A Country I Do Not Recognize: The Legal Assault on American Values
5/5
()
About this ebook
Robert H. Bork
Robert H. Bork has served as Solicitor General and Acting Attorney General of the United States, and as a United States Court of Appeals judge. A former professor of law at Yale Law School, he is currently a professor at Ave Maria School of Law, a Senior Fellow at the American Enterprise Institute, and the Tad and Dianne Taube Distinguished Visiting Fellow at the Hoover Institution. Also the author of the bestselling The Tempting of America, he lives with his wife in McLean, Virginia.
Read more from Robert H. Bork
Slouching Towards Gomorrah: Modern Liberalism and American Decline Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Tempting of America Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Idols for Destruction: The Conflict of Christian Faith and American Culture Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Time to Speak: Selected Writings and Arguments Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Antitrust Paradox: A Policy at War With Itself Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Related to A Country I Do Not Recognize
Related ebooks
The Federalist Society: How Conservatives Took the Law Back from Liberals Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Federalist Papers: The Ideas that Forged the American Constitution Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOriginalism: A Quarter-Century of Debate Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsRehnquist: A Personal Portrait of the Distinguished Chief Justice of the United States Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Critical Legal Studies Movement: Another Time, A Greater Task Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Our Republican Constitution: Securing the Liberty and Sovereignty of We the People Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Barry Goldwater: The Biography of a Conservative Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Federalist Papers Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Heritage Guide to the Constitution: Fully Revised Second Edition Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Rights of Man Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe American Republic : constitution, tendencies and destiny Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsConfrontational Politics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsClarence Thomas and the Lost Constitution Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Return of George Sutherland: Restoring a Jurisprudence of Natural Rights Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA Constitutional History of Secession Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsReligion in America: A Political History Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMere Natural Law: Originalism and the Anchoring Truths of the Constitution Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsReflections on the Revolution in France Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Judge as Political Theorist: Contemporary Constitutional Review Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIn Defense of Andrew Jackson Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Commentaries on the Laws of England, Volume 2: A Facsimile of the First Edition of 1765-1769 Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Conscience of the Constitution: The Declaration of Independence and the Right to Liberty Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsWilliam F. Buckley: A Biography of a Conservative American Icon and the Founder of National Review Magazine Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Commentaries on the Laws of England, Volume 4: A Facsimile of the First Edition of 1765-1769 Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5William F. Buckley Jr.: The Maker of a Movement Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The South Was Right! A New Edition for the 21st Century Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Ninth Amendment: Key to Understanding the Bill of Rights Rating: 1 out of 5 stars1/5
Politics For You
On Tyranny: Twenty Lessons from the Twentieth Century Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Cult of Trump: A Leading Cult Expert Explains How the President Uses Mind Control Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Devil's Chessboard: Allen Dulles, the CIA, and the Rise of America's Secret Government Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Unhumans: The Secret History of Communist Revolutions (and How to Crush Them) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Republic by Plato Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A People's History of the United States Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Capitalism and Freedom Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Real Anthony Fauci: Bill Gates, Big Pharma, and the Global War on Democracy and Public Health Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Fear: Trump in the White House Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Gaza in Crisis: Reflections on the U.S.-Israeli War on the Palestinians Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Parasitic Mind: How Infectious Ideas Are Killing Common Sense Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Government Gangsters: The Deep State, the Truth, and the Battle for Our Democracy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Great Awakening: Defeating the Globalists and Launching the Next Great Renaissance Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5On Palestine Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Son of Hamas: A Gripping Account of Terror, Betrayal, Political Intrigue, and Unthinkable Choices Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The U.S. Constitution with The Declaration of Independence and The Articles of Confederation Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Strange Death of Europe: Immigration, Identity, Islam Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Be an Antiracist Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Gulag Archipelago [Volume 1]: An Experiment in Literary Investigation Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Hide an Empire: A History of the Greater United States Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Souls of Black Folk: Original Classic Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Madness of Crowds: Gender, Race and Identity Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Ever Wonder Why?: And Other Controversial Essays Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Closing of the American Mind Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Freedom Is a Constant Struggle: Ferguson, Palestine, and the Foundations of a Movement Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Killing the SS: The Hunt for the Worst War Criminals in History Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Daily Stoic: A Daily Journal On Meditation, Stoicism, Wisdom and Philosophy to Improve Your Life Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5This Is How They Tell Me the World Ends: The Cyberweapons Arms Race Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Reviews for A Country I Do Not Recognize
3 ratings1 review
- Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Of all the manifold aspects of cultural decay, one of the most difficult to recognize is the corruption of constitutional law. When one thinks of the Supreme Court, or even of the judiciary overall, the image that comes to mind is a procession of old, graying men in black robes, blowing their noses into crusty handkerchiefs as they read dusty legal tomes. They sit on their lofty benches, refusing to budge from ancient precedent and the letter of the law. Humorless curmudgeons, they are capable of mercy only if the accused implores them, crying his eyes out in the process.Of course, nothing could be further from the truth. The persistence of this myth is one of the reasons why so much of the population is unaware that the Supreme Court has systematically raped the Anglo-American legal tradition as expressed in the Constitution. The Court, along with its enablers in the government, the media, and the law schools, has helped pave the way for the politically-correct, socialist nightmare that is now staring us in the face.If anyone understands this phenomenon down to its minutest details, it is Robert Bork, one of the world's most eminent and erudite legal scholars. In 2005, Bork assembled half a dozen articles on the subject from various authors (including himself) and published them in "A Country I Do Not Recognize: The Legal Assault on American Values." The title of the book is taken from a dissenting opinion written by Justice Antonin Scalia in 1996:"What secret knowledge, one must wonder, is breathed into lawyers when they become Justices of this Court, that enables them to discern that a practice which the text of the Constitution does not clearly proscribe, and which our people have regarded as constitutional for 200 years, is in fact unconstitutional?...Day by day, case by case, [the Court:] is busy designing a Constitution for a country I do not recognize."The crux of the matter, from a strictly legal point of view, is the invention by the Court of rights that do not exist in the Constitution. Emblematic is the "right to privacy," which has been used to disqualify virtually any governmental limits on individual behavior. A watershed was the 1965 case Griswold v. Connecticut, involving that state's limitations on public birth-control clinics. The statute in question offended the justices' progressive spirit, but they were faced with the annoying fact that it was the product of the democratic process. After all, the law was enacted by the people of Connecticut, in the body of their state legislature.The Court invalidated the state law by inventing a "right to privacy." As the legal scholar Lino Graglia writes in his article:"The inconvenient fact that there was no relevant constitutional right [Justice William] Douglas overcame by imagining and enacting a new one, the right of 'privacy'. Although this right could not be found in the Bill of Rights itself, it could be found, Douglas explained, in the 'penumbras, formed by emanations' from Bill of Rights provisions."How the Bill of Rights has emanations, and how these emanations form penumbras, is beyond me. Then again, I never attended an Ivy League law school.The Court moaned that the Connecticut law violated "a right of privacy older than the Bill of Rights--older than our political parties, older than our school systems." This from a Court that has consistently mocked legal and moral principles precisely because they were said to be old and outdated. The irony is excruciating.Graglia draws the following conclusion:"Griswold...exemplifies Supreme Court decision making on matters of fundamental social importance on no basis other than the justices' arrogant confidence in the rightness of their policy preferences and willingness to impose them on their fellow citizens. Because this constitutes an obvious abuse of office, convention requires that they make a pro forma attempt to show that the decision follows from the Constitution. This impossible task requires the permissibility of standards of reasoning in Supreme Court opinions that would not be acceptable in a discipline that aspired to the level of intellectual respectability of astrology."Today, we take for granted the Court's interference in state law. We have been conditioned to forget one of the founding principles of the republic: that interference by Washington in the affairs of the states should be limited to extreme cases and strictly defined realms, such as national defense. It is no accident that the Tenth Amendment to the Constitution states: "The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people."The revolutionary ruling in Griswold was followed by many others, such as Roe v. Wade, that amounted to the Supreme Court installing itself as America's super-legislature, invalidating laws at will, based on nothing more than its own moral and political predilections. As Graglia puts it:"Over the past half-century the justices have chosen to make themselves the final lawmakers on most basic issues of domestic social policy in American society. These include issues literally of life and death, as in the Court's decisions on contraception, abortion, capital punishment, and assisted suicide; issues of public order, as in its decisions on criminal procedure, public demonstrations, and vagrancy control; and issues of public morality, as in its decisions on pornography and homosexuality...In essence, the Court now performs in the American system of government a role similar to that performed by the Grand Council of Ayatollahs in the Iranian system: voting takes place and representatives of the people are elected as lawmakers, but the decisions they reach on basic issues of social policy are permitted to prevail only so long as they are not disallowed by the system's highest authority."The peak of this ayatollah-ism may have been the Court's rulings in Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey (1992) and Lawrence v. Texas (2003). In Planned Parenthood, the Court formulated its infamous "mystery passage":"These matters, involving the most intimate and personal choices a person may make in a lifetime, choices central to personal dignity and autonomy, are central to the liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment. At the heart of liberty is the right to define one's own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life."In his article, Gary McDowell of the University of Richmond has this to say on the subject:"The Court insisted that lying at the heart of the idea of liberty provided in the Constitution 'is the right to define one's own concept of existence, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life.' ... The essence of self-government is the right of the people to engage in public deliberation over what is right and what is wrong and to decide how those rights and wrongs are translated into what is deemed legal and illegal. In the end, the elevation of a judicially created notion of privacy that can be used to trump nearly every conceivable collective moral judgment made by the people undermines constitutionalism in any meaningful sense."The icing on the cake was the decision in Lawrence v. Texas, in which the Court struck down state laws against homosexual sodomy. In its reasoning, the Court effectively gave carte blanche to any subjective notion of "freedom," without requiring a basis in law. As McDowell explains:"Justice Anthony Kennedy insisted that the idea of liberty in the Constitution's due process clauses is not limited to protecting individuals from 'unwarranted governmental intrusions into a dwelling or other private places' but has 'transcendent dimensions' of a more moral sort. Properly understood, this notion of liberty 'presumes an autonomy of self that includes freedom of thought, belief, expression and certain intimate conduct,' whether those are mentioned in the Constitution or not...The essence of the Constitution for Justice Kennedy and his ilk is that it falls to 'persons in every generation [to] invoke its principles in their own search for greater freedom.' Put more simply, there is nothing permanent in the Constitution, no fundamental, unalterable principles; its meaning comes only from the changing moral views of successive generations of justices."I highly recommend this readable and relatively short book, which gives a basic primer on one of the most crucial challenges facing Western civilization today. I have only touched on a sliver of the topics covered. There are fascinating discussions of affirmative action, the escalating abuse of the Fourteenth Amendment, the Court's attack on freedom of religion, the encroachment of international law and NGOs on American sovereignty, and the overlap of Supreme Court doctrine with Leftist political dogma.I leave the final word to Robert Bork:"The cases discussed in this book demonstrate that a majority of the Court is willing to make decisions for which it can offer no intelligible argument. There is, therefore, a sharp decline in intellectual honesty and integrity in the law. Perhaps worse, generations of law students are taught by their professors and by the casebooks they study that constitutional law is not an intellectual discipline but a series of political impulses...Some academics, surveying the wreckage made of constitutional law, approvingly call it postmodern jurisprudence. Postmodernism has been defined as an uneasy alliance between nihilism and left-wing politics...Those who deny moral truth frequently simultaneously take uncompromising positions on their own versions of such truth, and those positions are invariably to the left of the American center."
Book preview
A Country I Do Not Recognize - Robert H. Bork
issues.
Introduction
Robert H. Bork
What has long been true has now become obtrusively apparent: There exists a fundamental contradiction between America’s most basic ordinance, its constitutional law, and the values by which Americans have lived and wish to continue to live. That disjunction promises to become even more acute as the United States, along with Europe, moves toward the internationalization of law. Several things are to be observed about these developments. First, much constitutional law bears little or no relation to the Constitution. Second, the Supreme Court’s departures from the Constitution are driven by elites
against the express wishes of a majority of the public. The tendency of elite domination, moreover, is to press America ever more steadily toward the cultural left. Finally, though this book concentrates on the role of judges, who constitute the most powerful single force in producing these effects, politicians and bureaucrats bear a share of the responsibility.
Though there have been instances of judicial perversity throughout our history, nothing prepared us for the sustained radicalism of the Warren Court, its wholesale subordination of law to an egalitarian politics that, by deforming both the Constitution and statutes, reordered our politics and our society. Some of these changes were both constitutionally legitimate and beneficial;¹ most were not. Today’s Court, though generally more honest in interpreting statutes, is, if anything, even bolder in rewriting the Constitution to serve a cultural agenda never even remotely contemplated by the founders. This Court strikes at the basic institutions that have undergirded the moral life of American society for almost four hundred years and of the West for millennia. As John Derbyshire put it, We Americans are heading into a ‘crisis of foundations’ of our own right now. Our judicial elites, with politicians and pundits close behind, are already at work deconstructing our most fundamental institutions—marriage, the family, religion, equality under the law.
²
Courts, even with the assistance of politicians and bureaucrats, have not, of course, accomplished this deconstruction entirely on their own. They both reflect and advance a broader cultural movement that has been growing and maturing among elites, including most members of the Supreme Court, for several decades and that erupted and became full-blown in the late 1960s and early 1970s, a period commonly called the Sixties decade. What was at first a counterculture gained traction and further radicalized attitudes among elites. The Court, now downplaying the question of economic equality in favor of lifestyle
issues, came to embrace and then to celebrate group identity and radical personal autonomy in moral matters. The Court majority, to put the matter plainly, has been overtaken by political correctness. Traditional values are being jettisoned and self-government steadily whittled away. The American people have no vote on these transformations; efforts by legislatures to set limits to cultural change and to control its direction are routinely, and almost casually, thwarted.
The complaint here is not that old virtues are eroding and new values rising. Morality inevitably evolves. A society that knew only change would exist in a state of constant frenzy and would soon cease to be a society; a society whose values never altered would resemble a mausoleum. But the merits of specific changes, how far and how rapidly they should proceed, and whether any particular aspect of morality should form the basis of law, are questions of prime importance to the way we live. And these questions, according to the postulates of the American republic, are matters to be resolved primarily within families, schools, churches, and similar institutions, and only occasionally by public debate, elections, and laws that embody, however imperfectly and temporarily, the current moral consensus. What is objectionable is that, in too many instances, a natural evolution of the moral balance is blocked and a minority morality forced upon us by judicial decrees.
This judicial gnosticism was described by Justice Antonin Scalia in a dissent: What secret knowledge, one must wonder, is breathed into lawyers when they become Justices of this Court, that enables them to discern that a practice which the text of the Constitution does not clearly proscribe, and which our people have regarded as constitutional for 200 years, is in fact unconstitutional? . . . Day by day, case by case, [the Supreme Court] is busy designing a Constitution for a country I do not recognize.
³
Less far advanced, but no less objectionable, is the ongoing internationalization of law, including even the internationalization of American constitutional law. It may seem bizarre that the Constitution of the United States, written and ratified over two hundred years ago, should be interpreted with the guidance of today’s foreign court decisions and even the nonbinding resolutions of international organizations, but that does not seem at all preposterous to some of our Supreme Court justices nor to the elites to which the justices respond. The Supreme Court reporter for the New York Times remarked, approvingly, that it is not surprising that the justices have begun to see themselves as participants in a worldwide constitutional conversation.
⁴ She might more accurately have said a worldwide constitutional convention.
Most of us understand law to mean rules laid down by a legislature, court, or regulatory agency, acting within its delegated authority. When the lawgiver acts without legitimate authority, its law
is to that degree bogus, but if its order cannot be effectively resisted, it is, nonetheless, for all practical purposes, law—power without legitimacy. It is a bedrock assumption of American republicanism that authority is only legitimate when its ultimate source is either the American citizenry (acting through elected and accountable representatives) or when it follows from acceptable limitations on majority rule (federal and state constitutions enforced by judges). These are contending principles and neither should encroach systematically on the other. Judges who regularly defeat democratic outcomes without any warrant in the Constitution are justified by neither principle; they have simply enlisted on the side of the intelligentsia against the general public in our culture war.
The first three chapters of this book deal with constitutional law. Lino A. Graglia provides an overview: Rightly revered as the guarantor of our rights, the Constitution has been made, instead, the means of depriving us of our most essential right, the right of self-government. . . . The central fact as to contemporary constitutional law . . . is that it has very little to do with the Constitution.
The Court has become the ultimate law-giver on most of the basic issues of domestic social policy,
and these are the issues that determine the basic values, nature, and quality of a society.
Racial and gender equality are denied by decisions favoring affirmative action and group identity while an egregiously broad scope for personal autonomy undercuts legitimate community desires for a degree of order and morality. The undercutting takes several forms: the creation of unjustified restraints on the criminal justice system that make policing, prosecution, and punishment difficult, often inordinately delayed, and sometimes impossible; disapproval of laws reinforcing morality, particularly in sexual matters, to the detriment of marriage, families, and the traditional moral order; virulent antagonism to public displays of religion; and, in a stunning inversion of the First Amendment’s guarantee of freedom of speech, protection of the worst forms of pornography and vulgarity but approval of even prior restraints on political speech, historically the heart of the Amendment. Graglia’s comprehensive indictment is entirely justified. The contest is one between democracy and oligarchy, and for half a century the oligarchs have been winning.
Gary L. McDowell brings into focus a major doctrine of relatively recent invention—the right of privacy—that has been used by the Court to constitutionalize the sexual revolution. Originally, as McDowell shows, the right of privacy was suggested in an article co-authored by Louis Brandeis as a tort doctrine to protect people from an intrusive press. On the Court, Brandeis tried to elevate privacy to constitutional status in a dissent extolling the right to be let alone—the most comprehensive of rights and the right most valued by civilized men.
That was surely merely empty rhetoric, for, as McDowell notes, the right is utterly at odds with the very possibility of constitutional self-government.
The Court, in a 1965 opinion by Justice William O. Douglas, concocted a constitutional right to privacy
in order to strike down a Connecticut law prohibiting the use of contraceptives⁵—a law that, for obvious reasons, was applied rarely and then only against birth control clinics that advertised contraceptives. The word privacy
has such favorable connotations, however, that it has proved impossible to confine it or to convince Americans that the doctrine had little to do with privacy and everything to do with freeing judges to do whatever they want. The question, Privacy to do what?, has little resonance. It was not long before the Court began to answer that question. More laws regulating sexual morality were invalidated, and the trend reached a crescendo with the 1973 invention by the Court of a right to abortion. So solicitous has the Court been in advancing abortion rights that it has even struck down laws requiring that parents be given notice when a minor child seeks an abortion, and it has refused to allow states to ban even partial-birth abortions, which are the moral equivalent of infanticide.
One might suppose that any number of Court decisions, particularly the right to abortion invented in Roe v. Wade,⁶ would qualify as the high-water mark of judicial arrogance, but McDowell awards that distinction to the separate concurrence of Justices Sandra Day O’Connor, Anthony Kennedy, and David Souter in Planned Parenthood of Southeastern Pennsylvania v. Casey (1993),⁷ upholding a somewhat modified abortion right. What was most shocking
about that opinion, McDowell writes, was the utter disdain it reflected for the idea of popular government.
The concurrence said the Court has the authority to speak before all others for [the people’s] constitutional ideals,
and, moreover, the people’s willingness to accept what the Court tells them are their ideals is what gives legitimacy to the people as ‘a nation dedicated to the rule of law.’
Why, one might ask, must the citizens of a free republic accept what the Court tells them are their own ideals? And why is it the legitimacy of the people that is in question rather than the legitimacy of the Court? It reminds one of Bertolt Brecht’s jest: the people have lost the confidence of the government and a new people must be formed. McDowell, like Graglia, is not optimistic about the future: as history shows, there is no reason to think that the expansion of . . . judicially created right[s] has reached its limits.
Terry Eastland provides a comprehensive survey of the Supreme Court’s religion decisions under the First Amendment. Whereas much of modern constitutional jurisprudence, as Graglia and McDowell demonstrate, consists of rights conjured up out of thin air, Eastland shows that the Court has so deformed a real constitutional provision that it bears little discernible relation to anything the framers and ratifiers understood themselves to be saying.
Of the two religion clauses—the one forbidding an establishment of religion and the other guaranteeing its free exercise—it is the establishment clause that has suffered the most abuse. Both the text and the history of its adoption show conclusively that what was to be placed beyond Congress’s power was the establishment of churches on the then-familiar European model. The anti-establishment clause manifested no hostility to organized religion as such nor any intention to forbid Congress from aiding religion generally. No amount of historical demonstration of what was intended⁸ has been capable, however, of deflecting a majority of the justices from antagonism to religion. Striking down a Pennsylvania law requiring that the school day begin with a reading from the Bible and with student recitation of the Lord’s Prayer, though a student could be excused on the written request of a parent, the Court said that this breach of [constitutional] neutrality that is today a trickling stream may all too soon become a raging torrent.
⁹ Have the justices no knowledge of history? For a century and a half the Republic staggered along without the Court’s protection from the perils of religion, and the trickling stream never achieved even the status of a sluggish creek. Vibrant religion there was, but no hint of theocracy or religious war. Now, under the tutelage of the Court and the American Civil Liberties Union, religious symbols and speech must everywhere be suppressed.
If any other kind of symbolism or speech, say, advocacy of Maoism, were expunged by government as thoroughly as are manifestations of religion, cries of censorship would resound throughout the land, and the Supreme Court would without doubt find the ban unconstitutional. The effect of the Court’s consistent denigration of religion in the name of the Constitution must be to so marginalize religion in our public life as to weaken the influence of religion throughout the society. As Eastland remarks, Legal scholars agree that [the Court’s religion jurisprudence] is an intellectual mess. Unfortunately, that is not the worst that can be said about it. The truth is that the Court’s religion decisions have done serious damage to the country.
Perhaps the Court’s majority is so antagonistic to religion because religion, at least its orthodox varieties, stands in the way of the moral relativism to which the Court seems dedicated.
At the outset, I made the claim that today’s Court manifests one of the less attractive hangovers from the Sixties, that it is, in fact, enacting, in the name of the Constitution, the modern liberal agenda of political correctness. That, I believe, is indisputable, shown not only by the decisions of the Court discussed in the chapters by Graglia, McDowell, and Eastland but by a comparison of the rhetoric of the Court majority and that of the founding document of the Sixties New Left, the 1962 Port Huron Statement, a document that became the most widely circulated manifesto of the New Left.¹⁰ The Statement asserted that The goal of man and society should be . . . finding a meaning in life that is personally authentic,
and this was to be accomplished through a (largely undefined) politics of meaning.
Perhaps the first explicit statement of this attitude came in Justice Harry A. Blackmun’s dissent, joined by three other justices, in Bowers v. Hardwick, arguing that there is a constitutional right to engage in homosexual sodomy. Rejecting the view that prior cases involving the right to privacy had confined that right to the protection of the family, Blackmun wrote:
We protect those rights [associated with the family] not because they contribute, in some direct and material way, to the general public welfare, but because they form so central a part of an individual’s life. The concept of privacy embodies the moral fact that a person belongs to himself and not to others nor to society as a whole.
¹¹
Moral facts there may be, but that assuredly is not one of them. Blackmun was saying that the family has no value except as it contributes to the individual’s gratification. Presumably, when there is a gratification deficit, individuals are morally free to shed themselves of spouse, children, and parents. On this reasoning, no-fault divorce should be a constitutional right. The second sentence sweeps even more broadly. There would seem to be no moral obligation to obey any inconvenient law and, moreover, no duty owed to colleagues, neighbors, nation, society, or anyone or anything outside one’s own skin. The ultimate in psychopathology is urged on us as a constitutional right. The four-member minority did not, of course, seriously mean anything so incomprehensible, but it speaks volumes about their mood that they could utter such a sentiment, as well as about the frivolity with which they justified their position to the nation. What they did mean was that the justices would choose which obligations a person must honor and that among the least of these are laws reinforcing morality.
Blackmun’s position became constitutional law when Bowers was overruled in Lawrence v. Texas.¹² In creating a right to homosexual sodomy, Justice Kennedy’s opinion for a six-member majority, repeating language from a special concurrence earlier,¹³ stated:
These matters, involving the most intimate and personal choices a person may make in a lifetime [abortion, etc.], choices central to personal dignity and autonomy, are central to the liberty protected by the Fourteenth Amendment. At the heart of liberty is the right to define one’s own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery of human life. [emphasis added]
That is not an argument but a Sixties oration. It has no discernible intellectual content; it does not even tell us why the right to define one’s own concept of meaning
includes a right to abortion or homosexual sodomy but not a right to incest, prostitution, embezzlement, or anything else a person might regard as central to his dignity and autonomy. Nor are we informed of how we are to know what other rights will one day emerge from some person’s concept of the universe.
The chaotic mood of Lawrence seems equivalent to that which animated the student radicals who composed the Port Huron Statement. A transcendental politics, whether that dreamed at Port Huron or at the Supreme Court, cannot be satisfied by the messiness and compromises of democratic politics; nor can it be satisfied by the list of particular freedoms embodied in the Bill of Rights and the Fourteenth Amendment. Transcendence requires an overarching principle, which is what the mystery passage
tried, unsuccessfully, to articulate.
That failure was inevitable. As Lord Patrick Devlin concluded, it is not possible to set theoretical limits to the power of the State to legislate against immorality. It is not possible to settle in advance exceptions to the general rule or to define inflexibly areas of morality into which the law is in no circumstances to be allowed to enter.
¹⁴ The Court, too, finds it impossible to articulate a theoretical limit to what other branches of government may do in curbing immorality. In attempting to establish a general, comprehensive statement of limits, the mystery passage,
like Blackmun’s Bowers dissent, necessarily goes well beyond the particularized limits on governmental power set out in the actual Constitution. That is also why the Court becomes increasingly authoritarian. Citizens and their elected representatives, displaying good sense, do not want an overarching theory of freedom and its limits and know no better than the judicial philosophes how to construct one. Faced with such recalcitrance, the Court resorts to insistence that the legitimacy of the people depends upon their acceptance of the Court’s ukases. In the absence of a real theory, political correctness will have to do. The Court, like the New Left, may practice a politics of expression and self-absorption, but that does not mean the politics is innocuous. To the contrary, it does serious, lasting, and perhaps permanent damage to valuable institutions, socially stabilizing attitudes, and essential standards.
Perhaps a better understanding of what is taking place may be gained by combining the insights of Max Weber and Kenneth Minogue. Weber wrote:
The intellectual seeks in various ways . . . to endow his life with a pervasive meaning, and thus to find unity with himself, with his fellow men, and with the cosmos. . . . As a consequence, there is a growing demand that the world and the total pattern of life be subject to an order that is significant and meaningful.¹⁵
Minogue lists three variants in the intellectuals’ quest for meaning. (These developed after religion ceased to provide meaning for the intelligentsia.) The first is the idea of progress, which eventually spawned a Marxist version, and then, when communism’s promises proved disastrous, was incorporated into an alternative endeavor that abandoned the quick fix of revolution
for a more gradual course of instructing the public in proper opinions. We may call it Olympianism,
he writes,
because it is the project of an intellectual elite that believes that it enjoys superior enlightenment and that its business is to spread this benefit to those living on the lower slopes of human achievement. And just as Communism had been a political project passing itself off as the ultimate in scientific understanding, so Olympianism burrowed like a parasite into the most powerful institution of the emerging knowledge economy—the universities.¹⁶
Minogue does not discuss the role of courts, but his analysis fits well with what we observe of the behavior of the Supreme Court and its intellectual-class allies. They display a formal adherence to democracy as a rejection of all forms of traditional authority, but with no commitment to taking any serious notice of what the people actually think. Olympians instruct mortals, they do not obey them.
¹⁷
Olympians are highly suspicious of the people: democracy is the only tolerable mode of social coordination, but until the majority of people have become enlightened, it must be constrained within a framework of rights, to which Olympian legislation is constantly adding. Without these constraints, progress would be in danger from reactionary populism appealing to prejudice.
¹⁸ As predicted, the Supreme Court, which is the Olympians’ favorite legislature, is constantly inventing new rights to constrain an unenlightened majority. It is amazing to the modern lawyer that in Joseph Story’s Commentaries on the Constitution of the United States,¹⁹ written in 1833, the discussion of the first ten amendments, the