Essays in Radical Empiricism
()
About this ebook
William James
William James (1842–1910) was an American philosopher, physician, and psychologist. The brother of novelist Henry James, William James is remembered for his contributions to the fields of pragmatism and functional psychology.
Read more from William James
The Existential Literature Collection Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Varieties of Religious Experience Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Pragmatism and Other Writings Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Principles of Psychology - Vol. I. Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Varieties of Religious Experience Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Principles of Psychology - Part II. Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Recovery Bible: Discover the Classic Books That Inspired the Founders of the Modern Recovery Movement Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Principles of Psychology Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA Pluralistic Universe Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Pragmatism Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Principles of Psychology (Vol. 1&2) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBe Not Afraid of Life: In the Words of William James Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Will to Believe and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Pluralistic Universe [Halls of Wisdom] Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsTHE PRINCIPLES OF PSYCHOLOGY (Complete Edition In 2 Volumes) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Varieties of Religious Experience Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Will to Believe Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5The Little Book of Life After Death Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Principles of Psychology, Vol. 1 Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Letters of William James, Vol. 1 Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Complete Works of William James. Illustrated: The Varieties of Religious Experience. The Principles of Psychology. Pragmatism Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Meaning of Truth Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Psychology (Barnes & Noble Digital Library) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Varieties of Religious Experience Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Will to Believe (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading): and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Will to Believe (Barnes & Noble Digital Library): And Other Essays in Popular Philosophy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Pluralistic Universe Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Related to Essays in Radical Empiricism
Related ebooks
Philosophy of Existence Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5On Wittgenstein and Buddhism. An Interactive Exploration Into Wittgenstein's Ideas, Buddhist Philosophy and a New Paradigm Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHegel on Self-Consciousness: Desire and Death in the Phenomenology of Spirit Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Hegel's Philosophy of Mind Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Social Contract & Discourse on Inequality: Including Discourse on the Arts and Sciences & A Discourse on Political Economy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPragmatism Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Meaning of Truth Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Varieties of Religious Experience Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHeidegger and Kant Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Will to Believe Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Letters of William James, Vol. I Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsParfit: A Philosopher and His Mission to Save Morality Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Phenomenology and the Problem of Meaning in Human Life and History Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Art of Literature Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature: Thirtieth-Anniversary Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Leibniz's New Essays Concerning the Human Understanding: A Critical Exposition Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA Pluralistic Universe Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Delphi Collected Works of Immanuel Kant (Illustrated) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsImmanuel Kant's Critique of Pure Reason Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Spinoza Reader: The Ethics and Other Works Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Simply Wittgenstein Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Kant's Philosophical Revolution: A Short Guide to the Critique of Pure Reason Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsKant’s Theory of Mental Activity: A Commentary on the Transcendental Analytic of the Critique of Pure Reason Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5An Ethics for Today: Finding Common Ground Between Philosophy and Religion Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Critique of Pure Reason Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsDelphi Complete Works of George Berkeley (Illustrated) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Principles of Psychology (Vol. 1&2) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPragmatism's Evolution: Organism and Environment in American Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Personal Growth For You
The Boy, the Mole, the Fox and the Horse Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Big Book of 30-Day Challenges: 60 Habit-Forming Programs to Live an Infinitely Better Life Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Alchemist: A Graphic Novel Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Gifts of Imperfection: Let Go of Who You Think You're Supposed to Be and Embrace Who You Are Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Four Loves Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Crucial Conversations Tools for Talking When Stakes Are High, Second Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Never Split the Difference: Negotiating As If Your Life Depended On It Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Self-Care for People with ADHD: 100+ Ways to Recharge, De-Stress, and Prioritize You! Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Subtle Art of Not Giving a F*ck: A Counterintuitive Approach to Living a Good Life Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Unfuck Your Brain: Using Science to Get Over Anxiety, Depression, Anger, Freak-outs, and Triggers Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5What Happened to You?: Conversations on Trauma, Resilience, and Healing Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The 7 Habits of Highly Effective People Personal Workbook Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The 5AM Club: Own Your Morning. Elevate Your Life. Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Present Over Perfect: Leaving Behind Frantic for a Simpler, More Soulful Way of Living Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Unfu*k Yourself: Get Out of Your Head and into Your Life Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The 7 Habits of Highly Effective People: The Infographics Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Think and Grow Rich (Illustrated Edition): With linked Table of Contents Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Maybe You Should Talk to Someone: A Therapist, HER Therapist, and Our Lives Revealed Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Girl, Wash Your Face: Stop Believing the Lies About Who You Are so You Can Become Who You Were Meant to Be Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Source: The Secrets of the Universe, the Science of the Brain Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Crucial Conversations: Tools for Talking When Stakes are High, Third Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Uninvited: Living Loved When You Feel Less Than, Left Out, and Lonely Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Grit: The Power of Passion and Perseverance Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Mastery of Self: A Toltec Guide to Personal Freedom Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Personality Types: Using the Enneagram for Self-Discovery Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Road Less Traveled: A New Psychology of Love, Traditional Values and Spiritual Growth Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Emotional Intelligence 2.0 Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Reviews for Essays in Radical Empiricism
0 ratings0 reviews
Book preview
Essays in Radical Empiricism - William James
Essays in Radical Empiricism
by William James
EDITOR'S PREFACE
The present volume is an attempt to carry out a plan which William James
is known to have formed several years before his death. In 1907 he
collected reprints in an envelope which he inscribed with the title
'Essays in Radical Empiricism'; and he also had duplicate sets of these
reprints bound, under the same title, and deposited for the use of
students in the general Harvard Library, and in the Philosophical
Library in Emerson Hall.
Two years later Professor James published _The Meaning of Truth_ and _A
Pluralistic Universe_, and inserted in these volumes several of the
articles which he had intended to use in the 'Essays in Radical
Empiricism.' Whether he would nevertheless have carried out his original
plan, had he lived, cannot be certainly known. Several facts, however,
stand out very clearly. In the first place, the articles included in the
original plan but omitted from his later volumes are indispensable to
the understanding of his other writings. To these articles he repeatedly
alludes. Thus, in _The Meaning of Truth_ (p. 127), he says: "This
statement is probably excessively obscure to any one who has not read my
two articles 'Does Consciousness Exist?' and 'A World of Pure
Experience.'" Other allusions have been indicated in the present text.
In the second place, the articles originally brought together as 'Essays
in Radical Empiricism' form a connected whole. Not only were most of
them written consecutively within a period of two years, but they
contain numerous cross-references. In the third place, Professor James
regarded 'radical empiricism' as an _independent_ doctrine. This he
asserted expressly: "Let me say that there is no logical connexion
between pragmatism, as I understand it, and a doctrine which I have
recently set forth as 'radical empiricism.' The latter stands on its own
feet. One may entirely reject it and still be a pragmatist."
(_Pragmatism_, 1907, Preface, p. ix.) Finally, Professor James came
toward the end of his life to regard 'radical empiricism' as more
fundamental and more important than 'pragmatism.' In the Preface to _The
Meaning of Truth_ (1909), the author gives the following explanation of
his desire to continue, and if possible conclude, the controversy over
pragmatism: "I am interested in another doctrine in philosophy to which
I give the name of radical empiricism, and it seems to me that the
establishment of the pragmatist theory of truth is a step of first-rate
importance in making radical empiricism prevail" (p. xii).
In preparing the present volume, the editor has therefore been governed
by two motives. On the one hand, he has sought to preserve and make
accessible certain important articles not to be found in Professor
James's other books. This is true of Essays I, II, IV, V, VIII, IX, X,
XI, and XII. On the other hand, he has sought to bring together in one
volume a set of essays treating systematically of one independent,
coherent, and fundamental doctrine. To this end it has seemed best to
include three essays (III, VI, and VII), which, although included in the
original plan, were afterwards reprinted elsewhere; and one essay, XII,
not included in the original plan. Essays III, VI, and VII are
indispensable to the consecutiveness of the series, and are so
interwoven with the rest that it is necessary that the student should
have them at hand for ready consultation. Essay XII throws an important
light on the author's general 'empiricism,' and forms an important link
between 'radical empiricism' and the author's other doctrines.
In short, the present volume is designed not as a collection but rather
as a treatise. It is intended that another volume shall be issued which
shall contain papers having biographical or historical importance which
have not yet been reprinted in book form. The present volume is intended
not only for students of Professor James's philosophy, but for students
of metaphysics and the theory of knowledge. It sets forth systematically
and within brief compass the doctrine of 'radical empiricism.'
A word more may be in order concerning the general meaning of this
doctrine. In the Preface to the _Will to Believe_ (1898), Professor
James gives the name _radical empiricism_
to his "philosophic
attitude, and adds the following explanation:
I say 'empiricism,'
because it is contented to regard its most assured conclusions
concerning matters of fact as hypotheses liable to modification in the
course of future experience; and I say 'radical,' because it treats the
doctrine of monism itself as an hypothesis, and, unlike so much of the
halfway empiricism that is current under the name of positivism or
agnosticism or scientific naturalism, it does not dogmatically affirm
monism as something with which all experience has got to square" (pp.
vii-viii). An 'empiricism' of this description is a "philosophic
attitude" or temper of mind rather than a doctrine, and characterizes
all of Professor James's writings. It is set forth in Essay XII of the
present volume.
In a narrower sense, 'empiricism' is the method of resorting to
_particular experiences_ for the solution of philosophical problems.
Rationalists are the men of principles, empiricists the men of facts.
(_Some Problems of Philosophy_, p. 35; cf. also, _ibid._, p. 44; and
_Pragmatism_, pp. 9, 51.) Or, "since principles are universals, and
facts are particulars, perhaps the best way of characterizing the two
tendencies is to say that rationalist thinking proceeds most willingly
by going from wholes to parts, while empiricist thinking proceeds by
going from parts to wholes." (_Some Problems of Philosophy_, p. 35; cf.
also _ibid._, p. 98; and _A Pluralistic Universe_, p. 7.) Again,
empiricism remands us to sensation.
(_Op. cit._, p. 264.) The
empiricist view
insists that, "as reality is created temporally day by
day, concepts ... can never fitly supersede perception.... The deeper
features of reality are found only in perceptual experience." (_Some
Problems of Philosophy_, pp. 100, 97.) Empiricism in this sense is as
yet characteristic of Professor James's philosophy _as a whole_. It is
not the distinctive and independent doctrine set forth in the present
book.
The only summary of 'radical empiricism' in this last and narrowest
sense appears in the Preface to _The Meaning of Truth_ (pp. xii-xiii);
and it must be reprinted here as the key to the text that follows.[1]
"Radical empiricism consists (1) first of a postulate, (2) next of a
statement of fact, (3) and finally of a generalized conclusion."
(1) "The postulate is that _the only things that shall be debatable
among philosophers shall be things definable in terms drawn from
experience_. (Things of an unexperienceable nature may exist ad libitum,
but they form no part of the material for philosophic debate.)" This is
the principle of pure experience
as a methodical postulate.
(Cf.
below, pp. 159, 241.) This postulate corresponds to the notion which the
author repeatedly attributes to Shadworth Hodgson, the notion "that
realities are only what they are 'known as.'" (_Pragmatism_, p. 50;
_Varieties of Religious Experience_, p. 443; _The Meaning of Truth_, pp.
43, 118.) In this sense 'radical empiricism' and pragmatism are closely
allied. Indeed, if pragmatism be defined as the assertion that "the
meaning of any proposition can always be brought down to some particular
consequence in our future practical experience, ... the point lying in
the fact that the experience must be particular rather than in the fact
that it must be active" (_Meaning of Truth_, p. 210); then pragmatism
and the above postulate come to the same thing. The present book,
however, consists not so much in the assertion of this postulate as in
the _use_ of it. And the method is successful in special applications by
virtue of a certain statement of fact
concerning relations.
(2) "The statement of fact is that _the relations between things,
conjunctive as well as disjunctive, are just as much matters of direct
particular experience, neither more so nor less so, than the things
themselves_." (Cf. also _A Pluralistic Universe_, p. 280; _The Will to
Believe_, p. 278.) This is the central doctrine of the present book. It
distinguishes 'radical empiricism' from the ordinary empiricism
of
Hume, J. S. Mill, etc., with which it is otherwise allied. (Cf. below,
pp. 42-44.) It provides an empirical and relational version of
'activity,' and so distinguishes the author's voluntarism from a view
with which it is easily confused--the view which upholds a pure or
transcendent activity. (Cf. below, Essay VI.) It makes it possible to
escape the vicious disjunctions that have thus far baffled philosophy:
such disjunctions as those between consciousness and physical nature,
between thought and its object, between one mind and another, and
between one 'thing' and another. These disjunctions need not be
'overcome' by calling in any "extraneous trans-empirical connective
support" (_Meaning of Truth_, Preface, p. xiii); they may now be
_avoided_ by regarding the dualities in question as only _differences of
empirical relationship among common empirical terms_. The pragmatistic
account of 'meaning' and 'truth,' shows only how a vicious disjunction
between 'idea' and 'object' may thus be avoided. The present volume not
only presents pragmatism in this light; but adds similar accounts of the
other dualities mentioned above.
Thus while pragmatism and radical empiricism do not differ essentially
when regarded as _methods_, they are independent when regarded as
doctrines. For it would be possible to hold the pragmatistic theory of
'meaning' and 'truth,' without basing it on any fundamental theory of
relations, and without extending such a theory of relations to residual
philosophical problems; without, in short, holding either to the above
'statement of fact,' or to the following 'generalized conclusion.'
(3) "The generalized conclusion is that therefore _the parts of
experience hold together from next to next by relations that are
themselves parts of experience. The directly apprehended universe needs,
in short, no extraneous trans-empirical connective support, but
possesses in its own right a concatenated or continuous structure_."
When thus generalized, 'radical empiricism' is not only a theory of
knowledge comprising pragmatism as a special chapter, but a metaphysic
as well. It excludes the hypothesis of trans-empirical reality
(Cf.
below, p. 195). It is the author's most rigorous statement of his theory
that reality is an experience-continuum.
(_Meaning of Truth_, p. 152;
_A Pluralistic Universe_, Lect. V, VII.) It is that positive and
constructive 'empiricism' of which Professor James said: "Let empiricism
once become associated with religion, as hitherto, through some strange
misunderstanding, it has been associated with irreligion, and I believe
that a new era of religion as well as of philosophy will be ready to
begin." (_Op. cit._, p. 314; cf. _ibid._, Lect. VIII, _passim_; and _The
Varieties of Religious Experience_, pp. 515-527.)
The editor desires to acknowledge his obligations to the periodicals
from which these essays have been reprinted, and to the many friends of
Professor James who have rendered valuable advice and assistance in the
preparation of the present volume.
RALPH BARTON PERRY.
CAMBRIDGE, MASSACHUSETTS.
January 8, 1912.
FOOTNOTES:
[1] The use of numerals and italics is introduced by the editor.
CONTENTS
I. DOES 'CONSCIOUSNESS' EXIST? 1
II. A WORLD OF PURE EXPERIENCE 39
III. THE THING AND ITS RELATIONS 92
IV. HOW TWO MINDS CAN KNOW ONE THING 123
V. THE PLACE OF AFFECTIONAL FACTS IN A WORLD
OF PURE EXPERIENCE 137
VI. THE EXPERIENCE OF ACTIVITY 155
VII. THE ESSENCE OF HUMANISM 190
VIII. LA NOTION DE CONSCIENCE 206
IX. IS RADICAL EMPIRICISM SOLIPSISTIC? 234
X. MR. PITKIN'S REFUTATION OF 'RADICAL EMPIRICISM' 241
XI. HUMANISM AND TRUTH ONCE MORE 244
XII. ABSOLUTISM AND EMPIRICISM 266
INDEX 281
I
DOES 'CONSCIOUSNESS' EXIST?[2]
'Thoughts' and 'things' are names for two sorts of object, which common
sense will always find contrasted and will always practically oppose to
each other. Philosophy, reflecting on the contrast, has varied in the
past in her explanations of it, and may be expected to vary in the
future. At first, 'spirit and matter,' 'soul and body,' stood for a pair
of equipollent substances quite on a par in weight and interest. But one
day Kant undermined the soul and brought in the transcendental ego, and
ever since then the bipolar relation has been very much off its balance.
The transcendental ego seems nowadays in rationalist quarters to stand
for everything, in empiricist quarters for almost nothing. In the hands
of such writers as Schuppe, Rehmke, Natorp, Münsterberg--at any rate in
his earlier writings, Schubert-Soldern and others, the spiritual
principle attenuates itself to a thoroughly ghostly condition, being
only a name for the fact that the 'content' of experience _is known_. It
loses personal form and activity--these passing over to the content--and
becomes a bare _Bewusstheit_ or _Bewusstsein überhaupt_, of which in its
own right absolutely nothing can be said.
I believe that 'consciousness,' when once it has evaporated to this
estate of pure diaphaneity, is on the point of disappearing altogether.
It is the name of a nonentity, and has no right to a place among first
principles. Those who still cling to it are clinging to a mere echo, the
faint rumor left behind by the disappearing 'soul' upon the air of
philosophy. During the past year, I have read a number of articles whose
authors seemed just on the point of abandoning the notion of
consciousness,[3] and substituting for it that of an absolute experience
not due to two factors. But they were not quite radical enough, not
quite daring enough in their negations. For twenty years past I have
mistrusted 'consciousness' as an entity; for seven or eight years past I
have suggested its non-existence to my students, and tried to give them
its pragmatic equivalent in realities of experience. It seems to me that
the hour is ripe for it to be openly and universally discarded.
To deny plumply that 'consciousness' exists seems so absurd on the face
of it--for undeniably 'thoughts' do exist--that I fear some readers will
follow me no farther. Let me then immediately explain that I mean only
to deny that the word stands for an entity, but to insist most
emphatically that it does stand for a function. There is, I mean, no
aboriginal stuff or quality of being,[4] contrasted with that of which
material objects are made, out of which our thoughts of them are made;
but there is a function in experience which thoughts perform, and for
the performance of which this quality of being is invoked. That
function is _knowing_. 'Consciousness' is supposed necessary to explain
the fact that things not only are, but get reported, are known. Whoever
blots out the notion of consciousness from his list of first principles
must still provide in some way for that function's being carried on.
I
My thesis is that if we start with the supposition that there is only
one primal stuff or material in the world, a stuff of which everything
is composed, and if we call that stuff 'pure experience,' then knowing
can easily be explained as a particular sort of relation towards one
another into which portions of pure experience may enter. The relation
itself is a part of pure experience; one of its 'terms' becomes the
subject or bearer of the knowledge, the knower,[5] the other becomes the
object known. This will need much explanation before it can be
understood. The best way to get it understood is to contrast