langage," lecture delivered to the Fifst International Phenomenology Colloquium in Brussels, 195I; reprinted in Signs. 4. Ibid., p. 49. 5. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Cahiers internationaux de sociologie, 10, pp. 55-69; reprinted in Signs, p. 98. 6. Claude Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. 88. 7. Merleau-Ponty, Signs, pp. u6, u8. 8. Vincent Descombes, interview with the author. 9. Merleau-Ponty, Signs, p. I22. 10. Vincent Descombes, interview with the author. 11. George W Stocking, Histoires de l'anthropologie: XVI' -XIX e sicles, pp. 421-3 I. 12. Langues Orientales trains students in Eastern (Arabic) and Oriental (Asian) lan- guages.-Trans. 13. Established by royal decree on February 22,1821, the cole des Chartes trained specialists in reading medieval documents (chartes). The school depends on the Min- istry of National Education, and prepares paleographic archivists during the three years and nine months of studies.-Trans. 14. Jean Jamin, Les Enjeux philosophiques des annes cinquante, p. 103. 15. Alfred Adler, Sminaire de Michel Izard, Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, November 17, 1988. 16. Michel Arriv, interview with the author. 17. Algirdas Julien Greimas, interview with the author. 18. Jean-Marie Benoist, interview with the author. 19. Michel Foucault, "Structuralism and Post-Structuralism," Telos, vol. 16 (1983): pp. 195-21 1; interview with Georges Raulet. 20. Michel Foucault, Les Mots et les choses; translated as The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. 21. Foucault, The Order of Things, p. 248. Seven. The Saussure an Break 1. Vincent Descombes, Le Mme et l'autre, p. 100. 2. Ferdinand de Saussure, Cours de linguistique gnrale. 3. Franoise Gadet, "Le signe et le sens," DRLAV, Revue de linguistique, no. 40 (1989). 4. Ibid., p. 4. 5. Algirdas Julien Greimas, interview with the author. 6. Gadet, "Le signe et le sens," p. 18. 7. Roland Barthes, "Saussure, le signe, la dmocratie," Le Discours social, nos. 3-4 (April 1973); reprinted in Roland Barthes, L'Aventure smiologique, p. 22I. 8. See Tzvetan Todorov, Thories du symbole. 9. Claudine Normand, interview with the author. 10. Ibid. 11. Ibid. 12. Jean-Claude Coquet, interview with the author. 13. Sylvain Auroux, interview with the author. 14. Andr Martinet, interview with the author. 15. Ibid. 16. Ibid. 406 Notes to Chapter Nine 17. Saussure, Cours de linguistique gnrale, p. u6. 18. Ibid. 19. Oswald Ducrot and Tzvetan Todorov, Dictionnaire encyclopdique du langage, p. I33 20. Louis-Jean Calvet, Pour et contre Saussure, pp. 82-83. 21. Saussure, Cours de linguistique gnrale, p. 33. 22. Sylvain Auroux, interview with the author. 23. Louis-Jean Calvet, interview with the author. 24. Calvet, Pour et contre Saussure. 25. Jean Starobinski, Mercure de France, February I964; then Les Mots sous les mots, I97I. 26. Saussure, COUIflS de linguistique gnrale, p. 30. 27. Claude Hagge, I.:homme de parole, p. 35. 28. Oswald Ducrot, interview with the author. Eight. Roman Jakobson: The Man Who Could Do Everything 1. Roman Jakobson, final text of the Conference of Anthropologists and Linguists, held at Indiana University in I952, Essais de linguistique gnrale. 2. Ibid., p. 42. 3. Ibid. (1:957), p. 72. 4. Ibid. (I957), p. 74. 5. Roman Jakobson, interview with Tzvetan Todorov, Potique, no. 57 (February I984): p. 4 6. Ibid., p. u. 7. Roman Jakobson, interviewed by Jean-Jos Marchand on the television program Archives du XX e sicle (February IO, I972;January 2, I973; September I4, I974), and rebroadcast on Channel 7 in October I990. 8. Potique, no. 57 (February I984): p. I6. 9. Roman Jakobson, preface to Tzvetan Todorov, Thorie de la littrature, p. 9. 10. Marina Yaguello, interview with the author. Il. Jean-Pierre Faye, interview with the author. 12. Ibid. 13. J. Makarovsky, reprinted in Change, no. 3 (I97I). 14. "I929 Theses," published by Change (I969): p. 3I. 15. Jakobson, in Archives du XX" sicle. 16. Editorial, Ward, no. I (I945). 17. Franoise Gadet, DRLAV, Revue de linguistique, no. 40 (I989): p. 8. 18. Jakobson, Essais de linguistique gnrale, pp. 35-36. 19. Roman Jakobson, "Les douze traits de sonorit," in "Phonologie et phontique" (I9 56), in Essais de linguistique gnrale, pp. U8-29. 20. Roman Jakobson, "Deux aspects du langage et deux types d'aphasie," in Essais de linguistique gnrale, pp. 5D-P. 21. Jean-Claude Chevalier, interview with the author. Nine. A Pilot Science without a Plane: Linguistics 1. Andr Martinet, in "La cration de revues dans les annes soixante," interview with Jean-Claude Chevalier and Pierre Encrev, Langue franaise, no. 63 (September I984): p. 6I. Notes ta Chapter Eleven 407 2. Robert-Lon Wagner, foreword to his Introduction to French Linguistics (1947); quoted by Chevalier and Encrev in ibid. 3. Bernard Qumada, in "La cration de revues dans les annes soixante," inter- view with Chevalier and Encrev. 4. Michel Arriv, interview with the author. 5. Bernard Pottier, in "La cration de revues dans les annes soixante," interview with Chevalier and Encrev. 6. Chevalier and Encrev, Langue franaise, no. 63 (September 1984). 7. Bernard Qumada, interview with Chevalier and Encrev. 8. Jean-Claude Chevalier, interview with the author. 9. Philippe Hamon, "Littrature," in Les Sciences du langage en France au XX e sicle, p. 285. 10. Ibid., p. 284. 11. Grard Genette, interview with the author. 12. Jean-Claude Chevalier, interview with the author. 13. Andr Martinet, interview with the author. 14. Andr-Georges Haudricout, interview with the author. 15. Ibid. 16. Ibid. 17. Ibid. 18. Ibid. Ten. At Alexandria's Gates 1. Algirdas Julien Greimas, interview with the author. 2. Ibid. 3. Roland Barthes, Michelet par lui-mme. 4. Algirdas Julien Greimas and Roland Barthes, quoted by Louis-Jean Calvet, Roland Barthes, p. 124. 5. Charles Singevin, quoted in ibid. 6. Algirdas Julien Greimas, preface ta Louis Hjelmslev, Prolegomena to a Theory of Language. 7. Louis Hjelmslev, Language: An Introduction, p. 96. 8. Thomas Pavel, Le Mirage linguistique, p. 92. 9. Hjelmslev, Prolegomena to a Theory of Language, p. 23. 10. Jean-Claude Coquet, interview with the author. 11. Ibid. 12. Andr Martinet, interview with the author. 13. Ibid. 14. Andr Martinet, review of Hjelmslev's Prolegomena to a Theory of Language in the Bulletin de la socit de linguistique, vol. 42 (1946): pp. 17-42. 15. Serge Martin, interview with the author. 16. Serge Martin, Langage musical, smiotique des systmes. Eleven. The Mother Figure of Structuralism: Roland Barthes 1. Le Degr zro de l'criture. 2. Ibid., p. 10. 3. Maurice Nadeau, Les Lettres nouvelles (July 1953): p. 599. 4. Jean-Bertrand Ponta lis, Les Temps modernes (November 1953): pp. 934-38. 408 Notes to Chapter Twelve 5. Barthes, Le Degr zro de l'criture, p. 24. 6. Ibid., p. 45. 7. Ibid., p. 55. 8. Ibid., p. 65. 9. Roland Barthes, interviews with Jean-Marie Benoist and Bernard-Henri Lvy, France-Culture, February I977, rerun December I, I988. 10. Roland Barthes, Ocaniques, FR3, November I97o-May I97I, rerun on Janu- ary 27, I988. 11. The Licence is a university degree awarded after the third year of study, before a master's or a doctorate. With it one can teach in high schools but not in the university or any advanced school.-Trans. 12. The Collge de France is a teaching institution established in Paris in IBO by Franois 1 as the Collge du Roi, through the initiative of Guillaume Bud, a classical scholar and humanist. The Collge elects its peers based on publications. A university diploma is not a prerequisite for election, which allowed "marginais" like Barthes to be recognized. For Barthes, the recognition by peers of his work legitimated him and salved the wound of having received no advanced university degree, which would have allowed him to teach as a regular faculty member.-Trans. 13. Louis-Jean Calvet, interview with the author. 14. Barthes, Ocaniques, FR3. 15. Roland Barthes, Mythologies, p. I09. 16. Louis-Jean Calvet, Roland Barthes, p. 67. 17. Ibid. 18. Barthes, Mythologies, p. 229. 19. Ibid., p. 25I. 20. Barthes could teach, therefore, without a university degree, having been recog- nized for the work he had published, even if he was not sanctioned by the official diploma-dispensing university.-Trans. 21. Andr Green, interview with the author. 22. Roland Barthes, "Mre courage aveugle," in Essais critiques, pp. 49-50. 23. Georges-Elia Sarfati, interview with the author. 24. Georges Mounin, Introduction la smiologie, p. I93. Twelve. An Epistemic Exigency 1. Alexandre Koyr, De la mystique la science; cours, confrences et documents (I922-62), p. I29 2. Jean-Louis Fabiani, Les Enjeux philosophiques des annes cinquante, p. I2 5. 3. Martial Guroult, Leon inaugurale au Collge de France (December 4, I95I), pp. I6-I 7 4. Ibid., p. 43. 5. Gilles Gaston-Granger, interview with the author. 6. Marc Abls, interview with the author. 7. Ibid. 8. Jean-Christophe Goddard, interview with the author. 9. Guroult, Leon inaugurale au Collge de France, p. I8. 10. Jolle Proust, Bulletin de la socit franaise de philosophie (July-September I988): p. 8I. 11. Martial Guroult, Descartes selon l'ordre des raisons. 12. Ibid., p. IO. 13. Jean-Christophe Goddard, interview with the author. Notes to Chapter Thirteen 409 14. Martial Guroult, Philosophie de l'histoire de la rmuo:mt'In,?, p. 243. 15. Jean Piaget, Psychologie et pistmologie, p. 10. 16. Jean Piaget, lments d'pistmologie gntique. 17. Vincent Descombes, interview with the author. 18. Jean Cavaills, Sur la logique et la thorie des sciences. 19. Pierre Fougeyrollas, interview with the author. 20. Ibid. 21. Georges Canguilhem, interview with Jean-Franois Sirinelli, Gnration intel- lectuelle, p. 597. 22. Ibid., p. 598. 23. Bertrand Saint-Sernin, Revue de mtaphysique et de morale (January 1985): p. 86. 24. "Essai sur quelques problmes concernant le normal et le pathologique." 25. Georges Canguilhem, Le Normal et le pathologique, p. 8. 26. Pierre Fougeyrollas, interview with the author. 27. Georges Canguilhem, "La dcadence de l'ide de progrs," Revue de mta- physique et de morale, no. 4 (I987): p. 450. 28. Michel Foucault, Revue de mtaphysique et de morale (January I985): p. 3. 29. Ibid., p. I4. 30. Pierre Macherey, "La philosophie de la science de Canguilhem," La Pense, no. II3 (January I964) 31. Ibid., p. 74. 32. Georges Canguilhem, "Qu'est-ce que la psychologie?" Lecture given Decem- ber I8, I956, at Jean Wahl's Collge Philosophique and reprinted in Revue de mta- physique et de morale (I958): pp. I2-25, in Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, no. 2 (March I966), and in Georges Canguilhem, tudes d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences. 33. Vincent Descombes, Les Enjeux philosophiques des annes cinquante, p. I59. 34. Michel Serres, La Traduction, p. 259. 35. Michel Serres, "Structure et importation: des mathmatiques aux mythes" (No- vember I96I); reprinted in Herms, vol. I, "La Communication" (Paris: Minuit, I968). 36. Ibid., p. 26. 37. Ibid., p. 32. 38. Serres, "Structure et importation," p. 34. Thirteen. A Rebel Named Jacques Lacan 1. lisabeth Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, p. I 5 5. 2. Ibid., p. I54. 3. Ibid., p. I24. 4. Ibid., p. I29. 5. "De la psychose paranoaque dans ses rapports avec la personnalit." 6. See Boris Souvarine et "La Critique sociale," ed. Anne Roche. 7. Bertrand Ogilvie, Lacan, le sujet, pp. 20-2I. 8. Jean Allouch, interview with the author. 9. This I936 version was later revised and delivered at the sixteenth International Congress of Psychoanalysis in Zurich in I949 and published in the Revue franaise de psychanalyse, no. 4 (October-December I949). This final version was translated as The Mirror Stage: Theory of a Structuring and Genetic Moment of the Constitution of Real- ity, Conceived in Relationship with the Experience of Psychoanalytic Doctrine, and in crits: A Selection, as "The Mirror Stage as Formative of the Function of the l as Re- vealed in Psychoanalytic Experience," pp. I-7. 10. Jol Dor, Introduction la lecture de Lacan, p. 100. 4IO Notes to Chapter Fourteen 11. Ibid., p. lOI. 12. "Le stade du miroir comme formateur de la fonction du Je" ("The Mirror Stage as Formative of the Function of the 1 as Revealed in Psychoanalytic Experience"). 13. Ogilvie, Lacan, le sujet, p. 107. 14. Anika Lemaire, Lacan, p. 27. 15. Ibid., p. 277. 16. Moustafa Safouan, interview with the author. 17. Jean Hyppolite, La Psychanlayse, vol. 1, pp. 29-39, with Lacan's response, reprinted in Jacques Lacan, crits, pp. 879-87. 18. Vincent Descombes, Les Enjeux philosophiques des annes cinquante, p. 155. 19. Like the poetic notion of scansion, the Lacanian use of the term involves punc- tuation, but in this case the punctuation, and end, of a therapeutic session. Lacan, and others, ended a session on a word uttered by the patient in a way that left its greater sig- nificance muted. Ending the session on the term drew attention to it and shifted the weight of its meaning.-Trans. 20. Wladimir Granoff, interview with the author. 21. Gennie Lemoine, interview with the author. 22. Jean Laplanche, interview with the author. 23. Jol Dor, interview with the author. 24. Wladimir Granoff, interview with the author. 25. Ibid. 26. Jean Clavreul, interview with the author. 27. Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse in France, p. 294. 28. Jean Clavreul, interview with the author. Fourteen. Rome CaUs (1953): The Return ta Freud 1. Andr Green, interview with the author. 2. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, La Structure du comportement. 3. Andr Green, interview with the author. 4. Claude Dumzil, interview with the author. 5. Ibid. 6. The French pun cornes from the auraI homology between le nom du pre, le non du pre, and le non dupe erre.-Trans. 7. Claude Demzil, interview with the author. 8. Ibid. 9. lisabeth Roudinesco, interview with the author. 10. Wladimir Granoff, interview with the author. 11. Ibid. 12. Ibid. 13. Grard Mendel, Enqute par un psychanalyste sur lui-mme, p. 165. 14. lisabeth Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, vol. 2, p. 272. 15. Jacques Lacan, "Rapport de Rome," in crits, vol. 1 (1953) ("Report to the Rome Congress held at the Istituto di Psicologia della Universit di Roma, 26 and 27 September, 1953," trans. Alan Sheridan, in crits: A Selection, p. 57). 16. Ibid., p. 40. 17. Ibid., p. 65. 18. Ibid., p. 66. 19. Ibid., p. 73. 20. Ibid., P.76. 21. Ren Major, interview with the author. Notes to Chapter Fiireen 4II 22. Lacan, "Report to the Rome Congress," p. 86. 23. Bernard Sichre, Le Moment lacanien, p. 59. 24. Charles Melman, interview with the author. 25. Psychiatry in France, as in America, is a medical field of specialization and there- fore practiced by medical doctors. Psychoanalysis can also be pracriced by doctors, but it is not a medical field. There is no single, formally recognized psychoanalytic training institute in France, but rather a proliferation of institutes and groups, which may or may not offer training programs. The situation appears chaotic and even dangerous in American eyes, particularly since a psychoanalyst can authorize himself or herself to practice, according to the Lacanian dictum. In terms of pathways to analysis, many practicing analysts are trained in philosophy, have themselves been in analysis, and are therefore close to the central, linguistic problematic around which French psychoanaly- sis has been focused, particularly since Lacan.-Trans. 26. Jacques Lacan, "Vinstance de la lettre dans l'inconscient," in crits, vol. l, p. 251; "The Agency of the Letter in the Unconscious or Reason since Freud," trans. Alan Sheridan, in crits: A Selection, p. 147. 27. Ibid., p. 149. 28. Ibid. 29. Ibid., p. 154. 30. Ibid., pp. 165-66. 31. Michel Arriv, interview with the author. 32. Jol Dor, Introduction la lecture de Lacan, pp. 55-56. 33. Jacques Lacan, "Sminaire sur la lettre vole," in crits, vol. l, pp. 35,4. 34. Dor, Introduction la lecture de Lacan, pp. 59-60. 35. Ibid., p. 63. 36. Jacques Lacan, "La chose freudienne" (1956), in crits, vol. l, p. 144; "The Freudian Thing," trans. Alan Sheridan, in crits: A Selection, p. 125. 37. Anika Lemaire, Lacan, p. 340. 38. Ibid., p. 347. 39. Georges Mounin, Introduction la smiologie, pp. 184-85, 40. Ibid., p. 188. 41. Lemaire, Lacan, p. 30. Fifteen. The Unconscious: A Symbolic Uni verse 1. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss, trans. Felicity Baker, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1987), p. xx. 2. Jacques Lacan, "Remarques sur le rapport de Daniel Lagache" (1958), in crits, p.648. 3. Claude Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. 107. 4. Janson High School in Paris is weil known as being one of the best high schools. Located in the rich west side of Paris, it is the high school for many French writers and intellectuals.-Trans. 5. Claude Lvi-Strauss, interview with the author. 6. Ibid. 7. Le Totmisme aujourd'hui. 8. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Le sorcier et sa magie," Les Temps modernes, no. 41 (March 1949): pp. 3-24; 'TEfficace Symbolique," Revue d'histoire des religions, no. 1 (1949): pp. 5-27; reprinted in Anthropologie Structurale. See "The Sorcerer and His Magic" and "The Effectiveness of Symbols," in Structural Anthropology, trans. Claire 412 Notes to Chapter Sixteen Jacobson and Brooke Grundfest Schoepf (New York: Anchor Books, 1967), pp. 161-80 and 181-201, respectively. 9. Lvi-Strauss, "Le sorcier et sa magie," p. 201; "The Sorcerer and His Magic," PI77 10. Lvi-Strauss, "L'Efficace symbolique," p. 224. ll.Ibid. 12. R. Georgin, De Lvi-Strauss Lacan, p. 125. 13. Lvi-Strauss, Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss, p. 56. 14. E. R. de Ipola, "Le Structuralisme ou l'histoire en exil," p. 122. 15. Ibid., p. 126. 16. Claude Lvi-Strauss, La Pense sauvage, p. 174; translated as The Savage Mind. 17. De Ipola, "Le Structuralisme ou l'histoire en exil," p. 244. 18. Claude Lvi-Strauss, interview with Raymond Bellour (1972), Paris: Ides- Gallimard, 1979), p. 205. 19. Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. 150. 20. Claude Lvi-Strauss, La Potire jalouse, p. 243; translated as The Jealous Potter, P 18 5 21. Ibid., p. 193. 22. Andr Green, Sminaire de Michel Izard, Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, December 8, 1988. 23. Grard Mendel, La Chasse structurale, p. 262. 24. Grard Mendel, interview with the author. 25. Franois Roustang, Lacan; see also Vincent Descombes, "L'quivoque du sym- bolique," Confrontations, no. 3 (1980): pp. 77-95. 26. Jacques Lacan, "Situation de la psychanalyse en 1956," in crits, vol. 2, p. 19. 27. Ibid. 28. Roustang, Lacan, pp. 36-37. 29. Jacques Lacan, Le Sminaire III: Les Psychoses, p. 208. 30. Jol Dor, interview with the author. 31. Claude Cont, interview with the author. 32. Jacques Lacan, Sminaire XX, Encore (1973-1974), p. 45. 33. Charles Melman, interview with the author. Sixteen. ReallSymboliclImaginary (RSI): The Heresy 1. Jean Allouch, interview with the author. 2. Ibid. 3. Moustafa Safouan, interview with the author. 4. The French original reads: "Tu t'y es mis un peu tard," and the acronym is "T.t.y.e.m.u.p.t. "-Trans. 5. Jacques-Alain Miller, Ornicar, no. 24 (1981). 6. Ibid. 7. Claude Cont, interview with the author. 8. Pierre Fougeyrollas, Contre Claude Lvi-Strauss, Lacan, Althusser (Paris: Lavelli, 1976), p. 99. 9. Franois George, I.:Effet yau de pole (Paris: Hachette, 1979), p. 65. [The pun in French is on perversion, which becomes pre-version.-Trans.] 10. Jacques Lacan, "Rapport de Rome," in crits, vol. 1 (1953), p. 168. 11. Information taken from lisabeth Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, vol. 2, p. 318. Notes to Chapter Seventeen 4I3 12. Maurice Colloque de Bonneval, L'Inconscient Descle de Brouwer, 1966). 13. Serge Leclaire, "L'inconscient, une tude psychanalytique," in L'Inconscient, pp. 95-130,170-77; reprinted in Psychanalyser, pp. 99 and II6. 14. Serge Leclaire, interview with the author. 15. Jean Laplanche, interview with the author. 16. Jean Laplanche, 6' Colloque de Bonneval, in L'Inconscient, p. II 5. 17. Ibid., p. 121. 18. Jean Laplanche, interview with the author. 19. Jean Laplanche, Psychanalyse l'Universit, voL 4, no. 15 (June 1979): pp. 523-28. 20. Ibid., p. 527. 21. Ibid. 22. Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, voL 2, p. 323. 23. Anika Lemaire, Lacan. 24. Jacques Lacan, "Position de l'inconscient," in crits, vol. 2, p. 196. 25. Ibid., p. 211. [The pun in French is between homme and hommelette.-Trans.] 26. Jacques Lacan, interview, Belgian Radio Television, December 14, 1966. 27. Lettre and l'tre ("Letter" and "Being") are homonyms punning on lettre (letter, language) and l'tre (being}.-Trans. Seventeen. The Cali of the Tropics 1. Serge Martin, interview with the author. 2. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Race et histoire" (1952); reprinted in Anthropologie structurale, vol. 2, p. 399; translated as "Race and History." 3. Ibid. 4. Ibid., p. 415. 5. Bertrand Ogilvie, interview with the author. 6. Roger Caillois, "Illusions rebours," Nouvelle Revue franaise (December l, 1954): pp. 1010-21; (January l, 1955): pp. 58-70. 7. Roger Caillois, "La rponse de R. Caillois," Le Monde, June 28,1974. 8. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Diogne couch," Les Temps modernes, no. 195 (1955): pp. Il87-122I. 9. Caillois, "Illusions rebours," p. 1021. la. Ibid., p. 1024. 11. Lvi-Strauss, "Diogne couch," p. Il87. 12. Ibid., p. 1202. 13. Ibid., p. 1214. 14. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Tristes Tropiques, trans. John and Doreen Weightman (New York: Atheneum, 1974). 15. Claude Lvi-Strauss, interview with Jean-Jos Marchand, Arts (December 25, 1955) 16. Claude Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. 76. 17. Lvi-Strauss, Tristes Tropiques, p. 408. 18. Ibid., p. 393. 19. Ibid., p. 413. 20. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Le droit au voyage," L'Express (September 21, 1956). 21. Lvi-Strauss, Tristes Tropiques, p. 386. 22. Ibid., p. 411. 23. Ibid., p. 390. 414 Notes ta Chapter Eighteen 24. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Antht"Oonlrlf'le structurale, vol. 2, p. 5 L 25. Ibid., pp. 46-47. 26. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Des Indiens et leur ethnographe," excerpts from "Tristes Tropiques Saon ta Be Published," Les Temps modernes, no. TI6 (August 1955)' 27. Raymond Aron, Le Figaro, December 24, 1955. 28. Franois-Rgis Bastide, Demain, January 29, 1956. 29. Madeleine Chapsal, L'Express, February 24, 1956. 30. Jean Lacroix, Le Monde, October 13-14, 1957. 31. P. A. Renaud, France-Observateur, December 29,1955. 32. J. Meyriat, Revue franaise de science politique, vol. 6, no. 2. 33. Claude Roy, Libration, November 16, 1955. 34. Georges Bataille, "Un livre humain, un grand livre," Critique, no. II5 (February 1956). 35. Alfred Mtraux, L'Ile de Pques (1956). 36. Bataille, "Un livre humain, un grand livre," p. 101. 37. Ren Etiemble, Evidences (April 1956): p. 32. 38. Ibid., p. 36. 39. Lvi-Strauss, Tristes Tropiques, p. 38. 40. Le Figaro, December l, 1956. 41. Maxime Rodinson, "Racisme et civilisation," Nouvelle Critique, no. 66 (1955); no. 69 (November 1955); La Pense (May-June 1957). 42. Rodinson, "Racisme et civilisation," p. 130. 43. Etiemble, vidences, pp. 33-34. 44. Lvi-Strauss, Anthropologie structurale, vol. 2, p. 331-32. 45. Michel Izard, interview with the author. 46. Michel Izard, Sminaire, Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, June l, 1989. 47. Michel Izard, interview with the author. 48. Ibid. 49. Ibid. 50. Izard, Sminaire. 51. Franoise Hritier-Aug, interview with the author. 52. Ibid. 53. Olivier Herrenschmidt, Sminaire de Michel Izard, Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, January 19, 1989. 54. Louis Dumont, quoted by Herrenschmidt in ibid. 55. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Leroi-Gourhan ou les voies de l'homme, pp. 205-6. 56. Hlne Balfet, Sminaire de Michel Izard, Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, 1989. Eighteen. Reason Raves: Michel Foucault's Work 1. Pierre Nora, Les Franais d'Algrie. 2. Jacques Rancire, interview with the author. 3. Edgar Morin, L'Esprit du temps, p. 149. 4. Didier ribon, Michel Foucault, p. 21. 5. Bernard Sichre, interview with the author. 6. Daniel Defert, France-Culture, July 7,1988. 7. Ibid. 8. Libration pol!, June 3,1984. 9. Michel Foucault, Ethos (fal! 1983): p. 5. 10. Histoire de la sexualit. Notes to Chapter Eighteen 4IJ 11. Michel Foucault, interview with Audr Berten, Catholic University of Louvain, 1981; shawn on FR3, January 13, 1988. 12. Michel Foucault, "Jean Hyppolite, 1907-1968," Revue de et de morale, vol. 14, no. 2 (April-June 1969): p. 13 1. 13. "Gense et structure de la phnomnologie de l'esprit." 14. Surveiller et punir. 15. Michel Foucault, quoted by ribon, Michel Foucault, p. 35. 16. "Nietzsche, la gnalogie, l'histoire." 17. Michel Foucault, Hommage Hyppolite. 18. Jacques Proust, Libration poli, June 30, I984. 19. Maladie mentale et personnalit. 20. ribon, Michel Foucault, p. 49. 2l. From the word for alligator, caman designates the ENS professor assigned par- ticularly to training students for the agrgation examination.-Trans. 22. Olivier Revault d'Allonnes, interview with the author. 23. Maurice Pinguet, Le Dbat, no. 4I (September-November 1986): pp. I25-26. 24. Ibid., pp. I29-30. 25. Quoted by ribon, Michel Foucault, p. I79. 26. Michel Foucault, quoted by Pinguet in Le Dbat, p. I26. 27. Quoted by ribon, Michel Foucault, p. 96. 28. Georges Dumzil, Entretiens avec Didier ribon, p. 2I5. 29. Michel Foucault, Folie et draison (Paris: Plon, I96I), Preface, p. x. 30. Michel Foucault, Le Monde, July 22,1961. 3l. Pierre Macherey, interview with the author. 32. Ibid. 33. Quoted by ribon, Michel Foucault, p. 133. 34. Michel Foucault, "Vrit et pouvoir," interview with M. Fontana, L'Arc, no. 70, p. I6. 35. Michel Foucault, Politique-Hebdo, interview, March 4, I976. 36. Ibid. 37. Foucault, Folie et draison, pp. i-v. 38. Ibid. 39. Vincent Descombes, Le Mme et l'autre, p. 138. 40. Pascal, Penses, ditions Brunschwicg, no. 4I4, quoted by Michel Foucault, His- toire de la folie, p. 47 (Madness and Civilization, trans. Richard Howard, Preface, p. ix). 41. Foucault, Madness and Civilization, p. 59. 42. Histoire de la folie, p. I47. 43. Ibid., p. 4I5. 44. Ibid., p. 523. 45. ribon, Michel Foucault, p. 131. 46. L'Enfant et la famille sous l'Ancien Rgime. 47. Philippe Aris, Un historien du dimanche, p. I45. 48. Roland Barthes, "De part et d'autre," Critique, no. 17 (I96I): pp. 915-22; re- printed in Essais critiques, p. I7L 49. Ibid., p. 168. 50. Maurice Blanchot, "L'oubli, la draison," Nouvelle Revue franaise (October I96I): pp. 676-86; reprinted in L'Entretien infini, p. 292. 51. Robert Mandrou, "Trois cls pour comprendre l'histoire de la folie l'poque classique," Annales, no. 4 (July-August I962): pp. 76I-7L 52. Michel Serres, "Gomtrie de la folie," Mercure de France, no. II88 (August 4I6 Notes to Chapter Twenty 1962): pp. 683-96, and no. II89 (September 1962): pp. 63-81; reprinted in Herms ou la communication. 53. Les Mots et les choses. 54. ribon, Michel Foucault, p. I47. 55. Robert Castel, "Les aventures de la pratique," Le Dbat, no. 41 (September- November, 1986): p. 43. 56. Marcel Gauchet and Gladys Swain, La Pratique de l'esprit humain: I.:institution asilaire et la rvolution dmocratique. 57. Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, La Pense 68, p. 131. 58. Ibid., p. 132. Nineteen. Marxism in Crisis: A Thaw or the Deep Freeze Again? 1. Marcel Gauchet, interview with the author. 2. Alain Renaut, interview with the author. 3. Georges Balandier, interview with the author. 4. Ren Lourau, interview with the author. 5. Quoted by Pascal Ory and Jean-Franois Sirinelli, Les Intellectuels en France, de l'affaire Dreyfus nos jours, p. 188. 6. Michel Foucault, Ocaniques, FR3, January 13, I988 (1977, at Vzelay, home of Maurice Clavel). 7. Pierre Fougeyrollas, interview with the author. 8. Grard Genette, interview with the author. 9. Olivier Revault d'Allonnes, interview with the author. 10. Jean-Pierre Faye, interview with the author. Il. Alfred Adler, interview with the author. 12. Alfred Adler, Sminaire de Michel Izard, Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, November 17, 1988. 13. Ibid. 14. Ibid. 15. Ibid. 16. Ibid. 17. Ibid. 18. Cornelius Castoriadis, "Les divertisseurs," Le Nouvel Observateur,June 20, 1977; reprinted in La Socit franaise (Paris: Io1I8, 1979), p. 226. 19. Edgar Morin, Le Vif du sujet (Paris: Seuil, 1969). 20. Edgar Morin, "Arguments, trente ans aprs," interviews, La Revue des revues, no. 4 (fall 1987): p. 12. 21. Kostas Axelos, in ibid., p. 18. 22. Kostas Axelos, "Le jeu de l'autocritique," Arguments, nos. 27-28 (1962). 23. Morin, "Arguments, trente ans aprs," p. 19. 24. Daniel Becquemont, interview with the author. 25. Ibid. Twenty. The French School of Economics Takes a Structural Path 1. Andr Nieola, interview with the author. 2. Michel Aglietta, interview with the author. 3. Ibid. 4. Andr Nicola, interview with the author. Notes to Chapter Twenty-one 4 Il 5. Mario Dehove, L'Etat des sciences sociales en France, p. 252.. 6. Robert Boyer, "La croissance franaise de l'aprs-guerre et les modles macro- conomiques," La Revue conomique, vol. 27, no. 5 (1976). 7. Franois Perrroux, in Sens et usages du terme de structure, ed. Roger Bastide (Paris: Mouton, 1972 [1962]), p. 6r. 8. Henri Bartoli, Economie et cration collective, p. 315, 9. Karl Marx, Le Capital, book 2, voL 3, p. 208. 10. Ren Clmens, "Prolgomnes d'une thorie de la structure," Revue d'conomie politique, no. 6 (195 2): p. 997. 11. Ernest Wagemann, Introduction la thorie du mouvement des affaires, pp. 372-73; and La Stratgie conomique, pp. 69-70. 12. Franois Perroux, Comptes de la nation, p. I26. 13. Andr Marchal, in Bastide, ed., Sens et usages du terme de structure. 14. Andr Marchal, Mthode scientifique et science conomique. 15. Andr Marchal, Systmes et structures. 16. Andr Nicola, Comportement conomique et structures sociales. 17. Andr Nicola, interview with the author. 18. Bartoli, conomie et cration collective, p. 344. 19. Henri Bartoli, interview with the author. 20. Bartoli, conomie et cration collective, p. 345. 21. Gilles Gaston-Granger, Pense formelle et science de l'homme, p. 53. Twenty-one. Get a Load of That Structure! 1. Roger Bastide, ed., Sens et usages du terme de structure. 2. Entretiens sur les notions de gense et de structure, colloquium at Cerisy, July-August 1959 (Paris: Mouton, 1965). There was also a colloquium in 1957, orga- nized by the Centre International de Synthse: Notion de structure et structure de la connaissance (Paris: Albin Michel, 1957). 3. tienne Wolff, in Bastide, ed., Sens et usages du terme de structure, p. 23. 4. Nicolai Trubetzkoy, "La phonologie actuelle," in Psychologie du langage (Paris, 1933), p. 245 5. Claude Lvi-Strauss, in Bastide, ed., Sens et usages du terme de structure, p. 44. 6. Daniel Lagache, in ibid., p. 81. 7. Raymond Aron, in ibid., p. II3. 8. Lucien Goldmann, in Entretiens sur les notions de gense et de structure, p. 10. 9. Lucien Goldmann, Le Dieu cach. 10. Jean Piaget, in Entretiens sur les notions de gense et de structure, p. 42. 11. Maurice de Gandillac, in ibid., p. 120. 12. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Anthropologie structurale, reprinted in Histoire et ethnolo- gie, Revue de mtaphysique et de morale, nos. 3-4 (1949): pp. 363-91 (Structural An- thropology, "History and Anthropology," pp. 1-28.) 13. Ibid., p. 13. 14. Ibid., p. 19. 15. Ibid., pp 23-24. 16. Ibid., p. 82. 17. Ibid., p. 95. 18. Ibid., p. 278. 19. Ibid. 20. Maurice Godelier, interview with the author. 21. Philippe Descola, interview with the author. 4 18 Notes to Twenty-two Claude Roy, "Claude Lvi-Strauss ou l'homme en question, La Nef; no. 28 (I959): p. 70. 23. Jean Duvignaud, Les Lettres nouvelles, no. 62 (I9 58). 24. Letter from Claude Lvi-Strauss, quoted by Jean Duvignaud in Le Langage perdu, p. 234. 25. Ibid., p. 251. 26. Georges Mounin, Introduction la smiologie, p. 202. 27. Ibid., p. 204. 28. Lvi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, p. 60. 29. Ibid., p. 41. 30. Ibid., p. 90. 31. Franois Dosse, L'Histoire en miettes. 32. "La Mditerrane et le monde mditerranen l'poque de Philippe IL" 33. "La Crise de l'conomie franaise la fin de l'Ancien Rgime." 34. Ernest Labrousse, "La Crise de l'conomie franaise la fin de l'Ancien Rgime et au dbut de la crise rvolutionnaire," p. 170. 35. Ernest Labrousse, Actes du congrs historique du centenaire de la rvolution de r848, p. 20. 36. Pierre Vilar, La Catalogne dans l'Espagne moderne. Recherches sur les fonde- ments conomiques des structures nationales. 37. Pierre Vilar, interview with the author. 38. Michelle Perrot, Essais d'ego-histoire, p. 277. 39. Michelle Perrot, interview with the author. 40. Ibid. [The French tide of Perrot's thesis is "Les Ouvriers en grve, France (1871-1890)." - Trans.] 41. Jean-Pierre Vernant, interview with the author. 42. Jean-Pierre Vernant, "Le mythe hsiodique des races: Essai d'analyse structurale," Revue de l'histoire des religions (1960): pp. 21-54. 43. Jean-Pierre Vernant, in Entretiens sur les notions de gense et de structure. 44. Jean-Pierre Vernant, "Le mythe hsiodique des races" (1960), in Mythe et pen- se chez les Grecs, p. 21. 45. Jean-Pierre Vernant, interview with the author. 46. Ibid. 47. Ibid. 48. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Leon inaugurale au Collge de France," January 5, 1960; reprinted in Anthropologie structurale, vol. 2, p. 20. 49. Ibid., p. 24. 50. Pierre Nora, interview with the author. 51. Lvi-Strauss, "Leon inaugurale au Collge de France." 52. Claude Lvi-Strauss, De prs et de loin, p. 96. 53. Claude Lvi-Strauss, in Georges Charbonnier, Entretiens avec Claude Lvi- Strauss, p. 181. Twenty-two. Contesting the Sorbonne: The Quarrel of the Ancients and the Modems 1. Alain Boissinot, interview with the author. 2. Ibid. 3. Andr Martinet, interview with the author. 4. Jean-Claude Chevalier, interview with the author. 5. Ibid. Notes to Chapter 1\venty-three 4I9 6. Jean-Claude Chevalier, "La Notion de chez les grammairiens." Jean-Claude Chevalier, interview with the author. 8. Ibid. 9. Tzvetan Todorov, interview with the author. 10. Ibid. 11. Ibid. 12. Marina Yaguello, interview with the author. 13. Franoise Gadet, interview with the author. 14. Ibid. 15. Philippe Hamon, interview with the author. 16. lisabeth Roudinesco, interview with the author. 17. Franois Ewald, interview with the author. 18. Ibid. 19. Roger-Pol Droit, interview with the author. 20. Sylvain Auroux, interview with the author. 21. Grard Genette, interview with the author. 22. Philippe Hamon, "Littrature," in Les Sciences du langage in France au XX e sicle, p. 289. 23. Work in Linguistics and Literature. 24. Louis Hay, interview with the author. 25. Ibid. 26. "Le Vocabulaire politique et social en France de I849 I872." 27. Henri Mitterand, interview with the author. 28. Knud Togeby, Les Structures immanentes de la langue franaise. 29. Maurice Gross, in "La cration de revues dans les annes soixante," interview with Jean-Claude Chevalier and Pierre Encrev, Langue franaise, no. 63 (September I984): p. 91. 30. Jean Dubois, in ibid. 31. Andr-Georges Haudricourt, interview with the author. 32. Henri Mitterand, interview with the author. 33. Ibid. 34. Jean-Claude Chevalier and Pierre Encrev, "La cration de revues dans les an- nes soixante," p. 97. 35. A directeur d'tudes can lecture without necessarily having an advanced univer- sity degree. Barthes's published work had justified his election at the EPHE.-Trans. 36. Hamon, "Littrature," p. 289. 37. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "La structure et la forme," Cahiers de l'ISEA, no. 99 (March I960), series M; no. 7; reprinted in Anthropologie structurale, vol. 2. 38. Claude Lvi-Strauss and Roman Jakobson, L'Homme, II, no. l (January-April, I962). 39. Jean Rousset, Forme et signification: Essais sur les structures littraires de Corneille Claudel. 40. Ibid., p. vii. 41. Ibid., p. xx. Twenty-three. 1964: The Semiologie al Adventure Makes a Breakthrough 1. Joseph Sumpf, interview with the author. 2. Ibid. 3. Ibid. 420 Notes to Chapter Twenty-four 4. Michel Foucault, "Le structuralisme et l'analyse littraire," in Mission culturelle franaise Information, French embassy in Tunisia, April Io-May 10, 1987 (1965); unedited tapes of two lectures by Michel Foucault at the Club Tahar Haddad, p. II (Centre Michel-Foucault, Bibliothque du Saluchoir). 5. Ibid. 6. Tzvetan Todorov, "La description de la signification en littrature," Communi- cations, no. 4 (1964): p. 36. 7. Claude Brmond, "Le message narratif," p. 4. 8. Ibid., p. 31. 9. Le Systme de la mode. 10. Roland Barthes, Ocaniques, FR3, January 27,1988 (interview, 1970). Il. Algirdas Julien Greimas, interview with the author. 12. Roland Barthes, Le Systme de la mode, p. 9. 13. Barthes, "Les lments de smiologie," Communications, no. 4 (1964); re- printed in I.:Aventure smiologique, p. 28. 14. Ibid., p. 29. 15. Ibid., p. 51. 16. Ibid., p. 82. 17. Louis-Jean Calvet, Roland Barthes, p. 83. 18. Roland Barthes, "L'activit structuraliste," Les Lettres nouvelles (1963); re- printed in Essais critiques, p. 214. 19. Ibid., p. 215. 20. Roland Barthes, "L'imagination du signe," Arguments (1962); reprinted In Essais critiques, p. 27. 21. Ibid., p. 209. 22. Roland Barthes, interview with Georges Charbonnier, France-Culture, Decem- ber 1967; rebroadcast November 21 and 22, 1988. 23. Ibid. 24. Ibid. 25. Ibid. Twenty-four. The Golden Age of FormaI Thinking 1. Algirdas Julien Greimas, interview with the author. 2. Ibid. 3. Andr Martinet, interview with the author. 4. Algirdas Julien Greimas, interview with the author. 5. Jean-Claude Coquet, "La smiotique," in Les Sciences du langage en France au XX' sicle, p. 175. 6. Algirdas Julien, Greimas, Smantique structurale, p. 6. 7. Ibid., p. 8. 8. Algirdas Julien Greimas, interview with the author. 9. Greimas, Smantique structurale, p. 31. 10. Ibid., p. 60. 11. Ibid., p. 223. 12. Thomas Pavel, Le Mirage linguistique, p. 151. 13. Claude Brmond, Logique du rcit. 14. Claude Brmond, interview with the author. 15. Ibid. 16. Ibid. 17. Jacques Hoarau, interview with the author. Notes to Chapter Twenty-five 42I 18. Marc Vernet, interview with the author. 19. Louis Hay, interview with the author. 20. Jean-Claude Coquet, interview with the author. 21. Ibid. 22. Ibid. 23. Claude Brmond, interview with the author. 24. Ibid. 25. Andr Martinet, interview with the author. 26. Algirdas Julien Greimas, interview with the author. 27. Ibid. 28. Roland Barthes, Le Systme de la mode, p. 16. 29. Ibid., p. 17. 30. Ibid., p. 18. 31. Ibid., p. 38. 32. Ibid., p. 282. 33. Jean-Franois Revel, "Le rat et la mode," L'Express, May 22, 1967. 34. Raymond Bellour, "Entretien avec R. Barthes," Les Lettres franaises, no. II72 (March 2, 1967). 35. Julia Kristeva, "Le sens et la mode," Critique, no. 247 (December 1967): p. 1008. 36. Roland Barthes, "De la science la littrature," Times Literary Supplement (1967); reprinted in Le Bruissement de la langue, p. 17. 37. Roland Barthes, interviews with Georges Charbonnier, France-Culture, Decem- ber 1967. 38. Ibid. 39. Jacques Hoarau, interview with the author. 40. Ibid. 41. Les Idalits mathmatiques. 42. Sylvain Auroux, interview with the author. 43. Jean Piaget, Psychologie et pistmologie, p. 145. 44. Oswald Ducrot, interview with the author. 45. Ibid. 46. Gottlob Frege, Les Fondements de l'arithmtique, p. 12. 47. lisabeth Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, vol. 2, p. 410. 48. Ibid., p. 413. 49. Jol Dor, interview with the author. 50. Gennie Lemoine, interview with the author. Twenty-five. Great Confrontations 1. Roland Barthes, "Histoire et littrature: propos de Racine," Annales (May-June 1960): pp. 52 4-37. 2. Ibid., in Sur Racine, p. 157. 3. Ibid., p. 146. 4. Ibid., p. 13. 5. Ibid., p. 14. 6. Ibid., p. 21. 7. Ibid., p. 60. 8. Raymond Picard, Nouvelle Critique ou nouvelle imposture (Paris: J.-J. Pauvert, 1965), pp. 30-34. 9. Ibid., p. 52. 10. Ibid., p. 66. 422 Notes to Chapter Twenty-five 11. Roland Barthes, Ocaniques, FR3, February 8, 1988 (November 1970-May 1971). 12. Jean Dubois, interview with the author. 13. Olivier Revault d'Allonnes, interview with the author. 14. Jacqueline Piatier, Le Monde, October 23, 1965; quoted by Louis-Jean Calvet, Roland Barthes, p. l87. 15. Ibid., p. l88. 16. Ibid. 17. Roland Barthes, Critique et vrit (Paris: Seuil, 1966), p. l3. 18. Ibid., p. 35. 19. Ibid., p. 56. 20. Ibid., p. 57. 21. Ibid., p. 7I. 22. Ren Pommier, Assez dcod (Paris: ditions Roblot, 1978), and R. Barthes, Ras le bol! (Paris: ditions Roblot, 1987), in which he attacks Barthes and the "jobarthi- ans." He writes, among other things: "The idiocies of a R. Barthes are, for me, an insult to human intelligence" (p. 40); "When I read him, I never say to myself that R. Barthes is too intelligent; I constantly say to myself, with an ever-present surprise: how can you be such an ass?" (p. 27). The tone is noteworthy. 23. Georges Gurvitch, "Le concept de structure sociale," Cahiers internationaux de sociologie, no. 19 (l955). 24. Ibid., p. 3 I. 25. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, p. 322. 26. Gilles Gaston-Granger, "vnement et structure dans les sciences de l'homme," Cahiers de l'ISEA (December 1959). 27. Ibid., p. l68. 28. Ibid., p. l74. 29. Ibid., p. l75. 30. Gilles Gaston-Granger, interview with the author. 31. Ibid. 32. Roger Establet, interview with the author. 33. Ibid. 34. Pierre Ansart, interview with the author. 35. Ibid. 36. Jean Duvignaud, interview with the author. 37. Jean Duvignaud; Le Langage perdu, p. 2l5. 38. Claude Lvi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, p. 268. 39. Ibid., p. I. 40. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Le Totmisme aujourd'hui, p. 25. 41. Ibid., p. I28. 42. Lvi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, p. l04. 43. Claude Roy, "Un grand livre civilis: La Pense sauvage," Libration, June 19, 1962. 44. Edmond Ortigues, Critique, no. l89 (February 1963): p. l43. 45. Jean Lacroix, Le Monde, November 27, I962. 46. Robert Kanters, Le Figaro littraire, June 3-23, I962. 47. Roland Barthes, "Sociologie et socio-Iogique," Informations sur les sciences sociales, no. 4 (December 1962): p. 242. 48. Lvi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, p. 254. 49. Ibid., p. 257. 50. Ibid., p. 258. Notes to Chapter Twenty-six 423 51. Ibid., p. 261. 52. Ibid., p. 262. 53. Pierre Verstraeten, "Claude Lvi-Strauss ou la tentation du nant," Les Temps modernes, no. 206 (July 1963): p. 83. 54. Claude Lvi-Strauss, remarks quoted by Jean-Marie Domenach, interview with the author. 55. Jean-Marie Domenach, interview with the author. 56. Paul Ricoeur, Esprit (November 1963): p. 605. 57. Ibid., p. 644. 58. Ibid., p. 618. 59. Claude Lvi-Strauss, in ibid., p. 637. 60. Andr Green, "La psychanalyse devant l'opposition de l'histoire et de la struc- ture," Critique, no. 194 (July 1963). 61. Ibid., p. 661. Twenty-six. Signifying Chains 1. Jean Laplanche, "Une rvolution sans cesse occulte," Communication aux journes scientifiques de l'Association Internationale d'Histoire de la Psychanalyse, April 23-24, 1988. 2. Jacques Lacan, "L'excommunication," Ornicar? (1977). 3. See lisabeth Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, vol. 2, pp. 399-43 4. Ibid., p. 383. 5. Jacques Lacan, crits, p. 805. 6. Marcel Arriv, Linguistique et psychanalyse, p. 12. 7. Jean Allouch, Littoral, nos. 23-24 (Oetober 1987): P.S. 8. "Objet petit a": "The 'a' in questions stands for 'autre' (other), the concept hav- ing been developed out of the Freudian 'object' and Lacan's own exploitation of 'other- ness.' The 'petit a' (small 'a') differentiates the object from (while relating it toi the 'Autre' or 'grand Autre' (the capitalized 'Other'). However, Lacan refuses to comment on either term here, leaving the reader to develop an appreciation of the concepts in the course of their use. Furthermore, Lacan insists that 'objet petit a' should remain un- translated, thus acquiring, as it were, the status of an algebraic sign" (crits: A Selec- tion, p. xi).-Trans. 9. Jean-David Nasio, Les Sept Concepts cruciaux de la psychanalyse. 10. Martin Heidegger, Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. A. Hofstadter (New York: Harper and Row, 1971 (1975)). Il. Alain Juranville, Lacan et la philosophie, p. 167. 12. Serge Leclaire, interview with the author. 13. Jacques-Alain Miller, Ornicar? no. 24 (1981): p. 43. 14. Lacan, crits, p. 863. 15. Juranville, Lacan et la philosophie, p. 175. 16. Ibid., p. 195. 17. Ibid., p. 286. 18. Gennie Lemoine, interview with the author. 19. Serge Leclaire, "L'objet a dans la cure," Rompre les charmes, p. 174. 20. Jean Clavreul, interview with the author. 21. Jol Dor, interview with the author. 22. Jean Laplanche, interview with the author. 23. Andr Green, "Le bon plaisir," France-Culture, February 25, 1989. 424 Notes ta Chapter 24. Ibid. 25. Andr Green, interview with the author. 26. Andr Green, "Le langage dans la psychanalyse," in Langages, Les Rencontres psychanalytiques d'Aix en Provence. 27. Lacan, crits, p. 873. 28. Andr Green, "Le langage dans la psychanalyse," p. 23 I. 29. Jean-Marie Benoist, interview with the author. 30. Grard Mendel, interview with the author. 31. Bernard Sichre, interview with the author. 32. Ibid. 33. Jacques Lacan, "Subversion of the Subject and Dialectic of Desire," in crits: A Selection, p. 297. 34. Andr Green, I:Affect. 35. Andr Green, interview with the author. 36. Ibid. 37. Charles BaUy, Le Langage et la vie. 38. Serge Viderman, interview with the author. 39. Wladimir Granoff, interview with the author. 40. Franois Roustang, Lacan, p. 58. 41. Jean Clavreul, interview with the author. 42. Serge Leclaire, interview with the author. 43. Jean Laplanche, interview with the author. 44. Claude Dumzil, interview with the author. Twenty-seven. Mythology's Earth Is Round 1. Claude Lvi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked: Introduction to a Science of Mythology, vol. I, p. 3. 2. Claude Lvi-Strauss, The Naked Man: Introduction to a Science of Mythology, vol. 4, p. 639 3. Lvi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked, p. 245. 4. Claude Lvi-Strauss, From Honey to Ashes: Introduction to a Science of My thol- ogy, vol. 2, p. 472. 5. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Paroles donnes, p. I4. 6. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "The Structural Study of Myths" (I9 5 5); reprinted in Struc- turai Anthropology, pp. 202-28. 7. Ibid., pp. 207-8. 8. Claude Lvi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, p. I30. 9. Lvi-Strauss, Structural Anthropology, p. 220. 10. Lvi Strauss, The Savage Mind, p. I7. 11. Jean-Marie Benoist, La Rvolution structurale, p. 32. 12. Lvi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked, p. I8. 13. Lvi-Strauss, "L'avenir de ethnologie, I959-I960," in Paroles donnes, p. 34. 14. Lvi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked, p. 341. 15. Lvi-Strauss, From Honey to Ashes, p. 303. 16. Ibid., p. 256. 17. Claude Lvi-Strauss, interview with Raymond BeUour, Les Lettres franaises, no. II65 (January I2, I967); reprinted in Le Livre des autres, p. 38. 18. Ibid., p. 38. 19. Lvi-Strauss, From Honey to Ashes, p. 356. 20. Jean Pouillon, La Quinzaine littraire, August I-3I, I968, p. 21. Notes to Chapter Twenty-eight 425 21. Claude Lvi-Strauss, interview with Raymond Bellour, Le Monde, November 5, 197I. 22. Claude Lvi-Strauss, The Naked Man, p. 598. 23. Ibid., pp. 621-22. 24. Ibid., p. 629. 25. Catherine Backs-Clment, in Le Magazine littraire (November 1971), points out that this analogy works with a single exception. 26. Lvi-Strauss, The Naked Man, p. 649. 27. Ibid., p. 653. 28. Ibid., p. 687. 29. Ibid. 30. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Le Magazine littraire (November 1971). 31. Jean Duvignaud, Le Langage perdu, p. 243. 32. Lvi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked, p. 341. 33. Ibid., p. 240. 34. Thomas Pavel, Le Mirage linguistique, p. 48. 35. Lvi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked, p. 135. 36. Manfred Frank, Qu'est-ce que le no-structuralisme? p. 56. 37. Lvi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked, p. 16. 38. Lvi-Strauss, From Honey to Ashes, p. 475. 39. Lvi-Strauss, The Naked Man, p. 322. 40. Ibid., p. 607. 41. Ibid.; quote taken from Marcel Proust, Le Temps retrouv, vol. 2 (Paris: Galli- mard, 1954), p. 15, 42. Benoist, La Rvolution structurale, p. 275. 43. Lvi-Strauss, The Naked Man, p. 694. 44. Jean-Marie Domenach, "Le requiem structuraliste," in Le Sauvage et l'ordina- teur, p. 81. 45. Ibid., p. 85. 46. Jean-Marie Domenach, interview with the author. , Twenty-eight. Africa: The Continental Divide of Structuralism 1. Georges Balandier, interview with the author. 2. Ibid. 3. Claude Lvi-Strauss, The Savage Mind, pp. 234-35 n. 4. Georges Balandier, interview with the author. 5. Ibid. 6. Ibid. 7. Georges Balandier, Histoire d'autres, p. 187. 8. Ibid., p. 183. 9. Georges Balandier, Anthropologie politique. 10. Ibid., p. 22. 11. Meyer Fortes and E. E. Evans-Pritchard, eds., African Political Systems, 1940. 12. Balandier, Anthropologie politique, p. 27. 13. Lundis de l'histoire, France-Culture, March II, 1968. 14. Marc Aug, interview with the author. 15. Ibid. 16. Ibid. 17. Dan Sperber, interview with the author. 18. In the French university system, the first two years of training, the first cycle, cul- 426 Notes to Twenty-nine minate in a DEUG (Diplme d'tudes universitaires the third year is the sec- ond cycle and leads to a Licence, and, during the third cycle, one prepares a matrise, after which a doctoral thesis. The first part of this cycle is the DEA or Diplme d'tndes approfondies, which is crowned, in its turn, by a doctoral thesis.-Trans. 19. Dan Sperber, interview with the author. 20. Ibid. 21. Ibid. 22. Claude Meillassoux, interview with the author. 23. Ibid. 24. Ibid. 25. Jean Duvignaud, interview with the author. 26. Jean Duvignaud, Chebika (1991). 27. Remparts d'argile. 28. Jean Duvignaud, "Aprs le fonctionalisme et le structuralisme, quoi?" in Une anthropologie des turbulences. Hommage G. Balandier, p. 151. 29. Ibid., p. 152. 30. A research group created by Lvi-Strauss within the institutional framework of the Collge de France. Izard therefore belonged to two different research institutions, the one at the Collge and the other at the EHESS. 31. Michel Izard, interview with the author. 32. Jean Pouillon, interview with the author. Twenty-nine. Reviews 1. La Psychanalyse, no. l (1956): p. iv. 2. La Linguistique, no. l (1966); director: Andr Martinet; general secretary, Georges Mounin. 3. Langages, no. l (March 1966), Larousse; editorial board: Roland Barthes, Jean Dubois, Aigirdas Julien Greimas, Bernard Pottier, Bernard Qumada, Nicolas Ruwet. 4. Ibid., Introduction. 5. Jean-Claude Chevalier, Pierre Encrev, Langue franaise, no. 63 (September 1984): p. 95 6. Algirdas Julien Greimas, Langages, no. l (March 1966): p. 96. 7. Jean Dubois, interview with the author. 8. Communications, no. l (Paris: Seuil, 1961), Introduction: pp. 1-2. 9. Communications, editorial board: Roland Barthes, Claude Brmond, Georges Friedmann, Edgar Morin, Violette Morin. 10. Contributors to Communications, no. 8, were Roland Barthes, Algirdas Julien Greimas, Claude Brmond, Umberto Eco, Jules Gritti, Violette Morin, Christian Metz, Tzvetan Todorov, and Grard Genette. 11. Tel Quel, secretary-general and director: Jean-Edern Hallier, editorial board: Boisrouvray, Jacques Coudol, Jean-Edern Hallier, Jean-Ren Huguenin, Renaud Matig- non, Philippe Sollers. 12. Jean-Pierre Faye, interview with the author. 13. Tel Quel, no. l (1960, Seuil), quote of Nietzsche. 14. Ibid., p. 3. 15. Marcelin Pleynet, interview with the author. 16. Ibid. 17. Ibid. 18. Ibid. Notes to Chapter Thirty 427 19. Ibid. 20. Tel Quel, no. 47 (fall I971): p. 142. 21. Ibid. 22. Claude Brmond, interview with the author. 23. Roland Barthes, Ocaniques, FR3 (I970-71),]anuary 27, 1988. 24. Julia Kristeva, "Le bon plaisir," France-Culture, December 10, 1988. 25. Jean-Pierre Faye, interview with the author. 26. Frdrique Matonti, "Entre Argenteuil et les barricades: La Nouvelle Critique et les sciences sociales," Cahiers de l'Institut d'histoire du temps prsent, no. II (April 1989): p. 102. 27. Louis Althusser, "Freud et Lacan," La Nouvelle Critique, nos. 161-62 (1964). 28. Jacques Milhau, "Les dbats philosophiques des annes soixante," La Nouvelle Critique, no. 130 (1980): pp. 50-51. 29. "Tel Quel rpond; prsentation," La Nouvelle Critique (November-December 1967): p. 5 30. Matonit, "Entre Argenteuil et les barricades," p. 18. 31. Pierre Vilar, "Les mots et les choses dans la pense conomique," La Nouvelle Critique, no. 5 (1967); Jeannette Colombel, "Les mots de Foucault et les choses," La Nouvelle Critique, no. 5 (1967); Georges Mounin, "Linguistique, structuralisme et marxisme," La Nouvelle Critique, no. 7 (1967); Lucien Sve, "Marxisme et sciences de l'homme," La Nouvelle Critique, no. 2 (1967). 32. Robert Linhart, quoted by Herv Hamon and Philippe Rotman, Gnration, vol. l,p. 313. 33. Dominique Lecourt, interview with the author. 34. Ibid. 35. Ibid. 36. Ibid. 37. Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, reprinted in Socit du Graphe, nos. 1-2 (Paris: Seuil,1969). Thirty. Ulm or Saint-Cloud: Althusser or Touki? 1. Jean-Toussaint Desanti, Un destin philosophique, p. 129. 2. Sylvain Auroux, interview with the author. 3. Jean-Toussaint Desanti, interview with the author. 4. Ibid. 5. Jean-Toussaint Desanti, Autrement, no. 102 (November 1988): p. II6. 6. Jean-Toussaint Desanti, interview with the author. 7. Ibid. 8. Sylvain Auroux, interview with the author. 9. Ibid. 10. Ibid. 11. Jacques Bouveresse, interview with the author. 12. Ibid. 13. Ibid. 14. Louis Althusser, Manifestes philosophiques de Feuerbach. 15. Pierre Macherey, interview with the author. 16. Ibid. 17. Roger Establet, interview with the author. 18. Ibid. 428 Notes to Chapter Thirty-one 19. lisabeth Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, vol. 2, p. 386. 20. Pierre Macherey, interview with the author. 21. Ibid. 22. Jacques Rancire, interview with the author. 23. Ibid. 24. Ibid. 25. Ibid. 26. Ibid. 27. Ibid. 28. Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, vol. 2, p. 387. Thirty-one. The Althusserian Explosion 1. Vincent Descombes, Le Mme et l'autre, p. 147. 2. Letter from Althusser to Jean Guitton, July 1972, in Lire, no. 148 (January 1988): p. 85 3. Jean Guitton, in ibid., p. 89. 4. Vincent Descombes, interview with the author. 5. Ibid. 6. tienne Balibar, interview with the author. 7. "Ouverture d'un dbat: marxisme et humanisme," La Nouvelle Critique, no. 164 (March 1965): p.!. 8. Michel Simon, La Nouvelle Critique, no. 165 (April 1965): p. 127. 9. Pierre Macherey, "Marxisme et humanisme," La Nouvelle Critique, no. 166 (May 1965): p. 132. 10. Michel Verret, La Nouvelle Critique, no. 168 (July-August 1965): p. 96. 11. Roger Garaudy, quoted by Jeannine Verds-Leroux in Le Rveil des somnam- bules, p. 296; full text of the meeting of philosophers at Choisy in January 1966, pp. 125-48. 12. Daniel Lindenberg, Le Marxisme introuvable, p. 38. 13. Interview 64, in Verds-Leroux, Le Rveil des somnambules, p. 197. 14. Central committee of the PCF, March II-13, 1966, Cahiers du communisme (May-June 1966), quoted in ibid., pp. II9-20. 15. Roger-Pol Droit, interview with the author. 16. Jacques Bouveresse, interview with the author. 17. Dominique Lecourt, interview with the author. 18. Pierre Macherey, interview with the author. 19. J. Verds-Leroux, Le Rveil des somnambules, p. 295. 20. Louis Althusser, Lire Le Capital, vol. l, p. 16. 21. Ibid., p. 20. 22. Daniel Becquemont, interview with the author. 23. Althusser, Lire Le Capital, vol. l, p. 26. 24. Dominique Lecourt, interview with the author. 25. Louis Althusser, Pour Marx, p. 27. 26. Ibid., p. 39. 27. Ibid., p. 171. 28. Ibid., p. 108. 29. Ibid., p. 196. 30. Pierre Vilar, interview with the author. 31. Paul Valadier, interview with the author. 32. Althusser, Pour Marx, p. 248. Notes to Chapter 33. Althusser, Lire Le voL 2, p. 59. 34. Ibid., p. 47. 35. K. Naf, "Marxisme ou structuralisme?" in Contre Althusser (Paris: roll8, 1974), p. 192. 36. Althusser, Lire Le Capital, voL 2, p. I7I. 37. Jean-Marie Vincent, "Le thoricisme et sa rectification," in Contre Althusser, p.226. 38. Vincent Descombes, interview with the author. 39. Althusser, Pour Marx, p. 212 n. 48. 40. Jean-Marie Benoist, La Rvolution structurale, p. 85. 41. Althusser, Pour Marx, p. 236. 42. tienne Balibar, interview with the author. 43. tienne Balibar, Lire Le Capital, vol. 2, p. 204. 44. Ibid., p. 205. 45. Ibid., p. 249. 46. Althusser, Lire Le Capital, vol. l, p. 170. Thirty-two. Marxism's Second Wind 1. Alain Badiou, "Le (re)commencement du matrialisme dialectique," Critique (May 1967). 2. Pierre Macherey, interview with the author. 3. Badiou, "Le (re)commencement du matrialisme dialectique," p. 441. 4. Jolle Proust, interview with the author. 5. Paul Henry, interview with the author. 6. Ibid. 7. Thomas Herbert, "Rflexions sur la situation thorique des sciences sociales, spcialement de la psychologie sociale," Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, no. 2 (March-April 1966); Thomas Herbert, "Remarques pour une thorie gnrale des idologies," Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, no. 9 (summer 1968): pp. 74-92. 8. Michel Pcheux, L'Analyse automatique du discours. 9. Paul Henry, "pistmologie de L'Analyse automatique du discours de Michel Pcheux," in Introduction to the Translation of M. Pcheux's Analyse automatique du discours (text given by Paul Henry). 10. Ibid. 11. Ibid. 12. Emmanuel Terray, interview with the author. 13. Emmanuel Terray, Le Marxisme devant les socits primitives. 14. Emmanuel Terray, interview with the author. 15. Marc Aug, interview with the author. 16. Marc Aug, J,.,e Rivage Alladian. 17. Marc Aug, interview with the author. 18. La Monnaie chez Marx. 19. Charles Bettelheim, Calcul conomique et formes de proprit. 20. Robert Linhart, Lnine, les paysans, Taylor. 21. Louis Althusser, "Freud et Lacan," La Nouvelle Critique, nos. 161-62 (December 1964-January 1965). 22. Ibid.; reprinted in Positions (Paris: ditions sociales, 1976), p. 16. 23. Ibid., p. 15. 24. Ibid., p. 26. 430 Notes ta Chapter Thirty-three Thirty-three. I966: Annum mirabile for Structuralism A Watershed Year 1. Gilles Lapauge, "Encore un effort et j'aurai pous mon temps," La Quinzaine littraire, no. 459 (March 16-30,1986): p. 30. 2. Roland Barthes, Essais critiques (Paris: Points-Seuil, I98I), "Avant-Propos: 1971," p. 7 3. Philippe Hamon, interview with the author. 4. Renaud Matignon, L'Express, May 2, 1966. 5. Algirdas Julien Greimas, quoted by Jean-Claude Chevalier and Pierre Encrev, Langue franaise, p. 97. 6. Jean Pouillon, interview with the author. 7. Franois Wahl, interview with the author. 8. Le Nouvel Observateur, no. 91 (August 10, 1966); quoted by Anne-Sophie Perriaux, "Le structuralisme en France," DEA thesis directed by Jacques Julliard, September 1987, p. 34. 9. Information provided by Pierre Nora. 10. Pierre Nora, interview with the author. Il. Masse et puissance. 12. Ethnologie et langage. 13. Les tapes de la pense sociologique. 14. Pierre Nora, interview with the author. 15. La Religion romaine archaque. 16. Georges Dumzil, interview with Jean-Pierre Salgas, La Quinzaine littraire, no. 459 (March 16, 1986). 17. L'Amour de l'art. 18. Pour une thorie de la production littraire. 19. Le Normal et le pathologique. 20. Les Paysans de Languedoc. 21. Louis XIV et vingt millions de Franais. 22. La Mditerrane et le monde mtiterranen l'poque de Philippe II. 23. Pense formelle et science de l'homme. 24. Philippe Hamon, interview with the author. 25. Forme et signification. 26. Jacques Lacan, Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, no. 3 (May 1966): pp. 5-13. 27. Algirdas Julien Greimas, "L'analyse structurale du rcit," Communications, no. 8 (1966); reprinted by Points-Seuil (1981), p. 34. 28. Claude Brmond, interview with the author. 29. Ibid. 30. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "La structure et la forme," Cahiers de l'Institut de science conomique applique, no. 9 (March 1960), M series, no. 7: pp. 3-36. 31. Lvi-Strauss, in ibid.; reprinted in Anthropologie structurale, vol. 2, p. 159. 32. Vladimir Propp, in the Appendix to Morphologia della fiaba. 33. Vladimir Propp, Les Racines historiques du conte (Theory and History of Folklore). 34. Claude Brmond, interview with the author. 35. Umberto Eco, Communications, no. 8 (1966); reprinted by Points-Seuil, 1981, P9 8 . 36. Tzvetan Todorov, in ibid., p. IF. 37. "Problmes du structuralisme," Les Temps modernes, no. 246 (November 1966); Notes to Chapter Thirty-four 431 contributors: Jean Pouillon, Marc Barbut, Greimas, Maurice Godelier, Pierre Bourdieu, Pierre Macherey, Jacques Ehrmann. 38. Jean Pouillon, in ibid., p. 769. 39. Ibid., p. 772. 40. Algirdas Julien Greimas, in ibid.; reprinted in Du sens, p. 106. 41. Ibid., p. 107. 42. Maurice Godelier, "Systme, structure et contradiction dans Le Capital," Les Temps modernes, no. 246 (November 1966): p. 832. 43. Ibid., p. 829. 44. Pierre Bourdieu, "Champ intellectuel et projet crateur," in ibid., p. 866. 45. Roland Barthes, interview in Althia (February 1966): p. 218. 46. "Structuralismes, idologies et mthodes," Esprit, no. 360 (May 1967); articles by Jean-Marie Domenach, Mikel Dufrenne, Paul Ricoeur, Jean Ladrire, Jean Cuisenier, Pierre Burge!in, Yves Bertherat, and Jean Cornilh. 47. Jean-Marie Domenach, "Le systme et la personne," Esprit, no. 360 (May 1967): pp. 771- 80. 48. Mike! Dufrenne, "La philosophie du no-positivisme," in ibid., pp. 781-800. 49. Paul Ricoeur, "La structure, le mot, l'vnement," in ibid., pp. 801-21. 50. L'Arc, no. 30 (fourth quarter 1966). 51. Bernard Pingaud, in ibid., p. 1. 52. Jean-Paul Sartre, in ibid., pp. 87-88. 53. Ibid., p. 89. 54. Ibid., pp. 91-92. 55. Ibid., p. 93. 56. Ibid., p. 94. 57. Jacques Lacan, Le Figaro littraire, December 29,1966, p. 4. 58. Ibid. 59. Jean-Franois Revel, "Sartre en ballottage," I:Express, no. 802 (November 7-13, 1966). 60. Les Chemins actuels de la critique, Cerisy proceedings. 61. See lisabeth Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, vol. 2, p. 414. 62. Jacques Derrida, "De la grammatologie," Critique, no. 223-24 (December 1965). 63. The Structuralist Controversy: The Languages of Criticism and the Sciences of Man, ed. Richard Marksey and Eugenio Donato (Baltimore and London: Johns Hop- kins University Press, 1970 and 1972). 64. Jean-Pierre Vernant, interview with the author. 65. Ibid. Thirty-four. 1966: Annum mirabile (II): Foucault Sells like Hotcakes 1. Miche! Foucault, The arder of Things, p. 208. 2. Michel Foucault, Lectures pour tous (1966), INA document, shown on Oca- niques, FR3, January 13, 1988. 3. Ibid. 4. Ibid. 5. Ibid. 6. Jean Lacroix, "La fin de l'humanisme," Le Monde, June 9, 1966. 7. Robert Kanters, "Tu causes, tu causes, c'est tout ce que tu sais faire," Le Figaro, June 23, 1966. 8. Franois Chatelet, "L'homme, ce Narcisse incertain," La Quinzaine littraire, April 1, 1966. 432 Notes to Chapter Thirty-five 9. Madeleine Chapsal, I.:Express, no. 779 (May 23-29, I966): pp. II9-2I. 10. Gilles Deleuze, "L'homme, une existence douteuse," Le Nouvel Observateur, June I, I966. 11. Michel Foucault, interview, La Quinzaine littraire, no. 5 (May I5, I966). 12. Crise de la conscience europenne. 13. Raymond Bellour, Les Lettres franaises, no. II25 (March 3I, I966); reprinted in Le Livre des autres, p. I4. 14. Didier ribon, Michel Foucault, p. I89. 15. Jean Piaget, Le Structuralisme, p. I08. 16. Franois Ewald, interview with the author. 17. Foucault, The arder of Things, p. xxiii. 18. Jean-Marie Benoist, La Rvolution structurale, p. 202. 19. Michel Foucault, France-Culture, rebroadcast, June I984. 20. Benoist, La Rvolution structurale, p. 27. 21. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Tristes Tropiques, p. 4I3. 22. Michel Foucault, The arder of Things, p. 379. 23. Ibid. 24. Benoist, La Rvolution structurale, p. 38. 25. Foucault, The arder of Things, p. 369. 26. Ibid., p. 32.7. 27. Ibid., pp. 368-69. 28. Ibid., p. 208. 29. Ibid., p. 332. 30. Pierre Ansart, interview with the author. 31. Foucault, The arder of Things, p. xxii. 32. Ibid., p. I7. 33. Ibid., p. 30. 34. Ibid., p. 47-48. 35. Ibid., p. 6I. 36. Ibid., p. I36. 37. Ibid., p. 226. 38. Ibid., p. 284. 39. Ibid., p. 370. 40. Michel Foucault, France-Culture, July IO, I969. 41. Hubert Dreyfus and Paul Rabinov, Foucault, un parcours philosophique, p. 7I. 42. Foucault, The arder of Things, pp. 26I-62. 43. tienne Balibar, interview with the author. Thirty-five. I966: Annum mirabile (III): Julia Cornes to Paris 1. Philippe Sollers, "Le bon plaisir de J. Kristeva," France-Culture, December IO, I988. 2. Philippe Sollers, "Littrature et totalit" (I966), in L'criture et l'exprience des limites, p. 73. 3. Stphane Mallarm, quoted by Sollers, in ibid., p. 87. 4. Jean Dubois, interview with the author. 5. Pour une thorie de la production littraire. 6. Ibid., p. I65. 7. Ibid., p. I67. 8. Ibid., p. I74. Notes ta Chapter Thirty-six 433 9. Grard Genette, "Structuralisme et critique littraire, " L'Arc, no. 26; renrmted in Figures, vol. l, p. 16r. 10. Ibid., p. 156. 11. Macherey, Pour une thorie de la production littraire, p. 88. 12. Antoinette Fouque, "Le bon plaisir," France-Culture, June 1989. 13. Jacques Lacan, "La science et la vrit," Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, no. 1 (1966); reprinted in crits, vol. 2, p. 226. 14. Ibid. 15. Lacan, crits, vol. 1, p. 80. 16. Rationalit et irrationalit en conomie. 17. Maurice Godelier, interview with the author. 18. Godelier, Rationalit et irrationalit en conomie, p. 95. 19. Maurice Godelier, interview with the author. Thirty-six. The Postmodern Hour Sounds 1. Carl Schorske, Fin de sicle Vienna. 2. Flix Torrs, Dj vu, p. 142. 3. See Jean-Luc Marion, "Une modernit sans avenir," Le Dbat, no. 4 (September 1980): pp. 54-60. 4. Michel Foucault, The Order of Things, p. 208. 5. Paul Valadier, interview with the author. 6. Jean Jamin, interview with the author. 7. Jean-Franois Lyotard, Le Magazine littraire, no. 225 (December 1985): p. 43. 8. Michel Foucault, interview with K. Boesers, "Die Folter, das ist die Vernunft," Literaturmagazin, no. 8 (Reibek: Rowohlt, 1977). 9. Michel Foucault, remarks made at Maurice Clavel's in Vzelay in 1977, Ocaniques, January 13, 1988. 10. Maurice Godelier, interview with the author. 11. Daniel Dory, interview with the author. 12. Marcel Gauchet, interview with the author. 13. Jean Antoine de Condorcet, Esquisse d'un tableau historique des progrs de l'esprit humain (1793)' 14. Rgis Debray, Critique de la raison politique, p. 290. 15. Ibid., p. 299. 16. Ibid., p. 52. 17. Jean Chesneaux, De la modernit, p. 50. 18. Franois Furet, "Les intellectuels franais et le structuralisme," Preuves, no. 92 (February 1967); reprinted in l}Atelier de l'histoire. 19. Michel Foucault, Arts, June 15, 1966. 20. Gilles Deleuze, Le Nouvel Observateur, April 5, 1967; reprinted in Lucien Sve, Structuralisme et dialectique. 21. Pierre Nora, Les Lieux de mmoire, La Rpublique, p. xviii. 22. Gilles Lipovetsky, L're du vide: Essais sur l'individualisme contemporain, p. IL 23. Jean-Franois Lyotard, La Condition post-moderne (Paris: Minuit, 1979), p. II (The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge, p. 3). 24. Ibid., p. 39. 25. Ibid., p. 41. 26. Claude Lvi-Strauss, interview with Jean-Marie Benoist, Le Monde, January 21, 1979 27. Claude Lvi-Strauss, Anthropologie structurale, vol. 2, p. 65. 434 Notes ta Chapter Thirty-seven 28. Claude Lvi-Strauss, The Naked Man, p. 694. 29. Michel Foucault, interview with Bernard-Henri Lvy, Le Nouvel Observateur, March 12, 1977; republished on June 29, 1984. 30. Pierre Daix, Structuralisme et rvolution culturelle, p. 29. 31. Paul Valadier, interview with the author. Thirty-seven. Nietzschean-Heideggerian Roots 1. Martin Heidegger, Questions, vol. l, p. 188. 2. Pierre Fougeyrollas, interview with the author. 3. Friedrich Nietzsche, Human, ail too human, vol. l, paragraph 248, pp. 117-18. 4. Ibid., vol. 2, paragraph 463, p. 169. 5. Jrgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: I2 Lectures. 6. Friedrich Nietzsche, Considrations inactuelles, vol. 2, p. 327. 7. Friedrich Nietzsche, Untimely Meditations, p. 62. 8. Nietzsche, Human, ail too human, vol. 2, paragraph 239, p. 114. 9. Ibid., paragraph 473, p. 173. 10. Ibid. 11. Gianni Vattimo, La Fin de la modernit, p. II. 12. Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, Heidegger et les modernes, p. 82. 13. Martin Heidegger, "Le discours du rectorat" (May 27, 1933), Le Dbat, no. 27 (November 1983): p. 97. 14. Georges Steiner, Martin Heidegger, p. 87. 15. Nietzsche, Human, ail too human, vol. l, p. 52. 16. Ibid., vol. l, paragraph 107, p. 57 (Hollingdale). 17. Martin Heidegger, An Introduction to Metaphysics. 18. Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism Is a Humanism. 19. Martin Heidegger, Lettre sur l'humanisme, p. 107. 20. Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. 21. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science, p. 336. 22. Rey, "La philosophie du monde scientifique et industriel," in Histoire de la philosophie, pp. 151-87. 23. Michel Foucault, Hommage Hyppolite, p. 168. 24. Friedrich Nietzsche, La Volont de puissance, vol. l, pp. 79 and 141. 25. Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, La Pense 68, pp. 28-36. 26. Georges-Elia Sarfati, interview with the author. 27. Michel Foucault, Les Nouvelles littraires, June 28, 1984. 28. Michel Foucault, Actes du Colloque de Royaumont: Nietzsche, Freud, Marx (Paris: Minuit, 1967 [1964]), p. 189. 29. Michel Foucault, The Order of Things, pp. 384-85. 30. Ibid., p. 353. 31. Foucault, Hommage Hyppolite, p. 150. 32. Jean Duvignaud, Le Langage perdu, p. 22 5. 33. Foucault, Les Nouvelles littraires, June 28, 1984. 34. Maurice Pinguet, Le Dbat, no. 41 (September-November 1986). 35. Foucault, The Order of Things, p. 343. 36. Marcel Gauchet, interview with the author. 37. lisabeth Roudinesco, Les Enjeux philosophiques des annes cinquante, p. 93. 38. lisabeth Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, vol. 2, p. 309. 39. Jacques Lacan, La Psychanalyse, vol. 1, p. 6. 40. Roudinesco, Histoire de la psychanalyse en France, vol. 2, pp. 309-10. Notes to Chapter Thirty-eight 435 41. Bertrand interview with the author. 42. lisabeth Roudinesco, interview with the author. 43. Victor Fadas, Heidegger and Nazism, ed. Joseph Margolis and Tom Rockmore (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1989). Born in Chile, Fadas teaches in Berlin and was a student of Heidegger. ln his book, he argued that Heidegger had been a vol- untary Nazi, his position based on lifelong convictions. This thesis created a contro- versy in France over the relationship between philosophy and politics.-Trans. 44. Jacques Derrida, France-Culture, March 21, 1988. 45. Jacques Derrida, Positions, p. 18. 46. Le Facteur de la vrit. Thirty-eight. Growing Pains 1. Jean Jamin, interview with the author. 2. Bernard Ogilvie, interview with the author. 3. Maurice Godelier, interview with the author. 4. Ibid. 5. Jean-Louis Fabiani, Les Enjeux philosophiques des annes cinquante, p. 125. 6. Paul Valadier, interview with the author. 7. Jean Viet, Les Mthodes structuralistes, p. II. 8. Vincent Descombes, Le Mme et l'autre, p. 96. 9. Ibid., p. 98. 10. Pierre Bourdieu, Choses dites, p. 16. 11. Michel Foucault (1977), Revue de mtaphysique et de morale, no. l (January- March 1985): p. 4. 12. Louis Pinto, Les Philosophes entre le lyce et l'avant-garde, p. 68. 13. tienne Balibar, interview with the author. 14. Pinto, Les Philosophes entre le lyce et l'avant-garde, p. 78. 15. Ibid., p. 96. 16. Fabiani, Les Enjeux philosophiques des annes cinquante, p. Il6. 17. Franois Dosse, L'Histoire en miettes. 18. Michelle Perrot, interview with the author. 19. Claude Lvi-Strauss, interview, Libration, June 2, 1983. 20. Louis-Jean Calvet, interview with the author. 21. Thomas Pavel, Le Mirage linguistique, p. 61. 22. Georges Balandier, interview with the author. 23. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "Leon inaugurale au Collge de France," January 5, 1960, in Anthropologie structurale vol. 2, p. 27. 24. Claude Lvi-Strauss, The Naked Man, p. 692. 25. Claude Lvi-Strauss, The View from Afar, p. Il8. 26. Claude Lvi-Strauss, "The Place of Anthropology in the Social Sciences," in Structural Anthropology, p. 359. 27. Maurice Godelier, interview with the author. 28. Franois Furet, "Les intellectuels franais et le structuralisme," Preuves, no. 92 (February 1967): p. 6; reprinted in L'Atelier de l'histoire, p. 42. 29. Jean Duvignaud, interview with the author. 30. Ibid. 31. Marcel Gauchet, interview with the author. 32. Pavel, Le Mirage linguistique, p. 188. Bibliography Adler, Alfred. Sminaire de Michel Izard. Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, November 17, 1988. Allouch, Jean. Littoral, nos. 23-24 (October 1987). Althusser, Louis. "Freud et Lacan." La Nouvelle Critique, nos. 161-62 (December 1964-January 1965); reprinted in Positions (Paris: ditions sociales, 1976). ---. Lire Le Capital. Vol. 1. Paris: Petite Collection Maspero, 1971 (1965). ---. Manifestes philosophiques de Feuerbach. Paris: PUF, 1960. ---. Pour Marx. Paris: Maspero, 1965. Aris, Philippe. Un historien du dimanche. Paris: Le Seuil, 1982. Aron, Raymond. Les tapes de la pense sociologique. Paris: Gallimard, 1967. Arriv, Marcel. Linguistique et psychanalyse. Paris: Klincksieck, 1987. Aug, Marc. Le Rivage Alladian. Paris: ORSTOM, 1969. Badiou, Alain. "Le (re}commencement du matrialisme dialectique." Critique (May 1967) Balandier, Georges. Anthropologie politique. Paris: PUF, 1967. ---. Histoire d'autres. Paris: Stock, 1977. Balibar, tienne. Lire Le Capital. Vol. 2. Paris: Maspero, 1967 (1965). Bally, Charles. Le Langage et la vie. Paris: Droz, 1965 (1913). Barthes, Roland. I.:Aventure smiologique. Paris: Seuil, 1985. (The Semiotic Challenge. Trans. Richard Howard [New York: Hill and Wang, 1988].) ---. Critique et vrit. Paris: Seuil, 1966. ---. "De la science la littrature." Times Literary Supplement (1967); reprinted in Le Bruissement de la langue (Paris: Seuil, 1984). ---. "De part et d'autre." Critique, no. 17 (1961): pp. 915-22; reprinted in Essais critiques (Paris: Seuil, 1971). ---. Le Degr zro de l'criture. Paris: Points-Seuil, 1972 (19 53). ---. "Les lments de smiologie." Communications, no. 4 (1964); reprinted in L'Aventure smiologique. ---. Essais critiques. Paris: Points-Seuil, 1971 (1964). ---. "Histoire et littrature: propos de Racine." Annales (May-June 1960). 437 ---. Interview with Charbonnier. France-Culture, December 1967. ---. Michelet par lui-mme. ---. Mythologies. 1957. Paris: Seuil. ---. "Saussure, le signe, la dmocratie." Le Discours social, nos. 3-4 (April 1973); reprinted in L'Aventure smiologique (Paris: Seuil, 1985). ---. "Sociologie et socio-logique." Informations sur les sciences sociales, no. 4 (December 1962). ---. Sur Racine. Paris: Points-Seuil, 1979 (1963). ---. Le Systme de la mode. Paris: Seuil, Points-Seuil, 1983 (1967). Bartoli, Henri. conomie et cration collective. Paris: Economica, 1977. Bastide, Roger, ed. Sens et usages du terme de structure. Colloquium, January 10-12, 1959. Paris: Mouton, 1972 (1962). Bataille, Georges. "Un livre humain, un grand livre." Critique, no. 115 (February 1956). Bellour, Raymond. "Entretien avec R. Barthes." Les Lettres franaises, no. 1172 (March 2, 1967). ---. Les Lettres franaises, no. II25 (March 3 1,1966); reprinted in Le Livre des autres (Paris: lOir 8, 1978). Benoist, Jean-Marie. La Rvolution structurale. Paris: Denol, 1980. Bettelheim, Charles. Calcul conomique et formes de proprit. Paris: Seuil-Maspero, 197 Blanchot, Maurice. "I:oubli, la draison." Nouvelle Revue franaise (October 1961): pp. 676-86; reprinted in L'Entretien infini (Paris: Gallimard, 1969). Bopp, Franz. Systme de conjugaison de la langue sanscrite, compar celui des langues grecque, latine, persane et germanique. Frankfurt am Main, 1816. (Analyti- cal Comparison of the Sanskrit, Greek, Latin, and Teutonic Languages Showing the Original Identity of Their Grammatical Structure [Amsterdam: Amsterdam Studies in the Theory and History of Linguistic Science, 1974].) Boris Souvarine et "La Critique sociale." Ed. Anne Roche. Paris: La Dcouverte, 1990. Bourdieu, Pierre. Choses dites. Paris: Minuit, 1987. Boyer, Robert. "La croissance franaise de l'aprs-guerre et les modles macro- conomiques." La Revue conomique, vol. 27, no. 5 (1976). Brmond, Claude. Logique du rcit. Paris: Seuil, 1972. ---. "Le message narratif." Communications, no. 4. Paris: Seuil, 1964. de Brunhoff, Suzanne. Marx on Money. Trans. Maurice J. Goldbloom. New York: Urizen Books, 1976. Caillois, Roger. "Illusions rebours." Nouvelle Revue franaise (December l, 1954; January l, 1955). ---. "La rponse de R. Caillois." Le Monde, June 28, 1974. Calvet, Louis-Jean. Pour et contre Saussure. Paris: Payot, 1975. ---. Roland Barthes. Paris: Flammarion, 1990. Canetti, lias. Masse et puissance. Paris: Gallimard, 1966. Canguilhem, Georges. "La dcadence de l'ide de progrs." Revue de mtaphysique et de morale, no. 4 (1987). ---. Le Normal et le pathologique. Paris: PUF, 1975 (1966). ---. "Qu'est-ce que la psychologie?" Revue de mtaphysique et de morale (1958), pp. 12-25, and in Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, no. 2 (March 1966), and in Georges Canguilhem, tudes d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences. Paris: Vrin, 1968. Castel, Robert. "Les aventures de la pratique." Le Dbat, no. 41 (September-November 1986). Bibliography 439 Castoriadis, Cornelius. "Les divertisseurs." Le Nouvel Observateur, June 20, 1977; in La Socite franaise (Paris: 10h8, 1979). Cavaills, Jean. Sur la logique et la thorie des sciences. Paris: P U t ~ 1947. Charbonnier, Georges. Entretiens avec Claude Lvi-Strauss. Paris: lOlr8, 1969 (1961). (Conversations with Claude Lvi-Strauss. Trans. John and Doreen Weightman [London: Jonathan Cape, 1969].) Chtelet, Franois. "L'homme, ce Narcisse incertain." La Quinzaine littraire, April l, 1966. Chesneaux, Jean. De la modernit. Paris: Maspero, 1973. Chevalier, Jean-Claude. "La Notion de complment chez les grammairiens." Paris: Droz, 1968. Chevalier, Jean-Claude, and Pierre Encrev. "La cration de revues dans les annes soixante." Langue franaise, no. 63 (September 1984). Clmens, Ren. "Prolgomnes d'une thorie de la structure." Revue d'conomie politique, no. 6 (1952). Cohen-Solal, Annie. Sartre. Paris: Gallimard, 1985. Condorcet, Jean Antoine de. Esquisse d'un tableau historique des progrs des l'esprit humain (1793). Coquet, Jean-Claude. "La smiotique." In Les Sciences du langage en France au xx e sicle, ed. Bernard Pottier. Paris: SELAF, 1980. Daix, Pierre. Structuralisme et rvolution culturelle. Paris: Casterman, 1971. Debray, Rgis. Critique de la raison politique. Paris: Gallimard, 1981. de Gandillac, Maurice. In Entretiens sur la notion de gense et de structure. Colloquium at Cerisy, July-August 1959. Paris: Mouton, 1965. Dehove, Mario. L'tat des sciences sociales en France. Paris: La Dcouverte, 1986. de Ipola, D. R. "Le Structuralisme ou l'histoire en exil." Thesis, 1969. Deleuze, Gilles. "L'homme, une existence douteuse." Le Nouvel Observateur, June l, 1966. Derrida, Jacques. "De la grammatologie." Critique, no. 223-24 (December 1965). ---. Positions. Paris: Minuit, 1972. Desanti, Jean-Toussaint. Autrement, no. 102 (November 1988). ---. Un destin philosophique. Paris: Grasset, 1982. Descombes, Vincent. Les Enjeux philosophiques des annes cinquante. Paris: ditions du Centre Georges Pompidou, 1989. ---. "L'quivoque du symbolique. Confrontations, no. 3 (1980). ---. Le Mme et l'autre. Paris: Minuit, 1979. Domenach, Jean-Marie. "Le requiem structuraliste." In Le Sauvage et l'ordinateur. Paris: Seuil, 1976. ---. "Le systme et la personne." Esprit, no. 360 (May 1967). Domenach, Jean-Marie, Mikel Dufrenne, Paul Ricoeur, Jean Ladrire, Jean Cuise nier, Pierre Burgelin, Yves Bertherat, and Jean Cornilh. "Structuralismes, idologies et mthodes." Esprit, no. 360 (May 1967). Dor, Jol. Introduction la lecture de Lacan. Paris: Denol, 1985. Dosse, Franois. L'Histoire en miettes. Paris: La Dcouverte, 1987. Dreyfus, Hubert L., and Paul Rabinow. Foucault, un parcours philosophique. Paris: Gallimard,1984' Dubois, Jean. Le Vocabulaire politique et social en France de 1849 1872. Paris: Larousse, 1962. Ducrot, Oswald, and Tzvetan Todorov. Dictionnaire encyclopdique du langage. Paris: Seuil, 1972. 440 Bibliography Dumzil, Georges. Entretiens avec Didier ribon. Paris: Gallimard, 1987. ---. Mythe et pope. "Introduction." Paris: Gallimard, 1973. ---. La Religion romaine archaque. Paris: Payot, 1966. Durkheim, mile. "La prohibition de l'inceste." L'Anne sociologique, vol. 1 (1898). Duvignaud, Jean. "Aprs le fonctionalisme et le structuralisme, quoi?" In Une anthro- pologie des turbulences. Hommage G. Balandier. 1985, ---. Chebika. Paris: Gallimard, 1968; reprinted by Plon (I991). ---. Le Langage perdu. Paris: PUF, 1973. ---. Les Lettres nouvelles, no. 62 (1958). Entretiens sur les notions de gense et de structure. Colloquium at Cerisy, July-August I959. Paris: Mouton, I965. ribon, Didier. Michel Foucault. Paris: Flammarion, 1989. Etiemble, Ren. vidences (April 1956). Fabiani, Jean-Louis. Les Enjeux philosophiques des annes cinquante. Paris: ditions du Centre Georges Pompidou, 1989. Ferry, Luc, and Alain Renaut. Heidegger et les modernes. Paris: Grasset, 1988. (Heidegger and Modernity. Trans. Franklin Philip [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, I990].) ---. La Pense 68. Paris: Gallimard, I985. Fortes, Meyer, and E. E. Evans-Pritchard, eds. African Political Systems. London: Oxford University Press, 1940. Foucault, Michel. Actes du Colloque de Royaumont: Nietzsche, Freud, Marx. Paris: Minuit I967 (I964). ---. The Archaeology of Knowledge. Trans. Alan Sheridan Smith. New York: Pan- theon Books, I972. ---. Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. Trans. Alan Sheridan. New York: Pantheon Books, 1977. --. Ethos (fall I983). Interview. ---. Folie et draison. Paris: Plon, 1961. (Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason. Trans. Richard Howard. New York: Pantheon, 1965].) ---. The History ofSexuality. 3 vols. Trans. Robert Hurley. New York: Vintage Books, I990. ---. Hommage Hyppolite. Paris: PUF, 1969. ---. Interview in Politique-Hebdo, March 4, 1976. ---. "Jean Hyppolite, 197-1968." Revue de mtaphysique et de morale, vol. 14, no. 2 (April-June 1969). ---. Lectures pour tous (1966). INA document, shown on Ocaniques, FR3, January I3, I988. ---. Les Mots et les choses. Paris: Gallimard, I966. (The arder of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. New York: Vintage Books, I973].) ---. Les Nouvelles littraires, June 28, 1984. ---. "Structuralism and Post-Structuralism." Telos, vol. I6 (I 983); interview with Georges Raulet. ---. "Le structuralisme et l'analyse littraire." in Mission culturelle franaise Information, French embassy in Tunisia, April lo-May IO, 1987 (1965); unedited tapes of two lectures by Michel Foucault at the Club Tahar Haddad. Centre Michel- Foucault, Bibliothque du Saluchoir. ---. "Vrit et pouvoir." Interview with M. Fontana, I.:Arc, no. 70. Fougeyrollas, Pierre. Contre Claude Lvi-Strauss, Lacan, Althusser. Paris: Lavelli, I976. Bibliography 441 Frank, Manfred. Qu'est-ce que le no-structuralisme? Paris: Cerf, 1989. (What Is Neostructuralism? Trans. Sabine Wilke and Richard Gray [Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1989].) Frege, Gottlob. Les Fondements de l'arithmtique. Paris: Seuil, 1969. Furet, Franois. "Les intellectuels franais et le structuralisme." Preuves, no. 92 (February 1967); reprinted in L'Atelier de l'histoire (Paris: Flammarion, 1982). Gadet, Franoise. "Le signe et le sens." DRLAY, Revue de linguistique, no. 40 (1989). Gaston-Granger, Gilles. "vnement et structure dans les sciences de l'homme." Cahiers de l'ISEA (December 1959). ---. Pense formelle et science de l'homme. Paris: Aubier, 1960. Gauchet, Marcel, and Gladys Swain. La Pratique de l'esprit humain: I:institution asilaire et la rvolution dmocratique. Paris: Gallimard, 1980. Genette, Grard. "Structuralisme et critique littraire." I: Arc, no. 26; reprinted in Figures, vol. 1 (Paris: Seuil, 1966; Points-Seuil, 1976). George, Franois. L'Effet yau de pole. Paris: Hachette, 1979. Georgin, R. De Lvi-Strauss Lacan. 1983, Godelier, Maurice. Rationalit et irrationalit en conomie. Paris: Maspero, 1966. ---. "Systme, structure et contradiction dans Le Capital." Les Temps modernes, no. 246 (November 1966). Goldmann, Lucien. Le Dieu cach. Paris: Gallimard, 1956. ---. In Entretiens sur les notions de gense et de structure. Colloquium at Cerisy, July-August 1959. Paris: Mouton, 1965. Goubert, Pierre. Louis XIV et vingt millions de Franais. Paris: Fayard, 1966. Green, Andr. L'Affect. Paris: PUF, 1970. ---. "Le bon plaisir." France-Culture, February 25,1989. ---. "Le langage dans la psychanalyse." In Langages: Les Rencontres psychanaly- tiques d'Aix-en-Provence (1983). Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1984. ---. La psychanalyse devant l'opposition de l'histoire et de la structure." Critique, no. 194 (July 1963). ---. Sminaire de Michel Izard. Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, 1988. Greimas, Algirdas Julien. Du sens. Paris: Seuil, 1970. ---. "L'actualit du saussurisme." Le Franais moderne, no. 3 (1956). ---. "L'analyse structurale du rcit." Communications, no. 8 (1966); reprinted by Points-Seuil, 1981. ---. Preface to Gottlob Frege, Les Fondements de l'arithmtique (Paris: Seuil, 1969). ---. Smantique structurale. Paris: Larousse, 1966. Gross, Maurice. "La cration de revues dans les annes soixante." Langue franaise, no. 63 (September 1984). Guroult, Martia. Descartes selon l'ordre des raisons. Paris: Aubier, 1953. ---. Leon inaugurale au Collge de France (December 4,1951). ---. Philosophie de l'histoire de la philosophie. Paris: Aubier, 1979. Gurvitch, Georges. "Le concept de structure sociale." Cahiers internationaux de sociologie, no. 19 (1955). Habermas, Jrgen. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity: I2 Lectures. Trans. Fredrick Laurence. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1987. Hagge, Claude. L'homme de parole. Paris: Gallimard, Folio, 1985. Hamon, Herv, and Philippe Rotman. Gnration. Vol. 1. Paris: Seuil, 1987. Hamon, Philippe. "Littrature." In Les Sciences du langage en France au XX' sicle, ed. Bernard Pottier. Paris: SELAF, 1980. 442 Bibliography Heidegger, Martin. "Le discours du rectorat" (May 27,1933). Le Dbat, no. 27 (November 1983). ---. An Introduction to Metaphysics. Trans. Ralph Mannheim. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1959. ---. Lettre sur l'humanisme. Paris: Aubier, 1983 (1946). ---. Poetry, Language, Thought. Trans. A. Hofstadter. New York: Harper and Row, 1971 (1975). ---. Questions. Vol. 1. Paris: Gallimard, n.d. Henry, Paul. "pistmologie de L'Analyse automatique du discours de Michel Pcheux." In Introduction to the Translation of M. Pcheux's Analyse automatique du discours. Herbert, Thomas [Michel Pcheux]. "Reflexions sur la situation thorique des sciences sociales, spcialement de la psychologie sociale." Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, no. 2 (March-April 1966); reprinted 1-2. ---. "Remarques pour une thorie gnrale des idologies." Les Cahiers pour l'analyse, no. 9 (summer 1968). Hertz, Robert. Mlanges de sociologie religieuse et folklore. 1928. Hjelmslev, Louis. Language: An Introduction. Trans. Francis J. Whitfield. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1970. ---. Prolegomena to a Theory of Language. Trans. Francis J. Whitfield. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1961. Hyppolite, Jean. La Psychanlayse, vol. 1. Paris: PUF, 1956; with Lacan's response, reprinted in Jacques Lacan, crits (Paris: ditions du Seuil, 1966). Izard, Michel. Sminaire. Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale. June 1, 1989. Jakobson, Roman. "Deux aspects du langage et deux types d'aphasie." In Essais de linguistique gnrale. Paris: Points-Seuil, 1970. ---. Essais de linguistique gnrale. 2 vols. Paris: Points-Seuil, 1970. ---. "Les douze traits de sonorit." In "Phonologie et phontique" (1956). In Essais de linguistique gnrale. ---. Preface to Tzvetan Todorov, Thorie de la littrature. Paris: Seuil, 1965. ---. Six leons sur le son et le sens. Paris: Minuit, 1976; preface by Claude Lvi- Strauss ("Les leons de la linguistique"), reprinted in Le Regard loign (Paris: Plon, 1983). Jamin, Jean. Les En;eux philosophiques des annes cinquante. Paris: ditions Centre Georges Pompidou, 1989. Juranville, Alain. Lacan et la philosophie. Paris: PUF, 1988 (1984). Kanters, Robert. "Tu causes, tu causes, c'est tout ce que tu sais faire." Le Figaro, June 23, 1966. Koyr, Alexandre. De la mystique la science; cours, confrences et documents (1922-62). Ed. Pietro Redondi. Paris: ditions de l'cole des Hautes tudes en Sciences Sociales, 1986. Kristeva, Julia. "Le sens et la mode." Critique, no. 247 (December 1967). Labrousse, Ernest. Actes du congrs historique du centenaire de la rvolution de I848. Paris: PUF, 1948. ---. "La Crise de l'conomie franaise la fin de l'Ancien Rgime et au dbut de la crise rvolutionnaire" (1944). Lacan, Jacques. "La chose freudienne" (1956). In crits, vol. 1. ("The Freudian Thing." Trans. Alan Sheridan, in crits: A Selection.) ---. crits. Paris: Seuil, 1966. ---. crits: A Selection. Trans. Alan Sheridan. New York: W. W. Norton, 1977. ---. "L'excommunication." Ornicar? (1977). Bibliography 443 ---. "L'instance de la lettre dans l'inconscient." In vol. I. ("The Agency of the Letter in the Unconscious or Reason since Freud." Trans. Alan Sheridan. In crits: A Selection.) ---. "Position de l'inconscient." crits, vol. 2. ---. La Psychanalyse. Vol. 1. Paris: PUF, 1956. ---. "De la psychose paranoaque dans ses rapports avec la personnalit." Thesis for medical degree, 1932. ---. "Rapport de Rome" (1953). In crits, vol. 1. "Report to the Rome Congress Held at the Istituto di Psicologia della Universit di Roma, 26 and 27 September, 1953." Trans. Alan Sheridan, in crits: A Selection.) ---. "Remarques sur le rapport de Daniel Lagache" (1958). In crits. ---. Le Sminaire. Vol. 3: Les Psychoses (1955-56). Paris: Seuil, 1981. ---. Sminaire XX, Encore (1973-1974). Paris: Seuil, 1975. ---. "Sminaire sur la lettre vole." In crits, vol. 1. ("Seminar on the Purloined Letter." Trans. Alan Sheridan. In crits: A Selection.) ---. "Situation de la psychanalyse en 1956." In crits, vol. 2. Paris: Points-Seuil, 1971. ---. "Le stade du miroir." crits, vol. 1. ("The Mirror Stage as Formative of the Function of the Ego as Revealed in Psychoanalytic Experience." Trans. Alan Sheridan. In crits: A Selection.) ---. "Subversion of the Subject and Dialectic of Desire." In crits, vol. 1. Lacroix, Jean. "La fin de l'humanisme." Le Monde, June 9,1966. Laplanche, Jean. Psychanalyse l'Universit. Vol. 4, no. 15 (June 1979). ---. "Une rvolution sans cesse occulte." Communication aux journes scien- tifiques de l'Association internationale d'histoire de la psychanalyse, April 23-24, 1988. Lapouge, Gilles. "Encore un effort et j'aurai pous mon temps." La Quinzaine littraire, no. 459 (March 16-30, 1986). Leclaire, Serge. "L'inconscient, une tude psychanalytique." In L'Inconscient. Paris: Descle de Brouwer, 1966; reprinted in Psychanalyser (Paris: Points-Seuil, 1968). ---. "L'objet a dans la cure." In Rompre les charmes. Paris: InterEditions, 1981 (1971). Lefort, Claude. "L'change et la lutte des hommes." Les Temps modernes, February 1951; reprinted in Claude Lefort, Les Formes de l'histoire (Paris: Gallimard, 1978). Lemaire, Anika, Lacan. Paris: Mardaga, 1977. Le Roy Ladurie, Emmanuel. Les Paysans de Languedoc. Paris: Annales, 1966. (The Peasants of Languedoc. Trans. John Day [Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1974].) Lvi-Strauss, Claude. "L'analyse structurale en linguistique et en anthropologie." Word, vol. l, no. 2 (1945); reprinted in Anthropologie structurale. ---. Anthropologie structurale. 2 vols. Paris: Plon, 1958. (Structural Anthropology. Trans. Claire Jacobson and Brooke Grundfest Schoepf [New York: Anchor Books, 1967].) ---. Le Cru et le cuit. Paris: Plon, 1964. (The Raw and the Cooked: Introduction to a Science of Mythology. Vol. 1. Trans. John and Doreen Weightman [New York and Evanston, Ill.: Harper Torchbooks, Harper and Row, 1969].) ---. De prs et de loin. Paris: Odile Jacob, 1988. ---. "Diogne couch." Les Temps modernes, no. 195 (1955). ---. "Le droit au voyage." L'Express, September 21,1956. ---. "Dumzil et les sciences humaines." France-Culture, October 2, 1978. ---. Du miel aux cendres. Paris: Plon, 1964. (From Honey to Ashes: Introduction 444 Bibliography to a Science of Mythoiogy. Vol. 2. Trans. John and Doreen Weightman [London: Jonathan Cape and Harper and Row, 1973].) ---. "L'Efficace Symbolique." Revue d'histoire des religions, no. l (1949). ("The Effectiveness of Symbols." Reprinted in Structural Anthropology, trans. Claire Jacobson and Brooke Grundfest Schoepf [New York: Anchor Books, 1967].) ---. "History and Anthropology." In Structural Anthropology. ---. L'Homme Nu. Paris: Plon, 1971. (The Naked Man: Introduction to a Science of Mythology. Vol. 4. Trans. John and Doreen Weightman [New York and Evanston, Ill.: Harper Torchbooks, Harper and Row, 1981].) ---. "Des Indiens et leur ethnographe." Excerpts from "Tristes Tropiques Soon to Be Published." Les Temps modernes, no. II6 (August 1955). ---. Interview with Jean-Jos Marchand. Arts (December 28, 1955). ---. Interview with Raymond Bellour. Le Monde, November 5, 1971. ---. "Introduction l'uvre de Marcel Mauss." In Marcel Mauss, Sociologie et anthropologie. Paris: PUF, 1968 (1950). (Introduction to the Work of Marcel Mauss. Trans. Felicity Baker [London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1987].) ---. "Leon inaugurale au Collge de France," January 5, 1960. Reprinted in Anthropologie structurale, vol. 2 (Paris: Plon, 1973). ---. Leroi-Gourhan ou les voies de l'homme. Paris: Albin Michel, 1988. ---. "Linguistics and Anthropology." In Supplement to the International Journal of American Linguistics, vol. 19, no. 2 (April 1953); reprinted in Structural Anthropology, trans. Claire Jacobson and Brooke Grundfest Schoepf (New York: Anchor Books, 1967). ---. The Origin of Table Manners, trans. John and Doreen Weightman (New York: 'Harper and Row, 1978). ---. Paroles donnes. Paris: Plon, 1984. ---. La Pense sauvage. Paris: Plon, 1962. (The Savage Mind [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1966].) ---. La Potire jalouse. Paris: Plon, 1985, (The Jealous Potter. Trans. Bndicte Choriet [Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1988].) ---. "Race et histoire" (1952). Reprinted in Anthropologie structurale, vol. 2 (Paris: Plon, 1958). ---. Le Regard loign. (The View from Afar. Trans. Joachim Neugroschel and Phoebe Hoss. New York: Basic Books, 1984].) ---. "Rponse Dumzil reu l'Acadmie Franaise." Le Monde, July 15, 1979. ---. "Le sorcier et sa magie." Les Temps modernes, no. 41 (March 1949); reprinted in Anthropologie structurale. Translated as "The Sorcerer and His Magic." ---. Structural Anthropology. Trans. Claire Jacobson and Brooke Grundfest Schoepf. New York: Anchor Books, 1967. ---. "La structure et la forme." Cahiers de l'ISEA, no. 99 (March 1960), series M, no. 7; reprinted in Anthropologie structurale, vol. 2. ---. Les Structures lmentaires de la parent. Paris: PUF, 1949. (The Elementary Structures of Kinship. Trans. James Harle Bell, John Richard von Sturmer, and Rodney Needham [London: Eyre and Spottiswoode,1969].) ---. Le Totmisme aujourd'hui. Paris: Plon, 1962. ---. Tristes Tropiques. Trans. John and Doreen Weightman. New York: Atheneum, 1974 ---. La Vie familiale et sociale des Indiens Nambikwara. Paris: Socit des amricanistes, 1948. Bibliography 445 Lvi-Strauss, Claude, and Roman Jakobson. L'Homme, Il, no. l, Mouton (January-April 1962). ---.Interview with Raymond Bellour. Les Lettres f'ranaises, no. II65 (January 12, 1967); reprinted in Le Livre des autres (Paris: IOIrS, 1978). Lindenberg, DanieL Le Marxisme introuvable. Paris: IOtI8, 1979 (reprint). Linhart, Robert. Lnine, les paysans, Taylor. Paris: Seuil, 1976. Lipovetsky, Gilles. L'Ere du vide: Essais sur l'individualisme contemporain. Paris: Gallimard,1983 Lowie, Robert H. "Exogamy and the Classificatory Systems of Relationship." American Anthropologist, voL 17 (April-June 1915). Lyotard, Jean-Franois. La Condition post-moderne. Paris: Minuit, 1979. (The Post- modern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Trans. Geoff Bennington and Brian Massumi [Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984].) Macherey, Pierre. "La philosophie de la science de Canguilhem." La Pense, no. II3 (January 1964). ---. Pour une thorie de la production littraire. Paris: Maspero, 1966. Mandrou, Robert. "Trois cls pour comprendre l'histoire de la folie l'poque classique." Annales, no. 4 (July-August 1962). Marchal, Andr. Mthode scientifique et science conomique. Paris: ditions de Mdicis, 1955. ---. In Sens et usages du terme de structure. Ed. Roger Bastide. Paris: Mouton, 1972 (1962). ---. Systmes et structures. Paris: PUF, 1959. Marion, Jean-Luc. "Une modernit sans avenir." Le Dbat, no. 4 (September 1980). Marksey, Richard, and Eugenio Donato, eds. The Structuralist Controversy: The Lan- guages of' Criticism and the Sciences of' Man. Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1970 and 1972. Martin, Serge. Langage musical, smiotique des systmes. Paris: Klincksieck, 1978. Marx, KarL Le Capital. Paris: ditions sociales, 1960. Matonti, Frdrique. "Entre Argenteuil et les barricades: La Nouvelle Critique et les sciences sociales." Cahiers de l'Institut d'histoire du temps prsent, no. II (April 1989). Mauss, MarceL "Essai sur le don. Forme et raison de l'change dans les socits archaques." In L'Anne sociologique (1921). (The Gif't. Trans. l. Cunnison [Lon- don: Cohen and West, 1954].) Mendel, Grard. La Chasse structurale. Paris: Payot, 1977. ---. Enqute par un psychanalyste sur lui-mme. Paris: Stock, 1981. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. Phnomnologie de la perception. Paris: Gallimard, 1945. ---. Signes. Paris: Gallimard, 1960. ---. La Structure du comportement. Paris: PUF, 1942. ---. "Sur la phnomnologie du langage." Lecture delivered to the First Inter- national Phenomenology Colloquium in Brussels, 1951. Reprinted in Signes. (Signs. Trans. Richard McCleary [Evanston, IlL: Northwestern University Press, n.d.].) Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, et aL 6 e Colloque de BonnevaL I:Inconscient. Paris: Descle de Brouwer, 1966. Mtraux, Alfred. L'Ile de Pques. Paris: Gallimard, 1941; 2d ed., 1956. Miller, Jacques-Alain. Ornicar? no. 24 (1981). Morin, Edgar. "Arguments, trente ans aprs." Interviews. La Revue des revues, no. 4 (fall 1987). ---. L'Esprit du temps. Paris: Grasset, 1962. 446 Bibliography ---. Le sujet. Paris: Seuil, 1969. Mounin, Georges. Introduction smiologie. Paris: Minuit, 1970. Nadeau, Maurice. Les Lettres nouvelles (July 1953). Naf, K. "Marxisme ou structuralisme?" In Contre Althusser. Paris: lOirS, 1974. Nasio, Jean-David. Les Sept Concepts cruciaux de la psychanalyse. Paris: ditions Rivages, 1988. Nicola, Andr. Comportement conomique et structures sociales. Paris: PUF, 1960. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science. Trans. Walter Kaufman. New York: Vintage Books, 1974. ---. Human, ail too human. Trans. R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986. ---. Human, ail too human. Trans. Walter Kaufman. New York: Portable Nietzsche, Viking Portable Library, 1968. ---. Untimely Meditations. Trans. R. J. Hollingdale. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983. ---. La Volont de puissance. 2 vols. Paris: Gallimard, n.d. Nora, Pierre. Les Franais d'Algrie. Paris: Julliard, 1961. ---. Les Lieux de mmoire, La Rpublique. Paris: Gallimard, 1984. Ogilvie, Bertrand. Lacan, le sujet. Paris: PUF, 1987. Ortigues, Edmond. Critique, no. 189 (February 1963). Ory, Pascal, and Jean-Franois Sirinelli. Les Intellectuels en France, de l'affaire Dreyfus nos jours. Paris: Armand Colin, 1986. Pavel, Thomas. Le Mirage linguistique. Paris: Minuit, 1988. Pcheux, Michel. L'Analyse automatique du discours. Paris: Dunod, 1969. Perrot, Michelle. Essais d'ego-histoire. Paris: Gallimard, 1987. Perroux, Franois. Comptes de la nation. Paris: PUF, 1949. ---. In Sens et usages du terme de structure. Ed. Roger Bastide. Paris: Mouton, 1972 (1962). Piaget, Jean. lments d'pistmologie gntique. Paris: PUF, 1950. ---. In Entretiens sur les notions de gense et de structure. Colloquium at Cerisy, July-August 1959. Paris: Mouton, 1965. ---. Psychologie et pistmologie. Paris: PUF, 1970 (1947, Amsterdam). ---. In Le Structuralisme. Collection "Que sais-je?" Paris: PUF, n.d. Picard, Raymond. Nouvelle Critique ou nouvelle imposture. Paris: J.-J. Pauvert, 1965, Pinguet, Maurice. Le Dbat, no. 41 (September-November 1986). Pinto, Louis. Les Philosophes entre le lyce et l'avant-garde. Paris: L'Harmattan, 1987. Pommier, Ren. Assez dcod. Paris: ditions Roblot, 1978. ---. R. Barthes, Ras le bol! Paris: ditions Roblot, 1987. Pouillon, Jean. "L'uvre de Claude Lvi-Strauss." Les Temps modernes, no. 126 (July 1956); reprinted in Jean Pouillon, Ftiches sans ftichisme (Paris: Maspero, 1975). ---. Sminaire de Michel Izard. Laboratoire d'Anthropologie Sociale, November 24, 1988. Pouillon, Jean, Marc Barbut, Algirdas Julien Greimas, Maurice Godelier, Pierre Bourdieu, Pierre Macherey, and J. Ehrmann. "Problmes du structuralisme." Les Temps modernes, no. 246 (November 1966). Propp, Vladimir. Morphologia della fiaba. Turin: Einaudi, 1966 (Morphology of the Folktale [Austin: University of Texas Press, 1968).) ---. Les Racines historiques du conte. Paris: Gallimard, 1983. (Theory and History of Folkore. Trans. Ariadna Y. Martin and Richard P. Martin [Minneapolis: Univer- sity of Minnesota Press, 1984).) Bibliography 447 Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. "The of Systems." ihzthrotJOlm"V lnstitute, 1941. Revel, Jean-Franois. "Le rat et la mode." L'Express, May 22, 1967. ---. "Sartre en ballottage." L'Express, no. 802 (November 7-13,1966). Rey, Jean-Michel. "La philosophie du monde scientifique et industriel." In Histoire de la philosophie, ed. Franois Chtelet. Paris: Hachette, 1973. Rodinson, Maxime. "Racisme et civilisation." Nouvelle Critique, no. 66 (1955). Roudinesco, lisabeth. Les Enjeux philosophiques des annes cinquante. Paris: ditions du Centre Georges Pompidou, 1989. ---. Histoire de la psychanalyse en France. Paris: Seuil, 1986. Rousset, Jean. Forme et signification: Essais sur les structures littraires de Corneille Claudel. Paris: Jos Corti, 1962. Roustang, Franois. Lacan. Paris: Minuit, 1986. ---. Smantique structurale. Paris: Larousse, 1966. Roy, Claude. "Claude Lvi-Strauss ou l'homme en question." La Nef, no. 28 (1959). ---. "Un grand livre civilis: La Pense sauvage." Libration, June 19, 1962. Saint-Sernin, Bertrand. Revue de mtaphysique et de morale (January 1985)' Saussure, Ferdinand de. Cours de linguistique gnrale. Paris: Payot, 1965 (1915)' Sartre, Jean-Paul. Existentialism Is a Humanism. Trans. and intro. Philip Mairet. Brooklyn: Haskell House, 1977. Schorske, Carl. Fin de sicle Vienna. New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1979. Serres, Michel. "Gomtrie de la folie." Mercure de France, no. II88 (August 1962): pp. 683-96, and no. II89 (September 1962): pp. 63-8I. Reprinted in Herms ou la communication (Paris: Minuit, 1968). ---. "Structure et importation: des mathmatiques aux mythes" (November 1961). Reprinted in Herms ou la communication (Paris: Minuit, 1968). ---. La Traduction. Paris: Minuit, 1974. Sve, Lucien. Structuralisme et dialectique. Paris: Messidor, 1984. Sheridan, Alan. crits: A Selection. New York: W. W. Norton, 1977. Sichre, Bernard. Le Moment lacanien. Paris: Grasset, 1983. Simonis, Yvan. Lvi-Strauss ou la passion de l'inceste. Paris: Champs-Flammarion, 1990 (1968). Sirinelli, Jean-Franois. Gnration intellectuelle. Paris: Fayard, 1988. Sollers, Philippe. "Le bon plaisir de J. Kristeva." France-Culture, December 10, 1988. ---. "Littrature et totalit" (1966). In L'Ecriture et l'exprience des limites. Paris: Point-Seuil, 1968. Sperber, Dan. Qu'est-ce que le structuralisme? Le structuralisme en anthropologie. Paris: Points-Seuil, 1968. Starobinski, Jean. "Les anagrammes de Ferdinand Saussure." Mercure de France, Feb- ruary 1964. ---. Les Mots sous les mots. Paris: Gallimard, 197I. Steiner, Georges. Martin Heidegger. Paris: Flammarion, 198I. Stocking, George W. Histoires de l'anthropologie: XVIe-XIx e sicles. Paris: Klinck- sieck, 1984. Terray, Emmanuel. Le Marxisme devant les socits primitives. Paris: Maspero, 1969. Todorov, Tzvetan. "La description de la signification en littrature." Communciations, no. 4. Paris: Seuil, 1964. ---. Thories du symbole. Paris: Le Seuil, 1977. (Theories of the Symbol. Trans. Catharine Porter [Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1982].) Torrs, Flix. Dj vu. 1986. 448 Bibliography Trubetzkoy, Nicolai. "La phonologie actuelle." In Psychologie du langage (1933). Vattimo, Gianni. La Fin de la modernit. Paris: Seuil, 1987 (1985). Verds-Leroux, Jeannine. Le Rveil des somnambules. Paris: Fayard, 1987. Vernant, Jean-Pierre. In Entretiens sur les notions de gense et de structure. Colloquium at Cerisy, July-August 1959. Paris: Mouton, 1965. ---. "Le mythe hsiodique des races" (1960). In Mythe et pense chez les Grecs. Vol. I. Paris: Maspero, 1970. ---. "Le mythe hsiodique des races: Essai d'analyse structurale." Revue de l'histoire des religions (1960). Verstraeten, Pierre. "Claude Lvi-Strauss ou la tentation du nant." Les Temps modernes, no. 206 (July 1963). Viet, Jean. Les Mthodes structuralistes. Paris: Mouton, 1965. Vilar, Pierre. La Catalogne dans l'Espagne moderne: Recherches sur les fondements conomiques des structures nationales. Paris: SEVPEN, 1962. Vincent, Jean-Marie. "Le thoricisme et sa rectification." In Contre Althusser. Paris: 101I8, 1974 Wagemann, Ernst. Introduction la thorie du mouvement des affaires. Paris: Payot, 1932. ---. La Stratgie conomique. Paris: Payot, 1938. Wagner, Robert Lon. Foreword to his Introduction to French Linguistics (1947). Quoted by Jean-Claude Chevalier and Pierre Encrev. Index Compiled by Hassan Melehy Abls, Marc, 79-80 Acadmie Franaise, the, 32, 33, 128 Adler, Alfred, 40-41,161,162 Adorno, Theodor, 226-27, 354 Aeschylus, 74 Aglietta, Michel, 416 ch. 20 nn. 2, 3 Agulhon, Maurice, 147, 182 Alain, 85 Alembett, Jean d', 88 Allouch, Jean, 409 n. 8,412 nn. 1,2; 423 n. 7 Alqui, Ferdinand, 123 Althusser, Helen, xxi, 295 Althusser, Louis, xiv, xxi, xxiv, 4,85, 147-49,193,221,240,280-82, 284-92,293-308,309-15,326,332, 341,345,347-48,378,384,385, 387,391 Annales, the, xxiv, 35-36, 65, 78, 134, 168,176,181186-87,197,206,223, 224,319,386 Ansart, Pierre, 231, 432 n. 30 Anzieu, Didier, 120 Apter, David, 267 Aragon, Louis, 281 Aris, Philippe, 154,361 Aristotle, 288 Aron, Jean-Paul, 144 Aron, Raymond, xxii, 133, 174-75, 196, 231,318,382 Arriv, Michel, 60-61, 411 n. 31 Artaud, Antonin, 209 Aubry, Pierre, 120 Audry, Colette, 163 Aug, Marc, 266, 268-69, 312, 403 ch. 3 n.2 Augustine, Saint, 245 Auroux, Sylvain, 286, 405 ch. 7 n. 13, 406 n. 22, 419 n. 20, 421 n. 42, 427 n.2 Austin, John L., 371 Axelos, Kostas, 163,324,377,416 nn. 21,22 Bachelard, Gaston, 84-85, 89, 137, 196, 201,293,301,384,385 Backs-Clment, Catherine, 257 Badiou, Alain, 19, 309-10, 312, 348 Bakhtin, Mikhail, 345 Balandier, Georges, 231, 264-68, 270, 402 n. 20, 416 ch. 19 n. 3, 435 n. 22 Balfet, Hlne, 140,414 n. 56 Balibar, tienne, 288, 289, 291, 299, 306-7,312,314,428 n. 6,432 n. 43 Bally, Charles, 44 Barbut, Marc, 323 Barthes, Roland, xiv, xxi, xxiii, xxiv, 5, 45-46,62,63,68-69,71-77,91, 154-55,163,194,195,198,200, 203,205-9,211,215-19,223-28, 449 450 Index 235,275,276,278,317,320,324, 328,344,345,346,381,387,388, 393,430 n. 2 Bartoli, Henri, 169,417 ch. 20 nn. 19,20 Bastide, Franois-Rgis, 133, 140 Bastide, Jacques, 138 Bastide, Roger, 170, 173, 174,264 Bataille, Georges, 27, 40, 92, 134, 145, 149,209 Baudelaire, Charles, 201 Baudelot, Christian, 288 Bayet, Albert, 18 Beattie, ]., 267 Beaufret, Jean, 147,291,370,376 Beauvoir, Simone de, 24-25 Beckett, Samuel, 149 Becquemont, Daniel, 416 nn. 24, 25; 428 ch. 31 n. 22 Bdarida, Franois, 146 Bellour, Raymond, 218, 257, 332 Benoist, Jean-Marie, 41, 246, 403 n. 9, 424 n. 11,429 n. 40, 432 nn. 18,20,24 Benveniste, mile, 18, 34, 70, 174, 183, 186,200,215,273,274,316,318, 327,344 Berger, Gaston, 61-62 Berques, Jacques, xxi Berryer, Jean-Claude, 135 Bertucelli, Andr, 271 Besanon, Alain, 182 Besse, Guy, 297, 299 Bettelheim, Charles, 313-14 Biardeau, Madeleine, 139 Blanchot, Maurice, 145, 148-49, 155 Bloch, Jules, 34 Bloch, Marc, Il,65,181,267 Boas, Franz, 15, 16, 53 Boccara, Pierre, 297 Boissinot, Alain, 418 nn. 1,2 Bonaparte, Marie, 112 Bonnaf, Lucien, 102 Bonnaf, Marc-Franois, 102 Bonnaf, Pierre, 268 Boole, George, 122 Bopp, Franz, 33,47,334 Borges, Jorge Luis, 281 Boudon, Raymond, 13,403 n. 21 Bougl, Clestin, Il Boulez, Pierre, 207 Bourbaki, Charles, 219 Bourdet, Claude, 270 Bourdieu, Pierre, xxiv, 87, 319, 324, 384 Bouveresse, Jacques, 287, 428 n. 16 Bouvet, Maurice, 101 Boyer, Robert, 417 ch. 20 n. 6 Braudel, Fernand, 139,161,166-67,168, 180-81,206,240,319,323-24,386 Brecht, Bertolt, 77 Brhier, Louis, Il Brmond, Claude, 204-5, 213, 320, 322, 421 n. 23, 427 n. 22, 430 n. 28 Breton, Andr, 4, 12, 92 Brondal, Viggo, 56, 70, 72 Bruneau, Charles, 67 Brunoff, Suzanne de, 313 Brunschvicg, Lon, 11, 83 Burke, Edmund, 361 Butor, Michel, 207 Caillois, Roger, 27, 128-30 Calame-Griaule, Genevive, 318 Calvet, Louis-Jean, 50, 74, 75, 227, 406 ch. 7 n. 20, 420 ch. 23 n. 17,435 n. 20 Camus, Albert, 4, 71 Canetti, Elias, 318 Canguilhem, Georges, 4,85-88,137,143, 147,150,153,196,282-83,289, 290,310,319,333,346,384,385 Carnap, Rudolf, 69, 83, 392 Carnot, Nicolas, 86 Carpentier, Alejo, 137 Cartry, Michel, 137, 161, 162,272 Castel, Robert, 87, 156 Castex, Grard, 195 Castoriadis, Cornelius, 123, 161, 163 Cavaills, Jean, 83-84, 87, 88,285,384 Cazeneuve, Jean, 134 Centre National de la Recherche Scien- tifique, the (CNRS), 12,61, 65, 186, 197,202,203,270,272,286,310 Certeau, Michel de, 246 Chapsal, Madeleine, 133, 331 Char, Ren, 149 Charbonnier, Georges, 187,218 Chtelet, Franois, 331, 358 Chesneaux, Jean, 433 ch. 36 n. 17 Chevalier, Jean-Claude, 60-61, 62, 193, 198,200,406 ch. 8 n. 21, 407 ch. 9 nn. 8, 12; 418 nn. 4, 5; 419 n. 34, 426 n.5 Victor, 54 Chomsky, Noam, 199,220,275 Cixous, Hlne, 257 Clastres, Pierre, 161, 162,257 Clavreul, Jean, 97, 249, 423 n. 20 Clemens, Ren, 169-70 CNRS. See Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, the Cohen, Marcel, 60, 65,199,210 Collge de France, the, 33, 34, 38,41, 61,74,78,130,146,169,173, 185-87,197,211,265,271,318, 321,387 Comte, Auguste, 13, 14, 128, 169,351, 387 Condorcet, Marquis de, 88, 128, 356 Cont, Claude, 97,412 n. 31, 412 n. 7 Cooper, David, 156 Copernicus, Nicholas, 334, 381 Coquet, Jean-Claude, 46, 211, 214, 407 ch. 10 nn. 10, 11 Cournot, Antoine, 196-97 Crevel, Ren, 92 Cuisenier, Jean, 236 Culioli, Antoine, 61, 62, 194-95, 199, 210,221 Curien, Raoul, 149 Cuvier, Georges, 334, 339 Daix, Pierre, 434 ch. 36 n. 30 Dali, Salvador, 92 Darbel, Alain, 319 Darwin, Charles, 205, 334, 364 Davy, Georges, 18 Dayan, Sonya, 231 Debray, Rgis, 4, 266, 288, 433 ch. 36 nn. 14, 15, 16 Ddyan, Charles, 195 Defert, Daniel, 414 nn. 6, 7 de Gaulle, Charles, 99, 158,269,276, 327,343 Dehove, Mario, 417 ch. 20 n. 5 de Ipola, E. R., 412 nn. 14, 16, 17 Delay, Jean, 154 Deleuze, Gilles, 331-32, 358 Deloffre, Jacques, 195 Deltheil, Robert, 85 Derrida, Jacques, xxiv, 243, 244, 278, 298-99,316,328,373,378-79,383, 384,391 Index 45I Desanti, Jean-Toussaint, 147,284-86, 287,220 Descartes, Ren, 79, 80, 81, 125, 152, 193,289,346,372,381 Descola, Philippe, 402 ch. 2 n. 17,417 ch. 21 n. 21 Descombes, Vincent, 40, 43, 295, 404 nn. 17,21; 405 ch. 6 nn. 2, 8; 409 nn. 17, 33; 410 ch. 13 n. 18,415 n. 39,428 n. 1,429 n. 38,435 nn. 8, 9 Destutt de Tracy, Antoine, 26 Dtienne, Marcel, 36, 257 Deyon, Pierre, 182 Diatkine, Ren, 122 Diderot, Denis, 88 Dieterlin, Germaine, 272 Diogenes, 129 Dolto, Franoise, 97, 246 Domenach, Jean-Marie, 236-37, 263, 325 Dor, Jol, 97, 107, 108, 118,409 n. 10, 410 ch. 13 n. 11,421 n. 49, 423 n. 21 Dort, Bernard, 77 Dreyfus, Franois, 182 Droit, Roger-Pol, 196,298-99 Dubois, Jean, 60-61, 62, 63,198, 199, 200,202-3,210,274,275,317,345, 422 n. 12 Duby, Georges, 36 Ducrot, Oswald, 50, 200, 210, 211, 275, 406 ch. 7 n. 19 Dufrenne, Mikel, 137, 325 Dumayet, Pierre, 330 Dumzil, Claude, 100,249 Dumzil, Georges, 9, 12, 32-36, 87, 100, 149-50,154,183,184,207,318-19, 330,332,387 Dumont, Louis, 139 Dumur, Guy, 76 Durkheim, mile, xxii, 6, 13-14, 170, 181,229,230,258,351 Duroux, Yves, 288 Durry, Marie-Jeanne, 195 Duvignaud, Jean, 76, 163, 164, 179, 231-32,264,271-72,375,392,425 n.31 Eco, Umberto, 320, 322-23, 388 cole Nationale de l'Administration, the (ENA), 159, 284, 385 452 Index cole Normale Suprieure, the (ENS), 4, 5,11,85,146,147-49,159,182, 196,197,221,240,266,268, 280-83,284-92,294,295,298, 305-6,310,312,314,320,341,375, 385,391 cole Pratique des Hautes tudes, the (EPHE), 6, 12,33,60,61,64,76,92, 138,139,166,173,181,186,197, 200,202,205,211,240,251-52, 265,310,319,344,387 cole Psychanalytique Freudienne, the, 122 Eikhenbaum, Boris, 54 Eliade, Mircea, 327 ENA. See cole Nationale de l'Adminis- tration, the Engels, Friedrich, 13 ENS. See cole Normale Suprieure, the EPHE. See cole Pratique des Hautes tudes, the Erasmus, Desiderius,151 Eribon, Didier, 14,432 n. 14 Ernout, Alfred, 34 Escarra, Jean, 18 Espinas, Alfred, 39 Establet, Roger, 230, 288, 299 Etiemble, Ren, 4, 134, 135 Evans-Pritchard, Edward, 267 Ewald, Franois, 195-96, 332 Ey, Henri, 99-100,122 Fabiani, Jean-Louis, 408 n. 2,435 nn. 5, 16 Faral, Edmond, 34 Farge, Arlette, 375 Faye, Jean-Pierre, 161,278,406 n. 10, 416 n. 10,426 n. 12 Febvre, Lucien, 34, 78, 134, 181,224 Feigl, Herbert, 392 Fejt, Franois, 163 Ferry, Luc, 373,416 nn. 57, 58; 434 n. 12 Feuerbach, Ludwig, 302 Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 79, 81, 302 Flaubert, Gustave, 8, 75, 201 Fleming, Ian, 322-23 Florenne, Yves, 234 Focillon, Henri, 69 Fontenelle, Bernard de, xxii Fortes, Meyer, 267 Fortini, Franco, 163-64 Foucault, Michel, xiv, xv, xxi, xxii, xxiv, 28,41-42,47,48,80,82,85,86-87, 88,142-57,160,193,203,208,238, 282,289,301,303,316-17,325-26, 330-42,346,351,353,361-62,373, 374-76,378,379, 384, 385,433 ch. 36 n. 19 Fougeyrollas, Pierre, 121-22, 161, 163, 164,409 nn. 19,20,26; 434 n. 2 Fouques, Antoine, 346 Fourni, Georges, 74 Frank, Manfred, 425 n. 36 Frege, Gottlob, 221, 244 French Communist Party, the (PCF), 3, 62, 102, 147-48, 158, 160-62, 164, 199,203,278-80,285,288,290, 292,294,296-98,332,344 Freud, Sigmund, 8,13, 19,39,43,58,91, 92-93,96,97-98,99-110,111, 112-13,114-18,119,121,147,148, 149,221,238,242,244,245, 246-47,248,254,258,273,290, 291-92,311,314-15,316,326,328, 334, 346, 347,351, 377, 404 ch. 4 n. 7 Freyre, Gilberto, 134 Friedmann, Georges, 275-76 Fromm, Erich, 103 Furet, Franois, 146, 358, 392 Gadet, Franoise, 44, 45,195,311,406 ch.8n.17 Galileo, 311, 381 Gandillac, Maurice de, 137, 150, 173, 176 Garaudy, Roger, 288, 289, 296, 297, 298 Gardin, Jean-Claude, 207 Gaston-Granger, Gilles, 79,169,172, 207,229-30,310,319,380 Gauchet, Marcel, 156-57,392,416 ch. 19 n. 1, 433 ch. 36 n. 12, 434 n. 36 Genette, Grard, xxiii, 148, 161, 194, 211,278,318,320,323,345-46,407 ch. 9 n. 11,419 n. 21 Gentilhomme, Yves, 211 Geoffroy Saint-Hilaire, tienne, 46 George, Franois, 122, 196 Gernet, Louis, 183 Gilson, tienne, 78 Goddard, 408 ch. 12 nn. 8, 13 Gode!, Kurt, 221 Godelier, Maurice, 257, 272, 324, 347-48,382,417 ch. 21 n. 20, 433 ch. 36 n. 10,435 n. 27 Goethe, Johann Wolfgang von, 46, 245 Goldmann, Lucien, 7, 173, 175,226, 231,328,343 Goldmann, Pierre, xx-xxi Goldschmidt, Victor, 79 Goldstein, Kurt, 99 Gombrowicz, Witold, 281 Gorky, Maxime, 55 Goubert, Pierre, 319 Gougenheim, Georges, 60, 62 Gouhier, Henri, 150 Gourou, Pierre, 186, 274 Grammont, Maurice, 59 Granai, Georges, 135 Granet, Marcel, 33 Granoff, Wladimir, 96, 97,101,424 n. 39 Green, Andr, 76, 116, 122,238,244, 245,247,249,410 nn. 1,3 Greimas, Algirdas Julien, xxiii, 26, 41, 45, 62,63,67-70,71,72,74,197,198, 200,202,210-16,218,222,226,274, 275,295,317,320-21,323-24,387 Griaule, Marcel, 18,40,136,140,272 Gritti, Jules, 320 Grosrichard, Alain, 282 Gross, Maurice, 199,210,275 Gruson, Claude, 168 Guattari, Flix, 137 Gurin, Daniel, 270 Guroult, Martial, 78-84, 147,286,310 Guilbert, Louis, 62, 200, 202 Guillaume, Gustave, 60 Guiraud, Pierre, 63 Guitton, Jean, xxi, 294-95 Gurvitch, Georges, 26, 30-31, 171, 228-32,264 Habermas, Jrgen, 368, 434 nn. 5,20 Hagge, Claude, 36, 406 n. 27 Hallier, Jean-Edern, 278 Hamon, Philippe, 63, 195,430 nn. 3,24 Harris, Zellig, 203 Haudricourt, Andr-Georges, 65-66, 135, 199 Index 453 Hay, Louis, 198,421 fi. 19 Hcaen, Henry, 275 Hegel, G. W. E, xxii, 86, 88, 92, 93, 94-95,103,125,128,129,137,146, 162,175,302-3,324 Heidegger, Martin, 93, 103, 104, 109, 147,148,158,242,273,290,291, 365,367-74,375-79,383 Helier, Clemens, 139 Henry, Paul, 310, 311 Hritier-Aug, Franoise, 138-39,272 Herrenschmidt, Olivier, 137, 139 Hertz, Robert, 27 Hesiod, 176, 183-84 Heusch, Luc de, 136 Hitler, Adolf, 85 Hjelmslev, Louis, xxii, 56, 62, 63, 68-70, 75,81,198,200,205-7,212,214, 215,217,219,316,323 Hoarau, Jacques, 420 ch. 24 n. 17,421 nn.39,40 Hobbes, Thomas, 381 Houphout-Boigny, Flix, 265 Hugo, Victor, 9 Husserl, Edmund, 37, 54, 56, 84, 88, 285,290 Huston, John, 8 Hyppolite, Jean, 4, 95,122,137,146-47, 148,150,162,266,294 Imbs, Paul, 62 Institut National de la Statistique et des tudes conomiques, the (INSEE), 168 International Psychiatric Association, the (IPA), 122,239,244,291 Isambert, Liliane, 203 Izard, Michel, 136-39,257,270-71,272 Jacquart, Jean, 182 Jakobson, Roman, xxii, 12, 16, 21-24, 30,44,45,52-58,64,66,72,105, 107,110,121,165,174,200,201, 207,216,225,228,316,318,389 Jambet, Christian, 298 Jamin, Jean, 27, 402 ch. 2 n. 23,403 ch. 4 n. 4, 404 ch. 4 n. 7,433 n. 6, 435 n. 1 Janklevitch, Vladimir, 137,294 Jaulin, Robert, 6-7 Jeanneney, Jean-Nol, 266 454 Index Jespersen, Otto, 63 Jodelet, Franois, 194 John Paul II, Pope, 295 Johnson, Lyndon, 327 Joyce, James, 331 Jung, Carl, 252 Juranville, Alain, 245, 423 nn. 11, 15, 16, 17 Jussieu, Antoine de, 339 Kant, Immanuel, 30-31, 41,81,85,89, 302,342,375 Kanters, Robert, 235, 331 Karcevsky, Serge, 44, 55,174 Khlebnikov, Vladimir, 53 Klein, Melanie, 244 Klossowski, Pierre, 145 Kojve, Alexandre, 92, 146, 404 ch. 4 n. 7 Koyr, Alexandre, 78, 384 Kriegel, Annie, 182 Kristeva, Julia, 50, 193,211,218,278, 343-47 Kroeber, Alfred, 15 Krushchev, Nikita, 158 Labiche, Eugne, 116 Labrousse, Ernest, 181-82 Lacan, Jacques, xiv, xv, xxi, xxii, xxiii, xxiv, 28-29, 41, 42, 45, 48-49, 58, 72,76,83,91-98,99-110,111-18, 119-25,144,148,149,155,162, 196,206,210,213,218,220, 221-22,228,239-49,250,255,261, 273,278,282,291-92,295,300, 301,305-6,308,311,314-15,317, 326-27,328-29,332,341,344,346, 347,353,373,376-78,379,384, 387,391,393 Lacroix, Jean, 133,234, 331 Lagache, Daniel, 100, 102, 147, 149, 150,171,174 Laing, Ronald, 156 Lalande, Andr, xxii Lamarck, Jean-Baptiste de, 334, 339 Laplanche, Jean, 122, 123-25, 147,239, 247,410 n. 22, 423 n. 22, 424 n. 43 Laporte, Jean, 11 Lapouge, Gilles, 316-17 Lapssade, Georges, 324 Lardreau, Guy, 298 Leach, Edmund, 267 Lebesque,Morvan,77 Lebovici, Serge, 122 Le Bret, Francine, 402 n. 8 Leclaire, Serge, 97, 120, 122, 123,242, 243,247,249 Lecourt, Dominique, 281-82, 428 ch. 31 nn.17,24 Lefebvre, Henri, 122, 174,231,357 Lefort, Claude, 4, 25, 30-31, 123, 137, 161,162,163,231 Lefranc, Georges, 11 Le Goff, Jacques, 36, 268 Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm, 88-89 Leiris, Michel, 25, 27, 39, 40, 41, 264, 265 Lejeune, Michel, 61 Lemaire, Anika, 125,410 ch. 13 nn. 14, 15; 411 nn. 37, 38, 41 Lemoine, Gennie, 346, 410 ch. 13 n. 21, 421 n. 50,423 n. 18 Lenin, Nicolai, 295, 314 Leroi-Gourhan, Andr, 140-41, 187 Le Roy Ladurie, Emmanuel, 182,319 Lvi-Strauss, Claude, xiv, xv, xix, xxi, xxii, xxiii, 5-8, 9,10-17,18-25, 26-31,32,33,34,35,38-41,45, 52-53,72,82,83,87,91,94,103-4, 105,110,111-18,121,123,126-41, 143,154,155,161,162-63,166, 169,171,174,175,176-81,182-83, 184,185-87,198,200-201,205, 206,207,208,211,213,214,216, 222,228-38,240,250-63,264,265, 267,268,269,271,282,289-90, 295,306,307-8,311,318,320-21, 323,324-25,326,328,330,331, 332,334,335,336,340,341,344, 346,347,348,353,354,355,361, 362,373,375,376,378,379,382, 384,387,389,390,393 Lvi-Strauss, Monique, 118 Lvy-Bruhl, Lucien, 40, 232, 355, 357 Lhomme, Jean, 168 Lingat, Robert, 139 Linhart, Robert, 281, 282, 314 Linn, Carl von, 205 Lipovetsky, Gilles, 433 n. 22 Loewenstein, Rudolph, 123 Longchambon, Henri, 266 Lourau, Ren, 416 ch. 19 n. 4 Lowie, Robert, 12, 15 Luther, Martin, 78 Lyotard, Jean-Franois, 161, 343-54, 360 Macherey, Pierre, 88, 150,288,289,291, 296-97,299,319,345,346,348,428 n. 18,429 n. 2 Major, Ren, 410 ch. 14 n. 21 Maldidier, Denise, 203, 311 Malevich, Cazimir, 53 Malinowski, Bronislaw, 15, 176,233-34, 250 Mallarm, Stphane, 53, 344-45, 374 Mannoni, Octave, 120 Mao Tse-tung, 292 Marcellesir, Jean-Baptiste, 203 Marchal, Andr, 168, 170, 175 Marcuse, Herbert, 359 Martin, Serge, 70, 413 n. 1 Martinet, Andr, 47, 60, 61, 62, 63-65, 70,139,192-93,195,203,211,216, 274,387,406 ch. 9 n. 1 Marx, Karl, xxii, 11, 13-14, 18, 19,41, 43,85,128,140,147,148,169,174, 175,212,221,230,258,278,280, 282,285,288-92,296-97,299-303, 306-7,309-15,324,326,341,345, 347,348,351,358,387 Mascolo, Dionys, 163 Massignon, Louis, 34 Mathesius, Wilm, 55 Matignon, Renaud, 317 Mator, Georges, 67, 198 Mauriac, Claude, 234-35 Mauron, Charles, 226 Mausi, Robert, 146 Mauss, Marcel, 13, 26-31, 33, 34, 39, 40,65,114,185,390 Mayakovski, Vladimir, 53, 55 Mazan, Andr, 34 McLuhan, Marshall, 391 Mead, Margaret, 29-30 Meillassoux, Claude, 203, 270-71, 312 Meillet, Antoine, 34, 54, 59-60, 65, 66, 174 Melman, Charles, 411 n. 24, 412 n. 33 Mendel, Grard, 116,424 n. 30 Mends-France, Pierre, 266 Index 455 Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 4, 37-42, 45, 90,99,122,147,169,171,285,384 Meschonnic, Henri, 62, 200 Mesliand, Claude, 182 Mtreaux, Alfred, 12, 40, 134 Metz, Christian, 200, 211, 320 Meyerson, Ygnace, 183 Meyriat, J., 414 n. 32 Michaud,Ren, 294 Middleton, John, 267 Milhau, Jacques, 427 n. 28 Miller, Jacques-Alain, 76, 121, 196,221, 244,281,282,289,291,320,423 n.13 Milner, Jean-Claude, 47, 76, 282, 289 Mitterand, Henri, 62, 198, 199,200 Mitterrand, Franois, xxi Molire, 43 Molino, Jean, 148 Mondrian, Piet, 207 Monnet, Georges, Il Montaigne, Michel de, 128 Montesquieu, Baron de, 288, 289 Montherlant, Henri de, 128 Montuclard, Maurice, 294 Moreno, Jacob-Lvy, 174 Morgan, Lewis Henry, xxii, 19 Morin, Edgar, 163, 164,414 n. 3 Morin, Violette, 320 Moscovici, Serge, 310, 311 Mounin, Georges, 77, 109-10, 180 Murdock, George Peter, 174,229 Mury, Gilbert, 297 Muse de l'Homme, the, 12, 16, 135, 140,173,265 102 Maurice, 73, 74 Siegfried-Frederick, 267 K., 429 n. 35 Jean-David, 242 Pierre, 203, 270 Rodney, 27, 269 Otto, 392 School for Social Research, the, 12, 56 Sir Isaac, 50, 302 Andr, 170-71,416 ch. 20 nn.l,4 Friedrich, xv, 144, 148, 149, 456 Index 158,276,290,333,341,364-67, 369,371-72,374-75,387 Nkrumah, Kwame, 265 Nora, Pierre, 142-43, 185-86, 318-19, 330,433 n. 21 Normand, Claudine, 46, 203, 311 Ogilvie, Bertrand, 409 n. 7,410 ch. 13 n. 13,413 n. 5, 435 nn. 41, 2 Ortigues, Edmond, 234 Ozouf, Jacques, 182 Pags, Robert, 174,310 Parain, Brice, 154 Pariente, Jean-Claude, 147 Pascal, Blaise, 151-52, 175, 245, 295, 381 Passeron,Jean-Claude, 87, 148 Pavel, Thomas, 392, 407 ch. 10 n. 8,420 ch. 24 n. 12,425 n. 34,435 n. 21 PCF. See French Cornrnunist Party, the Pcheux, Michel, 288, 289-90, 298,310, 311-12 Peirce, Charles Sanders, 52, 371 Perrier, Franois, 122 Perrot, Jean, 61 Perrot, Michel, 182, 375, 386 Perroux, Franois, 168, 169-70, 175 Ptain, Philippe, 85 Piaget, Jean, 82, 171, 173, 175,203,220, 373,432 n. 15 Piatier,Jacqueline,227 Picard, Raymond, 223-28, 345, 381 Pichon, douard, 60, 109 Picon, Gatan, 201 Piganiol, Andr, 34 Pingaud, Bernard, 325-26 Pinguet, Maurice, 148, 375 Pinto, Louis, 385 Piot, Colette, 203 Piot, Marc, 270 Pius xn, Pope, 102 Pividal, Rafael, 231 Plato, 43, 230, 288, 333 Pleynet, Marcelin, 277, 278 Poe, Edgar Allan, 107-8 Poincar, Henri, 83 Polivanov, E., 54-55 Pommier, Jean, 34 Pommier, Ren, 228 Pontalis, Jean-Bertrand, 73, 122,247 Popper, Karl, 214, 392 Pottier, Bernard, 61, 199,202,203,210 Pouillon, Jean, 5-8, 24, 25, 272, 323, 424 n. 20, 430 n. 6 Poulantzas, Nicos, xx-xxi Poulet, Georges, 328 Propp, Vladimir, 69, 201, 204-5, 207, 213,214,250-51,316,321-22 Proust, Jacques, 147 Proust, Jolle, 310 Proust, Marcel, 73,262 Pushkin, Aleksandr, 53 Qumada, Bernard, 62-63, 67, 198, 202, 407 ch. 9 n. 3 Rabelais, Franois, 78 Racine, Jean, 175,223,224-25 Radcliffe-Brown, Alfred, 15 Rancire, Jacques, 288, 289, 290-91, 299,414n.2 Rastier, Franois, 214 Raymond, Pierre, 219 Rebeyrol, Philippe, 227 Rgnault, Franois, 282, 288 Renaud, P. A., 414 n. 31 Renaut, Alain, 373,416 nn. 57, 58; 416 ch. 19 n. 2, 434 n. 12 Revault d'Allonnes, Olivier, 18, 148, 161, 226 Revel, Jean-Franois, 218,327 Rey, Jean-Michel, 434 n. 22 Ribaud, Albert, Il Ricardo, David, 300, 316, 334, 339 Ricardou,Jean,278 Richard, Jean-Pierre, 201, 207 Ricoeur, Paul, 122, 236-38, 240, 325 Riffaterre, Michael, 200 Rimbaud, Arthur, 209 Rivet, Paul, 16,40,126,381 Rivire, Georges-Henri, 187 Robbe-Grillet, Alain, 326 Robin, Rgine, 311 Roche, Denis, 278 Rodinson, Maxime, 135 Rossi, Tino, 67 Roudinesco, lisabeth, 195,221,346, 376,377,409 nn. 1,2,3,4,410 n. 9, 412 ch. 16 n. 11,423 nn. 3,4; 428 ch. 30 nn. 19,28; 435 n. 42 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 131, 132-33, 179,258,365 Roussel, Raymond, 149 Rousset, David, 4 Rousset, Jean, 201, 319 Roustang, Franois, 117,246,424 n. 40 Roy, Claude, 133-34, 160, 179,234 Royer-CoUard, Pierre, 236 Russell, Bertrand, 83 Ruwet, Nicolas, 210, 236, 257, 275, 328 Safouan, Moustafa, 120,410 ch. 13 n. 16 Saint-Simon, Claude de, 351 Sapir, Edward, 53 Sarfati, Georges-Elia, 408 n. 23, 434 n. 26 Sartre, Jean-Paul, xv, xxi, 3-9, 38, 129, 133,160,196,232,235-36,238, 263,265,309,323-24,325-27,330, 332,370,382-83,384,391 Saussure, Ferdinand de, xiv, xxii, 20, 22-23,33,34,38,39,41,43-51,52, 54,56,57,59,61,63,64,65,67, 68-69,75-76,77,79,80,81,91,94, 103,104-7,109,121-22,124,140, 165,174,185,203,205-6,210,212, 215,218,240,242,243,247-48,253, 258,290,316,321,323,325,328,387 Sauvy, Alfred, 168 Schlegel, August Wilhelm, 33, 46 Schlegel, Friedrich, 33, 46 Schleicher, August, 33 Schlick, Moritz, 83 Sebag, Lucien, 161, 162,210,324 Schehaye, Albert, 44 Seghers, Anna, 12 Semprun, Jorge, 296, 297 Senghor, Lopold Sdar, 130, 265 Serge, Victor, 12 Serres, Michel, xxiii, 88-90, 147 Sve, Lucien, 297 Sichre, Bernard, 246, 411 n. 23, 414 n. 5 Simiand, Franois, 13, 176, 181 Simon, Michel, 296, 310 Simonis, Yvan, 403 n. 15 Singevin, Charles, 68 Smith, Adam, 300, 334, 339 Smith, Michael Garfield, 267 Socialisme ou Barbarie, 123, 161, 163 Socit Psychanalytique de Paris, the (SPP),95-96, 102, 103, 122, 124,244 Index 4.57 Socrates, 366 Sollers, Philippe, 246, 278, 323, 344 Sophodes, 116 Sorbonne, the, xiii, 59-66, 67, 70, 74, 85, 139,140,145,147,150,161,171, 182,191-201,202,203,223-28, 266,287,294,310,319,387,391 Soustelle, Jacques, 12,40,138 Souvarine, Boris, 92 Spencer, Herbert, xxii, 351 Spengler, Oswald, 351, 365 Sperber, Dan, 269-70, 403 n. 6 Spinoza, Baruch, 79, 81, 84, 240, 307, 381 Spitzer, Leo, 63, 201 SPP. See Socit Psychanalytique de Paris, the Stalin, Joseph, 148, 149, 158, 160, 164, 171 Starobinski, Jean, 50 Stein, Conrad, 122, 123 Steiner, George, 434 n. 14 Straka, Georges, 62, 197 Sumpf, Joseph, 203 Swain, Gladys, 156 Tarde, Gabriel, 170,229 Taylor, Frederick, 314 Terray, Emmanuel, 19,266,270,272, 312-13,348 Texier, Jean, 297 Thibaudeau, Jean, 278, 323 Thomas Aquinas, Saint, 247 Thorez, Maurice, 298 Thomer, Daniel, 139 Todorov, Tzvetan, xxiii, 193-94,204, 210,211,275,278,318,320,323, 328,343,344,387,405 ch. 7 n. 8, 406 ch. 7 n. 19 Togeby, Knud, 62, 198-99 Torrs, Flix, 433 n. 2 Tort, Michel, 289 Tour, Skou, 265 Trotsky, Leon, 55 Trubetzkoy, Nicolai, xxii, 22, 30, 44, 54, 55,57,64,67,70,174,207 Tudesq, Andr, 182 UNESCO, 161 University of Paris VIII-Vincennes, 149, 200 458 Index University of Paris X-Nanterre, 202-203, 311 Uri, Pierre, 168 Vachek, J. 55 Vailland, Roger, 160 Valadier, Paul, 428 n. 31,434 ch. 36 n. 31,435 n. 6 Valry, Paul, 201, 234 Vattimo, Gianni, 434 n. Il Vaugelas, Claude de, xxii Veille, Jacques, 74 Vendrys, 59, 63 Verds-Leroux, Jeannine, 231, 428 ch. 31 n. 19 Verlaine, Paul, 53 Vernant, Jean-Pierre, xxiv, 36, 176, 183-85,257,328-29,384 Vernet, Marc, 421 n. 18 Verret, Michel, 297 Verstraeten, Pierre, 236 Veyne, Paul, 148, 149,375 Vico, Giambattista, 128 Vidal-Naquet, Pierre, 36, 268 Viderman, Serge, 248 Viet, Jean, 383 Vilar, Jean, 77 Vilar, Pierre, 175, 182, 303 Vincent, Jean-Marie, 429 n. 37 Vinogradov, Ivan, 199 Virilio, Paul, 360 Voltaire, 365 Wagemann, Ernst, 170 Wagner, Richard, 257, 259, 262 Wagner, Robert-Lon, 60, 62, 200, 202 Wahl, Franois, 240, 276, 317 Wahl, Jean, 137, 146, 147 Wallon, Henri, 93 Wanters, Arthur, Il Weil, Andr, 24, 83 Weil, Simone, 24 Weiller, Jean, 168 Westermarck, Edward, 19 Winnicott, D. W., 244, 245 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 69, 83, 371 Wolff, tienne, 174 Wormser, Andr, 146 Yaguello, Marina, 194-95,406 n. 10 Zola, mile, 89 Zonabend, Franois, 257 Franois Dosse received his degree in history from the University of Paris-Vincennes in 1972, and passed the prestigious agregation exam the following year. In 1974, he began teaching at Pontoise High School, and five years later began working on his doctorate, under Jean Ches- neaux, on the Annales School and the media since 1968, which be- came the basis for his first best-selling book, L'histoire en miettes: Des "Annales" la "nouvelle histoire" (1987) (published in translation as New History in France: The Triumph of the Annales [1994]). Today, Dosse te aches at the University of Paris-Nanterre and at the Political Science Institution in Paris, and is a guest lecturer at the University of Lausanne, where he lectures on historiography, methodology, histori- cal epistemology, and the relationship between history and the social sciences. He is the author of a rapidly growing list of publications, the most recent of which is L'Empire du Sens, l'humanisation des sciences humaines (forthcoming in translation from the University of Min- nesota Press). He is also on the editorial board of EspaceTemps, and is currently working on an intellectual biography of Paul Ricoeur. Deborah Glassman received a Ph.D. in French from Yale University in 1982. She is the author of Marguerite Duras: Fascinating Vision and Narrative Cure (1990), among other shorter works, and directed the Paris Center for Critical Studies from 1988 to 1992. She is working on a guide to ethnie eating in Paris, where she has lived and worked since 1988.
My Philosophy - And Other Essays on the Moral and Political Problems of Our Time: With an Essay from Benedetto Croce - An Introduction to his Philosophy By Raffaello Piccoli