Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

From $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Essays in Radical Empiricism
Essays in Radical Empiricism
Essays in Radical Empiricism
Ebook293 pages2 hours

Essays in Radical Empiricism

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Experience the life-changing power of William James with this unforgettable book.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateDec 16, 2020
ISBN9791220252164
Author

William James

William James (1842–1910) was an American philosopher, physician, and psychologist. The brother of novelist Henry James, William James is remembered for his contributions to the fields of pragmatism and functional psychology. 

Read more from William James

Related to Essays in Radical Empiricism

Related ebooks

Personal Growth For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Essays in Radical Empiricism

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Essays in Radical Empiricism - William James

    Essays in Radical Empiricism

    by William James

    EDITOR'S PREFACE

    The present volume is an attempt to carry out a plan which William James

    is known to have formed several years before his death. In 1907 he

    collected reprints in an envelope which he inscribed with the title

    'Essays in Radical Empiricism'; and he also had duplicate sets of these

    reprints bound, under the same title, and deposited for the use of

    students in the general Harvard Library, and in the Philosophical

    Library in Emerson Hall.

    Two years later Professor James published _The Meaning of Truth_ and _A

    Pluralistic Universe_, and inserted in these volumes several of the

    articles which he had intended to use in the 'Essays in Radical

    Empiricism.' Whether he would nevertheless have carried out his original

    plan, had he lived, cannot be certainly known. Several facts, however,

    stand out very clearly. In the first place, the articles included in the

    original plan but omitted from his later volumes are indispensable to

    the understanding of his other writings. To these articles he repeatedly

    alludes. Thus, in _The Meaning of Truth_ (p. 127), he says: "This

    statement is probably excessively obscure to any one who has not read my

    two articles 'Does Consciousness Exist?' and 'A World of Pure

    Experience.'" Other allusions have been indicated in the present text.

    In the second place, the articles originally brought together as 'Essays

    in Radical Empiricism' form a connected whole. Not only were most of

    them written consecutively within a period of two years, but they

    contain numerous cross-references. In the third place, Professor James

    regarded 'radical empiricism' as an _independent_ doctrine. This he

    asserted expressly: "Let me say that there is no logical connexion

    between pragmatism, as I understand it, and a doctrine which I have

    recently set forth as 'radical empiricism.' The latter stands on its own

    feet. One may entirely reject it and still be a pragmatist."

    (_Pragmatism_, 1907, Preface, p. ix.) Finally, Professor James came

    toward the end of his life to regard 'radical empiricism' as more

    fundamental and more important than 'pragmatism.' In the Preface to _The

    Meaning of Truth_ (1909), the author gives the following explanation of

    his desire to continue, and if possible conclude, the controversy over

    pragmatism: "I am interested in another doctrine in philosophy to which

    I give the name of radical empiricism, and it seems to me that the

    establishment of the pragmatist theory of truth is a step of first-rate

    importance in making radical empiricism prevail" (p. xii).

    In preparing the present volume, the editor has therefore been governed

    by two motives. On the one hand, he has sought to preserve and make

    accessible certain important articles not to be found in Professor

    James's other books. This is true of Essays I, II, IV, V, VIII, IX, X,

    XI, and XII. On the other hand, he has sought to bring together in one

    volume a set of essays treating systematically of one independent,

    coherent, and fundamental doctrine. To this end it has seemed best to

    include three essays (III, VI, and VII), which, although included in the

    original plan, were afterwards reprinted elsewhere; and one essay, XII,

    not included in the original plan. Essays III, VI, and VII are

    indispensable to the consecutiveness of the series, and are so

    interwoven with the rest that it is necessary that the student should

    have them at hand for ready consultation. Essay XII throws an important

    light on the author's general 'empiricism,' and forms an important link

    between 'radical empiricism' and the author's other doctrines.

    In short, the present volume is designed not as a collection but rather

    as a treatise. It is intended that another volume shall be issued which

    shall contain papers having biographical or historical importance which

    have not yet been reprinted in book form. The present volume is intended

    not only for students of Professor James's philosophy, but for students

    of metaphysics and the theory of knowledge. It sets forth systematically

    and within brief compass the doctrine of 'radical empiricism.'

    A word more may be in order concerning the general meaning of this

    doctrine. In the Preface to the _Will to Believe_ (1898), Professor

    James gives the name _radical empiricism_ to his "philosophic

    attitude, and adds the following explanation: I say 'empiricism,'

    because it is contented to regard its most assured conclusions

    concerning matters of fact as hypotheses liable to modification in the

    course of future experience; and I say 'radical,' because it treats the

    doctrine of monism itself as an hypothesis, and, unlike so much of the

    halfway empiricism that is current under the name of positivism or

    agnosticism or scientific naturalism, it does not dogmatically affirm

    monism as something with which all experience has got to square" (pp.

    vii-viii). An 'empiricism' of this description is a "philosophic

    attitude" or temper of mind rather than a doctrine, and characterizes

    all of Professor James's writings. It is set forth in Essay XII of the

    present volume.

    In a narrower sense, 'empiricism' is the method of resorting to

    _particular experiences_ for the solution of philosophical problems.

    Rationalists are the men of principles, empiricists the men of facts.

    (_Some Problems of Philosophy_, p. 35; cf. also, _ibid._, p. 44; and

    _Pragmatism_, pp. 9, 51.) Or, "since principles are universals, and

    facts are particulars, perhaps the best way of characterizing the two

    tendencies is to say that rationalist thinking proceeds most willingly

    by going from wholes to parts, while empiricist thinking proceeds by

    going from parts to wholes." (_Some Problems of Philosophy_, p. 35; cf.

    also _ibid._, p. 98; and _A Pluralistic Universe_, p. 7.) Again,

    empiricism remands us to sensation. (_Op. cit._, p. 264.) The

    empiricist view insists that, "as reality is created temporally day by

    day, concepts ... can never fitly supersede perception.... The deeper

    features of reality are found only in perceptual experience." (_Some

    Problems of Philosophy_, pp. 100, 97.) Empiricism in this sense is as

    yet characteristic of Professor James's philosophy _as a whole_. It is

    not the distinctive and independent doctrine set forth in the present

    book.

    The only summary of 'radical empiricism' in this last and narrowest

    sense appears in the Preface to _The Meaning of Truth_ (pp. xii-xiii);

    and it must be reprinted here as the key to the text that follows.[1]

    "Radical empiricism consists (1) first of a postulate, (2) next of a

    statement of fact, (3) and finally of a generalized conclusion."

    (1) "The postulate is that _the only things that shall be debatable

    among philosophers shall be things definable in terms drawn from

    experience_. (Things of an unexperienceable nature may exist ad libitum,

    but they form no part of the material for philosophic debate.)" This is

    the principle of pure experience as a methodical postulate. (Cf.

    below, pp. 159, 241.) This postulate corresponds to the notion which the

    author repeatedly attributes to Shadworth Hodgson, the notion "that

    realities are only what they are 'known as.'" (_Pragmatism_, p. 50;

    _Varieties of Religious Experience_, p. 443; _The Meaning of Truth_, pp.

    43, 118.) In this sense 'radical empiricism' and pragmatism are closely

    allied. Indeed, if pragmatism be defined as the assertion that "the

    meaning of any proposition can always be brought down to some particular

    consequence in our future practical experience, ... the point lying in

    the fact that the experience must be particular rather than in the fact

    that it must be active" (_Meaning of Truth_, p. 210); then pragmatism

    and the above postulate come to the same thing. The present book,

    however, consists not so much in the assertion of this postulate as in

    the _use_ of it. And the method is successful in special applications by

    virtue of a certain statement of fact concerning relations.

    (2) "The statement of fact is that _the relations between things,

    conjunctive as well as disjunctive, are just as much matters of direct

    particular experience, neither more so nor less so, than the things

    themselves_." (Cf. also _A Pluralistic Universe_, p. 280; _The Will to

    Believe_, p. 278.) This is the central doctrine of the present book. It

    distinguishes 'radical empiricism' from the ordinary empiricism of

    Hume, J. S. Mill, etc., with which it is otherwise allied. (Cf. below,

    pp. 42-44.) It provides an empirical and relational version of

    'activity,' and so distinguishes the author's voluntarism from a view

    with which it is easily confused--the view which upholds a pure or

    transcendent activity. (Cf. below, Essay VI.) It makes it possible to

    escape the vicious disjunctions that have thus far baffled philosophy:

    such disjunctions as those between consciousness and physical nature,

    between thought and its object, between one mind and another, and

    between one 'thing' and another. These disjunctions need not be

    'overcome' by calling in any "extraneous trans-empirical connective

    support" (_Meaning of Truth_, Preface, p. xiii); they may now be

    _avoided_ by regarding the dualities in question as only _differences of

    empirical relationship among common empirical terms_. The pragmatistic

    account of 'meaning' and 'truth,' shows only how a vicious disjunction

    between 'idea' and 'object' may thus be avoided. The present volume not

    only presents pragmatism in this light; but adds similar accounts of the

    other dualities mentioned above.

    Thus while pragmatism and radical empiricism do not differ essentially

    when regarded as _methods_, they are independent when regarded as

    doctrines. For it would be possible to hold the pragmatistic theory of

    'meaning' and 'truth,' without basing it on any fundamental theory of

    relations, and without extending such a theory of relations to residual

    philosophical problems; without, in short, holding either to the above

    'statement of fact,' or to the following 'generalized conclusion.'

    (3) "The generalized conclusion is that therefore _the parts of

    experience hold together from next to next by relations that are

    themselves parts of experience. The directly apprehended universe needs,

    in short, no extraneous trans-empirical connective support, but

    possesses in its own right a concatenated or continuous structure_."

    When thus generalized, 'radical empiricism' is not only a theory of

    knowledge comprising pragmatism as a special chapter, but a metaphysic

    as well. It excludes the hypothesis of trans-empirical reality (Cf.

    below, p. 195). It is the author's most rigorous statement of his theory

    that reality is an experience-continuum. (_Meaning of Truth_, p. 152;

    _A Pluralistic Universe_, Lect. V, VII.) It is that positive and

    constructive 'empiricism' of which Professor James said: "Let empiricism

    once become associated with religion, as hitherto, through some strange

    misunderstanding, it has been associated with irreligion, and I believe

    that a new era of religion as well as of philosophy will be ready to

    begin." (_Op. cit._, p. 314; cf. _ibid._, Lect. VIII, _passim_; and _The

    Varieties of Religious Experience_, pp. 515-527.)

    The editor desires to acknowledge his obligations to the periodicals

    from which these essays have been reprinted, and to the many friends of

    Professor James who have rendered valuable advice and assistance in the

    preparation of the present volume.

      RALPH BARTON PERRY.

      CAMBRIDGE, MASSACHUSETTS.

      January 8, 1912.

    FOOTNOTES:

    [1] The use of numerals and italics is introduced by the editor.

    CONTENTS

         I. DOES 'CONSCIOUSNESS' EXIST?                          1

        II. A WORLD OF PURE EXPERIENCE                          39

       III. THE THING AND ITS RELATIONS                         92

        IV. HOW TWO MINDS CAN KNOW ONE THING                   123

         V. THE PLACE OF AFFECTIONAL FACTS IN A WORLD

            OF PURE EXPERIENCE                                 137

        VI. THE EXPERIENCE OF ACTIVITY                         155

       VII. THE ESSENCE OF HUMANISM                            190

      VIII. LA NOTION DE CONSCIENCE                            206

        IX. IS RADICAL EMPIRICISM SOLIPSISTIC?                 234

         X. MR. PITKIN'S REFUTATION OF 'RADICAL EMPIRICISM'    241

        XI. HUMANISM AND TRUTH ONCE MORE                       244

       XII. ABSOLUTISM AND EMPIRICISM                          266

            INDEX                                              281

    I

    DOES 'CONSCIOUSNESS' EXIST?[2]

    'Thoughts' and 'things' are names for two sorts of object, which common

    sense will always find contrasted and will always practically oppose to

    each other. Philosophy, reflecting on the contrast, has varied in the

    past in her explanations of it, and may be expected to vary in the

    future. At first, 'spirit and matter,' 'soul and body,' stood for a pair

    of equipollent substances quite on a par in weight and interest. But one

    day Kant undermined the soul and brought in the transcendental ego, and

    ever since then the bipolar relation has been very much off its balance.

    The transcendental ego seems nowadays in rationalist quarters to stand

    for everything, in empiricist quarters for almost nothing. In the hands

    of such writers as Schuppe, Rehmke, Natorp, Münsterberg--at any rate in

    his earlier writings, Schubert-Soldern and others, the spiritual

    principle attenuates itself to a thoroughly ghostly condition, being

    only a name for the fact that the 'content' of experience _is known_. It

    loses personal form and activity--these passing over to the content--and

    becomes a bare _Bewusstheit_ or _Bewusstsein überhaupt_, of which in its

    own right absolutely nothing can be said.

    I believe that 'consciousness,' when once it has evaporated to this

    estate of pure diaphaneity, is on the point of disappearing altogether.

    It is the name of a nonentity, and has no right to a place among first

    principles. Those who still cling to it are clinging to a mere echo, the

    faint rumor left behind by the disappearing 'soul' upon the air of

    philosophy. During the past year, I have read a number of articles whose

    authors seemed just on the point of abandoning the notion of

    consciousness,[3] and substituting for it that of an absolute experience

    not due to two factors. But they were not quite radical enough, not

    quite daring enough in their negations. For twenty years past I have

    mistrusted 'consciousness' as an entity; for seven or eight years past I

    have suggested its non-existence to my students, and tried to give them

    its pragmatic equivalent in realities of experience. It seems to me that

    the hour is ripe for it to be openly and universally discarded.

    To deny plumply that 'consciousness' exists seems so absurd on the face

    of it--for undeniably 'thoughts' do exist--that I fear some readers will

    follow me no farther. Let me then immediately explain that I mean only

    to deny that the word stands for an entity, but to insist most

    emphatically that it does stand for a function. There is, I mean, no

    aboriginal stuff or quality of being,[4] contrasted with that of which

    material objects are made, out of which our thoughts of them are made;

    but there is a function in experience which thoughts perform, and for

    the performance of which this quality of being is invoked. That

    function is _knowing_. 'Consciousness' is supposed necessary to explain

    the fact that things not only are, but get reported, are known. Whoever

    blots out the notion of consciousness from his list of first principles

    must still provide in some way for that function's being carried on.

    I

    My thesis is that if we start with the supposition that there is only

    one primal stuff or material in the world, a stuff of which everything

    is composed, and if we call that stuff 'pure experience,' then knowing

    can easily be explained as a particular sort of relation towards one

    another into which portions of pure experience may enter. The relation

    itself is a part of pure experience; one of its 'terms' becomes the

    subject or bearer of the knowledge, the knower,[5] the other becomes the

    object known. This will need much explanation before it can be

    understood. The best way to get it understood is to contrast

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1