Humanitarian intervention in the long nineteenth century: Setting the precedent
By Alexis Heraclides and Ada Dialla
()
About this ebook
The book begins by tracing the genealogy of the idea of humanitarian intervention to the Renaissance, evaluating the Eurocentric gaze of the civilisation-barbarity dichotomy, and elucidates the international legal arguments of both advocates and opponents of intervention, as well as the views of major political theorists. It then goes on to examine four cases as humanitarian interventions: the Greek War of Independence (1821–31), the Lebanon and Syria (1860–61), the Bulgarian atrocities (1876–78), and the U.S. intervention in Cuba (1895–98).
Humanitarian intervention in the long nineteenth century will be of benefit to scholars and students of international relations, international history, international law and international political theory.
Alexis Heraclides
Alexis Heraclides is Professor of International Relations and Conflict Resolution at the Department of Political Science and History of the Panteion University of Social and Political Sciences, Athens
Related to Humanitarian intervention in the long nineteenth century
Related ebooks
The Origins of Major War Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Protest Beyond Borders: Contentious Politics in Europe since 1945 Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsP. C. Chang and the Universal Declaration of Human Rights Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAccordance with international law of the unilateral declaration of independence in respect of Kosovo Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsWars of Law: Unintended Consequences in the Regulation of Armed Conflict Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAmbassadors of Realpolitik: Sweden, the CSCE and the Cold War Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHow States Pay for Wars Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBanished: Common Law and the Rhetoric of Social Exclusion in Early New England Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsArms of Little Value: The Challenge of Insurgency and Global Instability in the Twenty-First Century Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMigration in a Globalizing World: Perspectives from Ghana Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPower Systems: Conversations on Global Democratic Uprisings and the New Challenges to U.S. Empire Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSyria Under Fire: a bloodied revolution Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFollowing the Leader: International Order, Alliance Strategies, and Emulation Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsZones of Rebellion: Kurdish Insurgents and the Turkish State Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAmerican Force: Dangers, Delusions, and Dilemmas in National Security Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMonitoring Democracy: When International Election Observation Works, and Why It Often Fails Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Purpose of Intervention: Changing Beliefs about the Use of Force Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Decisionist Imagination: Sovereignty, Social Science and Democracy in the 20th Century Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Syrian Rebellion Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Eden-Eisenhower Correspondence, 1955-1957 Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsInternational Justice and Impunity: The Case of the United States Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPainful Choices: A Theory of Foreign Policy Change Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIsolate or Engage: Adversarial States, US Foreign Policy, and Public Diplomacy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsRethinking the Korean War: A New Diplomatic and Strategic History Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGod, Guns and Israel Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOn the Path to Genocide: Armenia and Rwanda Reexamined Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAn Attorney's Guide to Secession Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Sea and International Relations Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsChechnya: From Nationalism to Jihad Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Social Science For You
Come As You Are: Revised and Updated: The Surprising New Science That Will Transform Your Sex Life Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Fourth Turning Is Here: What the Seasons of History Tell Us about How and When This Crisis Will End Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5All About Love: New Visions Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Three Women Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A People's History of the United States Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Witty Banter: Be Clever, Quick, & Magnetic Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5On Tyranny: Twenty Lessons from the Twentieth Century Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Men Explain Things to Me Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Dumbing Us Down - 25th Anniversary Edition: The Hidden Curriculum of Compulsory Schooling Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5My Secret Garden: Women's Sexual Fantasies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Close Encounters with Addiction Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Like Switch: An Ex-FBI Agent's Guide to Influencing, Attracting, and Winning People Over Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Weapons of Mass Instruction: A Schoolteacher's Journey Through the Dark World of Compulsory Schooling Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5You're Not Listening: What You're Missing and Why It Matters Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Strange Death of Europe: Immigration, Identity, Islam Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Unhumans: The Secret History of Communist Revolutions (and How to Crush Them) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Verbal Judo, Second Edition: The Gentle Art of Persuasion Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Fervent: A Woman's Battle Plan to Serious, Specific, and Strategic Prayer Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Barracoon: The Story of the Last "Black Cargo" Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Reviews for Humanitarian intervention in the long nineteenth century
0 ratings0 reviews
Book preview
Humanitarian intervention in the long nineteenth century - Alexis Heraclides
Preface and acknowledgements
The nineteenth-century precedent of humanitarian intervention was little known until recently. Most international relations and international law scholars as well as diplomats are unaware that humanitarian intervention has a longer history and is not simply a post-Cold War phenomenon. In the nineteenth century it was invoked and recognized by European states, public opinion and international jurists, from the three-power intervention in the Greek War of Independence (1821–32) until the more controversial US intervention in Cuba in 1898, but also with regard to other instances short of the use of armed force in cases of humanitarian plight from Peru to the Congo and from Naples to Russia.
But even among the few who are aware of the nineteenth-century experience there has been a reluctance to include it as a precedent, in view of the different circumstances and standards reigning prior to 1918, not least the embarrassing ‘civilized–barbarians’ dichotomy. Only a handful of international lawyers have used the nineteenth-century ‘doctrine’ of humanitarian intervention to butttress contemporary thinking on the idea.¹
In recent years the claim that the nineteenth century was a heyday of humanitarian intervention has been made more convincing with Gary Bass’s Freedom’s Battle: The Origins of Humanitarian Intervention (2009). Lesser known is a lengthy paper by Tonny Brems Knudsen given at a conference in 2009.² These two works, as well as a lecture by André Mandelstam³ in the inter-war period and a chapter by Martha Finnemore⁴ in the mid-1990s, convinced us that a book on our part was in order.
The idea for this book matured following a workshop on humanitarian intervention at the University of Malmö in March 2010, where a paper on humanitarian intervention in the nineteenth century by one of the authors of this volume was well received.⁵ By the time we had secured a contract with Manchester University Press, a second book appeared, edited by Brendan Simms and D. J. B. Trim, Humanitarian Intervention: A History (2011) and when writing our book, a third book was published, Davide Rodogno’s Against Massacre: Humanitarian Intervention in the Ottoman Empire, 1815–1914. The Emergence of a European Concept and International Practice (2012). Ours is the fourth book in English. Why yet another volume on the history of humanitarian intervention?
The book by Bass, well researched and written in an engaging manner to reach a wide audience, brings to life three cases of intervention in the nineteenth century, but does not deal with international law and the views of international jurists in those days (which is basic, for humanitarian intervention evolved as a concept or doctrine of international law), or with political theory and philosophy (for instance making only passing mention of J. S. Mill).
The Simms and Trim edited volume is an important scholarly book but is not focused on the nineteenth century: it begins with the sixteenth century and ends with interventions in the 1990s. ‘Humanitarian intervention’ is understood very broadly to include humanitarianism, and not as understood in the study of international law and international relations, namely as armed intervention to end suffering in humanitarian plight or protracted internal wars. Moreover, that book is not concerned with international law and the views of international lawyers in the nineteenth century. Having said this, we have benefited from several excellent chapters in the book, notably those by Trim on the Renaissance roots of humanitarian intervention, Rodogno on the Lebanon/Syria case, Schulz on the 1875–78 Balkan crisis and Sewell on the 1898 US intervention in Cuba.
Rodogno’s book is crisp and persuasive as regards its subject matter, humanitarian intervention in the Ottoman Empire and the Orientalist gaze of the Europeans, and its overall thrust is closer to what we had in mind when we started writing our book, though ours is broader; we cover not only the Ottoman Empire but also include specific chapters on political theory and the thinking behind international law.
This book is an attempt at a comprehensive presentation of humanitarian intervention in theory and practice. It starts with a brief presentation of the present situation and debate and then moves centuries back in time, with the genesis of the idea in the Renaissance followed by the nineteenth-century civilization–barbarity dichotomy, with its concomitant Eurocentric/Orientalist gaze towards the Ottomans. We continue with the pivotal international law dimension, examining the arguments of advocates and opponents of humanitarian intervention from the 1830s until the 1930s, concluding the first part of the book with international political theory and intervention. In the second part, four case studies are examined in detail in five chapters: the Greek case (1821–32), the Lebanon/Syria case (1860–61), the Balkan crisis and Bulgarian case (1875–78) in two chapters and the US intervention in Cuba (1895–98).
This volume is of course a joint venture. This is the case with five chapters, namely chapters 3, 6, 7, 8 and 11. The other six chapters have been written by one author, namely chapter 9 by Ada Dialla and chapters 1, 2, 4, 5 and 10 by Alexis Heraclides. Note that all the translations from the original languages are by the two authors unless otherwise stated.
We would like to thank a number of individuals for their advice and support. Special thanks are due to the Mill scholar Professor Georgios Varouxakis for his help and advice and to Professor Bertrand Taithe for his valuable comments and suggestions. We would also want to thank international law Professor Antonis Bredimas, Hegel scholar Professor Georges Faraklas and, at the LSE, Professor Kevin Featherstone and Dr Spyros Economides. Alexis Heraclides would also like to thank his Panteion colleague Dr Chrisafis Iordanoglou and his schoolmate and oldest friend John N. Faraclas for their generous hospitality in London when the research for the study began in the first part of 2011, and Ismini Demades, Ioanna Antonopoulou and Tena Prelec for technical assistance during two fruitful sojourns at the LSE in 2011 and 2013. Ada Dialla would like to thank the personnel of the Russian State Library and the State Archive of the Russian Federation for their assistance during her research trips in Moscow.
Notes
1 See e.g. J.-P. L. Fonteyne, ‘The Customary International Law Doctrine of Humanitarian Intervention: Its Current Validity Under the U.N. Charter’, California Western International Law Journal, 4 (1973–74), 203–36; R. B. Lillich, ‘Humanitarian Intervention: A Reply to Ian Brownlie and a Plea for Constructive Alternatives’, in J. N. Moore (ed.), Law and Civil War in the Modern World (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1974), 229–51.
2 T. B. Knudsen, ‘The History of Humanitarian Intervention: The Rule or the Exception?’, 50th ISA Annual Convention, New York, 15–18 February 2009.
3 A. Mandelstam, ‘La protection des minorités’, Recueil des cours de l’Académie de droit international, 1 (1923), 369–82, 388–91.
4 M. Finnemore, ‘Constructing Norms of Humanitarian Intervention’, in P. J. Katzenstein (ed.), The Culture of National Security (New York: Columbia University Press, 1996), 153–85.
5 See A. Heraclides, ‘Humanitarian Intervention in the 19th Century: The Heyday of a Controversial Concept’, Global Society: Journal of Interdisciplinary International Relations, 26:2 (2012), 215–40.
1
Humanitarian intervention today
Humanitarian intervention – that is, military intervention aimed at saving innocent people in other countries from massive violations of human rights (primarily the right to life) – entered public consciousness around 1990 as never before in the course of the twentieth century. It has earned a central place in scholarly research and in the preoccupations of decision-makers and international organizations and has captured the imagination of the wider public in a fashion few other political subjects have achieved in the post-Cold War world.¹ Ironically, it is in the limelight not due to its general acceptance but because of its controversial character, which has led to acrimonious debates. At the two ends of the scale there is, on the one hand, rejection, with the notion seen as nonsensical, an ‘oxymoron’,² the hallmark of deceit and, on the other, its acceptance as one of the clearest manifestations of altruism, the epitome of human solidarity and compassion (the ‘good Samaritan’), the willingness to face great risk and considerable loss to save the lives of ‘strangers’, with no gains.
Interestingly, rejection of, and sheer incredulity with, ‘humanitarian intervention’ is shared across the ideological spectrum, from realist scholarship in international relations to Marxism and other forms of leftist critique, as well as pacifism. From the realist line of reasoning, which has its origins in Thucydides, Machiavelli, Hobbes and Spinoza, so-called ‘humanitarian’ or other ethical concerns have no place in international politics and are damaging to rational foreign policy. More scathing is a critique from Carl Schmitt, who argued that ‘war in the name of humanity, is not war for the sake of humanity, but a war wherein a particular state seeks to usurp a universal concept against its military opponent’, identifying itself with humanity and denying it to the enemy.³ He adds (as if he were a Marxist) that it has been used as ‘an ideological instrument of imperialist expansion, and in its ethical-humanitarian form it is a specific vehicle of economic imperialism … whoever invokes humanity wants to cheat’.⁴
The question of intervention for humanitarian reasons poses agonizing dilemmas. There is the tension between the sanctity of life (saving human beings) and the veneration of sovereignty and independence; and there is the tension between doing something salutary in a humanitarian crisis if the United Nations Security Council is paralysed and abuse in the name of humanitarianism by intervening states. Most liberals opt for saving lives⁵ and for intervening, exceptionally, even without the authorization of the United Nations, provided the intervention has gained wide international legitimacy and the plight is so appalling that the interest in global humanity overrides narrowly defined national interest.⁶ Realists of course discard ethics in foreign affairs (with exceptions, such as those realists who take seriously the ‘morality of states’⁷) and regard only threats to vital interests worthy of intervention, and intervention for humanitarian reasons a delusion, or as bogus. Most leftist thinkers, such as Noam Chomsky,⁸ Edward Said, Tariq Ali,⁹ Jacques Derrida or Jean Baudrillard denounced the 1999 intervention in Kosovo and the whole idea of ‘humanitarian intervention’, as have other critical thinkers in more scholarly manner, such as Anne Orford,¹⁰ Antony Anghie¹¹ and Costas Douzinas.¹² For them, intervention is by definition abusive, the diktat of the powerful, a form of blatant neo-imperialism and neo-colonialism. But a minority of leftist thinkers, who put a premium on self-determination and saving the weak from the strong, are favourable to such interventions, albeit in very exceptional cases, such as Jürgen Habermas,¹³ Michael Walzer¹⁴ and the more controversial Bernard Kouchner, with his droit d’ingérence.¹⁵
Most international lawyers are opposed to such interventions, emphasizing state sovereignty and independence. There has, though, been a shift, which is far from insignificant, in that during the Cold War, among those opposed, the majority were against the whole notion, while in the post-Cold War era most are opposed to intervention only if it does not obtain UN authorization. Students of international relations are more nuanced, especially non-realists,¹⁶ with those in the field of international ethics, cosmopolitans in particular, who tend to be less burdened by sovereignty, supporting unilateral humanitarian intervention, followed more guardedly by communitarians, from Michael Walzer in the late 1970s onwards.¹⁷ They, together with international lawyers supportive of humanitarian intervention even without a UN mandate, disagree mainly as to the level of onslaught that warrants intervention, which ranges from systematic violations of fundamental human rights to a situation akin to genocide,¹⁸ and the point at which to intervene: early on or late in a conflict, when all attempts to stop the humanitarian plight peacefully have failed.
During the Cold War, humanitarian intervention was generally considered beyond the pale, although even then a minority of international lawyers supported armed intervention on humanitarian grounds.¹⁹ Some states, notably the US in the cases of the Dominican Republic (1965) and Grenada (1983), Belgium in Congo (1960–61), Belgium and the US in Congo (1964) or France in the Central African Republic (1979), had justified their actions on humanitarian grounds. But the near consensus is that only three military interventions qualify as humanitarian given that they put an end to widespread loss of life: India’s intervention in East Pakistan (1971) (hundreds of thousands of civilians dead and almost nine million refugees fleeing to India), which led to the creation of Bangladesh; Vietnam’s overthrow of the heinous Khmer Rouge regime under Pol Pot in Cambodia (1979) (with up to two million civilian deaths mainly from disease and malnutrition in forced labour camps); and the overthrow of Amin’s odious regime in Uganda (with 300,000 citizens murdered by Amin’s thugs) by Tanzania (1979). Interestingly, all three intervening states did not justify their action on humanitarian grounds (with the partial exception of India²⁰) but on grounds of self-defence, and all three intervened mainly for instrumental reasons, especially Vietnam. The first two interventions faced heavy wind internationally, notably in the UN (especially the Vietnamese invasion), even though they both saved many lives.²¹
Following the end of the Cold War, the first post-bipolar decade witnessed unprecedented interventionism on humanitarian grounds: safe haven for the Kurds of northern Iraq (1991), Somalia (1992), Bosnia (1992–95), the intervention of the Economic Community Of West African States (ECOWAS) in Liberia (1990–96), the US-led intervention in Haiti (1994), French-led forces in Rwanda (1994), NATO’s intervention in Serbia and Kosovo (1999) and the Australian-led intervention in East Timor (1999).
In Rwanda effective French intervention came very late, following three months of genocidal massacre by the Hutus of more than 800,000 Tutsis and many moderate Hutus.²² The peacemaking intervention of ECOWAS in Liberia headed by Nigeria²³ and NATO’s Kosovo/Serbia operation took place without authorization by the UN Security Council. NATO’s Kosovo/Serbia operation gave rise to a heated discussion not only because of its lack of UN endorsement but also due to the choice of means (high-altitude aerial bombardment), which led to hundreds of civilian deaths, more intense ethnic cleansing by the repugnant Milosevic regime, thousands of refugees, considerable destruction of infrastructure and environmental pollution.²⁴ Many had feared that this Kosovo precedent would open a Pandora’s box but this did not come about, partly due to these unintended consequences. In the second part of 1999, the Australian-led peacekeeping operation in East Timor took place with UN sanction, with no mismatch between the military means and humanitarian ends, and it turned out to be peaceful.²⁵ With the onset of the new millennium – and with ‘9/11’ and its repercussions as far as US priorities were concerned (the ‘war on terror’) – the idea of humanitarian intervention seemed to have ‘evaporated’,²⁶ although there were at least two candidates, Sierra Leone and Sudan’s Darfur. The next humanitarian interventions took place more than a decade later: the NATO-led operation in Libya (February–October 2011) and the French peacekeeping operation in the Central African Republic (December 2013), both authorized by the UN Security Council.²⁷
In the wake of the Kosovo experience, UN Secretary-General Kofi Annan pondered: ‘On the one hand is it legitimate for a regional organisation to use force without a UN mandate? On the other is it permissible to let gross and systematic violations of human rights, with grave humanitarian consequences, continue unchecked?’²⁸ Addressing the UN General Assembly in September 1999, he expressed his strong reservations about NATO’s unauthorized intervention in Kosovo and Serbia but added: ‘If in those dark days and hours leading to the genocide [in Rwanda] a coalition of States had been prepared to act in the defence of the Tutsi population, but did not receive prompt Council authorization, should such a coalition have stood aside and allowed the horror to unfold?’²⁹ And he challenged the member-states to come up with a new vision of sovereignty.³⁰
The Annan challenge was taken up by the Canadian-sponsored twelve-person International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS), which responded by subsuming humanitarian intervention under the novel concept of ‘responsibility to protect’ (R2P or RtoP).³¹ The aim of the R2P approach was to ‘shift the terms of the debate’;³² it amounts to a ‘rhetorical trick’ of flipping the coin and shifting the emphasis from the controversial right to intervene for humanitarian reasons to the ‘less confrontational idea of a responsibility to protect’,³³ but the substance remains the same.
In 2005 at intergovernmental level, the Outcome Document of the UN World Summit (15 September) made it a primary responsibility of states to protect their population against ‘genocide, war crimes, crimes against humanity and ethnic cleansing’; if they fail to do so, a ‘timely and decisive response’ becomes the responsibility of the international community. The ICISS had suggested that the permanent members of the Security Council refrain from using the veto in such cases as long as their vital interests are not at stake but this was unacceptable to the US, Russia and China.³⁴ The first test case of R2P was the intervention in Libya.³⁵
Given the situation during the Cold War and the interventionism of the 1990s and the ongoing debate, the general impression is that humanitarian intervention is basically a recent phenomenon, but in fact the concept of humanitarian intervention had been established in the nineteenth century.
Before moving back in time (in chapter 2), let us identify the main issues at stake in the present-day debate on the question of intervening or not intervening militarily for humanitarian reasons. Putting aside the proverbial question of whether ‘violent means can ever serve humanitarian ends’,³⁶ today’s debate includes six main questions and at least three secondary ones.
The first question concerns the legality–legitimacy spectrum. Is legality through UN authorization indispensable? Is non-authorized intervention by definition illegal or is it perhaps legal given an alternative reading of the UN Charter?³⁷ Can intervention be condoned if it appears legitimate even though it is technically illegal, as the Independent International Commission on Kosovo concluded in its detailed report?³⁸ Another tack is the contention that one is faced with a complex legal problem³⁹ which may or may not be resolved on an ad hoc basis.
A second question is where to place the threshold for intervening with or without UN authorization: on systematic human rights violations (such as systematic discrimination akin to apartheid or ‘internal colonialism’), on something more grave, such as so-called egregious crimes (i.e. ethnic cleansing, war crimes, crimes against humanity), or only at the level of mass extermination and genocide?⁴⁰
A third issue is in which cases to intervene (with or without UN authorization): in a protracted internal war (Liberia, Syria), in a Hobbesian ‘war of all against all’ (Somalia), a separatist war (Kosovo) or only to put an end to one-sided onslaught (Rwanda), or in all four cases?
A fourth problem is abuse (wrong intentions and ulterior motives) and how it can be checked, if at all. UN authorization, collective intervention and intergovernmental supervision may do the trick but what if they are not forthcoming? And even if they are, they may still be seen as suspect, for the permanent members of the Security Council (as in the case of the Concert of Europe in the nineteenth century) can hardly be counted upon – or live up – to being the moral consciousness of the world. A related factor is the presence of tangible interests as motives and how they can be reconciled with humanitarian motives and intentions, especially since ‘saving strangers’ on its own is unlikely to provoke intervention.⁴¹
Another question is timing. Should intervention take place only after the exhaustion of all peaceful means (i.e. as a last resort) or should there be early, anticipatory intervention and preventive deployment once egregious crimes have been spotted, such as ethnic cleansing, so as to forestall a humanitarian disaster (the Kosovo model) and to avoid greater use of military force later, even though early intervention would be more difficult to justify internationally?⁴²
There is also the need for a reasonable estimate of a successful outcome, that is, of attaining the humanitarian goals, avoiding ‘noble intentions and bloody results’,⁴³ with few deaths of civilians and little destruction of infrastructure (sparse ‘collateral damage’).⁴⁴ There is also the related issue of ensuring that less damage is done by intervening than by not intervening.⁴⁵
The three secondary questions concern: a quick exit strategy or a longer stay for fear that the bloodbath and anarchy will resume;⁴⁶ how many casualties of ‘our soldiers’ are acceptable;⁴⁷ and the fact that the intervening states are by definition more powerful, which smacks of the powerful bullying the weak under a smoke-screen of righteousness.⁴⁸
The recent tendency of advocates of humanitarian intervention is to borrow from the well developed ‘just war’ doctrine of the Middle Ages and Renaissance (see chapter 2), with the criteria for a just war remodelled to fit modern conditions. The following ‘just war’ criteria are all regarded as essential for a humanitarian intervention to be contemplated: right authority, in the sense of ‘legitimate authority’ and not simply legal (factual) authority, which also alludes to ‘failed states’ as illegitimate and not worthy of sovereignty;⁴⁹ just cause (massive suffering); right intention (humanitarian motives genuine and not a ruse); last resort; proportional means (good over harm); and a reasonable prospect of success, leading to a ‘just peace’.⁵⁰
Notes
1 B. Jahn, ‘Humanitarian Intervention – What’s in a Name?’, International Politics, 49:1 (2012), 36.
2 A. Roberts, ‘Humanitarian War: Military Intervention and Human Rights’, International Affairs, 69:3 (1993), 429.
3 C. Schmitt, The Concept of the Political (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1976, translated from the German, with Introduction and notes by G. Schwab) [1932], 54.
4 Ibid., 54.
5 M. J. Smith, ‘Humanitarian Intervention: An Overview of the Ethical Issues’, Ethics and International Affairs, 12:1 (1998), 73.
6 M. Walzer, ‘The Politics of Rescue’, Social Research, 62:1 (1995), 59.
7 D. C. Hendrickson, ‘In Defense of Realism: A Commentary on Just and Unjust War’, Ethics and International Relations, 11 (1997), 19–53; M. Wesley, ‘Toward a Realist Ethics of Intervention’, Ethics and International Affairs, 22:1 (2008), 55–72.
8 N. Chomsky, A New Generation Draws the Line: Kosovo, East Timor and the Standards of the West (New York: Verso, 2001).
9 T. Ali (ed.), Masters of the Universe? NATO’s Balkan Crusade (New York: Verso, 2000).
10 A. Orford, Reading Humanitarian Intervention: Human Rights and the Use of Force in International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
11 A. Anghie, Imperialism, Sovereignty and the Making of International Law (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2004), 274–308.
12 C. Douzinas, Human Rights and Empire: The Political Philosophy of Cosmopolitanism (Abingdon: Routledge-Cavendish, 2007).
13 J. Habermas, ‘Bestiality and Humanity: A War on the Border Between Legality and Morality’, Constellations, 6:3 (1999), 263–72.
14 Walzer, ‘The Politics of Rescue’, 53–66; M. Walzer, ‘The Argument About Humanitarian Intervention’, Dissent, 49:1 (2002), 29–37.
15 See S. Hoffmann, ‘The Politics and Ethics of Military Intervention’, Survival, 37:4 (1995–96), 34–6; Smith, ‘Humanitarian Intervention’, 70–5; T. Allen and S. Syan, ‘A Right to Interfere? Bernard Kouchner and the New Humanitarianism’, Journal of Development, 12 (2000), 825, 828–36, 840; G. J. Bass, Freedom’s Battle: The Origins of Humanitarian Intervention (New York: Vintage Books, 2009), 11–24.
16 See e.g. Hoffmann, ‘The Politics and Ethics of Military Intervention’, 29, 37–41; Smith, ‘Humanitarian Intervention’, 63–79; N. J. Wheeler, ‘Legitimating Humanitarian Intervention: Principles and Procedures’, Melbourne Journal of International Law, 2:2 (2001), 550–67.
17 M. Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Basic Books, 1977), 101–8.
18 For a low threshold see W. M. Reisman, ‘Sovereignty and Human Rights in Contemporary International Law’, American Journal of International Law, 84:4 (1990), 866–76; A. D’Amato, ‘The Invasion of Panama Was a Lawful Response to Tyranny’, American Journal of International Law, 84:2 (1990), 516–24; F. R. Tesón, ‘Eight Principles for Humanitarian Intervention’, Journal of Military Ethics, 5:2 (2006), 95–100, 105–6. For a high threshold, a ‘spike test’, see T. Farer, ‘Cosmopolitan Humanitarian Intervention: A Five-Part Test’, International Affairs, 19:2 (2005), 215–19.
19 They included some major figures from an older generation, such as Lauterpacht, Guggenheim, de Visscher, Reisman, McDougal and Jessup, as well as Lillich, D’Amato, Moore, Chilstrom, Levitin, Umozurike, Sornarajah and Tesón.
20 N. J. Wheeler, Saving Strangers: Humanitarian Intervention in International Society (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000), 64 n.43.
21 M. Leifer, ‘Vietnam’s Intervention in Kampuchea: The Rights of States Versus the Rights of People’, in I. Forbes and M. Hoffman (eds), Political Theory, International Relations, and the Ethics of Intervention (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1993), 145–56; F. Hassan, ‘Realpolitik in International Law: After Tanzanian–Ugandan Conflict, Humanitarian Intervention
Reexamined’, Willamette Law Review, 17 (1981), 897; Wheeler, Saving Strangers, 65–71, 80–106; M. Akehurst, ‘Humanitarian Intervention’, in H. Bull (ed.), Intervention in World Politics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), 95–9; S. Chesterman, Just War or Just Peace? Humanitarian Intervention and International Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001), 71–4, 77–80.
22 B. D. Jones, ‘Intervention without Borders
: Humanitarian Intervention in Rwanda, 1990–94’, Millennium: Journal of International Studies, 24:2 (1995), 225, 230–1.
23 See H. Howe, ‘Lessons of Liberia: ECOMOG and Regional Peacekeeping’, International Security, 21:3 (1997), 145–76.
24 For the international law debate see: R. A. Falk, ‘Kosovo, World Order, and the Future of International Law’, American Journal of International Law, 93:4 (1999), 847–57; B. Simma, ‘NATO, the UN and the Use of Force: Legal Aspects’, European Journal of International Law, 10 (1999), 1–22; A. Cassese, ‘Ex injuria jus oritur: Are We Moving Towards International Legitimation of Forcible Humanitarian Countermeasures in the World Community?, European Journal of International Law, 10, (1999), 23–30; L. Henkin, ‘Kosovo and the Law of Humanitarian Intervention
’, American Journal of International Law, 93:4 (1999), 824–8; R. Wedgewood, ‘NATO’s Campaign in Yugoslavia’, American Journal of International Law, 93:4 (1999), 828–34. More generally see Independent International Commission on Kosovo, Kosovo Report: Conflict, International Response, Lessons Learned (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000); A. Schnabel and R. Thakur (eds), Kosovo and the Challenge of Humanitarian Intervention (Tokyo: United Nations University Press, 2000).
25 N. J. Wheeler and T. Dunne, ‘East Timor and the New Humanitarian Interventionism’, International Affairs, 77:4 (2001), 805–37.
26 T. G. Weiss, ‘The Sunset of Humanitarian Intervention? The Responsibility to Protect in a Unipolar Era’, Security Dialogue, 25:2 (2004), 135.
27 J. Pattison, ‘The Ethics of Humanitarian Intervention in Libya’, Ethics and International Affairs, 25:3 (2011), 271–7.
28 K. Annan, ‘Two Concepts of Sovereignty’, The Economist, 18 September 1999, 49.
29 Press release SG/SM/7136, GA/9596 (20 September 1999), 2.
30 R. Thakur, ‘Outlook: Intervention, Sovereignty and the Responsibility to Protect: Experiences from ICISS’, Security Dialogue, 33:3 (2002), 325.
31 G. Evans and M. Sahnoun, ‘The Responsibility to Protect’, Foreign Affairs, 1:6 (2002), 99–100; T. G. Weiss, ‘R2P after 9/11 and the World Summit’, Wisconsin International Law Journal, 24:3 (2006), 741–60.
32 International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty (ICISS), Responsibility to Protect (Ottawa: International Development Research Centre, 2001), 16–18; Thakur, ‘Outlook’, 327–8.
33 C. Stahn, ‘Responsibility to Protect: Political Rhetoric or Emerging Legal Norm?’, American Journal of International Law, 101:1 (2007), 102.
34 A. J. Bellamy, ‘Whither the Responsibility to Protect? Humanitarian Intervention and the 2005 World Summit’, Ethics and International Affairs, 20:2 (2006), 146–7, 151–2, 167.
35 J. Welsh, ‘Civilian Protection in Libya: Putting Coercion and Controversy Back into RtoP’, Ethics and International Affairs, 25:3 (2011), 255–62.
36 Wheeler, ‘Legitimating Humanitarian Intervention’, 556.
37 For the alternative reading see e.g. W. D. Verwey, ‘Humanitarian Intervention Under International Law’, Netherlands International Law Review, 32 (1985), 357–418, especially 406–18; C. F. Amerasinghe, ‘The Conundrum of Recourse to Force – To Protect Persons’, International Organizations Law Review, 3 (2006), 7–53, especially 37–9, 47–53.
38 Independent International Commission on Kosovo, Kosovo Report, 2.
39 I. Hurd, ‘Is Humanitarian Intervention Legal? The Rule of Law in an Incoherent World’, Ethics and International Affairs, 25:3 (2011), 293–313.
40 M. J. Bazyler, ‘Reexamining the Doctrine of Humanitarian Intervention in Light of the Atrocities in Kampuchea and Ethiopia’, Stanford Journal of International Law, 23 (1987), 598–601; Hoffmann, ‘The Politics and Ethics of Military Intervention’, 37–8; D. Fisher, ‘The Ethics of Intervention’, Survival, 36 (1994), 51–9; Farer, ‘Cosmopolitan Humanitarian Intervention’, 215–17; M. Fixdal and D. Smith, ‘Humanitarian Intervention and Just War’, Mershon International Studies Review, 42:2 (1998), 296–9.
41 R. B. Lillich, ‘Forcible Self-Help by States to Protect Human Rights’, Iowa Law Review, 53 (1967–68), 53; Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars, 101–4; Wheeler, ‘Legitimating Humanitarian Intervention’, 238–9.
42 Hoffmann, ‘The Politics and Ethics of Military Intervention’, 44; Fixdal and Smith, ‘Humanitarian Intervention and Just War’, 301–2.
43 M. Ignatieff, ‘The Seductiveness of Moral Disgust’, Social Research, 62:1 (1995), 78.
44 G. Levy, ‘The Case for Humanitarian Intervention’, Orbis, 37:4 (1993), 624; A. Roberts, ‘The Crisis in U.S. Peacekeeping’, Survival, 36 (1994), 109.
45 Fixdal and Smith, ‘Humanitarian Intervention and Just War’, 305; Farer, ‘Cosmopolitan Humanitarian Intervention’, 219; B. Parekh, ‘Rethinking Humanitarian Intervention’, International Political Science Review, 18:1 (1997), 67.
46 Walzer, ‘The Politics of Rescue’, 56–7, 61; Hoffmann, ‘The Politics and Ethics of Military Intervention’, 41, 43.
47 Walzer, ‘The Politics of Rescue’, 58–9; Hendrickson, ‘In Defense of Realism’, 46.
48 Hassan, ‘Realpolitik in International Law’, 910.
49 Fixdal and Smith, ‘Humanitarian Intervention and Just War’, 291–2; A. Coates, ‘Humanitarian Intervention: A Conflict of Traditions’, in T. Nardin and M. S. Williams (eds), Humanitarian Intervention (New York: New York University Press, 2006), 62–3.
50 J. B. Hehir, ‘Expanding Military Intervention: Promise or Peril?’, Social Research, 62:1 (1995), 46–8; Fixdal and Smith, ‘Humanitarian Intervention and Just War’, 283–312; Wheeler, ‘Legitimating Humanitarian Intervention’, 550–67; Thakur, ‘Outlook’, 332–3; G. Reichberg and H. Syse, ‘Humanitarian Intervention: A Case of Offensive Force?’, Security Dialogue, 33:3 (2002), 309–22; J. Boyle, ‘Traditional Just War Theory and Humanitarian Intervention’, in Nardin and Williams (eds), Humanitarian Intervention, 31–57.
Part I
Theory
Introduction
Throughout the long nineteenth century and until 1939, ‘intervention’ (originally a French term) or ‘interference’ (the original British term) was ‘Protean’, covering an array of manifestations ‘from a speech in Parliament by Palmerston to the partition of Poland’.¹ Not only was the scope of intervention wide, but its meaning and consequences remained contentious.
The Argentinean diplomat and jurist Carlos Calvo points out, in his acclaimed 1870 treatise, that on intervention ‘there are almost as many different opinions as there are authors. Some admit it, approving intervention; others condemn it, repudiating it; for some it has become a right, others add the idea of duty; others see nothing else but a simple fact, a brutal fact, which has its place in history’.² The situation remained the same well into the twentieth century. As Percy Winfield put it in the early 1920s, ‘[t]he subject of intervention is one of the vaguest branches of international law. We are told that intervention is a right; that it is a crime; that it is the rule; that it is the exception; that it is never permissible at all’.³
Following the Second World War the problem with intervention continued to be discussed in the international law and international relations literature.⁴ In the post-Cold War era, with increasing interventionism, interest hardly diminished, the main focus now being on humanitarian intervention, which is even more contentious.⁵
But two things are clear. Intervention meant then – and today ⁶ – ‘coercive’, ‘dictatorial interference by a State in the [internal or external] affairs of another State for the purpose of maintaining or altering the actual conditions of things’.⁷ Moreover, non-intervention was – and is – the rule, intervention the exception.⁸
It is often assumed that the non-intervention norm was established in the Treaty of Westphalia (1648). In fact non-intervention was established as a principle of international law in the first half of the eighteenth century by jurists Christian Wolff and Emer de Vattel.⁹ Thereafter non-intervention became a fully fledged legal principle associated with the principles of sovereignty and independence. Half a century later, Kant lent considerable weight to this new norm in his quest for principles assuring peace, with his Preliminary Article 5 on non-intervention in his Toward Perpetual Peace (see chapter 5).
In the course of the long nineteenth century, five positions on the matter can be discerned in international law and international political theory: (1) strict adherence to non-intervention; (2) exceptions limited to instances of threats to national interests; (3) exceptions to include protracted civil wars when a state has collapsed into anarchy; (4) exceptions to include national struggles against alien rule, especially in order to offset a previous intervention in support of the incumbent government; and (5) exceptions to include intervening in order to stop massacres and other atrocities.
The English term ‘humanitarian intervention’ was coined by the British jurist and aesthete William Edward Hall in 1880 in his acclaimed International Law (renamed the very same year A Treatise on International Law).¹⁰ It appears in a footnote and not in the main text,¹¹ which might imply that the author was unaware of having launched a new term or was reluctant to do so. In fact he had not conceived a new concept but the English term that was to stick, for other terms had previously been used, such as ‘intervention in the general interests of humanity’¹² and ‘intervention for humanity’, which correspond to the French term in use, intervention d’humanité,¹³ or ‘intervention on the ground of humanity’, intervention ‘on behalf of the interests of humanity’,¹⁴ all with the same meaning.¹⁵
From the 1830s until the 1930s humanitarian intervention was understood as interfering ‘for the purpose of vindicating the law of nations against outrage’,¹⁶ ‘in the interests of humanity for the purpose of stopping religious persecution and endless cruelties in times of peace and war’.¹⁷ According to Antoine Rougier (in a seminal 1910 survey of the literature), ‘intervention on the grounds of humanity is properly that which recognizes the right of one state to exercise an international control over the acts of another in regard to its internal sovereignty when contrary to the laws of humanity’.¹⁸ Ellery Stowell (in 1921) defined humanitarian intervention, with the nineteenth-century experience in mind, ‘as the