Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

From $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

The Defense of the Faith
The Defense of the Faith
The Defense of the Faith
Ebook575 pages10 hours

The Defense of the Faith

Rating: 5 out of 5 stars

5/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

In this book Dr. Van Til indicates what the Reformed Faith is and how it should be defended and propagated. In so doing he at the same time replies in detail to his various critics. However, his main purpose is to show in broad outline the nature of the true Christian because truly Biblical, life and world view and how it alone enables men to find meaning in life.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateApr 23, 2020
ISBN9781839743429
The Defense of the Faith

Related to The Defense of the Faith

Related ebooks

Christianity For You

View More

Related articles

Related categories

Reviews for The Defense of the Faith

Rating: 5 out of 5 stars
5/5

1 rating0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    The Defense of the Faith - Cornelius van Til

    © Barakaldo Books 2020, all rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted by any means, electrical, mechanical or otherwise without the written permission of the copyright holder.

    Publisher’s Note

    Although in most cases we have retained the Author’s original spelling and grammar to authentically reproduce the work of the Author and the original intent of such material, some additional notes and clarifications have been added for the modern reader’s benefit.

    We have also made every effort to include all maps and illustrations of the original edition the limitations of formatting do not allow of including larger maps, we will upload as many of these maps as possible.

    THE DEFENSE OF THE FAITH

    BY

    CORNELIUS VAN TIL

    Table of Contents

    Contents

    Table of Contents 4

    DEDICATION 5

    PREFACE 6

    INTRODUCTION 7

    I—STANDARDS USED 7

    II—OBJECTIONS RAISED 7

    III—MEETING OF EXTREMES 9

    IV—CONCESSIONS MADE 11

    PART ONE—THE STRUCTURE OF MY THOUGHT 19

    CHAPTER I—CHRISTIAN THEOLOGY 19

    I—THE DOCTRINE OF GOD 20

    II—THE DOCTRINE OF MAN 23

    III—THE DOCTRINE OF CHRIST 25

    IV—THE DOCTRINE OF SALVATION 26

    V—THE DOCTRINE OF THE CHURCH 27

    VI—THE DOCTRINE OF THE LAST THINGS 28

    CHAPTER II—THE CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY OF REALITY 30

    I—ETERNAL UNITY AND PLURALITY 31

    II—TEMPORAL UNITY AND PLURALITY 32

    III—SIN AND ITS CURSE 33

    CHAPTER III—THE CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE 35

    I—GOD’S KNOWLEDGE OF HIMSELF 37

    II—GOD’S KNOWLEDGE OF THE WORLD 39

    III—MAN’S KNOWLEDGE OF GOD 40

    IV—MAN’S KNOWLEDGE OF THE WORLD UNIVERSE 42

    V—SIN AND ITS CURSE 45

    CHAPTER IV—THE CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY OF BEHAVIOR 49

    I—ETHICS AND THE CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE 49

    II—ETHICS AND THE CHRISTIAN PHILOSOPHY OF REALITY 56

    III—THE KINGDOM OF GOD AS MAN’S HIGHEST GOOD 57

    CHAPTER V—CHRISTIAN APOLOGETICS (POINT OF CONTACT) 60

    I—ROMAN CATHOLICISM 61

    II—EVANGELICALISM 67

    III—LESS CONSISTENT CALVINISM 68

    IV—THE REFORMED POSITION 75

    CHAPTER VI—CHRISTIAN APOLOGETICS (THE PROBLEM OF METHOD) 79

    I—REASONING BY PRESUPPOSITION 81

    II—SCRIPTURE 85

    III—BLOCKHOUSE METHODOLOGY 91

    CHAPTER VII—CHRISTIAN APOLOGETICS (AUTHORITY AND REASON) 97

    I—NON-CHRISTIAN VIEWS 97

    II—MODERN THEOLOGICAL VIEWS 100

    III—THE ROMAN CATHOLIC VIEW 102

    IV—THE ARMINIAN VIEW 108

    V—THE REFORMED VIEW 112

    CHAPTER VIII—COMMON GRACE AND SCHOLASTICISM 116

    I—ALL MEN UNAVOIDABLY KNOW GOD 118

    II—NATURAL THEOLOGY 120

    III—DIFFERENCES BETWEEN REFORMED THEOLOGIANS 124

    PART TWO—OBJECTIONS CONSIDERED 137

    CHAPTER IX—THEOLOGICAL PROBLEMS 137

    I—THE BIBLE 137

    II—THE DOCTRINE OF GOD 153

    CHAPTER X—CHRISTIAN METAPHYSICS 159

    I—DR. BUSWELL’S OBJECTIONS 161

    II—SECOND CAUSES 180

    III—CONTINGENCY 180

    CHAPTER XI—CHRISTIAN EPISTEMOLOGY 188

    I—THE PRESUPPOSITIONS OF REVELATION 188

    II—THE FIELDS OF REVELATION 189

    III—KUYPER ON WEIGHING AND MEASURING 192

    IV—KUYPER ON LOGIC 197

    V—SUPERNATURAL AND NATURAL REVELATION 200

    CHAPTER XII—CHRISTIAN APOLOGETICS 202

    I—THE PLACE OF REASON IN THEOLOGY 203

    II—DEFENDING THE FAITH 204

    III—THE BELIEVER MEETS THE UNBELIEVER 204

    IV—A CONSISTENT WITNESS 204

    V—THE AUTHORITY OF SCRIPTURE 204

    VI—PROOFS FOR THE EXISTENCE OF GOD 204

    CHAPTER XIII—AMSTERDAM AND OLD PRINCETON 204

    I—WARFIELD AND KUYPER 204

    II—WILLIAM BRENTON GREENE, JR. 204

    III—FLOYD E. HAMILTON 204

    IV—KUYPER 204

    V—BAVINCK 204

    CHAPTER XIV—COMMON GRACE AND EXISTENTIALISM 204

    I—THE FIRST POINT OF KALAMAZOO 204

    II—GOD’S ORIGINAL FAVOR TO MANKIND IN ADAM 204

    III—THE GENERAL OFFER OF THE GOSPEL 204

    IV—POINTS TWO AND THREE OF KALAMAZOO 204

    APPENDIX I 204

    APPENDIX II 204

    REQUEST FROM THE PUBLISHER 204

    DEDICATION

    TO MY WIFE

    PREFACE

    The present writer has from time to time prepared syllabi for his classes in Christian Apologetics. A number of outsiders have taken an interest in these syllabi. Some have used them for classroom teaching; others have subjected them to critical analysis.

    The present volume seeks to be of service to both types of readers. In the first place it seeks to set forth in positive fashion what seems to the writer to be the Biblical method of defending the Christian Faith. This necessitates making a comparison between the Romanist-Evangelical and the Reformed points of view concerning apologetics. In the second place this work deals with contemporary objections which have been made against the writer’s views of apologetics.

    While therefore this book is, in a sense, an answer to critics, that is not its primary purpose. Its primary purpose is to set forth, in broad outline, a method of defending Christianity which is consistent with the nature of Christianity.

    Acknowledgment is hereby made to publishers who kindly gave permission to quote from various books: To the Macmillan Company for permission to quote from Religious Realism, copyright, 1931, and from A. E. Taylor’s Does God Exist? copyright-reprint 1947; to the Cambridge University Press for permission to quote from James Jeans’ The Mysterious Universe; to William B. Eerdman’s Co. for permission to quote from James Daane’s A Theology of Grace and from Edward Carnell’s An Introduction to Christian Apologetics and from William Masselink’s General Revelation and Common Grace; to F. S. Crofts and Company for permission to quote from Martin, Clarke, Clark, Ruddick: A History of Philosophy; to Yale University Press for permission to quote from Cassirer’s Essay on Man, and Gilson’s God and Philosophy; to Charles Scribner’s Sons for permission to quote from Millikan’s Science and the New Civilization; and to the estate of Felix Cohen for permission to quote from Morris R. Cohen’s Reason and Nature, copyrighted, revised 1953.

    Special thanks are due to the Rev. Rousas John Rushdoony for carefully reading the entire manuscript; and to my former student, Robert G. DeMoss, Th.M., for painstaking help in the technical details of the manuscript, and for the Indexes.

    INTRODUCTION

    A brief survey of the criticism to which my views in theology and apologetics have been subjected will first be given to enable the reader to see the points at issue.

    I—STANDARDS USED

    The present writer and his critics are all adherents of orthodox Christianity. More than that, they have expressed allegiance to the Reformed Faith as set forth in its historic creeds. The historic Reformed Faith is distinguished from Roman Catholicism; within the Protestant fold it is distinguished from Arminianism; in the current theological situation it is distinguished from dialectical theology. The critics may therefore be expected to use the Scripture, taken to be the infallible rule of faith and practice, as their ultimate criterion and the historic Reformed Confessions as their secondary criterion in their evaluation of my thinking.

    In addition to the Scriptures and the Confessions, there are the writings of great Reformed theologians. There are first, the works of John Calvin, then the works of the three great men of recent Reformed theology, Abraham Kuyper, Herman Bavinck and Benjamin Breckinridge Warfield. All Reformed men hold these theologians in high esteem, and to differ from them is a serious matter. Other men of great stature, too, have written in exposition and defense of the Reformed Faith, but the writings of none have confessional standing. But to depart from them may, in a general sense, be conducive to a presumption that one has departed also from the creeds of the church. These men have the status of authorities in the field of Reformed thinking and represent the tradition of Reformed thought; they are the classical representatives of the Reformed Faith.

    Now the charges against me are that I have not only departed from the classical tradition of Reformed thinking, but that I have departed from the creeds and even from the idea of the Bible as the infallible standard of faith and practice.

    II—OBJECTIONS RAISED

    Before taking up these charges in detail, it is well to look at the specific and basic objections raised in each instance.

    a. Masselink

    Masselink’s main objection appears to be well expressed in the following words: Our great difficulty with Van Til’s philosophy of common grace is his premise or starting point, namely, the absolute ethical antithesis.{1} Masselink finds a basic disagreement between my views and those of Kuyper, Bavinck, Hepp and the Old Princeton Theology on general revelation and common grace. This difference goes back to a difference in epistemology. And this disagreement on epistemology is directly related to his major premise of the absolute ethical antithesis between God and the natural man.{2}

    b. The Calvin Forum Articles

    The Forum articles cannot readily be reduced to one main point. Yet one emphasis recurs repeatedly. It is to the effect that I have largely borrowed my epistemology from the idealist school of philosophy.

    1. Cecil De Boer. In asserting that the givens with which we must begin are not facts but ‘God-interpreted facts,’ the new apologetic seems to have taken over uncritically the idealist theory of knowledge and truth, a theory leading logically to a kind of pantheism.{3}

    2. Jesse De Boer. In common with the majority of post-Renaissance philosophers Van Til is exercised by the problem of knowledge. I do not wish to discuss such a general topic as the symptoms in Van Til of kinship with modern epistemologists. Instead, I want to point out specifically how he uses terms and arguments borrowed from speculative idealism, and thereby to underline my view that he is skating on thin ice; his purism is turning into a boomerang. For modern idealism is no friend of Christianity.{4} Therefore I give warning that he is in danger of substituting idealism for Christianity.{5}

    I suggest that Van Til’s apologetics, because it does not grow out of painstaking and complete mastery of great Christian texts, ancient, medieval, and modern, is twisted and victimized by the categories and techniques of the idealists whose works he read in his student days.{6}

    3. Orlebeke. Less outspoken than the others, Orlebeke is also concerned to discover how my thought may be distinguished from that of idealism. He quotes the following words of mine: "For Christianity, God’s thoughts are constitutive. By God’s thoughts do the facts of the universe come into existence. Then he asks: Are we to understand that the knowledge of God cannot be distinguished from the objects of that knowledge? If it is possible to say that God’s thought is constitutive of facts, is it not also necessary to say that the facts are constitutive of God’s knowledge, and therefore of God? In order to maintain a sharp distinction between God and his creation it would seem to be necessary to make a sharp distinction between the being of created reality, and God’s knowledge of it."{7}

    4. Van Halsema. Mr. Van Halsema speaks of my Berkeleian notion of God. He reports further that over against the Kantian creativity theory of thought I want to place the creativity theory of divine thought. He thereupon exclaims: By what notion of Christianity are such idealist aberrations included in a ‘Christian apologetic’?{8}

    c. Daane

    Daane’s basic criticism may be summed up in the following words:

    One half of my thesis is that Van Til has not delivered common-grace theology from the Hegelian rationalism underlying the theology of Hoeksema, nor from the non-Christian philosophical remnants which Van Til thinks to discover in the common grace position of all the leading theological thinkers of the Reformed tradition. On the contrary he has enmeshed the doctrine of common grace more deeply in philosophical speculation than it has ever been before. Instead of presenting a purged basis for a Christian philosophy of history and a purified common grace theology he has proffered a compound of Hegelian rationalism and modern existentialism in which the rational dialecticism of Hegel is not only retained but enlarged so as to include within itself an existential dialecticism.{9}

    III—MEETING OF EXTREMES

    The reader may be struck by two things. First, there is the extreme seriousness of these charges. I am accused of borrowing my epistemology from idealism and presenting a compound of Hegelian rationalism and modern existentialism. Idealism and existentialism do not take the Scriptures to be the Word of God; they do not believe in the God of the Bible. They do not believe in the creation of this world and of man by God. They do not believe in God’s providential control over the world. They do not believe Jesus Christ to have been the Son of God and Son of man. They do not believe in atonement, nor in the return of Christ on the clouds of heaven to judge the quick and the dead. Yet I am said to have borrowed my epistemology from such enemies of the Christian Faith, and Daane asserts that the structure of the argument in Common Grace is not taken from Scripture but from modern existentialism. Such charges are serious indeed.

    On the other hand Masselink’s main charge is that I hold to an absolute ethical antithesis, and this implies that I have no appreciation at all either of the knowledge or of the work of unbelievers. Van Til contends that the reaction of unbelievers to common grace is only negative, and, therefore, they have nothing in common epistemologically with the believers.{10} This too is a serious charge, though not nearly so serious a one as that pertaining to idealism and existentialism.

    Note how completely opposed to one another these charges appear to be. On the one hand the essential structure of my thought is said to be that of total unbelief. On the other hand I am said to classify Aristotle with the devil. For I am said to believe in the absolute antithesis, and the idea of the absolute antithesis means that man is as bad as he can be, for the dictionary meaning of the word absolute is that there are no qualifications.

    But I cannot take any comfort in the mutually exclusive nature of these charges, for Masselink agrees with my other critics that I tend to think in terms of non-Christian philosophy. And some of the other critics agree with Masselink when he charges me with having an absolutist theology.

    As already noted, according to Masselink I start my thinking from the absolute ethical antithesis. And this absolute ethical antithesis, he says, logically involves an absolute logical and aesthetic antithesis. But, in the other direction, I am said with Schilder to deny the general external and internal testimony of the Holy Spirit. And this denial involves a twofold error, the denial of Total Depravity and the denial of human responsibility.{11} With the reconstructionists, therefore there exists great confusion regarding the antithesis. On the one hand they all but deny it, and on the other hand they make it absolute. In saying that natural man, apart from general revelation and common grace, has knowledge of God and morality because of the remaining elements of the original image, they practically wipe out this antithesis.{12} With Schilder I am said to make much of the assertion that the origin of all knowledge is in the natural man himself.{13} In historic Reformed theology the point of contact for missions has always been found in general revelation—or in the twofold witness of the Holy Spirit by which natural man has God consciousness and moral consciousness. But Van Til finds the point of contact in man himself.{14} So Masselink agrees with the other critics in charging me with working in terms of non-Christian concepts. The fundamental weakness in the whole philosophic system of this ‘New Movement’ according to my judgment must be precisely attributed to the fact that these conclusions have been arrived at by means of a process of involved philosophic reasoning instead of Scriptural exposition.{15}

    On the other hand, some of the other critics agree with Masselink when he says that I hold to an absolutist position. Cecil De Boer presents my position as teaching that in philosophy the Christian and the non-Christian cannot even approximate identical meanings whenever they use identical terms.{16} "Anyway, it is evidently useless to argue that because a man does not accept the Christian religion he cannot really (i.e. ultimately, metaphysically) distinguish an egg from a cucumber.{17} Asks Jesse De Boer, Does the Bible teach that the radical difference between regenerate and unregenerate people is such that they do not share the same algebra or numismatics, or meteorology?{18} He speaks of my oft-stated and basic thesis that the unregenerate man can know no facts at all.{19} Again he says: Finally, is it not entirely improper for Van Til, the Reformed purist who really wants to avoid sharing common insights with non-Christians, to defend his interpretation of what Christianity implies by an appeal to idealist logic? The statement by which one justifies or defends another statement must be better known than the latter statement; so Van Til is more sure of idealist logic than he is of Christian theism.{20} Van Halsema says that in contradistinction from Kuyper and even Dooyeweerd I hold that the laws of thinking are not held in common by Christian and non-Christian."{21}

    On the one hand, I am said to be more sure of idealist logic than of Christianity, and on the other hand I am said to hold that Christians and non-Christians do not even think according to the same laws of thought!

    IV—CONCESSIONS MADE

    The sharpness of this view of my apologetics is somewhat tempered by certain concessions made by the critics.

    a. Masselink

    Masselink appears to make certain concessions to my absolutism. He says: How can there be any affinity between the unregenerate reason and the depths of the Christian religion which makes the understanding possible?{22} Van Til correctly asserts that there is an absolute difference between the pantheistic Greek conception of deity and the Scriptural view. Van Til also says that when the Greek poets think of ‘in Him we live and move and have our being’; they interpret this in pantheistic fashion, whereas Paul sees in this God’s immanence in the Biblical way. With all of this, no Reformed theologian can find any disagreement.{23}

    Then too, Masselink grants that in spite of my absolutism I want to maintain the 1924 Three Points on Common Grace of the Synod of the Christian Reformed Church. He quotes Ridderbos as saying: Van Til excellently maintains Common Grace as a favorable disposition of God.{24}

    Ridderbos also asserts that I have in his opinion the right view of the third point with respect to civil righteousness.{25} Elsewhere he says: That Van Til believes the Three Points’ is not questioned by us for a moment, but our problem is...how can all this be squared with his major premise?{26} And when Ridderbos says that in spite of my maintaining the first and third points he does not see how I can escape intellectual anabaptism, Masselink thinks this judgment may be too sharp."{27}

    Masselink himself, therefore, believes that in some sense the antithesis between the Christian and the non-Christian is absolute. The depravity of the natural man, in principle, is even absolute.{28} The basic principles for the correct science of nature are only found in the Scripture.{29} And when he stresses the idea that because of common grace there is the retention of some right knowledge of God with the natural man, and of fragments of morality, he refers this knowledge and morality to an outside source, namely, to God. But without common grace, the knowledge of God would be absolutely false.{30}

    b. Cecil De Boer

    When Cecil De Boer criticizes my absolutism by suggesting that it requires men to accept the Bible in order to solve problems in geometry, he appends the following note. In fairness to Professor Van Til of Westminster Seminary it should be stated that he seems recently to have repudiated some of his earlier and more extreme assertions relative to the present issue. And in his syllabi one occasionally finds such statements as that created beings have a nature and an activity of their own, and that unbelievers have knowledge which is ‘true as far as it goes.’ Nevertheless, such statements are so obviously out of character with the general tenor of his apologetic that one is justified in saying that they amount to little more than lip service to what Dr. Kuyper and others have called common grace.{31} Thus he grants that in rarer moments I have some measure of appreciation for the truth that unbelievers possess. He adds that my absolutism was more absolutistic in earlier days than it is now.

    On the other hand Cecil De Boer, like Masselink, also has an absolutism of his own. The antithesis between the Christian way of life and non-Christian ways can hardly be exaggerated, but that does not mean that it cannot be made to look a bit silly by Christians with a pet theory to defend. No Christian denies that the unbeliever in rejecting God’s self-revelation is out of touch with reality. But there are, after all, degrees of being out of touch, and the unbeliever is not as a rule so out of touch as to cease being a man made in the image of God. And as bearer of God’s image he would seem to have considerable in common with the believer. To him the idea of God as the creator and sustainer of the universe is at least not meaningless, since otherwise he could hardly deny it.{32}

    c. Jesse De Boer

    Jesse De Boer also makes concessions. In fact he warns his readers at the outset in the following words: Nor do I wish to encourage anyone who inclines to suppose that there is no agreement between Van Til and myself on many basic matters. That would be a pure mistake. Though some readers are likely to make that mistake, I choose not to use their time, by presenting summaries of whole areas of Van Til’s thought, to render that mistake less likely.{33} There are therefore whole areas of my thought with which he agrees in spite of the fact that In talking as if God is part’ of a ‘system of truth’ Van Til is talking himself out of classic Christian modes of thought.{34}

    d. Orlebeke

    Orlebeke deals particularly with my view of facts. He speaks of the idealist view in which "the being of a fact is identical with the being-known of a fact." He thinks there is evidence for thinking that I have been influenced by this idealist interdependence of being and knowledge. Even so Orlebeke says that I have never defended the thesis that the knowledge of a fact and the being of the fact are identical and that I sometimes presuppose its falsity.{35} When Orlebeke deals with the question of common ground between believer and unbeliever he quotes a passage of mine referred to by Masselink and others in order to show how radically I have departed from the views of Kuyper. The passage reads as follows:

    Weighing and measuring and formal reasoning are but aspects of one unified act of interpretation. It is either the would-be autonomous man, who weighs and measures what he thinks of as brute or bare facts by the help of what he thinks of as abstract impersonal principles, or it is the believer, knowing himself to be a creature of God, who weighs and measures what he thinks of as God-created facts and by what he thinks of as God-created laws. Looking at the matter thus allows for a larger common territory than Kuyper allows for, but this larger territory is common with a qualification...it allows us to do full justice to the antithesis, which Kuyper has taught us to stress. It keeps us from falling into a sort of natural theology, patterned after Thomas Aquinas, that Kuyper has taught us to reject.{36}

    And he adds, I have quoted this passage at length to show the importance which Professor Van Til attaches to the question of ‘common ground.’ Because Kuyper believed in such a thing, he is charged with tendencies toward Thomistic natural theology.{37} But he also adds: There are times when Professor Van Til seems to admit this point. He says, for example, ‘We are well aware of the fact that non-Christians have a great deal of knowledge about this world which is true as far as it goes. That is, there is a sense in which we can and must allow for the value of knowledge of non-Christians. This has always been a difficult point.’{38} Orlebeke therefore allows that while Kuyper believes in common ground I also believe in it. He does not here stop to note the exact criticism I make of Kuyper. Orlebeke’s point is that Kuyper believes in a common territory without qualification while I believe in a common territory with qualification.

    On the following page, however, Orlebeke does go on to deal with the notion of commonness with qualification. He seeks to resolve the ambiguity which exists in my writing when on the one hand I admit the value of the knowledge of unbelievers and on the other hand maintain that "no sinner can interpret reality aright. He speaks, even as I have, of the knowledge that both believers and unbelievers may have, of such a simple object as a flower. If a human being is to ‘know’ this flower with essential accuracy, he must know it as a creation of God, revelatory of his wisdom, power, and glory. From this ultimate point of view the ‘natural man’ knows nothing truly, and from this same ultimate point of view the Christian knows everything truly. But it does not follow from the foregoing that every bit of knowledge held by the unbeliever is for that reason false, except from the ‘ultimate point of view.’ That is to say, concerning the spatial relation of flower A to B alone, the unbeliever can have true knowledge as far as it goes, and the believer can be wrong about that same relation as far as that relation is concerned. Such would be the case if the Christian should, perchance, misjudge the distance between A and B."{39}

    Here Orlebeke quotes another passage of mine as follows:

    Something similar to this should be our attitude toward science. We gladly recognize the detail work of many scientists as being highly valuable. We gladly recognize the fact that science has brought to light many details. But we cannot use modern scientists and their method as the architects of our structure of Christian interpretation....We offer the God and Christ of the Bible as the concrete universal in relation to which all facts have meaning.{40}

    He concludes this section by saying:

    This would seem to confirm my thesis. It is hard to see how the details furnished by non-Christians would be themselves altered in a Christian system of interpretation, unless one denies the value of these details. In terms of the analogy, the Israelites did not have to recut the timbers fashioned by the Phoenicians in order to fit them into the temple.{41}

    There is here then a considerable measure of agreement admitted. The remaining difference will be taken up later. Orlebeke has perhaps helped us to see the problem about which all are concerned, more closely.

    In the conclusion of his article Orlebeke says concerning apologetics:

    The view which I have sketched, an avowed defense of Kuyper’s conception of common ground, in no way implies the possibility of a natural theology. Unless there be revelation, man can know nothing about God. But there is revelation. General revelation, as Calvin says, is objectively perspicuous and sufficient to convince any right-minded man that God, the Creator and Ruler of the universe, exists. The beauty of the flowers in the field, for example, would be impossible if God did not exist.

    For the Christian this is obviously true. Suppose, now, that he attempts to convince his unbelieving friend that it is true. He must presuppose that the latter knows that the flowers are there, and that they are beautiful. This is common ground. He may then seek to prove that there must be some principle of Absolute Beauty which is necessary in order to explain this example of Beauty. To this his friend may or may not assent (Plato, e.g., would). Suppose he does, however. Then this second principle becomes common ground. Thus the discussion may proceed to a divine Being, then to the God of Christianity.

    Two things may be observed about this discussion. A) The Christian, at every point, appeals to revealed facts as his evidence. B) Unless the saving Grace of God intervenes in the mind of the unbeliever, he will not be genuinely convinced of the final conclusion.

    Professor Van Til has a slightly different approach. He says that ...the only conclusive argument for Christianity is precisely the fact that only upon the presupposition of the truth of its teaching does logic or predication in general touch reality at all. It is true that this is a good argument, but it is not evident that it is the only, or even the best, argument. If it is appropriate to claim the truth of Christianity by pointing to the fact of meaningful predication, is it not even more appropriate to claim that it is true by arguing the necessity of a Creator to explain the fact of contingent being?

    Professor Van Til makes much of the point that the Christian must not appeal to brute facts in apology for his faith. This is entirely true. It does not, however, imply that we cannot appeal to facts or to reality in apology for the faith. Indeed, to what else can one appeal?

    Perhaps the difficulty here stems from a failure to distinguish between the unbeliever’s knowledge of facts and the theories which he advances to explain that knowledge. The latter, no doubt, can be shown to be inadequate in their bowing to brute facts. Fortunately, however, what men do is often better than what they say they do. We must capitalize on this inconsistency.{42}

    e. Van Halsema

    As noted previously Van Halsema maintains that I am committed to the idea that Christians and non-Christians differ not only on the philosophy of logic but that they think according to different laws of thought. He also says that I deny any community of facthood between believers and unbelievers. His whole criticism is summed up as follows:

    Apparently then Professor Van Til’s view, critically considered, is that the laws of logic are for the Christian and for the non-Christian just as they differently conceive them to be. With this phenomenalistic stroke Van Til denies a common logic (or, common laws of thought); and with community of facthood in any sense also denied, apologetic debate becomes an obvious impossibility. Even so, Van Halsema also makes a concession when he adds; "It is the question not so much whether Professor Van Til’s intentions are good or certain of his formulations correct, as whether he is consistent with himself. For although the discussed defects and excesses are a conspicuous part of his works, rather formidable documentation could be mustered, from other passages in them, which would support a contrary evaluation. But unless these conflicting evaluations can be exhibited to be resolvable, any evidence ranged for either one is but evidence that there is an unfortunate contradiction in Van Til’s writings—a contradiction that leaves our first and last exclamations the same: Cur spargit voces in vulgum ambiguas"?{43}

    There is therefore, according to Van Halsema, the possibility of a rather formidable documentation for a different evaluation than he has given of my teaching. Of course, even if such an evaluation were presented, if the evidence he has produced of my idealistic penchant and of my tendency to think that one’s interpretation of a fact is the fact remains, then I might be shown to be very self-contradictory in my view. But at least in that case I would not be fairly presented as being idealistic and phenomenalistic in my thought.

    f. Daane

    Daane deals exclusively with my little book on Common Grace. His point is not that my position would logically lead to Hegelianism, rationalism and existentialism, but rather that the whole structure of my thought is controlled by these modern forms of non-Christian thought.

    Therefore the point is not that Van Til’s common grace thought comes near to an irrational existentialism. On the contrary, it is because Van Til’s thought is grounded in, and expressive of, an existential dialectic that he can assert that in the post-Fall as in the pre-Fail world mankind as a generality has things in common by virtue of its non-existence (because they do not yet exist) and that in the degree that the generality’s non-existence is progressively overcome by the forward movement of the process of coming into existence commonality ceases and common grace is withdrawn.{44}

    In particular he argues that for me time does not mean ordinary historical time. Van Til’s thought reveals that characteristic disregard for chronological time which appears in all absolutistic systems of thought.{45} Van Til speaks of an ‘earlier stage of history.’ This is confusing for what he really means is an earlier stage of existence.{46} When I speak of the general offer of salvation it means, says Daane, the offer is meaningful for those who are still in the earlier limbo of non-existence.{47} Van Til’s wholly unbiblical conception of grace stems from, and is the result of, a conception of grace which holds that grace is something which is by nature earlier grace—earlier than real existence.{48}

    My position therefore involves that I must reduce the reality of Adam to a mere generality of mankind. But now at this point he surrenders Adam’s representative function along with Adam’s individual reality.{49} If Van Til admitted that Adam falls into the category of men as men, he would be compelled to admit that the gospel offer was already partly meaningless at the time it was first offered.{50} Van Til’s common grace theology has no room for Adam. A careful search ends in the cry: Adam, where art thou?{51}

    As I am forced by my existential dialectic to exclude the factual reality of Adam{52} so he says that, Van Til does not, in fact cannot, take into account either the Moment of Christ’s first coming or the Moment of grace created by gospel proclamation.{53} Finally, it is this existential version of the moment of becoming that prevents Van Til from giving any significance to the Moment of Jesus Christ’s first coming.—Nor is there room for the eschatological moment created by gospel preaching. Nor is there room in his thought for the moment of regeneration.{54} All of this evaporation of the facts of historic Christianity is due to the fact that, Van Til’s ethical moment of decision is deterministically determined by the unbreakable and irreversible correlation between nonexistence and existence.{55}

    In view of this basic contention of Daane’s that I have delivered myself even less than some modern dialectical theologians from the secular philosophic tradition,{56} it is a considerable concession for him to make when he says that he does not doubt my belief in Adam’s real historical existence. The question indeed is not whether Van Til believes in the reality of Adam. I do not doubt that he does.{57} There is no doubt that Van Til does not wish to deny the reality of Adam, and passages could be indicated showing that he believes in Adam’s reality. But there is also no doubt about the fact that his common grace theology cannot recognize the reality of Adam. The same is true of Van Til and the doctrine of creation.{58}

    This may suffice to present to the reader a general picture of the criticism with which we are concerned. I propose to deal with this criticism in the following manner. In the first part I shall deal with the general structure of my thought. I shall attempt to show that it is the exact opposite of what my critics think it to be, and that it is controlled by the idea of the Bible as the infallible Word of God and by the system of doctrine contained in the Bible.

    This section will be largely composed of quoted material from my writings. The reader will thus be able to judge for himself of the structure of my thought. He will find it to be informed by simple, generic Calvinism rather than by idealism, Hegelian rationalism, existentialism and/or phenomenalism.

    In each instance I shall attempt to demonstrate that in setting the Christian view of life over against ancient and especially modern forms of non-Christian thought no absolutism of the sort the critics speak of is in view. To be sure, the Christian view of life is true and all other views are false; that is to say, the Bible presents a view of God, of man, and of Christ which is exclusive of all other views. The natural man serves and worships the creature more than the Creator. The Christian has by the grace of God learned to serve the Creator more than the creature. And this fact expresses itself in whatever he does. But even those who worship and serve the creature more than the Creator are not finished products in this world. They can and therefore do make their positive contribution to the realization of the cultural mandate given to Adam, the first man of history, the representative of all succeeding generations.

    In all this I think I am only presenting generic or historic Calvinism. If I have proposed variations, they are certainly not of basic import. Even the apologetic methodology I have proposed rests upon Calvin and upon the classical Reformed theologians. To the extent that these differ among one another I have been compelled to choose between them. Even so these differences have not been of such a basic nature that I could not appeal to a common view held by both parties. I have tried to use elements both of Kuyper’s and of Warfield’s thinking. If the construction that has resulted differs somewhat from both and is in that sense original, its soundness may be judged on its merits.

    In the second part I shall deal directly with some of the main points of criticism on my point of view.

    PART ONE—THE STRUCTURE OF MY THOUGHT

    CHAPTER I—CHRISTIAN THEOLOGY

    Detailed replies to the detailed criticisms made of my views by the critics mentioned would not be very useful unless seen in the light of the general structure of my thought. Then too, Daane has specifically dealt with this general structure so far as he found it expressed in Common Grace. It would be quite impossible to deal with his criticism otherwise than by stating what I myself consider the structure of my thought to have been, and to be.

    Now the basic structure of my thought is very simple. I have never been called upon to work out any form of systematic theology. My business is to teach Apologetics. I therefore presuppose the Reformed system of doctrine. I try to show my students that it is this system of doctrine that men need. Since most students have not had much systematic theology when they first come to my classes, I give them a brief survey of it. Then as they take courses in systematic theology with my colleague, Professor John Murray, they come to me again and look at the apologetic problem afresh.

    An examination of my syllabus on Apologetics shows that the first chapter deals with the question what we are to believe and defend. We must defend Christian-theism as a unit.

    It is impossible and useless to seek to defend Christianity as an historical religion by a discussion of facts only. We say that Christ arose from the grave. We say further that this resurrection proves his divinity. This is the nerve of the historical argument for Christianity. Yet a pragmatist philosopher will refuse to follow this line of reasoning. Granted he allows that Christ actually arose from the grave, he will say that this proves nothing more than that something very unusual took place in the case of that man Jesus. The pragmatists philosophy is that everything in this universe is unrelated and that such a fact as the resurrection of Jesus, granted it were a fact, would have no significance for us who live two thousand years after him. It is apparent from this that if we would really defend Christianity as an historical religion we must at the same time defend the theism upon which Christianity is based and this involves us in philosophical discussion.{59}

    But to engage in philosophical discussion does not mean that we begin without Scripture. We do not first defend theism philosophically by an appeal to reason and experience in order, after that, to turn to Scripture for our knowledge and defense of Christianity. We get our theism as well as our Christianity from the Bible.

    The Bible is thought of as authoritative on everything of which it speaks. And it speaks of everything. We do not mean that it speaks of football games, of atoms, etc., directly, but we do mean that it speaks of everything either directly or indirectly. It tells us not only of the Christ and his work but it also tells us who God is and whence the universe has come. It gives us a philosophy of history as well as history. Moreover, the information on these subjects is woven into an inextricable whole. It is only if you reject the Bible as the word of God that you can separate its so-called religious and moral instruction from what it says, e.g., about the physical universe.{60}

    It is therefore the system of truth as contained in Scripture which we must present to the world. The various theological disciplines contribute to the setting forth of this system. It is the business of dogmatic or systematic theology to set forth this system under several main headings. So we take the headings of systematic theology as we find them worked out, for instance, in such manuals as Professor Louis Berkhof has written. In them we find discussions on (a) the doctrine of God, (b) the doctrine of man, (c) the doctrine of Christ, (d) the doctrine of the church, (e) the doctrine of salvation, and (f) the doctrine of the last things.

    In each case the Reformed position is shown to be that which Scripture teaches. The Romanist, the Arminian and other views are shown not to be fully Biblical. So before turning to the question of the defense of the Reformed Faith, we must know, in general, what it is.

    I—THE DOCTRINE OF GOD

    Naturally in the system of theology and in apologetics the doctrine of God is of fundamental importance. We must first ask what kind of a God Christianity believes in before we can really ask with intelligence whether such a God exists. The what precedes the that; the connotation precedes the denotation; at least the latter cannot be discussed intelligently without at once considering the former.

    What do we mean when we use the word God? Systematics answers this question in its discussion of the attributes or properties of God. These attributes are divided into incommunicable and communicable. Under the incommunicable attributes we have:

    First, independence or aseity of God. By this is meant that God is in no sense correlative to or dependent upon anything beside his own being. God is the source of his own being, or rather the term source cannot be applied to God. God is absolute. He is sufficient unto himself.

    Secondly, we speak of the immutability of God. Naturally God does not and cannot change since there is nothing besides his own eternal Being on which he depends (Mal. 3:6; James 1:7).

    Thirdly, we speak of the infinity of God. In relation to the question of time we speak of the eternity of God while with respect to space we speak of the omnipresence of God. By the term eternity we mean that there is no beginning or end or succession of moments in Gods being or consciousness (Ps. 90:2; 2 Pet. 3:8). This conception of eternity is of particular importance in Apologetics because it involves the whole question of the meaning of the temporal universe: it involves a definite philosophy of history. By the term omnipresence we mean that God is neither included in space nor absent from it. God is above all space and yet present in every part of it (1 Kings 8:27; Acts 17:27).

    Fourthly, we speak of the unity of God. We distinguish between the unity of singularity (singularitatis) and the unity of simplicity (simplicitatis). The unity of singularity has reference to numerical oneness. There is and can be only one God. The unity of simplicity signifies that God is in no sense composed of parts or aspects that existed prior to himself (Jer. 10:10; I John 1:5).

    The attributes of God are not to be thought of otherwise than as aspects of the one simple original being; the whole is identical with the parts. On the other hand the attributes of God are not characteristics that God has developed gradually; they are fundamental to his being; the parts together form the whole. Of the whole matter we may say that the unity and the diversity in God are equally basic and mutually dependent upon one another. The importance of this doctrine for Apologetics may be seen from the fact that the whole problem of philosophy may be summed up in the question of the relation of unity to diversity; the so-called problem of the one and the many receives a definite answer from the doctrine of the simplicity of God.

    Man cannot partake of these incommunicable attributes of God. Man cannot in any sense be the source of his own being; man cannot in any sense be immutable or eternal or omnipresent or simple. These attributes therefore emphasize the transcendence of God. Under the communicable attributes we have:

    Spirituality. God is a Spirit (John 4:24).

    Invisibility.

    Omniscience. God knows his own being to its very depths in one eternal act of knowledge. There are no hidden depths in the being of God that he has not explored. God’s knowledge of himself may best be said to be analytical. This does not mean that God must by a slow process analyze himself but it emphasizes that which needs most emphasis, namely, that God does not need to look beyond himself for additions to his knowledge.

    Then what about God’s knowledge of the facts of the created world, of the things that exist besides himself? As human beings we must know or interpret the facts after we look at the facts, after they are there and perhaps after they have operated for some time. In the case of God, on the other hand, God’s knowledge of the facts comes first. God knows, or interprets the facts before they are facts. It is God’s plan or his comprehensive interpretation of the facts that makes the facts what they are (P. 6).

    The incommunicable attributes of God stress his transcendence and the communicable attributes stress his immanence. The two imply one another. A Christian notion of transcendence and a Christian notion of immanence go together.

    It is not a sufficient description of Christian theism when we say that as Christians we believe in both the transcendence and the immanence of God while pantheistic systems believe only in the immanence of God and deistic

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1