A union of hearts? Republican social democracy and Scottish nationalism 1
Ben Jackson
Faculty of History & University College, Oxford University
[email protected]
Published in H. Schattle and J. Nuttall (eds.), Making Social Democrats: Citizens,
Mindsets, Realities: Essays for David Marquand (Manchester University Press, 2018), pp.
161-73
The movement of opinion in favour of Scottish nationalism registered by the 2014 Scottish
independence referendum has catapulted the case for a separate Scottish state to the heart of
British political debate. Yet the resulting argument is often an unsatisfactory one, hobbled by
the readiness of both sides to impute bad faith to the other and simply to ignore the stronger
points put forward by the opposing camp. For the defenders of the Anglo-Scottish Union in
particular, a much more in-depth and forensic engagement with the ideas of Scottish
nationalism is badly needed. The advocates of Scottish independence have by necessity
already spent a long time scrutinising the case for the Union, whatever else might be said
about the quality of their political thought. By contrast, many of their opponents have not
reckoned with the fact that Scottish nationalist ideas are in fact now highly sophisticated and,
crucially, designed to resonate with important beliefs held by the broader British left. These
ideas are also too often misunderstood or even caricatured by the critics of Scottish
1
An earlier and much shorter version of this chapter was first published as my contribution to
G. Hassan, B. Jackson, A. Ramsay, and D. Torrance, ‘Roundtable on the Scottish
independence referendum: What happened and what next?’, Renewal, 23 (2015), pp. 68-71. I
am grateful to Jeremy Nuttall and Hans Schattle for their comments on a draft of the chapter.
1
nationalism, who tend to attack it as a more ethnic and nativist tradition than it actually is,
with correspondingly diminishing returns in terms of rebutting its key claims.
The main aim of this chapter is to consider how far it is possible to distinguish this
progressive strand of Scottish nationalist thinking that coalesced in the 1980s and 1990s from
the similar discourse of constitutional reform at the British level associated with movements
such as Charter 88 and their leading intellectual advocates such as David Marquand, Paul
Hirst and Will Hutton. This latter body of opinion was in the 1980s and 1990s generally
indifferent or hostile to Scottish nationalism, but it has become harder in recent years to
formulate a hard and fast distinction between them. Should those committed to a more
democratic and pluralist British constitutional settlement such as David Marquand in fact
‘logically’ favour Scottish independence as part of such wide-ranging reform?
Towards a republican social democracy
My answer to this question begins with John Mackintosh, the great Scottish Labour MP and
advocate for constitutional reform (and also a close colleague and friend of David
Marquand). On the threshold of the Donald Dewar Room of the Scottish Parliament, some
words from Mackintosh are cut into the stone. They read: ‘People in Scotland want a degree
of government for themselves. It is not beyond the wit of man to devise the institutions to
meet these demands’ (quoted in Walker, 2013, p. 557). These words were spoken by
Mackintosh during the House of Commons debate on the Scotland and Wales Act 1976, and
they express the classic case for Scottish devolution espoused by Mackintosh and indeed
Donald Dewar himself. Scots, Mackintosh famously argued, have a dual identity, partly
Scottish and partly British, and the political institutions that govern Britain should therefore
2
reflect that dual identity by creating a devolved Scottish parliament to operate within the
context of the United Kingdom.
But we should note that Mackintosh’s notion of dual identity was more complex than
this bald summary suggests. Mackintosh’s point was also that at different times one side of
Scots’ dual identity assumes greater importance than the other. In the context of the Scottish
nationalist surge of the 1970s, Mackintosh observed that the hold of Britishness had been
loosened first by the change in Britain’s status in the world after 1945 and then by the poor
performance of the British economy and government in the late 1960s and 1970s. This left
many Scots feeling that the Scottish pole of their dual identity offered a more satisfactory
expression of national pride than the British one. Ultimately, Mackintosh argued that a
successful British response to the rise of Scottish nationalism would require not just
devolution to Scotland but also a period of successful British government, one that would
give Scots the feeling that Britain was, as he put it, ‘a successful, worthwhile country to
belong to for those who do have other places where they can go and other traditions and titles
to which they can turn’ (Mackintosh, 1974; see also Mackintosh, 1982). I think there is still
something to be said for this as a reply to Scottish nationalism, although I want to reformulate
slightly Mackintosh’s prescription.
Before I turn to that, however, I will first consider why modern Scottish nationalism
presents such a searching challenge to the reforming republican social democracy that authors
such as David Marquand delineated during the 1980s and 1990s. Over the last thirty years or
so, Marquand, along with colleagues such as the late Paul Hirst and Will Hutton, have
eloquently set out the connection between a programme of constitutional reform designed to
make the British state more democratic and a programme of economic reform designed to
make the British economy more stable and socially just. They have argued that, in order to
tackle the pathologies of a short-termist, financialised British capitalism, a more open,
3
pluralist and decentralised British state and political culture will have to be nourished. The
creation of a politically durable economic model in which power is shared between labour
and capital, and resources pooled more equally between social classes, would in turn require
a new British constitution characterised by power-sharing and negotiation rather than
classical Westminster majoritarianism (see O’Neill and White, 2014, and Stuart White’s
chapter in this book, for valuable discussions of these ideas).
Marquand argued in his influential 1988 book, The Unprincipled Society, that British
economic underperformance in the post-war period could be traced to the failure of the
British state to become an effective developmental state, capable of managing the
modernisation of the British economy in the way that other leading nations had undertaken
successful state-led economic reform programmes. Marquand connected the absence of a
suitably dynamic British state to wider pathologies in British public culture and ultimately to
the dominance of an inherited ideology and ethos of classical liberal individualism, which,
Marquand continued, should be displaced by a politics of ‘mutual education’ that prioritises a
republican commitment to the common good. More precisely, Marquand argued that modern
British political and economic culture is organised around an ideal of absolute sovereignty.
Politically, he claimed, the absolute legislative sovereignty of parliament is complemented by
its economic counterpart, a belief in the untrammelled rights of a managerial or
entrepreneurial class to control the firm. Both are hostile to the notion of power-sharing or
division, so that federalism and consensus-building seem alien. Yet in Marquand’s view, for
Britain to undergo a successful period of economic adjustment and reform – as opposed to
the dysfunctional corporatism or Thatcherite shock therapy that had dominated British
politics after 1945 – consensus-building and power-sharing was precisely the approach that
would have to be taken (Marquand, 1988, pp. 241-2). Indeed, Marquand further remarked
that he thought the classical notion of the sovereign European nation state was ‘obsolescent’
4
because of the need for economic co-operation and decision-making at a supranational level
(Marquand, 1988, p. 244). But while some powers would have to be transferred upwards to
an international level, it was also necessary to devolve powers downwards ‘to create neocorporatist institutions in the regions’, effectively creating ‘a number of developmental states,
region by region’, which would be able to respond with greater flexibility than a centralised
state to economic change (Marquand, 1988, p. 243; for Marquand’s later reflections and
expansions on these arguments, see Marquand, 1997, especially pp. 25-9).
These arguments were an important conceptual breakthrough for the British left, since
they postulated a close connection between a revived republican constitutionalism and a
fairer and more productive economic settlement. Such ideas were also articulated around the
same time as Marquand by Paul Hirst, who sought to resuscitate the pluralism of earlier
socialist thinkers such as Harold Laski and G. D. H. Cole in a fully-fledged doctrine of
‘associationalism’. Hirst followed Marquand in suggesting that the creation of a new culture
of social dialogue and bargaining would be critical in shaping a more dynamic and inclusive
model of British capitalism. Such a culture could only be created through wide-ranging
constitutional reform designed to abolish single-party rule and untrammelled executive power
and inculcate instead new norms of power-sharing and coalition-building. As a starting point,
Hirst (and Marquand) had in mind such measures as the introduction of proportional
representation, a written constitution with entrenched individual rights, a democratised
second chamber, and some form of federalism, although Hirst ultimately advocated a more
radical programme of economic democratisation and decentralisation designed to make
capitalist institutions more accountable and efficient (Hirst, 1989, pp. 39-81, 197-204; Hirst,
1994, pp. 112-57). Hirst saw the cultivation of local political and economic institutions as
critical to reviving British industry, since it was at this local level that the most informed
economic and social decision-making could take place. Local government and economic
5
actors would collaborate on service provision, industrial innovation, and the management of
new local investment agencies (Hirst, 1989, p. 219).
The ideas developed by Marquand and Hirst achieved a significant impact on high
political argument when they were synthesised and popularised by Will Hutton in The State
We’re In (1995). Hutton foregrounded the European parallels present in the works of
Marquand and Hirst, demonstrating that it was something like the West German (or possibly
Scandinavian) model of capitalism – with its longer time horizons, integration between
industry and finance, and consensual, federalised political culture – that could serve as a
practical example of the sort of polity that Britain should aspire to become. Hutton’s book
was widely read and debated, and even for a brief period thought to offer an intellectual
framework for the incoming policies of Tony Blair’s New Labour government. But, as
Hutton himself would have been the first to acknowledge, the intellectual core of the book
drew on the connection between democratic and economic reform first established by
Marquand: ‘the semi-modern nature of the British state is a fundamental cause of Britain’s
economic and social problems’ (Hutton, 1995, pp. xi-xii; for his debt to Marquand, see
Hutton, 2000, pp. 59-60). In Britain, Hutton argued, ‘parliament and the firm are sovereign;
individuals are subjects and workers. They have no formal stake in the society and economy
of which they are alleged to be part’ (Hutton, 1995, p. 287). Hutton therefore proposed a shift
towards a republican political and economic settlement of the sort adumbrated by Marquand
and Hirst a few years earlier.
It is significant that Marquand, Hirst and Hutton all played leading roles in Charter
88, the pressure group that campaigned for constitutional reform in Britain during the run-up
to Labour’s return to office in 1997 (Hirst chaired the Charter 88 executive committee,
Marquand served as a member of the executive and Hutton on its council). Charter 88 is
rightly credited with placing systematic reform of the British constitution back on the
6
political agenda and with winning over a section of the British political elite to the cause of a
more democratic polity (see Erdos, 2009). Charter 88’s success in promoting debate about the
British constitution meant that many of the concrete democratic reforms advocated by figures
such as Marquand achieved much greater attention than would otherwise have been the case.
However, Charter 88’s energies were, for understandable reasons, chiefly directed at the
reform of the central British state. The question of the relationship between the nations and
regions of the United Kingdom was given less attention – although the example of the
Scottish Constitutional Convention and the wider debate over Scottish devolution was
undoubtedly a powerful influence on Charter 88’s work. The Charter itself referred to
Scotland as being ‘governed like a province from Whitehall’ and demanded that any new
constitutional settlement should ‘guarantee an equitable distribution of power between local,
regional and national government’ (reprinted in Facey, Rigby and Runswick, 2008, pp. 316,
319). The phrasing here was vague, although it seems clear that it was generally understood
to entail a commitment to devolution to Scotland, Wales and Northern Ireland and the
creation of a much more robust – possibly federal – decentralisation of power throughout the
United Kingdom. At any rate, the possibility that Scottish independence might be one
desirable outcome of such a process was given short shrift by key figures within the
organisation and Scottish nationalists were not generally included within the parameters of
the imagined progressive alliance of Labour and the Liberal Democrats that was thought to be
the most plausible political vehicle for the realisation of Charter 88’s goals (although this was
also because the SNP chose to absent itself from the Scottish Constitutional Convention, thus
maintaining a hostile stance towards devolutionary proposals). From the perspective of post2014 political developments, both of these assumptions now look less easily defensible than
they did in the 1990s.
7
The Scottish nationalist challenge
At one level the challenge that is posed to a British republican social democracy by the rise of
Scottish nationalism is simply to question the assumption that the appropriate territorial unit
for this sort of political project is Britain. But it also runs deeper than that, because the claim
of the most articulate exponents of Scottish independence is in essence that, if we take the
case made by thinkers such as Marquand, Hutton and Hirst seriously, then we ought in fact to
support the dissolution of the Anglo-Scottish Union. How exactly do Scottish nationalists
seek to recruit such leading figures of the British left to the ranks of the SNP? They do so by
drawing on two strands of argument that are indebted to the constitutional reform discourse
of the 1980s and 1990s (for a more detailed analysis of the political ideas of Scottish
nationalism, on which the following account draws, see Jackson, 2014).
First, the Scottish nationalist critique of the British state is broadly similar to the one
in, say, The Unprincipled Society, The State We’re In, or the discourse of Charter 88. The
British state is depicted as in essence pre-democratic and imperial, the product of an
idiosyncratic historical path that thwarted a thorough-going bourgeois democratic revolution.
Britain is thus an antiquated relic, dominated by the interests of the City of London, and
unreformable except by a radical constitutional break, in this case the secession of Scotland.
The intellectual provenance of the version of these arguments articulated by Scottish
nationalists is more directly indebted to New Left thinkers such as Tom Nairn and Perry
Anderson than to Marquand or Hutton, but they ultimately take roughly the same shape (and
in any case the latter were to some extent also directly and indirectly influenced by the
former’s pioneering analysis). Anderson and Nairn famously argued that Britain’s unique
historical trajectory was determined by the capacity of the aristocracy and the middle class to
form a social alliance that staved off a bourgeois revolution, excluding the working class
8
from significant political power. This alliance was cemented by the rise of the British empire
and the creation of what became an imperial British state. The British state of the late
twentieth century was thus, on this account, the creature of a long and inescapable history of
aristocratic power politics, empire, and ultimately post-imperial economic stagnation
(Anderson 1964; Nairn 1964a; Nairn 1964b). These ‘Anderson-Nairn theses’, as they were
later dubbed, formed a set of arguments about the nature of Britain that were subsequently
very influential on Scottish nationalist thought and which arrive at a diagnosis of Britain as
fundamentally undemocratic that has many affinities with the analysis sponsored by
Marquand and his colleagues in Charter 88. Indeed, Anthony Barnett, the first Director of
Charter 88, was himself a former member of the Editorial Committee of Perry Anderson’s
New Left Review and a close colleague of Nairn’s (see for example Nairn’s warm tribute to
Barnett in Nairn, 2000, p. ix). The key difference between the Scottish nationalist analysis of
Britain and its counterpart in the writings of Marquand, Hirst and Hutton is the more
pessimistic conclusions of the former, namely the Scottish nationalist view is that the
regressive character of the contemporary British state is so tied to specifically English
hierarchies and inequalities that it won’t be possible for Scotland or England to achieve a
more democratic and egalitarian settlement while still part of the same political union (see
Nairn, 1977, for the most influential statement along these lines). For the advocates of
Scottish independence, a developmental state and economy can only be created separately
first by Scotland and then subsequently by the rest of the UK, which will, so the argument
goes, have been shocked by the secession of Scotland into a fundamental constitutional and
economic reappraisal.
Second, the Scottish nationalist understanding of the concept of sovereignty is, like
that of Marquand and Hirst, a pluralist one. Scottish nationalists have learned over the years
that a claim for undivided Scottish sovereignty is not credible or convincing as an account of
9
what Scottish independence would look like. Rather than making a claim for Scottish
autarchy, Scottish nationalists have elaborated a sophisticated account of how an independent
Scotland could simultaneously enjoy self-determination in certain respects but in other
respects share institutions, laws, and society with foreign nations. Contemporary Scottish
nationalism has therefore been deeply influenced by a pluralist view that envisages a
diffusion of power across different levels of government and society. For Scottish
nationalists, this approach to sovereignty was developed most fully in the writings of the late
Neil MacCormick, the legal theorist and sometime SNP MEP (1999-2004), who advanced the
case for what he called the ‘post-sovereign state’. MacCormick observed that his own
‘diffusionist’ theories pointed back towards earlier ideas about associational autonomy
associated with figures such as the German jurist and historian Otto von Gierke and the
French jurist and sociologist Maurice Hauriou, who had rejected the ‘undue pretensions of
the state to total mastery of a territory’ and were concerned about ‘the independence and
vitality of the manifold communities, guilds, associations, and corporations to be found in
civil society’ (MacCormick, 1999, p. 77). MacCormick argued that European integration had
replaced the absolute sovereignty previously exercised by EU member states with a more
pluralistic arrangement in which new rules bind together these states at the European level,
removing certain of the powers previously exercised nationally. At the same time, the
doctrine of subsidiarity – that decisions should be taken at the lowest possible level –
mandated that powers should also be decentralised from the state towards regional authorities
or even to newly-created national institutions that break away from existing large multinational states. On MacCormick’s account, the demise of the traditional model of absolute
state sovereignty invites Scotland to participate in a new era in which Scottish institutions can
take over some important powers previously held at Westminster, while in other domains
10
simultaneously remaining subject to institutions at a European and perhaps even British level
(MacCormick 1999, pp. 137-56).
In some respects MacCormick’s analysis left tantalisingly indeterminate how far it
would indeed be desirable on these grounds for Scotland to secure independence rather than
some form of advanced home rule (Walker, 2012, pp. 163-90). But MacCormick’s case was
ultimately that a British federalism, because of the disproportionate size of England, could
never work, and that asymmetric devolution to Scotland along the lines undertaken in 1999
would ultimately prove to be an unstable settlement, since it would expose the anomalous
role of Scottish MPs in determining public policy in England but not in Scotland. Even were
England to be divided into regional assemblies, MacCormick noted, this would not tackle the
central difficulty of the legislative powers held by the Scottish parliament. It seemed to
MacCormick highly unlikely that English law-making powers of the kind exercised in
Edinburgh would or could be split between different English regions (for example by
splitting up the English NHS into regional units). A similar, although more sovereigntist,
argument about the instability of devolution was also made by Tom Nairn in 1997. Nairn
predicted that once Scottish popular sovereignty was given an institutional form in the
Scottish Parliament it would inevitably conflict with the parliamentary sovereignty of the
British state. Nairn perceptively noted that the key fact about the new Scottish Parliament
would not be the precise policy domains or fiscal powers it had, but rather its embodiment for
the first time of a distinctively Scottish democratic will which would, inevitably, be able to
address ‘whether to try to alter the conditions of UK affiliation’ (Nairn, 1997, p. 223). While
conversant with the increasing salience of debates about federal and ‘post-sovereign’ powersharing arrangements between states and regions, Nairn’s view was that in the British case
there was simply no chance of such a comprehensive recasting of British constitutional
practice.
11
Both MacCormick and Nairn therefore argued that the most promising solution to this
impasse was an independent Scotland as a member of the EU, complemented by an
intergovernmental Council of the Isles to deal with issues specific to the British archipelago.
With these arrangements in place, Scotland would secure a relationship of equality with the
rest of the UK, and other European states, as an equal member of the European confederation
(MacCormick, 1999, pp. 61-2, 193-9; Nairn, 2000, pp. 223-78).
After the 2016 referendum on Britain’s membership of the EU, this argument is
clearly in need of significant renovation. Indeed, it may even have been rendered irrelevant to
current policy debates, since it seems that a more fundamental and irrevocable choice
between Scotland’s membership of either a European or a British union will now be pressed
on Scottish nationalists. But if that is the case, then the republican social democracy
associated with David Marquand also faces serious challenges, since this is also ultimately
grounded on a vision of shared sovereignty between Brussels, London and Edinburgh
(Marquand, 2011). The difference between the two once again hinges on the more pessimistic
assessment of the prospects for British federalism on the part of Scottish nationalists.
Responding to the challenge
The extent to which Scottish nationalism has assimilated both the democratic critique of the
British state and a pluralist conception of sovereignty is testament to the sophistication of the
current campaign for Scottish independence and the skill with which Scottish nationalists
have managed to disorientate their unionist opponents. The argument for Scottish nationalism
is now in short that it is the logical culmination of the British left’s arguments about
constitutional and economic reform developed over the last three decades.
12
How might those sympathetic to the creation of a more federal British settlement
respond to this colonisation of their arguments? One pragmatic view, which tempted a
number of English progressives during the 2014 referendum campaign, was simply to
concede that, since serious constitutional reform is frozen at the British level and British
politics is now dominated by the right, the appropriate response is to wish Scottish
nationalists good luck, support Scotland in going its own way, and observe with interest if it
can do any better than the rest of the UK in advancing democracy and social justice. This
argument has likely gained a number of new adherents in the wake of the 2016 EU
referendum. A second response, also espoused by some figures on the left in England, would
go even further and argue that in fact Scottish independence is not simply the least worst
option available now, but rather a positively desirable outcome of the agenda first set out in
the 1980s and 1990s by Charter 88 and other constitutional reformers. This line of argument
accepts that the Scottish nationalist use of the ideas I have discussed is in fact correct. This
was not the view initially taken by the advocates of constitutional change when Labour took
office in 1997. Anthony Barnett, for example, replied to Tom Nairn’s scepticism with an
optimistic view of the radical constitutional possibilities opened up by the Blair government,
although Barnett also stressed that in the absence of any wider rethinking of British
constitutional structures Scottish independence would inevitably command greater credibility
(Barnett, 1997a; Barnett, 1997b, pp. 186-93).
A third option, of course, would be to resist the Scottish nationalist conclusion by
suggesting that a more federal and decentralised British state remains, in spite of the
scepticism of Neil MacCormick and Tom Nairn, an achievable and desirable political goal.
And this takes us back to John Mackintosh. I noted earlier that Mackintosh’s insight was that
it was not enough simply to grant devolution to Scotland; there also had to be something
more positive and attractive to say about what Britain stood for, an attempt by unionists to
13
activate and amplify the British element of Scots’ dual nationality. If such a strategy to avert
Scottish independence is to succeed, then part of such an effort to revivify Britishness will
indeed be constitutional; it will rest on creating a more democratic and inclusive British
political system, featuring proportional representation, a new second chamber, and so on. It
will also face the testing task of resolving the difficult imbalances and anomalies identified
by Neil MacCormick as severe obstacles to the creation of a successful British federalism.
But I would add that this strategy cannot only be constitutional; it also has to encompass
political economy. Just as, say, The Unprincipled Society spelled out the connections between
constitutional reform and the reform of Britain’s political economy, the revised case for
Britain must also have a socio-economic dimension.
This point has some similarities to the case for the Anglo-Scottish union articulated
by Gordon Brown during the 2014 independence referendum campaign (see Jackson, 2016
for a fuller discussion of this point, which the following account draws on). While in office
between 1997 and 2010, Brown perceived that Labour’s failure to create a new British civic
patriotism to accompany Labour’s constitutional reforms was a problem, but he failed to
articulate an account of Britishness capable of achieving any substantial political or social
resonance, instead invoking an impressionistic collection of historical episodes and political
values that were collectively said to add up to a progressive British tradition. Until the
Scottish independence referendum, few within the Labour Party regarded this failure as a
serious problem. Brown’s own attention to Britishness tended to be dismissed by allies and
opponents alike as chiefly motivated by his need to present a Scottish MP as a legitimate
British Prime Minister. But during the hectic spring and summer of 2014, Labour’s profound
inarticulacy on British identity was clearly revealed. It proved surprisingly difficult for
leading Labour figures to give a compelling positive account of British identity to go
alongside the ferocious economic critique of Scottish independence. The main exception to
14
this was Gordon Brown, who succeeded in refining his ideas about Britishness to the point
where they at last had a significant political cutting edge. Brown’s concept of the union as
about risk-sharing and resource-pooling between England, Scotland, Wales and Northern
Ireland was a fertile one, which offered a distinctively social democratic characterisation of
British institutions and traditions. The best argument for the Union, Brown said, was that it
had provided the framework for the creation of ‘social and economic rights that the citizens
of the four nations have built up and share in common throughout the United Kingdom’,
including social insurance, the NHS, and pensions. In the United Kingdom, ‘it is not
nationality that decides who benefits, it is need’ (Brown, 2014, pp. 231, 227).
The weakness of Brown’s analysis, as Scottish nationalists pointed out, is that postThatcher the ‘pooling and sharing’ case for British institutions is harder to make. After rapid
deindustrialisation, growing economic inequality, a period of relatively right-wing Labour
government, and then Westminster-sponsored austerity, the argument that Britain stands for
egalitarian collective action unsurprisingly proved difficult to land with some long-standing
Scottish Labour voters. While Brown could point to a number of powerful individual
examples of British risk-sharing and resource-pooling that nonetheless persisted even after
the Thatcher years, it was undeniable that levels of inequality and poverty remain
unacceptably high in Britain in the twenty-first century, even though New Labour in office
had made a creditable and effective start on improving them. Campaigners for the AngloScottish Union were therefore left with the uninspiring line of argument that the fiscal and
monetary constraints on an independent Scotland would leave a new Scottish state with few
options to improve on Britain’s dismal record and were indeed likely to make matters worse.
This argument was just about politically effective in 2014, but it is hard to see it recreating
among Scots the sort of stronger positive affinity for Britain that John Mackintosh
recommended as necessary for ultimately diminishing support for Scottish independence.
15
This places left-wing defenders of the Anglo-Scottish Union in a bind that can
probably only be broken by a successful period of left-of-centre government in Westminster.
The best way to meet the arguments for Scottish independence is to show through concrete
and effective policy action that a new, pluralist British state can also be a state in which
poverty, economic insecurity, and material inequality will all be lower than under our present
constitutional order. So although there has been a lot of discussion about how to renew the
case for the Union in the wake of the 2014 independence referendum (and some limited
subsequent action), in fact one important way of capturing the initiative from Scottish
nationalism would be for a government in Westminster to undertake serious reform to
Britain’s economic model. Until such a period of (presumably) non-Conservative government
can be engineered, the dual identity of many Scots will continue listing to the Scottish side,
and the question of Scottish independence will accordingly be a pressing issue of debate for
years to come.
References
Anderson, P. (1964) ‘Origins of the present crisis’, New Left Review, No. 23, pp. 26-53.
Barnett, A. (1997a) ‘Constitutional Possibilities’, Political Quarterly, 68 (4), pp. 361-71.
Barnett, A. (1997b) This Time: Our Constitutional Revolution, London, Vintage.
Brown, G. (2014) My Scotland, Our Britain: A Future Worth Sharing, London, Simon &
Schuster.
16
Erdos, D. (2009) ‘Charter 88 and the constitutional reform movement: a retrospective’,
Parliamentary Affairs, 62 (4), pp. 537-51.
Facey, P., Rigby, B. and Runswick, A. (eds.) (2008) Unlocking Democracy: 20 Years of
Charter 88, London, Politico’s.
Hirst, P. (1989) After Thatcher, London, Collins.
Hirst, P. (1994) Associative Democracy, Cambridge, Polity.
Hutton, W. (1995) The State We’re In, London, Jonathan Cape.
Hutton, W. (2000) ‘Interview’, in R. English and M. Kenny (eds.), Rethinking British
Decline, Basingstoke, Macmillan.
Jackson, B. (2014) ‘The political thought of Scottish nationalism’, Political Quarterly, 85 (1),
pp. 50-56.
Jackson, B. (2016) ‘Labour and the nation’, Fabian Review, 128 (3), autumn 2016.
MacCormick, N. (1999) Questioning Sovereignty, Oxford, Oxford University Press.
Mackintosh, J. (1974) ‘The new appeal of nationalism’, New Statesman, 27 September 1974.
17
Mackintosh, J. (1982) John P. Mackintosh on Scotland, ed. by H. Drucker, London,
Longman.
Marquand, D. (1988) The Unprincipled Society, London, Cape.
Marquand, D. (1997) The New Reckoning, Cambridge, Polity.
Marquand, D. (2011) The End of the West: The Once and Future Europe, Princeton,
Princeton University Press.
Nairn, T. (1964a) ‘The nature of the Labour Party, part one’, New Left Review, No. 27, pp.
37-65.
Nairn, T. (1964b) ‘The nature of the Labour Party, part two’, New Left Review, No. 28, pp.
33-62.
Nairn, T. (1977) The Break-Up of Britain: Crisis and Neo-Nationalism, London, New Left
Books.
Nairn, T. (1997) Faces of Nationalism, London, Verso.
Nairn, T. (2000) After Britain, London, Granta.
O’Neill, M. and White, S. (2014) ‘That was the New Labour that wasn’t’, in G. Lodge and G.
Gottfried (eds.), Democracy in Britain: Essays in Honour of James Cornford, London, IPPR.
18
Walker, G. (2013) ‘John Mackintosh, devolution and the union’, Parliamentary Affairs, 66
(3), pp. 557-78.
Walker, N. (2012) ‘Scottish nationalism for and against the union state’, in N. Walker (ed.),
MacCormick’s Scotland, Edinburgh, Edinburgh University Press.
19