Aleph-null, the smallest infinite cardinal number

In set theory, a discipline within mathematics, the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality (or size) of infinite sets. They are named after the symbol used to denote them, the Hebrew letter aleph (Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph ).

The cardinality of the natural numbers is Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_0

(read aleph-naught, aleph-null or aleph-zero), the next larger cardinality is aleph-one Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_1

, then Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_2

and so on. Continuing in this manner, it is possible to define a cardinal number Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_\alpha
for every ordinal number α, as described below.

The concept goes back to Georg Cantor, who defined the notion of cardinality and realized that infinite sets can have different cardinalities.

The aleph numbers differ from the infinity (∞) commonly found in algebra and calculus. Alephs measure the sizes of sets; infinity, on the other hand, is commonly defined as an extreme limit of the real number line (applied to a function or sequence that "diverges to infinity" or "increases without bound"), or an extreme point of the extended real number line.

Contents

Aleph-naught [link]

Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_0

is the cardinality of the set of all natural numbers, and is the first infinite cardinal. A set has cardinality Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_0
if and only if it is countably infinite, which is the case if and only if it can be put into a direct bijection, or "one-to-one correspondence", with the natural numbers. Such sets include the set of all prime numbers, the set of all integers, the set of all rational numbers, the set of algebraic numbers, the set of binary strings of all finite lengths, and the set of all finite subsets of any countably infinite set.

If the axiom of countable choice (a weaker version of the axiom of choice) holds, then Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_0

is smaller than any other infinite cardinal.

Aleph-one [link]

Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_1

is the cardinality of the set of all countable ordinal numbers, called ω1 or (sometimes) Ω. Note that this ω1 is itself an ordinal number larger than all countable ones, so it is an uncountable set. Therefore  Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_1
is distinct from Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_0

. The definition of Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_1

implies (in ZF, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice) that no cardinal number is between Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_0
and Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_1

. If the axiom of choice (AC) is used, it can be further proved that the class of cardinal numbers is totally ordered, and thus Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_1

is the second-smallest infinite cardinal number. Using AC we can show one of the most useful properties of the set ω1: any countable subset of ω1 has an upper bound in ω1.  (This follows from the fact that a countable union of countable sets is countable, one of the most common applications of AC.)  This fact is analogous to the situation in Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_0
every finite set of natural numbers has a maximum which is also a natural number; that is, finite unions of finite sets are finite.

ω1 is actually a useful concept, if somewhat exotic-sounding. An example application is "closing" with respect to countable operations; e.g., trying to explicitly describe the σ-algebra generated by an arbitrary collection of subsets (see e. g. Borel hierarchy). This is harder than most explicit descriptions of "generation" in algebra (vector spaces, groups, etc.) because in those cases we only have to close with respect to finite operations—sums, products, and the like. The process involves defining, for each countable ordinal, via transfinite induction, a set by "throwing in" all possible countable unions and complements, and taking the union of all that over all of ω1.

The continuum hypothesis [link]

The cardinality of the set of real numbers (cardinality of the continuum) is Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): 2^{\aleph_0} . It is not clear where this number fits in the aleph number hierarchy. It follows from ZFC (Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice) that the celebrated continuum hypothesis, CH, is equivalent to the identity

Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): 2^{\aleph_0}=\aleph_1.


CH is independent of ZFC: it can be neither proven nor disproven within the context of that axiom system (provided that ZFC is consistent). That it is consistent with ZFC was demonstrated by Kurt Gödel in 1940 when he showed that its negation is not a theorem of ZFC. That it is independent of ZFC was demonstrated by Paul Cohen in 1963 when he showed, conversely, that the CH itself is not a theorem of ZFC by the (then novel) method of forcing.

Aleph-ω [link]

Conventionally the smallest infinite ordinal is denoted ω, and the cardinal number Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_\omega

is the least upper bound of
Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \left\{\,\aleph_n : n\in\left\{\,0,1,2,\dots\,\right\}\,\right\}

among alephs.

Aleph-ω is the first uncountable cardinal number that can be demonstrated within Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory not to be equal to the cardinality of the set of all real numbers; for any positive integer n we can consistently assume that Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): 2^{\aleph_0} = \aleph_n , and moreover it is possible to assume Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): 2^{\aleph_0}

is as large as we like. We are only forced to avoid setting it to certain special cardinals with cofinality Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_0

, meaning there is an unbounded function from Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_0

to it.

Aleph-α for general α [link]

To define Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_\alpha

for arbitrary ordinal number Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \alpha

, we must define the successor cardinal operation, which assigns to any cardinal number ρ the next larger well-ordered cardinal ρ+. (If the axiom of choice holds, this is the next larger cardinal.)

We can then define the aleph numbers as follows

Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_{0} = \omega
Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_{\alpha+1} = \aleph_{\alpha}^+


and for λ, an infinite limit ordinal,

Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_{\lambda} = \bigcup_{\beta < \lambda} \aleph_\beta.


The α-th infinite initial ordinal is written Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \omega_\alpha . Its cardinality is written Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph_\alpha . See initial ordinal.

In ZFC the Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \aleph

function is a bijection between the ordinals and the infinite cardinals.[1]

Fixed points of omega [link]

For any ordinal α we have

Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \alpha\leq\omega_\alpha.

In many cases Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \omega_{\alpha}

is strictly greater than α. For example, for any successor ordinal α this holds. There are, however, some limit ordinals which are fixed points of the omega function, because of the fixed-point lemma for normal functions. The first such is the limit of the sequence
Failed to parse (Missing texvc executable; please see math/README to configure.): \omega,\ \omega_\omega,\ \omega_{\omega_\omega},\ \ldots.


Any weakly inaccessible cardinal is also a fixed point of the aleph function.

Role of axiom of choice [link]

The cardinality of any infinite ordinal number is an aleph number. Every aleph is the cardinality of some ordinal. The least of these is its initial ordinal. Any set whose cardinality is an aleph is equinumerous with an ordinal and is thus well-orderable.

Each finite set is well-orderable, but does not have an aleph as its cardinality.

The assumption that the cardinality of each infinite set is an aleph number is equivalent over ZF to the existence of a well-ordering of every set, which in turn is equivalent to the axiom of choice. ZFC set theory, which includes the axiom of choice, implies that every infinite set has an aleph number as its cardinality (i.e. is equinumerous with its initial ordinal), and thus the initial ordinals of the aleph numbers serve as a class of representatives for all possible infinite cardinal numbers.

When cardinality is studied in ZF without the axiom of choice, it is no longer possible to prove that each infinite set has some aleph number as its cardinality; the sets whose cardinality is an aleph number are exactly the infinite sets that can be well-ordered. The method of Scott's trick is sometimes used as an alternative way to construct representatives for cardinal numbers in the setting of ZF.

References [link]

Notes

External links [link]


https://wn.com/Aleph_number

Podcasts:

PLAYLIST TIME:

Ivory Tower

by: Alphaville

Here is the news from my little hideaway
My sweet Ivory Tower
I've sent you songs about so many thing
Mighty moondogs skipping waves
Dolphins playing their lives away
Golden circus girls and pharaohs
Fallen angels, streetside Romeos
Patricia's park and Anyway
Eternal youth and neverending summer days
Lonely girls, music halls, the mysteries of love
In the event that I don't return
Please take this message to understand...
In the event...
I am a stranger in a strange land
Welcome, stranger, to the land of the free
Welcome, Carol, to Phantasy
Oh my God, I feel so alone
A million lightyears far from home
It seems to be a tragedy
How can I live in Germany?
Another house is burning down
It's time to face the cruel reality
This is a game no more
Disasters in the 20th Century
In the event that I don't return
Please take this message to understand




×