The Art of Being Right
5/5
()
About this ebook
Arthur Schopenhauer
Arthur Schopenhauer (1788–1860) entwickelte eine Philosophie, die zeitgenössische Annahmen der Erkenntnistheorie, Metaphysik, Ästhetik und Ethik richtungsweisend und vorgreifend mit empiristischen, hermeneutischen und phänomenologischen Elementen verbindet. Sein Denken wirkt weit über die Philosophie hinaus in Literatur, Musik und Bildender Kunst.
Read more from Arthur Schopenhauer
The World as Will and Representation Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Essential Schopenhauer: Key Selections from The World as Will and Representation and Other Writings Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Suffering of the World: From the Essays of Arthur Schopenhauer Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Complete Works of Arthur Schopenhauer Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Art of Being Right Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficien and On the Will in Nature Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe World as Will and Idea - Vol. I. Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The World As Will And Idea (Vol. 1 of 3) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsStudies in Pessimism, On Human Nature, and Religion: a Dialogue, etc. Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOn The Suffering of the World - Schopenhauer Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe World as Will and Representation, Vol. 2 Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Collected Works of Arthur Schopenhauer: The Complete Works PergamonMedia Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsReligion Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe World as Will and Representation or Idea III Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsEssays Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5On the Suffering of the World Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The World as Will and Idea - Vol. II. Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Related to The Art of Being Right
Related ebooks
On the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Sufficient Reason, and on the Will in Nature - Two Essays Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Art Of Rhetoric Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Rules of Persuasion: How the World’s Greatest Communicators Convince, Inspire, Lead—and, Sometimes, Deceive Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMeditations Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsCrystallizing Public Opinion Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Win an Argument: An Ancient Guide to the Art of Persuasion Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5What Would Machiavelli Do?: The Ends Justify the Meanness Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Always Being Right: The 38 Subtle Ways of Persuation Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Wealth of Nations Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsStrategy Six Pack: Six Essential Texts Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5The Republic Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsWinning the Room: Public Speaking Skills for Unforgettable Storytelling Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Prince Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5THE ART OF WORDLY WISDOM - Gracian Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Art of Worldly Wisdom Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Twilight of the Idols Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Socratic Method: A Practitioner's Handbook Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Politics: A Treatise on Government Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThus Spake Zarathustra Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Thinking Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Treatise of Human Nature Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Machiavellian Management: A Chief Executive's Guide Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsEthics in Service Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsLeviathan Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Poetry of Robert Greene: 'He is dead, at this her sorowes were so sore: And so she wept that she could speake no more'' Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSummary of Dan Davies's Lying for Money Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOn the Genealogy of Morals Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Quotable Machiavelli Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Art of Logical Thinking or the Laws of Reasoning Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Negotiating with Giants: Get what you want against the odds Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Classics For You
Flowers for Algernon Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Fellowship Of The Ring: Being the First Part of The Lord of the Rings Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Color Purple Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Things They Carried Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Silmarillion Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Rebecca Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Farewell to Arms Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Dune Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Confederacy of Dunces Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Poisonwood Bible: A Novel Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Count of Monte Cristo Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Wuthering Heights (with an Introduction by Mary Augusta Ward) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Odyssey: (The Stephen Mitchell Translation) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5We Have Always Lived in the Castle Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Old Man and the Sea: The Hemingway Library Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Master & Margarita Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Mythos Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Ulysses: With linked Table of Contents Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Jungle: A Novel Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Princess Bride: S. Morgenstern's Classic Tale of True Love and High Adventure Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Jonathan Livingston Seagull: The New Complete Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sense and Sensibility (Centaur Classics) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/520000 Leagues Under the Sea Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Count of Monte Cristo (abridged) (Barnes & Noble Classics Series) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Count of Monte-Cristo English and French Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5For Whom the Bell Tolls: The Hemingway Library Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Bell Jar: A Novel Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Little Women (Seasons Edition -- Winter) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Republic by Plato Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Canterbury Tales Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Related categories
Reviews for The Art of Being Right
1 rating0 reviews
Book preview
The Art of Being Right - Arthur Schopenhauer
Self-Publishing
Preliminary: Logic and Dialectic.
By the ancients, Logic and Dialectic were used as synonymous terms; although [Greek: logizesthai], to think over, to consider, to calculate,
and [Greek: dialegesthai], to converse,
are two very different things.
The name Dialectic was, as we are informed by Diogenes Laertius, first used by Plato; and in the Phaedrus, Sophist, Republic, bk. vii., and elsewhere, we find that by Dialectic he means the regular employment of the reason, and skill in the practice of it. Aristotle also uses the word in this sense; but, according to Laurentius Valla, he was the first to use Logic too in a similar way.* Dialectic, therefore, seems to be an older word than Logic. Cicero and Quintilian use the words in the same general signification.†
* He speaks of [Greek: dyscherelai logicai], that is, difficult points,
[Greek: protasis logicae aporia logicae]
† Cic. in Lucullo: Dialecticam inventam esse, veri et falsi quasi disceptatricem. Topica, c. 2: Stoici enim judicandi vias diligenter persecuti sunt, ea scientia, quam Dialecticen appellant. Quint., lib. ii., 12: Itaque haec pars dialecticae, sive illam disputatricem dicere malimus; and with him this latter word appears to be the Latin equivalent for Dialectic. (So far according to Petri Rami dialectica, Audomari Talaei praelectionibus illustrata.
1569.)
This use of the words and synonymous terms lasted through the Middle Ages into modern times; in fact, until the present day. But more recently, and in particular by Kant, Dialectic has often been employed in a bad sense, as meaning the art of sophistical controversy
; and hence Logic has been preferred, as of the two the more innocent designation. Nevertheless, both originally meant the same thing; and in the last few years they have again been recognised as synonymous.
It is a pity that the words have thus been used from of old, and that I am not quite at liberty to distinguish their meanings. Otherwise, I should have preferred to define Logic (from [Greek: logos], word
and reason,
which are inseparable) as the science of the laws of thought, that is, of the method of reason
; and Dialectic (from [Greek: dialegesthai], to converse
— and every conversation communicates either facts or opinions, that is to say, it is historical or deliberative) as the art of disputation,
in the modern sense of the word. It it clear, then, that Logic deals with a subject of a purely à priori character, separable in definition from experience, namely, the laws of thought, the process of reason or the [Greek: logos], the laws, that is, which reason follows when it is left to itself and not hindered, as in the case of solitary thought on the part of a rational being who is in no way misled. Dialectic, on the other hand, would treat of the intercourse between two rational beings who, because they are rational, ought to think in common, but who, as soon as they cease to agree like two clocks keeping exactly the same time, create a disputation, or intellectual contest. Regarded as purely rational beings, the individuals would, I say, necessarily be in agreement, and their variation springs from the difference essential to individuality; in other words, it is drawn from experience.
Logic, therefore, as the science of thought, or the science of the process of pure reason, should be capable of being constructed à priori. Dialectic, for the most part, can be constructed only à posteriori; that is to say, we may learn its rules by an experiential knowledge of the disturbance which pure thought suffers through the difference of individuality manifested in the intercourse between two rational beings, and also by acquaintance with the means which disputants adopt in order to make good against one another their own individual thought, and to show that it is pure and objective. For human nature is such that if A. and B. are engaged in thinking in common, and are communicating their opinions to one another on any subject, so long as it is not a mere fact of history, and A. perceives that B.‘s thoughts on one and the same subject are not the same as his own, he does not begin by revising his own process of thinking, so as to discover any mistake which he may have made, but he assumes that the mistake has occurred in B.‘s. In other words, man is naturally obstinate; and this quality in him is attended with certain results, treated of in the branch of knowledge which I should like to call Dialectic, but which, in order to avoid misunderstanding, I shall call Controversial or Eristical Dialectic. Accordingly, it is the branch of knowledge which treats of the obstinacy natural to man. Eristic is only a harsher name for the same thing.
Controversial Dialectic is the art of disputing, and of disputing in such a way as to hold one’s own, whether one is in the right or the wrong — per fas et nefas.* A man may be objectively in the right, and nevertheless in the eyes of bystanders, and sometimes in his own, he may come off worst. For example, I may advance a proof of some assertion, and my adversary may refute the proof, and thus appear to have refuted the assertion, for which there may, nevertheless, be other proofs. In this case, of course, my adversary and I change places: he comes off best, although, as a matter of fact, he is in the wrong.
* According to Diogenes Laertius, v., 28, Aristotle put Rhetoric and Dialectic together, as aiming at persuasion, [Greek: to pithanon]; and Analytic and Philosophy as aiming at truth. Aristotle does, indeed, distinguish between (1) Logic, or Analytic, as the theory or method of arriving at true or apodeictic conclusions; and (2) Dialectic as the method of arriving at conclusions that are accepted or pass current as true, [Greek: endoxa] probabilia; conclusions in regard to which it is not taken for granted that they are false, and also not taken for granted that they are true in themselves, since that is not the point. What is this but the art of being in the right, whether one has any reason for being so or not, in other words, the art of attaining the appearance of truth, regardless of its substance? That is, then, as I put it above.
Aristotle divides all conclusions into logical and dialectical, in the manner described, and then into eristical. (3) Eristic is the method by which the form of the conclusion is correct, but the premisses, the materials from which it is drawn, are not true, but only appear to be true. Finally (4) Sophistic is the method in which the form of the conclusion is false, although it seems correct. These three last properly belong to the art of Controversial Dialectic, as they have no objective truth in view, but only the appearance of it, and pay no regard to truth itself; that is to say, they aim at victory. Aristotle’s book on Sophistic Conclusions was edited apart from the others, and at a later date. It was the last book of his Dialectic.
If the reader asks how this is, I reply that it is simply the natural baseness of human nature. If human nature were not base, but thoroughly honourable, we should in every debate have no other aim than the discovery of truth; we should not in the least care whether the truth proved to be in favour of the opinion which we had begun by expressing, or of the opinion of our adversary. That we should regard as a matter of no moment, or, at any rate, of very secondary consequence; but, as things are, it is the main concern. Our innate vanity, which is particularly sensitive in reference to our intellectual powers, will not suffer us to allow that our first position was wrong and our adversary’s right. The way out of this difficulty would be simply to take the trouble always to form a correct judgment. For this a man would have to think before he spoke. But, with most men, innate vanity is accompanied by loquacity and innate dishonesty. They speak before they think; and even though they may afterwards perceive that they are wrong, and that what they assert is false, they want it to seem the contrary. The interest in truth, which may be presumed to have been their only motive when they stated the proposition alleged to be true, now gives way to the interests of vanity: and so, for the sake of vanity, what is true must seem false, and what is false must seem true.
However, this very dishonesty, this persistence in a proposition which seems false even to ourselves, has something to be said for it. It often happens that we begin with the firm conviction of the truth of our statement; but our opponent’s