Books in Review
A Secular Age, by Charles Taylor. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 2007. 896 pp. $39.95 (cloth).
DOI: 10.1177/0090591708315144
Political Theory
Volume XX Number X
Month XXXX xx-xx
© 2008 Sage Publications
http://ptx.sagepub.com
hosted at
http://online.sagepub.com
A Secular Age sets out with the impressive ambition of explaining how
“the modern secular world emerged from and out of the more and more
rule-bound and norm-governed Reform of Latin Christendom” (pp. 741–42).
Or, with a more individualistic spin, how it became possible for many
Europeans and their cultural heirs around the world “to experience moral
fullness, to identify the locus of our highest moral capacity and inspiration,
without reference to God, but within the range of purely intra-human powers” (pp. 244–45). Taylor proposes this framing as an alternative to “subtraction stories” of modernity in which superstition and belief are understood
to have finally withered away, leaving room for modern science and
humanism to flourish uninhibited by metaphysical constraints. In place of
this well-worn narrative, he offers a tremendously rich and multifaceted
genealogy of the creation and discovery of new moral sources that comprise
what he calls “secularity 3,” which differs in significant ways both from the
retreat of religion in public life (secularity 1) and the falling off of religious
belief and practice (secularity 2). Secularity 3 refers to a modern context of
understanding in which belief and unbelief coexist uneasily, in which one
believes or refuses to believe in God, a cross-pressured condition “in which
our experience of and search for fullness occurs” (p. 19). Taylor insists that
transformative political and spiritual changes, rather than merely economic
ones, have contributed to the constitution of this modern moral order, leading him to argue that “God-forsakenness” was part of “a move from one
religious life to another, long before it came to be (mistakenly) seen by
some as a facet of the decline of religion altogether” (p. 553). This new religious life under “secularization” is thus characterized by both a continuous
destabilization and recomposition of religious forms (p. 461).
This is a magnificent book. Diverging from both mainline accounts of
secularization as well as more critical accounts exemplified in recent work
on political theologies,1 Taylor develops a third position that will contribute
to an interesting dialogue between these accounts by emphasizing the intimacies between secularism and religion, while also defending to some
extent the emergence of exclusive humanism understood as “a novel form
of moral self-understanding, not definable simply by the negation of what
preceded it” (p. 571). Taylor offers a compelling portrait of the enchanted
world before the development of the buffered self (and the abolition of the
1
2
Political Theory
porous self in favor of a humanist alternative), and a rich discussion of the
multidimensional and differential premodern modes of perceiving time. He
explains how many historical developments associated with secularization
occurred not through and out of opposition to religion but were inherent to
and deeply intertwined with developments associated with Reform within
Christianity, such as the sanctification of ordinary life as a site for the highest forms of Christian life and the exultation of the humble at the expense
of the monastic and contemplative vocations (p. 179). To cite one example
of this religious inheritance in modern secular forms, Taylor describes the
“drive to beneficence in modern humanist moral psychology” as the “historical trace” of Agape (p. 247). He concludes forcefully that the
main motor of the drive for order and disenchantment was the religious one
. . . the movements which could draw masses of people, cultivated or not, into
the slipstream of disenchantment were the religious ones, Catholic and
Protestant . . . as a result of this, the new humanism bears the mark of its origins . . . not only in being committed to goals of active, instrumental ordering of self and world; but also in the central place within it of universalism
and benevolence. (pp. 807–8, n3)
Chapter 12 offers a thought-provoking discussion of religiously defined
political identity mobilization, including the introduction of an important
new set of typologies. I particularly like the concept of “neo-Durkheimian”
polities, in which, as Taylor suggests, “God is present because it is his Design
around which society is organized,” such that British and American national
identities have been based in part on “a self-ascribed pre-eminence in realizing a certain civilizational superiority” (p. 456). The discussion of “closed
world structures” in chapter 15 is also outstanding, as are Taylor’s insights
into the parallel tensions, dilemmas, and contradictions faced by both modern forms of belief and unbelief (p. 674), which he describes provocatively
as “brothers under the skin” (p. 675). In what follows I focus on three dimensions of the argument that left me with concerns, in what is otherwise certain
to be one of the most important books published in our time.
It is because Taylor draws on such a rich historical and literary repertoire, and writes with such philosophical dexterity and generosity, that his
repeated dismissal of what he calls the “immanent counter-Enlightenment”
(chapter 10) strikes me as somewhat out of place. It seems that this dismissal is related to his (in my view reductive) construal of the transcendent/
immanent distinction such that what he identifies as the “place of fullness”
is either: (1) outside or beyond human life, the position of “religious”
transcenders, who also believe in a higher power and that our lives extend
Books in Review
3
beyond “this life” (p. 20); or (2) within human life in a variety of ways,
making “no reference to transcendent reality,” (p. 415) “without interventions from outside,” (p. 832, n.7) also described as those who, in his reading, lack faith (immanentists). Those who are “religious,” then, approach
fullness as transcendence in this particular way. Other ways of approaching the immanent-transcendent relationship fall by the wayside, with significant implications for theorists of immanence, as we shall see in a
moment. Religious faith in Taylor’s “strong sense” is defined as and by
“belief in transcendent reality” along with the “connected aspiration to a
transformation which goes beyond ordinary human flourishing” (p. 510).
So “religion,” at least in the historical European experience, is defined as,
essentially, Christianity.2
Fair enough, until you get to the implications for those who fall outside
the bounds of both “religion” and exclusive humanism. These radical theorists of immanence trouble Taylor throughout the book insofar as, in his
view, they “stress reception over against self-sufficiency; but they are views
which intend to remain immanent, and are often as hostile, if not more so,
to religion than the disengaged ones” (p. 10). These dissenting perspectives
cannot be accommodated in the “face-off” (p. 321) between conventional
forms of faith and secular humanism so richly described in this book
because they are not playing the same game—which in this case translates
to either endorsing “religion” or eschewing metaphysics altogether. Though
Taylor wrestles with the need to adjust his categories and amend the rules
of the game such that a three-way face-off between these contestants
becomes a genuine possibility, he struggles with the implications of doing
so, and fears losing hold of the intimacy between religion and secularism
that he seeks to capture. And so he never quite commits to that path.
Instead, he consigns a range of “unbelievers” to living in a “universe whose
outer limits touch nothing but absolute darkness,” in which there is
a sense of an absence; it is the sense that all order, all meaning comes from
us. We encounter no echo outside . . . a race of humans has arisen which has
managed to experience its world entirely as immanent. In some respects, we
may judge this achievement as a victory for darkness, but it is a remarkable
achievement nonetheless. (p. 376)
Although I sympathize to a degree with Taylor’s misgivings about the unreflectively anti-Christian strains of modern unbelief, I hesitate to transfer
them to all modes of believing or unbelieving (the categories themselves
become problematic here) that fall beyond the bounds of both “religion” as
he defines it and exclusive humanism. There are many such alternatives, as
4
Political Theory
Taylor readily acknowledges with his figure of the “supernova.” Yet despite
this acknowledgment, he repeatedly criticizes not only anti-Christian
polemics and tendencies in modernity, which is understandable given his
position, but also a variety of alternative modes of belief/unbelief that operate outside of and differentially in relation to the Christian categories that
animate his otherwise extraordinarily rich analysis. It is as if he is pulled so
strongly toward his version of the transcendent that what becomes defined
as most threatening are not those exclusive humanists who “close the transcendent window” (p. 638) (they are relatively easy to counter) but rather
the potential of their “nonreligious” rivals to represent an alternative to both
a philosophy of transcendence and a philosophy of radical atheism. These
radical immanentists are threatening because unlike exclusive humanists,
who share (though in a different register) Taylor’s commitment to “fullness,” the former take a very different approach to this fundamental set of
concerns. Deleuze’s transcendental empiricism comes to mind in this context, though it makes no appearance in this book; instead, a very particular
reading of Nietzsche appears to stand in for the various thinkers associated
with the immanent counter-Enlightenment. For non-Christian metaphysicians such as Deleuze, the transcendental field is differently configured; as
William Connolly notes, “it is transcendental in residing above or below
appearance, but not in being unquestionable or in authorizing a morality of
command.”3 Can the field of immanence also be “experience-far,” can it
also hold mystery, and, if so, does this not alter the calculation somewhat?
What about religious practices that experience the religious and the sacred
immanently? I would have appreciated a more nuanced engagement with
these alternatives, rather than their dismissal as “not in any sense a return
to religion or the transcendent” but as “resolutely naturalist” (p. 369).
Though open to the insights of non-Western traditions, evidenced by his
interest in Buddhism, Taylor appears less willing to open the door to alternative possibilities that emerge from within Western experience itself. It is
as if exclusive humanism is seen as the legitimate and rightful heir (through
the processes of Reform) of Christianity, whereas the immanent revolt is
shunned as “a resistance against the primacy of life, but which has abandoned these traditional sources” (p. 372). The revolt is the illegitimate offspring of Reform. It is shunned not only because it rejects outright (Taylor’s
mode of) transcendence (though this matters too), but because in equating
a diverse tradition with a particular reading of Nietzsche the revolt becomes
nearly synonymous with proclivities toward fascism and fascination with
death and violence (pp. 637–38). Condemned both politically and metaphysically, Taylor bypasses an opportunity for a fascinating engagement
between rival metaphysical positions.
Books in Review
5
A second concern involves the place of history in Taylor’s account of the
emergence of exclusive humanism. It was as if there could be no alternative, as if (as Taylor half-jokes at one point) “we might even be tempted to
say that modern unbelief is providential” (p. 637). As I was reading A
Secular Age, a bridge I had crossed hundreds of times as a child in
Minneapolis collapsed, drawing my attention to the bridge on the cover
which symbolizes the multiple, zigzag trajectories leading Europeans away
from their ancestral Christian faith(s) and into the secular age, with stops or
“ante-chambers” (p. 624) (impersonal religion, Romanticism, etc.) along the
way (the bridge metaphor appears in the discussion of Carlyle on p. 378 and
again on p. 387). Were there no historical ruptures, epistemic collapses,
breaking the tight chain of historical evolution that binds his narrative over
many centuries? Do these bridges ever collapse? Taylor comes close to
acknowledging such a rupture in his discussion of the devastating effects of
World War I on Europeans (pp. 416–19), but there persists a sense in which
his narrative comes to feel inevitable, as if one were moving inexorably
toward a destination that is a foregone conclusion. You can’t get off the
bridge. And it definitely won’t give way beneath you.
Finally there is the question of global politics, and particularly colonial
and postcolonial politics and history. A genealogy of the secular age
requires grappling not only with developments within Latin Christendom,
as Taylor undertakes so impressively, but also relations between Europe and
other societies. The West has never existed outside and above the rest of the
world but has always already included the non-Western via travel, trade,
migration, colonization, etc. A Secular Age confirms Zachary Lockman’s
observation that
exploration of how the modern West has in crucial ways been shaped, if not
constituted, by its interactions with other societies is still at an early stage and
remains vastly outweighed by the huge scholarly and popular literature that
takes for granted the West’s self-conception as a distinct and self-generated
civilization and then focuses on the West’s impact on the rest of the world.4
I have argued, for instance, that more than any other single religious or political tradition, Islam has come to represent the “nonsecular” in European and
American political discourse. Modern Euro-American traditions of secularism
have been consolidated in part through opposition to the idea of an antimodern, anti-Christian, and theocratic Islamic Middle East. Representations of
Islam as antimodern, anti-Christian, and theocratic are not a coincidental
byproduct of an inert, pregiven secular political authority—they actually help
to constitute it. Secularist political authority is produced through our
6
Political Theory
actions and beliefs, and cannot be understood absent this global perspective.5 To understand the history and significance of various European forms
of modernity at the macro level, as Taylor aspires to do, requires at least
some level of engagement with global history and politics that is missing
from this account. As Peter van der Veer, Dipesh Chakrabarty, Tomoko
Masuzawa, and others have shown,6 Europe has never existed in a vacuum;
it is rather through Europe’s historical and contemporary relations with the
rest of the world that the contested and evolving categories, modes of order,
and ways of life associated with European modernity—including modern
varieties of secularism—have taken shape. This means that Taylor’s project
calls out for an encounter on the one hand with radical immanentism and
on the other hand with Islam and other non-Christian beliefs and traditions
in their historical settings. By illustrating the intimate connections between
Christianity and humanist secularism, two worldviews normally cast as
oppositional, Taylor models how to go on to specify these fascinating connections between places, times, and worldviews that are too often assumed
to be mutually exclusive and at odds.
Notes
1. On the former Taylor cites among others the work of Steve Bruce, including Religion in
the Modern World (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996); on the latter see Hent DeVries
and Lawrence E. Sullivan, eds. Political Theologies: Public Religions in a Post-Secular World
(New York: Fordham University Press, 2006).
2. The force of this set of guiding assumptions is confirmed near the end of the book when
Taylor asserts that “in our religious lives we are responding to a transcendent reality. We all
have some sense of this, which emerges in our identifying and recognizing some mode of what
I have called fullness, and seeking to attain it. Modes of fullness recognized by exclusive
humanisms, and others that remain within the immanent frame, are therefore responding to
transcendent reality, but misrecognizing it. They are shutting out crucial features of it” (p. 768).
3. William E. Connolly, Why I Am Not a Secularist (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1999), p. 41.
4. Zachary Lockman, Contending Visions of the Middle East: The History and Politics of
Orientalism (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2004), p. 62.
5. Elizabeth Shakman Hurd, The Politics of Secularism in International Relations,
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007), chap. 3.
6. Peter van der Veer, Imperial Encounters: Religion and Modernity in India and Britain
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001); Dipesh Chakrabarty, Provincializing
Europe (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2000, 2007); Tomoko Masuzawa, The
Invention of World Religions: Or, How European Universalism Was Preserved in the Language
of Pluralism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005).
Elizabeth Shakman Hurd
Northwestern University