The Problems of Philosophy
4/5
()
About this ebook
Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, historian, social reformer, and pacifist. Although he spent the majority of his life in England, he was born in Wales, where he also died. Russell led the British “revolt against Idealism” in the early twentieth century and is one of the founders of analytic philosophy along with his protégé Wittgenstein and his elder Frege. He co-authored, with A. N. Whitehead, Principia Mathematica, an attempt to ground mathematics on logic. His philosophical essay “On Denoting” has been considered a “paradigm of philosophy.” Both works have had a considerable influence on logic, mathematics, set theory, linguistics and analytic philosophy. He was a prominent anti-war activist, championing free trade between nations and anti-imperialism. Russell was imprisoned for his pacifist activism during World War I, campaigned against Adolf Hitler, for nuclear disarmament. He criticized Soviet totalitarianism and the United States of America’s involvement in the Vietnam War. In 1950, Russell was awarded the Nobel Prize in Literature, “in recognition of his varied and significant writings in which he champions humanitarian ideals and freedom of thought.”
Read more from Bertrand Russell
The Complete Works of Bertrand Russell Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe ABC of Relativity Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5An Outline of Philosophy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A World Apart: Imprisonment in a Soviet Labor Camp During World War II Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Essays in Skepticism Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Understanding History: And Other Essays Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Art of Philosophizing: And Other Essays Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Will to Doubt Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Modern Essays Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBertrand Russell's Dictionary of Mind, Matter and Morals Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Analyses of Mind Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Great Philosophers Volume Two: Science and Philosophy, The Preservation of Youth, and Understanding History Rating: 1 out of 5 stars1/5Why I Am Not a Christian and What I Believe (Warbler Classics Annotated Edition) Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Why Men Fight (Serapis Classics) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBertrand Russell – The Complete Collection Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Analysis of Mind Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Problems of Philosophy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Great Philosophers Volume One: The Road to Inner Freedom, The Art of Philosophizing, and Pilgrimage to Humanity Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Bertrand Russell Collection Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIntroduction to Mathematical Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSceptical Essays Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsEducation of Character: The Psychology of Children Going to School Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Analysis of Mind Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Essential Bertrand Russell Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsWhy Men Fight Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Related to The Problems of Philosophy
Related ebooks
The Problems with Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsDelphi Collected Works of René Descartes (Illustrated) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Will to Doubt Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Bertrand Russell's Dictionary of Mind, Matter and Morals Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Art of Philosophizing: And Other Essays Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Understanding History: And Other Essays Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5What Kind of Creatures Are We? Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Genealogy of Morals Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAn Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Problems of Philosophy Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Analyses of Mind Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Pragmatism Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Essays in Skepticism Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Logic Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Critique of Pure Reason by Immanuel Kant - Delphi Classics (Illustrated) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Life of the Mind: The Groundbreaking Investigation on How We Think Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Treatise On Human Nature Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Emotions: Outline of a Theory Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Symposium Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Bertrand Russell: The Complete Works Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Beyond Good and Evil Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Social Construction of Reality: A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Critique of Pure Reason Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Rediscovered Books): Complete and Unabridged Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Mysticism and Logic and Other Essays Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Meditation on First Philosophy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Road to Inner Freedom: The Ethics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsEssays in Metaphysics: Identity and Difference Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5
Philosophy For You
The Courage to Be Happy: Discover the Power of Positive Psychology and Choose Happiness Every Day Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Boy, the Mole, the Fox and the Horse Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of War Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Little Book of Hygge: Danish Secrets to Happy Living Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Source: The Secrets of the Universe, the Science of the Brain Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sun Tzu's The Art of War: Bilingual Edition Complete Chinese and English Text Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Four Loves Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Experiencing God (2021 Edition): Knowing and Doing the Will of God Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Dictionary of Obscure Sorrows Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Republic by Plato Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Be Here Now Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Meditations: Complete and Unabridged Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato's Republic Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Egyptian Book of the Dead: The Complete Papyrus of Ani Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Art of Loving Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5THE EMERALD TABLETS OF THOTH THE ATLANTEAN Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sapiens: A Brief History of Humankind Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Think Like a Roman Emperor: The Stoic Philosophy of Marcus Aurelius Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Communicating Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5My Big TOE - Awakening H: Book 1 of a Trilogy Unifying Philosophy, Physics, and Metaphysics Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Beyond Good and Evil Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Denial of Death Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Course in Miracles: Text, Workbook for Students, Manual for Teachers Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Laws of Connection: The Scientific Secrets of Building a Strong Social Network Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsInward Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/512 Rules for Life: An Antidote to Chaos Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Reviews for The Problems of Philosophy
4 ratings0 reviews
Book preview
The Problems of Philosophy - Bertrand Russell
The Problems of Philosophy
by Bertrand Russell
First published in 1912
This edition published by Reading Essentials
Victoria, BC Canada with branch offices in the Czech Republic and Germany
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or by any information storage or retrieval system, except in the case of excerpts by a reviewer, who may quote brief passages in a review.
The Problems of Philosophy
by
Bertrand Russell
Preface
In the following pages I have confined myself in the main to those problems of philosophy in regard to which I thought it possible to say something positive and constructive, since merely negative criticism seemed out of place. For this reason, theory of knowledge occupies a larger space than metaphysics in the present volume, and some topics much discussed by philosophers are treated very briefly, if at all.
I have derived valuable assistance from unpublished writings of G. E. Moore and J. M. Keynes: from the former, as regards the relations of sense-data to physical objects, and from the latter as regards probability and induction. I have also profited greatly by the criticisms and suggestions of Professor Gilbert Murray.
1912
Chapter 1 Appearance and reality
Is there any knowledge in the world which is so certain that no reasonable man could doubt it? This question, which at first sight might not seem difficult, is really one of the most difficult that can be asked. When we have realized the obstacles in the way of a straightforward and confident answer, we shall be well launched on the study of philosophy—for philosophy is merely the attempt to answer such ultimate questions, not carelessly and dogmatically, as we do in ordinary life and even in the sciences, but critically, after exploring all that makes such questions puzzling, and after realizing all the vagueness and confusion that underlie our ordinary ideas.
In daily life, we assume as certain many things which, on a closer scrutiny, are found to be so full of apparent contradictions that only a great amount of thought enables us to know what it is that we really may believe. In the search for certainty, it is natural to begin with our present experiences, and in some sense, no doubt, knowledge is to be derived from them. But any statement as to what it is that our immediate experiences make us know is very likely to be wrong. It seems to me that I am now sitting in a chair, at a table of a certain shape, on which I see sheets of paper with writing or print. By turning my head I see out of the window buildings and clouds and the sun. I believe that the sun is about ninety-three million miles from the earth; that it is a hot globe many times bigger than the earth; that, owing to the earth’s rotation, it rises every morning, and will continue to do so for an indefinite time in the future. I believe that, if any other normal person comes into my room, he will see the same chairs and tables and books and papers as I see, and that the table which I see is the same as the table which I feel pressing against my arm. All this seems to be so evident as to be hardly worth stating, except in answer to a man who doubts whether I know anything. Yet all this may be reasonably doubted, and all of it requires much careful discussion before we can be sure that we have stated it in a form that is wholly true.
To make our difficulties plain, let us concentrate attention on the table. To the eye it is oblong, brown and shiny, to the touch it is smooth and cool and hard; when I tap it, it gives out a wooden sound. Anyone else who sees and feels and hears the table will agree with this description, so that it might seem as if no difficulty would arise; but as soon as we try to be more precise our troubles begin. Although I believe that the table is ‘really’ of the same colour all over, the parts that reflect the light look much brighter than the other parts, and some parts look white because of reflected light. I know that, if I move, the parts that reflect the light will be different, so that the apparent distribution of colours on the table will change. It follows that if several people are looking at the table at the same moment, no two of them will see exactly the same distribution of colours, because no two can see it from exactly the same point of view, and any change in the point of view makes some change in the way the light is reflected.
For most practical purposes these differences are unimportant, but to the painter they are all-important: the painter has to unlearn the habit of thinking that things seem to have the colour which common sense says they ‘really’ have, and to learn the habit of seeing things as they appear. Here we have already the beginning of one of the distinctions that cause most trouble in philosophy—the distinction between ‘appearance’ and ‘reality’, between what things seem to be and what they are. The painter wants to know what things seem to be, the practical man and the philosopher want to know what they are; but the philosopher’s wish to know this is stronger than the practical man’s, and is more troubled by knowledge as to the difficulties of answering the question.
To return to the table. It is evident from what we have found, that there is no colour which pre-eminently appears to be the colour of the table, or even of any one particular part of the table—it appears to be of different colours from different points of view, and there is no reason for regarding some of these as more really its colour than others. And we know that even from a given point of view the colour will seem different by artificial light, or to a colour-blind man, or to a man wearing blue spectacles, while in the dark there will be no colour at all, though to touch and hearing the table will be unchanged. This colour is not something which is inherent in the table, but something depending upon the table and the spectator and the way the light falls on the table. When, in ordinary life, we speak of the colour of the table, we only mean the sort of colour which it will seem to have to a normal spectator from an ordinary point of view under usual conditions of light. But the other colours which appear under other conditions have just as good a right to be considered real; and therefore, to avoid favouritism, we are compelled to deny that, in itself, the table has any one particular colour.
The same thing applies to the texture. With the naked eye one can see the grain, but otherwise the table looks smooth and even. If we looked at it through a microscope, we should see roughnesses and hills and valleys, and all sorts of differences that are imperceptible to the naked eye. Which of these is the ‘real’ table? We are naturally tempted to say that what we see through the microscope is more real, but that in turn would be changed by a still more powerful microscope. If, then, we cannot trust what we see with the naked eye, why should we trust what we see through a microscope? Thus, again, the confidence in our senses with which we began deserts us.
The shape of the table is no better. We are all in the habit of judging as to the ‘real’ shapes of things, and we do this so unreflectingly that we come to think we actually see the real shapes. But, in fact, as we all have to learn if we try to draw, a given thing looks different in shape from every different point of view. If our table is ‘really’ rectangular, it will look, from almost all points of view, as if it had two acute angles and two obtuse angles. If opposite sides are parallel, they will look as if they converged to a point away from the spectator; if they are of equal length, they will look as if the nearer side were longer. All these things are not commonly noticed in looking at a table, because experience has taught us to construct the ‘real’ shape from the apparent shape, and the ‘real’ shape is what interests us as practical men. But the ‘real’ shape is not what we see; it is something inferred from what we see. And what we see is constantly changing in shape as we move about the room; so that here again the senses seem not to give us the truth about the table itself, but only about the appearance of the table.
Similar difficulties arise when we consider the sense of touch. It is true that the table always gives us a sensation of hardness, and we feel that it resists pressure. But the sensation we obtain depends upon how hard we press the table and also upon what part of the body we press with; thus the various sensations due to various pressures or various parts of the body cannot be supposed to reveal directly any definite property of the table, but at most to be signs of some property which perhaps causes all the sensations, but is not actually apparent in any of them. And the same applies still more obviously to the sounds which can be elicited by rapping the table.
Thus it becomes evident that the real table, if there is one, is not the same as what we immediately experience by sight or touch or hearing. The real table, if there is one, is not immediately known to us at all, but must be an inference from what is immediately known. Hence, two very difficult questions at once arise; namely, (1) Is there a real table at all? (2) If so, what sort of object can it be?
It will help us in considering these questions to have a few simple terms of which the meaning is definite and clear. Let us give the name of ‘sense-data’ to the things that are immediately known in sensation: such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so on. We shall give the name ‘sensation’ to the experience of being immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, we have a sensation of the colour, but the colour itself is a sense-datum, not a sensation. The colour is that of which we are immediately aware, and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is plain that if we are to know anything about the table, it must be by means of the sense-data—brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness, etc.—which we associate with the table; but, for the reasons which have been given, we cannot say that the table is the sense-data, or even that the sense-data are directly properties of the table. Thus a problem arises as to the relation of the sense-data to the real table, supposing there is such a thing.
The real table, if it exists, we will call a ‘physical object’. Thus we have to consider the relation of sense-data to physical objects. The collection of all physical objects is called ‘matter’. Thus our two questions may be re-stated as follows: (1) Is there any such thing as matter? (2) If so, what is its nature?
The philosopher who first brought prominently forward the reasons for regarding the immediate objects of our senses as not existing independently of us was Bishop Berkeley (1685-1753). His Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, in Opposition to Sceptics and Atheists, undertake to prove that there is no such thing as matter at all, and that the world consists of nothing but minds and their ideas. Hylas has hitherto believed in matter, but he is no match for Philonous, who mercilessly drives him into contradictions and paradoxes, and makes his own denial of matter seem, in the end, as if it were almost common sense. The arguments employed are of very different value: some are important and sound, others are confused or quibbling. But Berkeley retains the merit of having shown that the existence of matter is capable of being denied without absurdity, and that if there are any things that exist independently of us they cannot be the immediate objects of our sensations.
There are two different questions involved when we ask whether matter exists, and it is important to keep