Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

From $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Social Systems Engineering: The Design of Complexity
Social Systems Engineering: The Design of Complexity
Social Systems Engineering: The Design of Complexity
Ebook693 pages7 hours

Social Systems Engineering: The Design of Complexity

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Uniquely reflects an engineering view to social systems in a wide variety of contexts of application

Social Systems Engineering: The Design of Complexity brings together a wide variety of application approaches to social systems from an engineering viewpoint. The book defines a social system as any complex system formed by human beings. Focus is given to the importance of systems intervention design for specific and singular settings, the possibilities of engineering thinking and methods, the use of computational models in particular contexts, and the development of portfolios of solutions. Furthermore, this book considers both technical, human and social perspectives, which are crucial to solving complex problems.

Social Systems Engineering: The Design of Complexity provides modelling examples to explore the design aspect of social systems. Various applications are explored in a variety of areas, such as urban systems, health care systems, socio-economic systems, and environmental systems. It covers important topics such as organizational design, modelling and intervention in socio-economic systems, participatory and/or community-based modelling, application of systems engineering tools to social problems, applications of computational behavioral modeling, computational modelling and management of complexity, and more. 

  • Highlights an engineering view to social systems (as opposed to a “scientific” view) that stresses the importance of systems intervention design for specific and singular settings
  • Divulges works where the design, re-design, and transformation of social systems constitute the main aim, and where joint considerations of both technical and social perspectives are deemed important in solving social problems
  • Features an array of applied cases that illustrate the application of social systems engineering in different domains

Social Systems Engineering: The Design of Complexity is an excellent text for academics and graduate students in engineering and social science—specifically, economists, political scientists, anthropologists, and management scientists with an interest in finding systematic ways to intervene and improve social systems.

LanguageEnglish
PublisherWiley
Release dateOct 25, 2017
ISBN9781118974421
Social Systems Engineering: The Design of Complexity

Related to Social Systems Engineering

Related ebooks

Mathematics For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Social Systems Engineering

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Social Systems Engineering - César García-Díaz

    Preface

    We, the editors of this volume, are trained as both engineers and social scientists, and have contrasted the two different mindsets during our careers. Since the time when we were PhD students in the social sciences, we have felt that ‘praxis’ does not have the same status as theorizing in generating knowledge, as opposed to what happens in engineering. Even the recognition of engineering knowledge as a distinctive kind of knowledge, different from scientific knowledge, seems to remain elusive for both academics and practitioners. In fact, ‘praxis’ embodies a set of differential elements from pure science. This volume is an effort to bring together elements of engineering thinking and social science into the study of social systems, and more importantly, aims to be a vehicle that emphasizes the necessity of developing practical knowledge – through its proper ways and under its own ‘validation’ criteria – to provide feasible, yet informed, paths for intervening and improving social systems; that is, systems created and driven by human beings.

    Also, through this volume we would like to make explicit the inherent link between systemic thinking and engineering knowledge through the consideration of multiple perspectives and methods. We believe that the merger of both the qualitative and quantitative worlds is essential in order to cope with the complexity of contemporary social systems. Moreover, we believe that engineering thinking, along with its tools and methods, is one of the best chances that we have for designing, redesigning and transforming the complex world of social systems.

    This project would not have been possible without the initial motivation provided by Debbie Jupe (commissioning editor at John Wiley & Sons), who was the first editor we met at the Social Simulation Conference in Warsaw (Poland), back in 2013. Debbie invited us to put our ideas in a written proposal, and encouraged us to come up with a book on engineering perspectives to social systems. Thank you Debbie for your encouragement!

    We are grateful to all the authors who contributed to this volume for their patience, commitment and understanding over the course of the many months it took to make this book a reality. We are also indebted to the Department of Industrial Engineering of Universidad de los Andes (Colombia) for their continued support and to Claudia Estévez‐Mujica, who helped us immensely in putting all the chapters together, checking inconsistencies and assembling the whole book.

    Introduction: The Why, What and How of Social Systems Engineering

    César García‐Díaz and Camilo Olaya

    The Very Idea

    The expression ‘social systems engineering’ is not new. As far as we know, its first appearance in the literature dates from the mid‐1970s. In 1975, the Proceedings of the IEEE published a special issue on social systems engineering (Chen et al., 1975). Here, Chen and colleagues referred to social systems engineering as the application of systems engineering concepts to social problems. Likewise, the special issue seemed to emphasize that the potential contribution of engineering to social issues was predominantly based on the consideration of quantitative modelling as the workhorse for intervention. Although we concur with some of these points, for us the expression ‘social systems engineering’ has a broader connotation, not meaning that we advocate exclusively for the application of engineering methods to social issues, but rather that we stand up for the consideration of design perspectives as a pivotal way to generate knowledge and transform systems. The intrinsic engineering orientation to action and transformation as its ultimate goals for improving a system, for meeting needs, for addressing successfully a specific problematic situation that someone wants to improve, etc. are emphases that this book highlights. Such goals demand the recognition of specific engineering considerations and their implications for addressing social systems. We want to emphasize the complexity of engineering ‘social’ (human) systems (as opposed to engineering mechanical systems, electrical systems, etc.), since such systems are then in fact ‘social’ (formed by purposeful actors that display agency, with diverse, clashing interests and goals) and therefore their design, redesign and transformation, unlike in other engineering domains, cannot be completely determined or planned beforehand. These designs are formal and informal, emergent, always ‘in progress’, adapting and evolving out of diverse dynamics.

    Social systems engineering has a paradoxical status. On the one hand, it is an under‐researched topic whose theoria has rarely been explored. On the other hand, it is perhaps one of the most common endeavours in society since it concerns the praxis that seeks to design, create and transform human organizations. Consequently, we need to understand what engineering thinking means, and how it relates to social systems. Steven Goldman, one of the contributors to this book, stated more than 20 years ago regarding the autonomy of engineering (as distinct from other activities such as science or arts) that ‘while engineering has a theoria, analogous to, but different from, that of the physical sciences, unlike science, engineering is quintessentially a praxis, a knowing inseparable from moral action’ (Goldman, 1991, p. 139). The recognition of engineering as an autonomous activity, independent from science (though related in many ways), seems just a recent explicit realization that can be identified with what can be called a ‘philosophy of engineering’ (Bucciarelli, 2003; Goldman, 2004; Miller, 2009; Sinclair, 1977; Van de Poel and Goldberg, 2010). Perhaps the key word to understand the autonomy of engineering is design (Goldman, 1990; Layton, 1984, 1991; Pitt, 2011b; Schmidt, 2012; Van de Poel, 2010). Engineering, being driven by design, shows a distinct rationality, as Goldman shows in Chapter 1 of this book. He characterizes engineering design as ‘compromised exactness’, since its formal apparatus delivers approximate ‘solutions’ that are subject to their context of application, which means that they are always subjective, wilful and contextual. Social systems, as belonging to the realm of artificial systems, exhibit design, which means that they are, and can be, engineered, but not in the traditional sense (Remington et al., 2012; Simon, 1996). Traditional engineering, design‐based methods, which essentially aim at control and prediction, cannot be applied to social systems due to the very nature of these systems – unlike mechanical systems, social systems do not ‘obey laws’, as Galileo imagined (Galileo Galilei, 1623), but are driven by the agency of human beings. Yet, engineering thinking can be used in several other ways, for instance for steering social systems towards a given direction, for influencing action (Pennock and Rouse, 2016), for opening new possibilities, for driving conversations among its members, for imagining different futures, for learning about the complexity that social systems entail, etc.

    Whenever engineering concerns social systems (i.e., firms, public and private organizations, urban systems, etc.) it implies the design of social artefacts and social constructions such as management structures, incentive schemes, routines, procedures, ways of working (formal and informal, planned and spontaneous), agreements, contracts, policies, roles and discourses, among others (Jelinek et al., 2008; March and Vogus, 2010). Therefore, such types of engineering face a special type of complexity, since these artefacts depend on and are constructed through human action, meaning that not only individuals but also their emotions, language and meanings are involved.

    This book seeks to offer an overview of what social systems engineering entails. The reader might hasten to think that this is a mechanistic approach to social systems. However, there is no such thing as optimal design in social systems (Devins et al., 2015). In contrast, the very idea of social systems engineering, although it emphasizes action, does not necessarily rely on prediction; it is context‐dependent, iterative, builds upon different modelling perspectives and decisively aims at influencing the path of, rather than deliberatively designing, the evolving character of self‐organization of human societies. This is a starkly different approach from a purely scientific viewpoint. The book encompasses three sections that follow an intuitive inquiry in this matter. The first section deals with the very idea of what social systems engineering might be and the need for addressing the topic in its own terms. The second section samples illustrative methodologies and methods. The final section illustrates examples of the challenge of designing the complexity that results from systems created through human action.

    Epistemic Notions on the Engineering of Social Systems

    There are diverse beliefs regarding what engineering is about. Perhaps the most popular is to believe that engineering is ‘applied science’. However, this would mean assuming that ‘scientists generate new knowledge which technologists then apply’ (Layton, 1974, p. 31) and therefore would suggest that what makes an engineer an engineer, and what an engineer delivers, is (applied) scientific knowledge, instead of a different type of knowledge (Davis, 2010), which is, at best, misleading (Goldman, 2004; Hansson, 2007; Layton, 1974; McCarthy, 2010; Pitt, 2010; Van de Poel, 2010). The recognition that science and engineering stand on different epistemic grounds (Goldman, 1990; Koen, 2003; Krige, 2006; Layton, 1984, 1987, 1991; Petroski, 2010; Pitt, 2011b; Vincenti, 1990; Wise, 1985) is perhaps the first step in thinking of social systems engineering and requires a brief overview.

    If it is not ‘applied science’, what are the defining characteristics of engineering? We can start by realizing that engineering and science usually pursue different goals: scientists, first and foremost, look for systematic explanations of phenomena; engineers, on the other hand, pursue the transformation of a situation through the design of artefacts that serve as vehicles to solve problems. In short, as Petroski (2010) puts it, scientists seek to explain the world while engineers try to change it. The scientist deals primarily with the question ‘what is it?’ The engineer deals with ‘how must this situation be changed?’ and ‘what is the right action to do?’ Engineering is concerned ‘not with the necessary but with the contingent, not with how things are but with how they might be’ (Simon, 1996, p. xii). Such different missions lead to different values, norms, rules, apparatus for reasoning, considerations, type of knowledge, methods, success criteria, standards for evaluating results; in short, different epistemologies.

    Engineering knowledge is intrinsic to engineering and different from scientific knowledge. Engineering know‐how is a distinctive type of knowledge, different from the scientific know‐that (Ryle, 1945). For example, ‘engineering knowledge is practice‐generated… it is in the form of knowledge‐how to accomplish something, rather than knowledge‐that the universe operates in a particular way’ (Schmidt, 2012, p. 1162). Knowledge‐how is not concerned with the truth or falsehood of statements, ‘you cannot affirm or deny Mrs. Beeton’s recipes’ (Ryle, 1945, p. 12). Engineers know how to do things. It is a type of practical knowledge. Therefore, the resources and information to get the job done can be varied and diverse, in principle they are not rejected under any a‐priori principle, ‘resolving engineering problems regularly requires the use of less than scientifically acceptable information’ (Mitcham, 1994). The scientific ‘empirical evidence’ might be useful, but it is not a necessary requirement. Such a practical approach requires also that designs must work in real life; the effects of friction or air resistance cannot be ignored (Hansson, 2007). Since the task of the engineer is to be effective, to accomplish, then mathematical precision and analytical solutions are not required. Unlike the scientist, the engineer does not assume ideal conditions, s/he knows what to do in imperfect situations.

    Engineers address practical problems: their know‐how is constructed contingently and for very specific contexts (McCarthy, 2010). Engineering deals with particulars in its particularity, they are not taken as instantiations of a universal (Goldman, 1990). This implies that engineering design faces a variety of constraints related to idiosyncratic values and factors (economic, cultural, political, reliability, viability, ethical) that co‐define and specify the design problem, unlike scientific research in which such constraints are absent in the definition of a scientific question (Kroes, 2012). This singularity of each design problem explains why there is no unique solution for an engineering problem: ‘an engineer who understands engineering will never claim to have found the solution… This is why there are so many different‐looking airplanes and automobiles and why they operate differently… they are simply one engineer’s solution to a problem that has no unique solution’ (Petroski, 2010, p. 54). Moreover, there is usually more than one way to solve an engineering problem. Such diversity of possibilities, methods and solutions contrasts with the goal of scientific communities that typically pursue the one best theory, at any given time, for explaining a phenomenon; when a theory is shown to be erroneous, it can be replaced with a better one.

    The activity of engineering does not need epistemic justifications. The intentional creation of artefacts is done by experimental methods that are more fundamental than (and not derived from) any type of theory (Doridot, 2008). The origin of design is irrelevant, it does not necessarily have to be a priori supported by anything, including theories or data. Design can be freely generated with the help of any procedure, sourced from reason, or guided by previous expectations – ‘theoretic’ or not (Stein and Lipton, 1989), guided with the help of a model, or just based on imagination, or instincts. ‘Empirical evidence’, or any other indirect mechanism of representing the world, is just another option, but it is not a requisite. For instance, ‘the inventor or engineer… can proceed to design machines in ignorance of the laws of motion… These machines will either be successful or not’ (Petroski, 2010, p. 54). Engineering handles a pragmatic concept of ‘truth’ (Doridot, 2008). An artefact or an engineering solution is not false or true (or closer to), simply it works or it doesn’t. If it works, engineers succeed. The popular notion of knowledge as ‘justified true belief’ means nothing in a pragmatic approach in which knowledge is unjustified. In the words of Pitt: ‘If it solves our problem, then does it matter if we fail to have a philosophical justification for using it? To adopt this attitude is to reject the primary approach to philosophical analysis of science of the major part of the twentieth century, logical positivism, and to embrace pragmatism’ (2011a, p. 173).

    We are interested in particular in the engineering of social systems. What are the implications of the recognition of such philosophy of engineering for the domain of social systems? Let us consider, for instance, that the predictive logic of scientific causal models relates to the idea that prediction is a requirement of control (Sarasvathy, 2003). A fundamental question is how much prediction, derived from causal explanations, is needed to transform a social system. Before the apparent unpredictability of the behaviour of social systems, one idea is to operate under a different logic and to drop the very idea of prediction in design, as Sarasvathy (2003) puts it. Sarasvathy (2003) claims that, in relation to endeavours of enterprise creation, a design logic highlights the fact that ‘to the extent we can control the future, we do not need to predict it’ (Sarasvathy, 2003, p. 208), implying that ‘a large part of the future actually is a product of human decision‐making’ (Sarasvathy, 2003, p. 209). And yet, the future remains uncertain. How to deal with such uncertainty of social systems? William Bulleit offers a possible answer in this book. The unpredictable and complex nature of human action means to face a special type of uncertainty that is, as Bulleit develops in Chapter 2, much larger than that found in other engineered systems. The uncertainty that engineers usually confront resembles an explorer in a jungle with unknown dangers; this explains why engineers consider as part of their design considerations, elements such as ‘safety factors’, ‘safety barriers’, ‘unforeseen factors’, etc. (Doorn and Hansson, 2011; Hansson, 2009a,b). However, unlike probabilistic risk analysis, the design of social systems deals with true uncertainty under unknown probabilities. As Hansson (2009a) pictures it, such uncertainty is unlike that which a gambler faces at the roulette wheel. Social systems represent perhaps the extreme case, whose design and maintenance requires a distinct mindset that brings together bottom‐up and top‐down solutions, along with the recognition of the adaptive nature of social systems, as Bulleit suggests.

    How to engineer problem‐solving designs in such unpredictable social systems? The recognition of adaptive and evolutionary dynamics leads us to think of the possibility of producing designs without ‘knowing’ beforehand the way in which the system to be designed or transformed ‘works’. Perhaps the main contribution of Charles Darwin is in the realm of philosophy, indicating a way to produce a design without a ‘designer’ (Ayala, 2007; Dennett, 1995; Mayr, 1995, 2001). Evolution already shows how and why the selection of blind variations explains the success of any system that adapts to changing and unknown environments (Campbell, 1987; Harford, 2011; Popper, 1972). Perhaps we must resist the apparent requisite of having knowledge beforehand for doing something. Bruce Edmonds makes an analogy in Chapter 3 that compares social systems engineering with farming. Since there is no such thing as ‘designing’ a farm, farmers instead know that they must continuously act on their farms to achieve acceptable results. Edmonds underlines that, since we are far from even having a minimal and reliable understanding of social systems, then engineers of social systems must recur to system farming. Edmonds emphasizes that traditional design‐based engineering approaches are simply not possible to be applied to social systems; a systems farming lens should rely more on experience rather than on system control, should operate iteratively rather than as a one‐time effort, and should make use of partial rather than full understanding, among other considerations.

    Yet, the notion of evolution challenges the very idea of whether humans can deliberately improve social systems. Is it possible to control, manage or at least direct an evolutionary process? Martin Schaffernicht deals with this question in Chapter 4. Like Edmonds, Schaffernicht questions whether deliberate social system designs can actually be made and if they can really be translated into improvement. Schaffernicht rather suggests that engineering can contribute to influence the pace of the evolutionary nature of social systems through policy engineering. He underlines that collective policies are evolving artefacts that drive behaviours – they are never definitive but in constant revision and adaptation – and become the central elements for developing an interplay between evolution and engineering that ends up shaping open‐ended social systems.

    These brief ideas indicate the immense challenge in ‘engineering’ (designing and redesigning, that is) social systems, or as put by Vincent Ostrom, it means a problem of ‘substantial proportions… In Hobbes’s words, human beings are both the matter and the artificers of organizations. Human beings both design and create organizations as artifacts and themselves form the primary ingredient of organizations. Organizations are, thus, artifacts that contain their own artisans’ (Ostrom, 1980, p. 310). Human beings co‐design the social systems that they form, this is why those designs might be intentional up to some point but they are also emergent, dynamic, incomplete, unpredictable, self‐organizing, evolutionary and always ‘in the making’ (Bauer and Herder, 2009; Garud et al., 2006, 2008; Kroes, 2012; Krohs, 2008; Ostrom, 1980). The ultimate challenge is to address the complexity posed by the relations between human beings. Joseph Pitt illustrates this concern with a concrete example: what does it mean to be a friend of someone? This question will lead us to challenge the very possibility of designing a social system. In Chapter 5, Pitt suggests that we can only design an environment in which a social system emerges and evolves, a suggestion that is in line with the first part of this book that calls for the need to recognize the experimental, evolving and open‐ended nature of social systems. This is the first requisite for anyone aspiring to transform a social system.

    Using Engineering Methods

    How to engineer social systems? The second part of this book introduces different methods for engineering social systems. Engineers proceed in a distinctive way. Billy Vaughn Koen in his book The Discussion of the Method (2003) defines engineering by its method. For him, the engineering method is any ‘strategy for causing the best change in a poorly understood situation with the available resources’ (p. 7). Engineers call such strategies ‘heuristics’. ‘A heuristic is anything that provides a plausible aid or direction in the solution of a problem but is in the final analysis unjustified, incapable of justification, and potentially fallible’ (Koen, 2010, p. 314). Koen highlights the distinctive nature of heuristics as opposed to other ways of facing the world; in particular, he considers the differences from scientific theories. A heuristic does not guarantee a solution, it may contradict other heuristics (Koen 2009); it does not need justification, its relevance depends on the particular situation that the heuristic deals with and its outcome is a matter of neither ‘truth’ nor generalizability. The engineering method – as opposed to the scientific method – is a heuristic; that is, unjustified, fallible, uncertain, context‐defined and problem‐oriented. Hence, the second part of this book can be seen as a small sample of heuristics that in particular share a common preferred strategy of engineers: modelling.

    Engineering design requires the capacity to ‘see’ and imagine possible (both successful and unsuccessful) futures. Zhongyuan Yu and her colleagues show in Chapter 6 how policy flight simulators may help to address ‘what if…’ questions through model‐based interactive visualizations that enable policy‐makers to make decisions and anticipate their consequences. Policy flight simulators drive the exploration of management policies according to possible factors that contribute to an existing or potential state of a system. Through two detailed cases, the chapter shows how such simulators can be developed and how groups of people (rather than individuals) interact with them. These interactions are the central piece of the method, since the involved stakeholders and policy‐makers bring conflicting priorities and diverse preferences for courses of action. The chapter illustrates with practical cases the mentioned idea of Schaffernicht: the centrality of the evolution of ‘collective policies’ for transforming social systems and the way in which such evolution can be enhanced through learning. Yu and her colleagues underline that the key value of their models and visualizations lies in the insights that they provide to those intending to engineer their own social systems.

    Models are powerful tools for supporting design activities (Dillon, 2012; Dodgson et al., 2007; Elms and Brown, 2012; Will, 1991). Unlike scientific models that are usually built for analysis of observations and generating ‘true’ explanations (Norström, 2013), engineering models are judged against their usefulness for specific, diverse (Epstein, 2008) purposes. For engineers, they serve as focal points ‘for a story or conversation about how a system behaves and how that behaviour can be changed. It is by mediating in this process – acting to focus language by stressing some features of the real system while ignoring others – that models contribute to new shared understandings in a community of engineering practice’ (Bissell and Dillon, 2012, p. vi). Chapter 7 by Peer‐Olaf Siebers and colleagues introduces a structured framework for guiding such conversation processes through model development, from conceptual design to implementation. In particular, this framework organizes both the process of building and using agent‐based models and the way in which the resulting simulation models can be used as decision‐support tools for exploring the application of policies. Being a heuristic, they adapt what they consider appropriate for developing their framework; in particular, they borrow ideas from software engineering for tackling problem analysis and model design. The chapter uses international peacebuilding activities in South Sudan as an example to illustrate the practical possibilities of their proposal.

    There are diverse ways of building models. Sandra Méndez‐Fajardo and colleagues show, in Chapter 8, how social systems engineering can employ (social) science through a methodological framework that uses actor‐network theory as a heuristic for designing and building agent‐based models. They use an applied case in waste of electrical and electronic equipment management as an illustrative example. Their proposal presents a way to overcome the distinction between human and non‐human actors, and underlines the centrality of ‘actor‐networks’ (rather than just actors) in social systems. Although these theoretic contributions stand on their own as valuable results, they unmistakably underline the engineering character of their proposal, which concerns the pragmatic usefulness of modelling rather than its theoretical validity. They frame the application of actor‐network theory as a heuristic for intervening social systems through the use of simulation models to enact policy changes.

    Engineering may use scientific theories but may also contribute to science. Computational modelling can complement diverse theoretic approaches, for instance it is useful for supporting theory building in social science (e.g., Schwaninger and Grösser, 2008). To complete the second part of the book, in Chapter 9 Russell Thomas and John Gero use social theory to explore the process of institutional innovation and how to influence innovation trajectories in pre‐paradigmatic settings (which the authors call ‘contested territories’), where there are rival worldviews regarding the nature of problems and innovations. The authors illustrate their methodological approach with the case of cyber security and the problem of quantifying security and risk under two rival worldviews: the ‘quants’ (for whom cyber security and risk can and should be quantified) and the ‘non‐quants’ (who believe that cyber security and risk either cannot be quantified or its quantification does not bring enough benefits). The chapter frames the process of institutional innovation in Boisot’s theory of the social learning cycle and the role of knowledge artefacts during the cycle. A computational model helps to explore how knowledge artefacts of different characteristics affect innovation rate and learning. The chapter makes provocative suggestions regarding not only how social science can contribute to social systems engineering but also the other way around: how this latter approach can contribute to deal with scientific questions, such as the assessment of the scientific merit of each school of thought (in terms of explanatory coherence) and the possibility of addressing further theoretic issues of social dynamics such as legitimization, power struggles and structuration, among others.

    Into Real‐World Applications

    Since social systems engineering is praxis, then real‐world applications become perhaps the true way to depict this type of engineering. The last part of the book places the emphasis on practical applications that illustrate the richness and possibilities that the first two parts suggest.

    Chapter 10 by Adam Douglas Henry and Heike Brugger deals with developing strategic scenarios for the adoption of environmentally friendly technologies. Through agent‐based computational modelling, they inspect non‐trivial policy answers to two simultaneously desirable outcomes regarding sustainable technologies: the speed of their adoption and the guarantee of equal access to them. Chapter 11 by Clifford‐Holmes and colleagues combines ethnographic data collection with participatory system dynamics modelling in the design of potential strategies in water resource management in South Africa. Clifford‐Holmes and colleagues emphasize the ‘muddled middle’ between policy and implementation, and propose new directions in participatory modelling. In Chapter 12 Markus Schwaninger and Johann Klocker provide an account of the 30‐year evolution of the oncological care system in Klagenfurt, Austria, exposing the threat of organizational over‐specialization in patient treatment and highlighting the importance of holistic approaches to healthcare system design by using causal loop diagrams and organizational cybernetic concepts. Last but not least, in Chapter 13 Jenny O’Connor and colleagues explore four case studies of smart city projects in the United Kingdom and highlight the importance of understanding the unpredictability of individual and societal behaviour when confronted with new sustainable‐related policies derived from technical aspects only. O’Connor and colleagues explicitly call for the inclusion of the social dimension in the engineering of social systems.

    In summary, social systems engineering goes beyond the application of engineering methods to social problems. In different instances there has been a tendency to equate engineering a social system with a traditional, mechanistic, one‐shot undertaking that attempts to reach optimality according to some well‐pre‐established objective (Devins et al., 2015). That is not what social systems engineering is about. In contrast, we aim to highlight the importance of trial and error, failure, iteration, adaptability and evolution as salient features of any design‐oriented process. Stimulating self‐organization (as opposed to direct intervention) as a way to foster growth of desirable properties (e.g., adaptability and resilience) is also intrinsic to any design‐oriented endeavour. Engineering a social system implies ‘steering’ a system towards a desirable state (Penn et al., 2013), even if such a state is not completely understood and is subject to different interpretations (e.g., a sustainable community), and even if the journey towards it is filled with unexpected occurrences. We hope that this book will provide a broader, multidisciplinary, conceptual approach to social systems design, and stimulate the growth of ideas towards solution‐oriented perspectives (Watts, 2017) in dealing with social systems issues.

    References

    Ayala, F.J. (2007) Darwin's greatest discovery: Design without designer. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 104(1), 8567–8573.

    Bauer, J.M. and Herder, P.M. (2009) Designing socio‐technical systems, in A. Meijers (ed.), Philosophy of Technology and Engineering Sciences, North Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 602–630.

    Bissell, C. and Dillon, C. (2012) Preface, in C. Bissell and C. Dillon (eds), Ways of Thinking, Ways of Seeing. Mathematical and other modelling in engineering and technology (Vol. 1), Springer‐Verlag, Berlin, pp. v–vii.

    Bucciarelli, L. (2003) Engineering Philosophy, Delft University Press, Delft.

    Campbell, D.T. (1987) Evolutionary epistemology, in G. Radnitzky and W.W. Bartley III (eds), Evolutionary Epistemology, Rationality, and the Sociology of Knowledge, Open Court, La Salle, IL, pp. 47–73.

    Chen, K., Ghaussi, M. and Sage, A.P. (1975) Social systems engineering: An introduction. Proceedings of the IEEE, 63(3), 340–344.

    Davis, M. (2010) Distinguishing architects from engineers: A pilot study in differences between engineers and other technologists, in I. Van de Poel and D.E. Goldberg (eds), Philosophy and Engineering. An emerging agenda, Springer‐Verlag, Dordrecht, pp. 15–30.

    Dennett, D.C. (1995) Darwin's Dangerous Idea, Penguin Books, London.

    Devins, C., Koppl, R., Kauffman, S. and Felin, T. (2015) Against design. Arizona State Law Journal, 47, 609.

    Dillon, C. (2012) Models: What do engineers see in them?, in C. Bissell and C. Dillon (eds), Ways of Thinking, Ways of Seeing. Mathematical and other modelling in engineering and technology (Vol. 1), Springer‐Verlag, Berlin, pp. 47–69.

    Dodgson, M., Gann, D.M. and Salter, A. (2007) The impact of modelling and simulation technology on engineering problem solving. Technology Analysis & Strategic Management, 19(4), 471–489.

    Doorn, N. and Hansson, S.O. (2011) Should probabilistic design replace safety factors? Philosophy & Technology, 24, 151–168.

    Doridot, F. (2008) Towards an 'engineered epistemology'? Interdisciplinary Science Reviews, 33(3), 254–262.

    Elms, D.G. and Brown, C.B. (2012) Professional decisions: The central role of models. Civil Engineering and Environmental Systems, 29(3), 165–175.

    Epstein, J.M. (2008) Why model? Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Simulation, 11(4), 12.

    Galileo Galilei (1623) The assayer, in S. Drake (ed.), Discoveries and Opinions of Galileo (trans. S. Drake 1957), Anchor Books, New York, NY.

    Garud, R., Kumaraswamy, A. and Sambamurthy, V. (2006) Emergent by design: Performance and transformation at Infosys Technologies. Organization Science, 17(2), 277–286.

    Garud, R., Jain, S. and Tuertscher, P. (2008) Incomplete by design and designing for incompleteness. Organization Studies, 29(3), 351–371.

    Goldman, S.L. (1990) Philosophy, engineering, and western culture, in P.T. Durbin (ed.), Broad and Narrow Interpretations of Philosophy of Technology, Kluwer, Amsterdam, pp. 125–152.

    Goldman, S.L. (1991) The social captivity of engineering, in P.T. Durbin (ed.), Critical Perspectives on Nonacademic Science and Engineering, Lehigh University Press, Bethlehem, PA.

    Goldman, S.L. (2004) Why we need a philosophy of engineering: A work in progress. Interdisciplinary Science Reviews, 29(2), 163–176.

    Hansson, S.O. (2007) What is technological science? Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 38, 523–527.

    Hansson, S.O. (2009a) From the casino to the jungle. Dealing with uncertainty in technological risk management. Synthese, 168, 423–432.

    Hansson, S.O. (2009b) Risk and safety in technology, in A. Meijers (ed.), Philosophy of Technology and Engineering Sciences, North Holland, Amsterdam, pp. 1069–1102.

    Harford, T. (2011) Adapt. Why success always starts with failure, Picador, New York, NY.

    Jelinek, M., Romme, A.G.L. and Boland, R.J. (2008) Introduction to the special issue. Organization studies as a science for design: Creating collaborative artifacts and research. Organization Studies, 29(3), 317–329.

    Koen, B.V. (2003) Discussion of the Method, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Koen, B.V. (2009) The engineering method and its implications for scientific, philosophical, and universal methods. The Monist, 92(3), 357–386.

    Koen, B.V. (2010) Quo vadis, humans? engineering the survival of the human species, in I. Van de Poel and D.E. Goldberg (eds), Philosophy and Engineering. An emerging agenda, Springer‐Verlag, Dordrecht, pp. 313–341.

    Krige, J. (2006) Critical reflections on the science–technology relationship. Transactions of the Newcomen Society, 76(2), 259–269.

    Kroes, P. (2012) Engineering design, in P. Kroes (ed.), Technical Artefacts: Creations of mind and matter, Springer‐Verlag, Dordrecht, pp. 127–161.

    Krohs, U. (2008) Co‐designing social systems by designing technical artifacts, in P.E. Vermaas, P. Kroes, A. Light and S.A. Moore (eds), Philosophy and Design, Springer‐Verlag, Dordrecht, pp. 233–245.

    Layton, E.T. Jr. (1974) Technology as knowledge. Technology and Culture, 15(1), 31–41.

    Layton, E.T. Jr. (1984) Science and engineering design. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 424(1), 173–181.

    Layton, E.T. Jr. (1987) Through the looking glass, or news from lake mirror image. Technology and Culture, 28(3), 594–607.

    Layton, E.T. Jr. (1991) A historical definition of engineering, in P.T. Durbin (ed.), Critical Perspectives on Nonacademic Science and Engineering, Lehigh University Press, Bethlehem, PA, pp. 60–79.

    March, S.T. and Vogus, T.J. (2010) Design science in the management disciplines, in A. Hevner and S. Chatterjee (eds), Design Research in Information Systems, Springer‐Verlag, New York, NY, pp. 195–208.

    Mayr, E. (1995) Darwin's impact on modern thought. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 139(4), 317–325.

    Mayr, E. (2001) The philosophical foundations of Darwinism. Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, 145(4), 488–495.

    McCarthy, N. (2010) A world of things not facts, in I. Van de Poel and D.E. Goldberg (eds), Philosophy and Engineering. An emerging agenda. Springer‐Verlag, Dordrecht, pp. 265–273.

    Miller, G. (2009) London calling philosophy and engineering: WPE 2008. Science and Engineering Ethics, 15, 443–446.

    Mitcham, C. (1994) Thinking Through Technology. The path between engineering and philosophy, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL.

    Norström, P. (2013) Engineers’ non‐scientific models in technology education. International Journal of Technology and Design Education, 23(2), 377–390.

    Ostrom, V. (1980) Artishanship and artifact. Public Administration Review, 40(4), 309–317.

    Penn, A.S., Knight, C.J., Lloyd, D.J., Avitabile, D., Kok, K., Schiller, F. et al. (2013) Participatory development and analysis of a fuzzy cognitive map of the establishment of a bio‐based economy in the Humber region. PLoS ONE, 8(11), e78319.

    Pennock, M.J. and Rouse, W.B. (2016) The epistemology of enterprises. Systems Engineering, 19(1), 24–43.

    Petroski, H. (2010) The Essential Engineer. Why science alone will not solve our global problems, Vintage Books, New York, NY.

    Pitt, J.C. (2010) Philosophy, engineering, and the sciences, in I. Van de Poel and D.E. Goldberg (eds), Philosophy and Engineering. An emerging agenda, Springer‐Verlag, Dordrecht, pp. 75–82.

    Pitt, J.C. (2011a) Doing Philosophy of Technology, Springer‐Verlag, Dordrecht.

    Pitt, J.C. (2011b) What engineers know, in J.C. Pitt (ed.), Doing Philosophy of Technology, Springer‐Verlag, Dordrecht, pp. 165–174.

    Popper, K. (1972) Objective Knowledge. An evolutionary approach, Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Remington, R., Boehm‐Davis, D.A. and Folk, C.L. (2012) Natural and engineered systems, in Introduction to Humans in Engineered Systems, John Wiley & Sons, Hoboken, NJ, pp. 7–13.

    Ryle, G. (1945) Knowing how and knowing that. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 46, 1–16.

    Sarasvathy, S.D. (2003) Entrepreneurship as a science of the artificial. Journal of Economic Psychology, 24(2), 203–220.

    Schmidt, J.A. (2012) What makes engineering, engineering?, in J. Carrato and J. Burns (eds), Structures Congress Proceedings, American Society of Civil Engineers, Reston, VA, pp. 1160–1168.

    Schwaninger, M. and Grösser, S. (2008) System dynamics as model‐based theory building, Systems Research and Behavioral Science, 25, 447–465.

    Simon, H.A. (1996) The Sciences of the Artificial (3rd edn), MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Sinclair, G. (1977) A call for a philosophy of engineering. Technology and Culture, 18(4), 685–689.

    Stein, E. and Lipton, P. (1989) Where guesses come from: Evolutionary epistemology and the anomaly of guided variation. Biology and Philosophy, 4, 33–56.

    Van de Poel, I. (2010) Philosophy and engineering: Setting the stage, in I. Van de Poel and D.E. Goldberg (eds), Philosophy and Engineering. An emerging agenda, Springer‐Verlag, Dordrecht, pp. 1–11.

    Van de Poel, I. and Goldberg, D.E. (2010) Philosophy and Engineering. An emerging agenda, Springer‐Verlag, Dordrecht.

    Vincenti, W.G. (1990) What Engineers Know and How They Know It, The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, MD.

    Watts, D.J. (2017) Should social science be more solution‐oriented? Nature Human Behaviour, 1, 0015.

    Will, P. (1991) Simulation and modeling in early concept design: An industrial perspective. Research in Engineering Design, 3(1), 1–13.

    Wise, G. (1985) Science and technology. Osiris, 1, 229–246.

    Part I

    Social Systems Engineering: The Very Idea

    1

    Compromised Exactness and the Rationality of Engineering

    Steven L. Goldman

    1.1 Introduction

    In the spring of 1929, on the occasion of the Gifford Lectures at Edinburgh University, John Dewey asked: ‘Are there in existence the ideas and the knowledge that permit experimental method to be effectively used in social interests and affairs?’ (Dewey, 1988, p. 218). By ‘experimental method’, Dewey meant systematic reasoning about effective means for achieving a specified end. This was problem‐solving reasoning par excellence for Dewey, because it was reasoning that was reflexively shaped by its consequences in a cognitive positive feedback loop characteristic of applied science and engineering. It was just this ‘experimental method’, Dewey argued, that by uniting the results of experiment‐validated scientific knowledge with the objectives of engineering practice had enabled the society‐ and culture‐transforming accomplishments of nineteenth‐century technological innovations. What Dewey was asking in the Gifford Lectures, then, was: Do we know enough, not in science and engineering, but about the methodologies employed in applied science and engineering, to apply those methodologies to ‘social interests and affairs’?

    Here we are, eighty‐six years later, asking the same question: Is there, in the kind of reasoning routinely employed so successfully by engineers to solve technical problems, a model for the design of more effective social systems? Do we, today, know enough about engineering practice – specifically engineering practice rather than the practice of science – to help us formulate more effective public policies, create more effective organizational structures and develop better social systems: educational systems, health‐care systems, judicial systems, financial systems, even political systems?

    A first step towards answering these questions would be clarifying the distinctiveness of engineering reasoning vis‐à‐vis scientific reasoning. This would help us to understand why it is that we ask about a model for developing better public policies and better social systems in engineering and not in science.

    A second step would be to describe the centrality to engineering reasoning of the design process, and within that process, of trade‐off decision‐making, in order to assess its transposability to the design of public policies and social systems. Even if it seems transposable in principle, however, the roles of two fundamental features of engineering practice in the reasoning underlying the design process must be taken into account, namely, its experimental and its evolutionary character.

    Of course, people have been designing and redesigning social systems, and implementing public policies, for all of recorded history, and for a long time before that. As nearly as we can tell, they did this without asking for help from the ‘engineers’ of the day, that is, from contemporary possessors of craft know‐how. What seems new in assessing social systems today is a perception on the one hand of manifest expertise in applied science and engineering and on the other hand of a problematic situation confronting humanity for which science and engineering clearly bear some responsibility: a technology‐enabled, globalized social, political and economic life causing a threatening reaction of the physical world to our science‐ and technology‐based action upon it. The distinctive re‐engineering of human being in the world that has taken place over the past 200 years has clearly contributed to this threatening situation, so, we ask, can engineering show us how to ameliorate, if not resolve, its most threatening features?

    That question will be explored here, beginning with putting the perception that science and engineering could play a role in designing new social systems into a historical context. As a matter of fact, this perception has a history, one extending back some 400 years. That it does, implies that the turn to science and/or engineering today for guidance in formulating public policies and designing social

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1