Historical materialism and the economics of Karl Marx
By C. M. Meredith and Benedetto Croce
()
Related to Historical materialism and the economics of Karl Marx
Related ebooks
Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (Second Edition Text) (Impact Books): Second Edition Text Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsCapitalism, Socialism, and Democracy: Second Edition Text Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Essential Marx Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Understanding Marx’s Capital: A reader’s guide Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsWeber: Sociologist of Empire Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsUnderstanding Capital: Marx’s Economic Theory Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Max Weber: A Critical Introduction Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Reading 'Capital' Today: Marx after 150 Years Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Moral Economists: R. H. Tawney, Karl Polanyi, E. P. Thompson, and the Critique of Capitalism Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Making of Marx's Capital Volume 1 Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Analyzing Marx: Morality, Power and History Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Law of Accumulation and Breakdown of the Capitalist System Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBeyond the Developmental State: Industrial Policy into the Twenty-first Century Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsCAPITAL (All 3 Books) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsCAPITAL (Complete 3 Volume Edition): Including The Communist Manifesto, Wage-Labour and Capital, & Wages, Price and Profit Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHistory of Communism Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsInequality and Democratic Egalitarianism: 'Marx's Economy and Beyond' and Other Essays Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGeneral Economic History Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Marx and the Alternative to Capitalism Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Marx's 'Capital' Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsCivil Society and Dictatorship in Modern German History Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Poverty of Capitalism: Economic Meltdown and the Struggle for What Comes Next Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSocialism and Modern Science (Darwin, Spencer, Marx) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFrench and German Socialism in Modern Times Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Political Economy of Development: The World Bank, Neoliberalism and Development Research Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsCorruption and Human Development in Africa Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsRebuilding Liberalism: Social Justice with Individual Freedom Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Revolution Betrayed Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Globalization in Historical Perspective Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Communist Manifesto (Diversion Classics) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Reviews for Historical materialism and the economics of Karl Marx
0 ratings0 reviews
Book preview
Historical materialism and the economics of Karl Marx - C. M. Meredith
The Project Gutenberg EBook of Historical materialism and the economics of
Karl Marx, by Benedetto Croce
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or
re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included
with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org/license
Title: Historical materialism and the economics of Karl Marx
Author: Benedetto Croce
Translator: C. M. Meredith
Release Date: May 8, 2012 [EBook #39653]
Language: English
*** START OF THIS PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK HISTORICAL MATERIALISM ***
Produced by Adrian Mastronardi and the Online Distributed
Proofreading Team at http://www.pgdp.net (This file was
produced from images generously made available by The
Internet Archive/Canadian Libraries)
Transcriber's Note:
Inconsistent hyphenation and spelling in the original document have been preserved.
Obvious typographical errors have been corrected. For a complete list, please see the
end of this document
.
HISTORICAL MATERIALISM
HISTORICAL MATERIALISM
AND THE
ECONOMICS OF KARL MARX
By BENEDETTO CROCE
TRANSLATED BY C.M. MEREDITH
With an Introduction by A.D. LINDSAY
Fellow and Lecturer of Balliol College, Oxford
LONDON: GEORGE ALLEN & UNWIN LTD.
RUSKIN HOUSE, MUSEUM STREET, W.C.
NEW YORK : : : : : : : : THE MACMILLAN CO.
First published by Howard Latimer Ltd. 1914
Transferred to George Allen & Unwin Ltd. 1915
[ALL RIGHTS RESERVED]
CONTENTS
INTRODUCTIONToC
The Essays in this volume, as will be apparent, have all of them had an occasional origin. They bear evident traces of particular controversy and contain much criticism of authors who are hardly, if at all, known in this country. Their author thought it worth while to collect them in one volume and it has been, I am sure, worth while to have them translated into English, because though written on different occasions and in different controversies they have all the same purpose. They are an attempt to make clear by philosophical criticism the real purpose and value of Marx's work.
It is often said that it is the business of philosophy to examine and criticise the assumptions of the sciences and philosophy claims that in this work it is not an unnecessary meddler stepping in where it is not wanted. For time and again for want of philosophical criticism the sciences have overstepped their bounds and produced confusion and contradiction. The distinction between the proper spheres of science and history and moral judgment is not the work of either science or history or moral judgment but can only be accomplished by philosophical reflection, and the philosopher will justify his work, if he can show the various contending parties that his distinctions will disentangle the puzzles into which they have fallen and help them to understand one another.
The present state of the controversy about the value of the writings of Karl Marx obviously calls for some such work of disentangling. No honest student can deny that his work has been of great historic importance and it is hard to believe that a book like Das Kapital which has been the inspiration of a great movement can be nothing but a tissue of false reasoning as some of its critics have affirmed. The doctrine of the economic interpretation of history has revivified and influenced almost all modern historical research. In a great part of his analysis of the nature and natural development of a capitalist society Marx has shown himself a prophet of extraordinary insight. The more debatable doctrine of the class war has at least shown the sterility of the earlier political theory which thought only in terms of the individual and his state. The wonderful vitality of the Marxian theory of labour value in spite of all the apparent refutations it has suffered at the hands of orthodox political economists is an insoluble puzzle if it had no more in it than the obvious fallacy which these refutations expose. Only a great book could become 'the Bible of the working classes.'
But the process of becoming a Bible is a fatal process. No one can read much current Marxian literature or discuss politics or economics with those who style themselves orthodox Marxians without coming to the conclusion that the spirit of ecclesiastical dogmatism daily growing weaker in its own home has been transplanted into the religion of revolutionary socialism. Many of those whose eyes have been opened to the truth as expounded by Marx seem to have been thereby granted that faith which is the faculty of believing what we should otherwise know to be untrue, and with them the economic interpretation of history is transformed into a metaphysical dogma of deterministic materialism. The philosopher naturally finds a stumbling-block in a doctrine which is proclaimed but not argued. The historian however grateful he may be for the light which economic interpretation has given him, is up in arms against a theory which denies the individuality and uniqueness of history and reduces it to an automatic repetition of abstract formulæ. The politician when he is told of the universal nature of the class war points triumphantly to the fact that it is a war which those who should be the chief combatants are slow to recognise or we should not find the working classes more ready to vote for a Liberal or a Conservative than for a Socialist. The Socialist must on consideration become impatient with a doctrine that by its fatalistic determinism makes all effort unnecessary. If Socialism must come inevitably by the automatic working out of economic law, why all this striving to bring it about? The answer that political efforts can make no difference, but may bring about the revolution sooner, is too transparently inadequate a solution of the difficulty to deceive anyone for long. Lastly the economist can hardly tolerate a theory of value that seems to ignore entirely the law of supply and demand, and concludes with some justice that either the theory of labour value is nonsense or that Marx was talking about something quite apart in its nature from the value which economics discusses. All these objections are continually being made to Marxianism, and are met by no adequate answer. And just as the sceptical lecturer of the street corner argues that a religion which can make men believe in the story of Balaam's ass must be as nonsensical as that story, so with as little justice the academic critic or the anti-socialist politician concludes that Socialism or at least Marxianism is a tissue of nonsensical statements if these ridiculous dogmas are its fruit.
A disentangler of true and false in so-called Marxianism is obviously needed, and Senatore Croce is eminently fitted for the work. Much of the difficulty of Marx comes from his relation to Hegel. He was greatly influenced by and yet had reacted from Hegel's philosophy without making clear to others or possibly to himself what his final position in regard to Hegel really was. Senatore Croce is a Hegelian, but a critical one. His chief criticism of Hegel is that his philosophy tends to obscure the individuality and uniqueness of history, and Croce seeks to avoid that obscurity by distinguishing clearly the methods of history, of science and of philosophy. He holds that all science deals with abstractions, with what he has elsewhere called pseudo-concepts. These abstractions have no real existence, and it is fatal to confuse the system of abstraction which science builds up with the concrete living reality. 'All scientific laws are abstract laws,' as he says in one of these essays, (III p. 57), 'and there is no bridge over which to pass from the concrete to the abstract; just because the abstract is not a reality but a form of thought, one of our, so to speak, abbreviated ways of thinking. And although a knowledge of the laws may light up our perception of reality, it cannot become that perception itself.'
The application to the doctrine of historic materialism is obvious. It calls attention to one of the factors of the historical process, the economic. This factor it quite rightly treats in abstraction and isolation. A knowledge of the laws of economic forces so obtained may 'light up our perception' of the real historical process, but only darkness and confusion can result from mistaking the abstraction for reality and from the production of those a priori histories of the stages of civilisation or the development of the family which have discredited Marxianism in the eyes of historians. In the first essay and the third part of the third Croce explains this distinction between economic science and history and their proper relation to one another. The second essay reinforces the distinction by criticism of another attempt to construct a science which shall take the place of history. A science in the strict sense history is not and never can be.
Once this is clearly understood it is possible to appreciate the services rendered to history by Marx. For Croce holds that economics is a real science. The economic factors in history can be isolated and treated by themselves. Without such isolated treatment they cannot be understood, and if they are not understood, our view of history is bound to be unnecessarily narrow and onesided. On the relative importance of the economic and the political and the religious factors in history he has nothing to say. There is no a priori answer to the question whether any school of writers has unduly diminished or exaggerated the importance of any one of these factors. Their importance has varied at different times, and can at any time only be estimated empirically. It remains a service of great value to have distinguished a factor of such importance which had been previously neglected.
If then the economic factor in history should be isolated and treated separately, how is it to be distinguished? For it is essential to Croce's view of science that each science has its own concepts which can be distinguished clearly from those of other sciences. This question is discussed in Essay III Q. 5 and more specifically in Essay VI. Croce is specially anxious to distinguish between the spheres of economics and ethics. Much confusion has been caused in political economy in the past by the assumption that economics takes for granted that men behave egoistically, i.e. in an immoral way. As a result of this assumption men have had to choose between the condemnation of economics or of mankind. The believer in humanity has been full of denunciation of that monstrosity the economic man, while the thorough-going believer in economics has assumed that the success of the economic interpretation of history proves that men are always selfish. The only alternative view seemed to be the rather cynical compromise that though men were sometimes unselfish, their actions were so prevailingly selfish that for political purposes the unselfish actions might be ignored. Croce insists, and surely with justice, that economic actions are not moral or immoral, but in so far as they are economic, nonmoral. The moral worth of actions cannot be determined by their success or failure in giving men satisfaction.