Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

From $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

More Than Marriage: Forming Families after Marriage Equality
More Than Marriage: Forming Families after Marriage Equality
More Than Marriage: Forming Families after Marriage Equality
Ebook333 pages4 hours

More Than Marriage: Forming Families after Marriage Equality

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Introduces an expansive vision of the family and a brilliant legal arrangement that will protect the lives of millions of adults.
 
Today, about half of all adults are unmarried. Many of those are in significant relationships—some intimate, others based in friendship, finances, or family ties—but the law offers them few protections. Amid the growing recognition that modern families take all shapes, More Than Marriage presents a refreshing vision for the future.
 
With this book, noted family-law expert John G. Culhane takes us on a guided tour of how the march toward marriage equality spun off a number of other legal statuses, and explores how the law has expanded and where it falls short. This lively living history is grounded in relatable, in-depth interviews that give voice to the millions of Americans building family structures outside the protections of marriage—whether by choice, necessity, or exclusion. Culhane proposes an updated legal status that offers flexible and portable benefits for a diverse range of commitments and needs. As More Than Marriage shows, this "choose your own adventure" structure more accurately reflects, and more equitably protects, the many kinds of families we choose to build.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateMay 2, 2023
ISBN9780520391673
More Than Marriage: Forming Families after Marriage Equality
Author

John G. Culhane

John G. Culhane is Professor of Law and Codirector of the Family Health Law & Policy Institute at Delaware Law School (Widener University). He is a frequent contributor to Slate and Politico and is the author of casebooks in the areas of both family law and torts, as well as Same-Sex Legal Kit for Dummies.

Related to More Than Marriage

Related ebooks

Law For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for More Than Marriage

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    More Than Marriage - John G. Culhane

    More Than Marriage

    More Than Marriage

    FORMING FAMILIES AFTER MARRIAGE EQUALITY

    John G. Culhane

    UC Logo

    UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA PRESS

    University of California Press

    Oakland, California

    © 2023 by John G. Culhane

    Cataloging-in-Publication Data is on file at the Library of Congress.

    ISBN 978-0-520-39165-9 (cloth : alk. paper)

    ISBN 978-0-520-39166-6 (pbk. : alk. paper)

    ISBN 978-0-520-39167-3 (ebook)

    Manufactured in the United States of America

    32  31  30  29  28  27  26  25  24  23

    10  9  8  7  6  5  4  3  2  1

    This book is dedicated to my family, in the broadest sense of that word.

    Contents

    List of Tables

    Preface

    Introduction: Marriage Equality—an Important but Limited Victory

    1. The Dawn of the Domestic Partnership, or We Bored Them to Death

    2. Civil Unions: Not Marriage, but an Incredible Simulation!

    3. The Designated Beneficiary Agreement Act: Colorado’s Successful Experiment

    4. What Is Marriage, Anyway? (And What Isn’t Marriage?)

    5. Matching Relationship Law to Reality

    Notes

    References

    Index

    Tables

    1. Excerpt of a Sample Designated Beneficiary Agreement

    2. Designated Beneficiary Agreements between Different-Sex Denver County Couples

    3. Designated Beneficiary Agreements between Same-Sex Denver County Couples

    4. Civil Unions in Denver County

    Preface

    This book is a tribute to the many people who gave generously of their time in sharing with me (and now with you) eloquent testimonials to their roles in creating and living in the various legal relationships that I discuss throughout this volume: domestic partnerships, civil unions, domestic beneficiary agreements, and, of course, marriages. The countless fruitful hours I spent talking with them via phone, Skype, or Zoom or through long email chains not only were necessary for illustrating the arguments I wanted to make on the law’s need for growth and flexibility but also ended up honing and improving those arguments. I can’t imagine the book without their stories. Remember their names: Tom Brougham and Barry Warren; John Kennedy; Tom Gibson (pseud.); Leah Whitesel and Justin Gates; Alex Rifman and Jennifer Tweeton; Emil Roe and Margaret Koe (pseuds.); Lisa Goodman; Sheila Blackburn; Colorado State Senator Pat Steadman; Patricia Yarrow and Liz Gettings; Marilyn McCord; May and April Doe (pseuds.); Anne Quinn and Terry McKeon; and John Hunter and Hal Kooden.

    Like the marriage equality movement that spawned these legal alternatives, this book’s gestation has been a long and, at times, difficult process. I greet its completion with a mixture of joy and—let’s face it!—relief. And like the hard-fought path to the Supreme Court’s ultimate recognition of the rights of gay and lesbian couples to marry, the proposals I put forth here will require sedulous effort and deep dedication to a fuller, fairer legal recognition of all adults in committed relationships. But obstacles will not daunt those determined to carry this fight forward and to continue to protect marriage equality from a Supreme Court that now seems bent on rolling back decades of increasing recognition of fundamental rights and liberties. (That’s another whole book.)

    In addition to the everyday heroes whose stories form its spine, so many others have helped to push this book across the finish line that I’m sure I’ll omit some of them from the acknowledgments to follow. For that, I apologize in advance. But let’s give it a try.

    First, thanks to my editor nonpareil, Maura Roessner. She’s believed in this book from the first time she read it and has been my sounding board, coach, and confidant. Her suggestions and contributions, along with her patience and good humor, have been wise and comforting. The anonymous reviewers she selected, whom I wish I could thank personally, spurred me to think more deeply about the tough issues I raised and led to important changes. And Maura’s assistants, Madison Wetzell and Sam Warren, were quickly responsive to my questions and very helpful. Juliana Froggatt is a careful and thorough copy editor, whose attention to every detail of the writing process has significantly improved this book.

    Thanks too to Jessica Feinberg and Jean Eggen, who read and commented extensively on earlier drafts. Nancy Polikoff provided indispensable information on and context for the early days of domestic partnerships. My colleague and friend Alicia Kelly convinced me of the importance of including a more comprehensive treatment of cohabitation. I also benefited enormously from workshopping portions of this book at various events over the past several years. In particular, my presentation at the Nonmarriage Roundtable at Arizona State University in 2019 elicited helpful comments and suggestions from many of the panelists, especially Kaipo Matsumura, Naomi Cahn, Albertina Antognini, June Carbone, and Barbara Atwood. I have gained invaluable insights from discussing earlier work leading to this book at the Midyear Meetings of both the Family and Juvenile Law Section and the Sexual Orientation and Gender Identity Issues Section of the Association of American Law Schools, during a presentation to faculty and students at the University of Akron School of Law, and in two presentations to my own faculty at the Delaware Law School. Thanks also to Dahlia Lithwick, who somehow found the time to read and comment favorably on the book. I am also grateful for my role as an official observer for the Uniform Law Commission’s work that led to the adoption of the Uniform Cohabitants’ Economic Remedies Act (although I am disappointed that the drafters did not include a registration option in their final draft).

    I also thank my long-suffering family, friends, and random passersby who have had to listen to me talk about this book for the past several years. In particular, thanks to Paulette Greenwell; Iris, Douglas, and Lisa Culhane; Alexa and Courtnee Girasole-Culhane; and—especially—my husband, David Girasole.

    Introduction

    MARRIAGE EQUALITY—AN IMPORTANT BUT LIMITED VICTORY

    The nature of marriage is that, through its enduring bond, two persons together can find other freedoms, such as expression, intimacy, and spirituality. This is true for all persons, whatever their sexual orientation. There is dignity in the bond between two men or two women who seek to marry and in their autonomy to make such profound choices.

    Supreme Court Justice Anthony M. Kennedy

    There are almost as many kinds of relationships as there are people in combination. . . . The marriage issue . . . seems to be a way of denying recognition to [most] relations.

    Michael Warner

    What do adults in committed relationships need from government?

    This vital question has been submerged for far too long by the focus on marriage as the ideal—no, the only—form of adult relationship that deserves recognition. That’s not a healthy or realistic view, but there’s been little appetite at either the state or (especially) the federal level for sober consideration of how people in all sorts of interdependent relationships might be legally supported.

    A moment’s reflection reveals some of the problems with elevating marriage to its unique and unchallenged status. First, marriage is too bossy. It comes with a strong set of default rules. Although couples can modify the terms of marriage through prenuptial agreements, these are rarely executed and are often seen as antithetical to the promise and premise of marriage by the couples choosing to wed. By and large, then, married couples don’t actively select (and are often not even aware of) all of the terms and conditions of their union. Second, continuing with marriage as the unique status is willfully blind to the many millions of adults who are in fact in committed relationships other than marriage but nonetheless need and deserve support. Third, marriage is just the wrong status for many couples.

    This book provides a foundation for creative thinking about how we might build something new and more capacious—perhaps even sprawling. The inspiration for this model is an institution called the designated beneficiary agreement. This legal creature is currently in effect only in Colorado, but it deserves to be expanded and exported to every state. Its unwieldy name notwithstanding, some version of this status stands to do immeasurable good for many—perhaps millions of—people. As we’ll see, a retooled designated beneficiary agreement law provides people with the greatest flexibility to organize their relationships and, if it is properly designed, to gain state support for them. ¹

    This reckoning with the deficiencies of marriage is long overdue and has been obscured for at least the past thirty years by the laser focus on a different but related legal disability: the exclusion of gay and lesbian couples from the institution of marriage. That spotlight diverted focus from the wider issues with the marriage-only concentration. Yet the step-by-step path to marriage equality led to an unintentional but providential spin-off. It has inspired the creation of several compromise legal statuses designed to provide same-sex couples with some of the rights and benefits of marriage. The debates that led to those statuses, as well as their content, have allowed for a clearer focus on how the law might better help all committed adults—not just gay and lesbian couples.

    We begin at the end of the momentous battle for marriage equality.

    On June 26, 2015, many Americans—gay and straight alike—celebrated victory in the decades-long struggle for marriage equality. On that day, the United States Supreme Court issued its seminal decision in Obergefell v. Hodges. ² By a slim 5–4 vote, the justices held that same-sex couples have a constitutional right to cement their love and commitment through marriage. The decision is rightly seen as one of the great triumphs in the perpetual movement toward ever greater civil rights, because marriage was the one place where members of the LGBTQ community were denied an important government benefit—and a coveted status—by virtue of their willingness to be open about their lives and their love.

    As many predicted when Obergefell was decided, the conversation has now shifted to what might be considered questions collateral to marriage. Some of these should be easily answered. Married gay and lesbian couples must be entitled to the same government benefits as straight couples, for instance—even though the Texas Supreme Court has held otherwise. ³ Other questions are more challenging, such as whether business owners can claim religious or expressive exemptions to their obligation to serve gay and lesbian people—often in connection with the very wedding ceremonies that cement the status that these couples are finally entitled to enjoy. ⁴

    Despite these post-Obergefell skirmishes, most observers seem to take marriage equality itself as settled and not likely to be upended—even with a more conservative SCOTUS in place. ⁵ There’s an understandable inclination to move on, and, for the most part, that’s happened. Victory has been achieved.

    Yet the marriage equality movement is in an important sense incomplete. While successful on its own terms, it mostly avoided raising broader questions. Gay and lesbian couples were placed on equal footing with other marriage-eligible folks, but Obergefell—and the movement that led to it—ended up reinforcing the divide that separates married couples from everyone else. As Professor Melissa Murray has said, the Obergefell decision promoted marriage—and only marriage—as the normative ideal for intimate life. ⁶ This insight concisely states one of the persistent criticisms of marriage equality: by emphasizing the rights of gay and lesbian couples to be granted the perquisites of marriage on the same basis as their straight counterparts, the marriage equality movement implicitly reinforced the strong legal fence that separates married couples from others in committed relationships.

    The movement also mostly sidestepped questions about what marriage is. What does it mean, and how should it be supported in the twenty-first century? And what other types of adult relationships—intimate and otherwise—should the law recognize?

    These questions are more vital than ever today. Misty-eyed paeans to marriage can’t disguise the fact that an ever-increasing number of people are choosing not to wed. A watershed moment was reached in 2013, when, for the first time, the number of unmarried adults exceeded the number of married adults in the United States. ⁷ Of perhaps greater significance is the uneven distribution of marriage within society. While marriage rates were once relatively even across socioeconomic classes, over the past forty years or so those with higher levels of education and greater wealth have married at significantly higher rates than the less well educated and the poor. ⁸ There is also now a sharp distinction between marriage rates between races—Black men and women are far less likely to marry than white men and women, for instance. ⁹ Laws and policies that ignore such large and diverse parts of the population need serious rethinking.

    A useful way to begin thinking about the place of marriage and the limitations of focusing too narrowly on that singular status is to consider United States v. Windsor, decided just two years before Obergefell. ¹⁰ The litigation involved a challenge to the Defense of Marriage Act (DOMA), a federal law that applied to same-sex couples who were legally married in their home state. ¹¹ Through DOMA, their rights faded at the state border, because the act fenced them out of the many, many federal goodies that are showered on their different-sex counterparts. These include income tax benefits, preferential immigration status, and certain social security benefits, as well as a host of other advantages that come to a spouse under a variety of social programs. In Windsor, the Supreme Court declared DOMA unconstitutional and held that the federal government had to recognize marriages that were legal at the state level. ¹²

    The case was powerful precisely because of the side-by-side contrast between the plaintiff, Edie Windsor, and other surviving spouses. When her wife, Thea Spyer, died, in 2009, Windsor didn’t qualify for an exemption from the federal estate tax, even though she would have had she been married to a man. The story was made more compelling by the sheer length of the two women’s relationship. Although they had been legally married for only six years, they had been together for almost four decades. ¹³ For all that, Windsor and Spyer were legal strangers under federal law—and Windsor was slapped with an estate tax bill of $363,000.

    So the fact that the two women were married under state law didn’t do them much good—especially financially, and especially after Spyer’s death. During oral argument on the case, the late justice Ruth Bader Ginsburg memorably referred to the women’s union as a skim milk (federal-benefit-free!) marriage. ¹⁴ The comparison was devastating. How could Congress get away with creating such rank inequality? A purer denial of basic justice would be harder to imagine, so striking down DOMA was an easy call. Windsor got her tax exemption, and all gay and lesbian married couples were able to share in the victory—their marriages were now just as good as everyone else’s.

    But are everyone else’s marriages too good? Perhaps Justice Ginsburg’s metaphor was more apt than she realized. If straight marriages are whole milk, as she implied, then they contain an unhealthy amount of fat. Maybe the solution should be skim-milk marriages for all.

    What ingredients would such fat-free marriages contain? We can start thinking about that question by acknowledging that marriage contains too many benefits (fat), some of which aren’t closely related to why the state supports the institution. During the litigation over whether same-sex couples should be allowed to marry, the Government Accountability Office estimated that marital status was a factor in determining rights, benefits, and obligations in some 1,138(!) statutory provisions. ¹⁵ The best known and most significant among these are federal income tax and estate tax rules that treat married and unmarried couples differently, eligibility for Social Security survivor and retirement benefits, and the allowance in immigration law for US citizens to sponsor their spouses into the country as permanent residents. ¹⁶ Marriage is also the trigger for many benefits at the state level, including inheritance rights, economic protection at divorce, the right to sue for wrongful death under tort law, and the right to hold property in a privileged legal form. ¹⁷ And it’s not just the government that privileges marriage either—as anyone who receives spousal health or life insurance benefits from a private employer will attest.

    But while these benefits are showered, indiscriminately, on those who are married, others have no access to them at all—no matter the depth or length of their commitment to another person. The marriage laws are problematic, then, and neither Windsor nor Obergefell addressed this divide. The decisions added gay and lesbian couples to the privileged side of the ledger but left untouched the disparity the law has erected between the married and the unmarried. Because the inclusion of these newly eligible pairs into the marriage club was in one sense radical, it was easy to miss that the movement was, in another sense, quite conservative. The velvet rope was unclasped for gay and lesbian couples but not for others. While the voices of the more creative opponents of this formal equality were hard to hear over the celebrations, the seeds of a more expansive view of relationship recognition and state support had already been planted. We’ll take a close look at some of these efforts over the course of this book.

    None of this should detract from recognizing the extraordinary, and swift, accomplishment of marriage equality. In the earliest cases challenging the exclusion of gay and lesbian couples from marriage, courts were uncomprehending and unsympathetic. But as the LGBTQ community became more visible over the past thirty years, so too did its members’ relationships. Courts and then lawmakers began to take notice. ¹⁸ Windsor isn’t the only case where a profile of the law’s effect on actual people insinuated itself into a judicial opinion. The Massachusetts Supreme Court foregrounded its pathbreaking 2003 marriage equality decision, Goodridge v. Department of Public Health, by telling the stories of the fourteen couples seeking marriage licenses—a committed, responsible, and in some cases child-rearing group of unfairly treated citizens. ¹⁹ Justice Anthony Kennedy’s majority decision in Obergefell followed a similar path, revealing heartbreaking details about James Obergefell’s marriage in Maryland to a dying man and the state of Ohio’s subsequent refusal to acknowledge that union by placing his name on his deceased partner’s death certificate. Also featured was a lesbian couple who had not been able to jointly adopt two seriously ill babies, so that each child had only one legal parent. ²⁰

    This book follows this narrative approach, presenting profiles of people in adult relationships that the law does not consistently recognize or support. For instance, the lifelong bond between two elderly sisters from Philadelphia underscores the dichotomy between Edie Windsor and Thea Spyer and other adults in committed relationships. These siblings, who appear in chapter 4, have lived together all their lives. They are emotionally and financially interdependent, no less than were Windsor and Spyer. But since they are sisters, they of course remain ineligible for marriage—meaning that the survivor will not enjoy the estate tax exemption that Windsor ultimately received. Is that fair? Why or why not? And is the estate tax exemption fair in the first place? More broadly, how should the law support couples in relationships of different kinds?

    Although the marriage equality movement achieved victory without answering these questions, it did not quite manage to avoid raising them—in two different but related ways. First, in tackling the issue of whether government had a valid reason for excluding same-sex couples from marriage, courts and legislatures were occasionally drawn into a broader discussion of what marriage means—what is it for, and why does the state support it? I address these crucial questions and make suggests for reforming the institution. Second, the growing realization among gay and lesbian couples that they were being treated unfairly in their relationships led them to advocate for consolation prizes: other legal statuses that conferred benefits on them (and sometimes on other unmarried couples) short of marriage. These statuses began to appear in the 1980s and now flourish in cities, counties, and states. They carry several names and varying legal incidents, with attendant uncertainty and confusion. But they have the potential to serve as auguries of a more comprehensive alternative to marriage—one for which I enthusiastically make the case in this book.

    In searching for real, defensible reasons for barring same-sex couples from marriage, defenders of traditional marriage could not avoid delving into existential issues about marriage itself. For instance, Supreme Court Justice Samuel Alito, in dissenting from the ruling in Obergefell, identified two competing views of marriage. The traditional view (which, he argued, states had a right to maintain) is that marriage is to encourage procreation in a stable setting—and since only different-sex couples can procreate without assistance, states can limit marriage rights to those couples. He went on to express a concern that once the marriage-procreation link was sundered, over time the institution might be seriously undermine[d]. ²¹

    The other side of the debate, for Alito, was the modern view that marriage is mostly about promot[ing] the well-being of those who choose to marry. This, he acknowledged, results in good things for society too: by providing emotional fulfillment and the promise of support in times of need . . . marriage indirectly benefits society because persons who live in stable, fulfilling, and supportive relationships make better citizens. That’s why states encourage and formalize marriage, confer special benefits on married persons, and also impose some special obligations. ²² Alito concluded that the contest over the meaning of marriage had not been resolved and was best left to the political process.

    The triumph of the marriage equality movement signified at least that marriage no longer meant only what traditionalists maintained was its one, true purpose—whether that was a version of Alito’s natural law view, that the institution exists only to bring men and women together in recognition of their biological complementarity, ²³ or, more dismally, the view of people like the conservative political commentator Maggie Gallagher, for whom it is a way of keeping men from leaving the children they’d otherwise be tempted to run from. ²⁴

    Even on its own terms, Justice Alito’s perception misses a few things—like the tenuous connection in the twenty-first century between procreation and marriage, or the government’s interest in supporting adoptive families too—but it is a useful starting point for a discussion about what marriage does and should signify. Marriage equality didn’t end that debate; it just represented the legal triumph of the more modern view. It also failed to address the more practical question of how far the state should go in privileging marriage above other forms of relationships—intimate and otherwise—and whether the benefits attached to it are central to its purpose.

    Beyond forcing at least a limited debate on the meaning of marriage, the struggle for gay and lesbian equality did something else that could stand to remake life in the twenty-first century. Although the issue was mostly avoided by marriage equality advocates, the movement triggered the creation of several new legal statuses—sometimes indirectly and sometimes quite directly. The earliest of these was the domestic partnership. This status resists concise description, because it is actually a polymorph of sometimes distantly related things, conferred by different authorities. There are local domestic partnerships, offered by some cities and towns; statewide domestic partnerships; domestic partnership benefits provided by employers to employees as part of their compensation packages; and even de facto domestic partnerships created by courts to protect people whose reasonable expectations of support are defeated when their cohabitating partners skip out. And they’re just as diverse in the benefits and rights they establish. Among these are health benefits, rights to hospital visitation, the ability to be named as a beneficiary of various pension plans—and many more, depending on where the partnership is formed and who’s doing the conferring. Finally, domestic partnerships vary in the classes of couples eligible for them, as we’ll see.

    Chapter 1 profiles Tom Brougham and Barry Warren, the pioneering couple who invented the term domestic partnership and have been joined in that status since it became legal—way back in the 1980s. Their struggle and the explosion of domestic partnerships for which they lit the fuse have important implications for the future of nonmarital relationships.

    A much tidier legal status arrived in 2000: the civil union. Perhaps the best known of the marriage alternatives and a direct outgrowth of the marriage

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1