Jump to content

Argument from authority: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
→‎top: rm poor souce
Line 7: Line 7:
: ''A'' is probably correct
: ''A'' is probably correct


Fallacious examples of using the argument include any appeal to an authority who is not an expert in the subject of discussion, as well as appealing to the position of an authority or authorities to dismiss evidence,<ref name="Bex">{{cite journal|last1=F. Bex, H. Prakken, C. Reed| title=Towards a formal account of reasoning about evidence: argumentation schemes and generalisations| journal=Artificial Intelligence and Law| date=2003| page=133| url=http://150.162.138.5/portal/sites/default/files/anexos/6487-6486-1-PB.pdf}}</ref>{{sfn|Baronett|2008|p=304}}{{sfn|Walton|2008|p=89}} as authorities can come to the wrong judgments through error, bias, dishonesty, or falling prey to [[groupthink]]. <ref> {{cite AV media |people= Easton, Matt |date= July 9, 2015 |title= Don't trust historians! or English archers... |url= https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=CEfCVujdfXU |publisher= Schola Gladiatoria |ref= Easton_Archers}}</ref>
Fallacious examples of using the argument include any appeal to an authority who is not an expert in the subject of discussion, as well as appealing to the position of an authority or authorities to dismiss evidence,<ref name="Bex">{{cite journal|last1=F. Bex, H. Prakken, C. Reed| title=Towards a formal account of reasoning about evidence: argumentation schemes and generalisations| journal=Artificial Intelligence and Law| date=2003| page=133| url=http://150.162.138.5/portal/sites/default/files/anexos/6487-6486-1-PB.pdf}}</ref>{{sfn|Baronett|2008|p=304}}{{sfn|Walton|2008|p=89}} as authorities can come to the wrong judgments through error, bias, dishonesty, or falling prey to [[groupthink]].


== Forms ==
== Forms ==

Revision as of 22:43, 7 January 2016

Argument from authority (Latin: argumentum ad verecundiam) also appeal to authority, is a common form of argument. When the authority being appealed to is not an authority on the subject in question, or when the the authority being appealed to espouses a controversial or contention position, this can lead to a logical fallacy.[1][2]

The legitimate use of the appeal to authority is an argument which is intended to establish a statistical syllogism.[3] The appeal to authority relies on an argument of the form:[4]

A is an authority on a particular topic
A says something about that topic
A is probably correct

Fallacious examples of using the argument include any appeal to an authority who is not an expert in the subject of discussion, as well as appealing to the position of an authority or authorities to dismiss evidence,[5][6][7] as authorities can come to the wrong judgments through error, bias, dishonesty, or falling prey to groupthink.

Forms

General

The legitimate form of the argument goes as follows:

X holds that A is true.
X is an authority on the subject.
The consensus of authorities agrees with X.
There is a presumption that A is true.[8]

Dismissal of evidence

The fallacious counter-argument from authority takes the form:[9]

B has provided evidence for position T.
A says position T is incorrect.
Therefore, B's evidence is false.

This form is fallacious as it does not actually refute the evidence given by B, it merely notes that there is disagreement with position T.[9] This form is especially unsound when there is no indication that A is aware of the evidence given by B.[10]

Appeal to non-authorities

Fallacious arguments from authority can also be the result of citing a non-authority as an authority.[11] These arguments assume that a person without status or authority is inherently reliable. The appeal to poverty for example is the fallacy of thinking a conclusion is probably correct because the one who holds or is presenting it is poor.[12] When an argument holds that a conclusion is likely to be true precisely because the one who holds or is presenting it lacks authority, it is a fallacious appeal to the common man.[6][13][14] A common example of the fallacy is appealing to an authority in one subject to pontificate on another - for example citing Albert Einstein as an authority on philosophy when his expertise laid in astrophysics. [2]

However, it is also a fallacious ad hominem argument to argue that a person presenting statements lacks authority and thus their arguments do not need to be considered.[15] As appeals to a perceived lack of authority, these types of argument are fallacious for much the same reasons as an appeal to authority.[16]

Use in logic

Because experts are not invariably correct, an appeal to authority is never considered to be proof of a conclusion.[11] Asserting that a conclusion must be true simply because a legitimate authority agrees that it is true is a logical non sequitur, as even legitimate authorities can be wrong.[17][18]

The only exception to this would be an authority which is logically required to always be correct, such as an omniscient being that does not lie.[5][19]

Notable examples

Inaccurate chromosome number

In 1923, leading American zoologist Theophilus Painter declared based on his findings that humans had 24 pairs of chromosomes. From the 1920s to the 1950s, this continued to be held based on Painter's authority,[20] despite subsequent counts totaling the correct number of 23.[21] Even textbooks with photos clearly showing 23 pairs incorrectly declared the number to be 24 based on the authority of the then-consensus of 24 pairs.[21]

As Robert Matthews said of the event, "Scientists had preferred to bow to authority rather than believe the evidence of their own eyes".[21] As such, their reasoning was an appeal to authority.[22]

The tongue map

Another example is that of the tongue map, which purported to show different areas of taste on the tongue. While it originated from a misreading of the original text, it got taken up in textbooks and the scientific literature[23] for nearly a century, and remained even after being shown to be wrong in the 1970s[24][25] and despite being easily disproven on one's own tongue.[26][27]

Cause and treatment of puerperal infections

In the mid-to-late 19th century a small minority of doctors, most notably Ignaz Semmelweis, argued that puerperal fevers were caused by an infection or toxin[28] the spread of which was preventable by aseptic technique by physicians such as hand washing with chlorine.[29] This view was largely discounted because, as one 1843 paper noted, "writers of authority...profess a disbelief in [such a] contagion", and instead held that puerperal fevers were caused by environmental factors which would render such techniques irrelevant.[29]

This was in spite of evidence against their proposed explanations, such as Semmelweis' observations that two side-by-side clinics had radically different rates of puerperal infection, that puerperal infection was extremely rare in births that took place outside of hospitals, and that infection rates were unrelated to weather or seasonal variations, all of which went against the prevailing explanation of environmental causes such as miasma.[30] However, those who presented this evidence found themselves "fighting against hospital authorities".[31]

It is estimated that hundreds of thousands of women's lives would have been saved if the contagious disease explanation had been accepted when the evidence was presented.[32]

Psychological basis

An integral part of the appeal to authority is the cognitive bias known as the Asch effect.[22] In repeated and modified instances of the Asch conformity experiments, it was found that high-status individuals create a stronger likelihood of a subject agreeing with an obviously false conclusion, despite the subject normally being able to clearly see that the answer was incorrect.[33]

Further, humans have been shown to feel strong emotional pressure to conform to authorities and majority positions. A repeat of the experiments by another group of researchers found that "Participants reported considerable distress under the group pressure", with 59% conforming at least once and agreeing with the clearly incorrect answer, whereas the incorrect answer was much more rarely given when no such pressures were present.[34]

Scholars have noted that the academic environment produces a nearly ideal situation for these processes to take hold, and they can affect entire academic disciplines, giving rise to groupthink. One paper about the philosophy of mathematics for example notes that, within mathematics,

"If...a person accepts our discipline, and goes through two or three years of graduate study in mathematics, he absorbs our way of thinking, and is no longer the critical outsider he once was. In the same way [that] a critic of Scientology who underwent several years of 'study' under 'recognized authorities' in Scientology might well emerge a believer instead of a critic. If the student is unable to absorb our way of thinking, we flunk him out, of course. If he gets through our obstacle course and then decides that our arguments are unclear or incorrect, we dismiss him as a crank, crackpot, or misfit." [35]

See also

References

  1. ^ Gass, Robert. "Common Fallacies in Reasoning". California State University Fullerton. Retrieved 13 August 2015.
  2. ^ a b Carroll, Robert. "Appeal to Authority". The Skeptic's Dictionary.
  3. ^ Boyd, Robert (1993). "Argument Analysis and Critical Thinking". Korean Journal of Thinking and Problem Solving: 55.
  4. ^ Gootendorst, Rob. Some Fallacies about Fallacies. Argumentation: Across the lines of discipline. p. 388.
  5. ^ a b F. Bex, H. Prakken, C. Reed (2003). "Towards a formal account of reasoning about evidence: argumentation schemes and generalisations" (PDF). Artificial Intelligence and Law: 133.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  6. ^ a b Baronett 2008, p. 304.
  7. ^ Walton 2008, p. 89.
  8. ^ Gensler, Harry J. (2010). The A to Z of Logic. Lanham, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield. p. 62. Retrieved 7 January 2016.
  9. ^ a b Walton 2008, p. 91.
  10. ^ Walton 2008, p. 92.
  11. ^ a b Gensler, Harry J. (2003). Introduction to Logic. New York, NY: Routedge. pp. 333–4.
  12. ^ Silverman, Henry (2011). "Principles of Trust or Propaganda?". Journal of Applied Business Research.
  13. ^ See generally Irving M. Copi (1986). Introduction to Logic (7th ed.). Macmillan Publishing Company. pp. 98–99.
  14. ^ Bennett, B. "Appeal to the Common Man". Logically Fallacious.
  15. ^ Walton, D. N. (1989). "Reasoned use of expertise in argumentation". Argumentation. 3 (1): 69.
  16. ^ Van Eemeren, Frans; Grootendorst, Rob (1987). "Fallacies in pragma-dialectical perspective". Argumentation. 1 (3): 283–301. doi:10.1007/bf00136779.
  17. ^ Foster, Marguerite H.; Martin, Michael L., eds. (1966). Probability, Confirmation, and Simplicity: Readings in the Philosophy of Inductive Logic. Odyssey Press.[page needed]
  18. ^ Peirce, Charles Sanders; et al. (1883) [Digitized Jun 15, 2007]. Studies in logic. By members of the Johns Hopkins university. Little, Brown. ISBN 978-1-236-07583-3.[page needed] (available as a free google eBook)
  19. ^ Wierenga, Edward. "Omniscience". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford University.
  20. ^ O'Connor, Clare (2008), Human Chromosome Number, Nature, retrieved April 24, 2014
  21. ^ a b c Matthews, Robert (2011), The bizarre case of the chromosome that never was, Fortune City, retrieved May 14, 2011
  22. ^ a b Grootendorst, Robert (1992), Argumentation, Communication, and Fallacies: A Pragma-dialectical Perspective, p. 158
  23. ^ nytimes.com
  24. ^ Midura, Margaretta. "On the Road to Sweetness: A Clear-Cut Destination?". Yale Scientific Magazine.
  25. ^ http://www.livescience.com/7113-tongue-map-tasteless-myth-debunked.html
  26. ^ http://www.nytimes.com/2008/11/11/health/11real.html
  27. ^ http://www.aromadictionary.com/articles/tonguemap_article.html
  28. ^ Sutton, Mike. "Mythbusted: Why the Semmelweis story is both myth and supermyth". BestThinking. Retrieved 5 May 2015.
  29. ^ a b Carter, Codell (1981). "Semmelweis and his predecessors" (PDF). Medical History.
  30. ^ Nuland, Sherwin (30 January 1979). "The enigma of Semmelweis—an interpretation" (PDF). Nuland, S. B. (1979). The enigma of Semmelweis—an interpretation. Journal of the history of medicine and allied sciences: 259–260.
  31. ^ Vickers, Rebecca (September 1, 2010). Medicine. Heinemann-Raintree Library. p. 36. ISBN 1410939081.
  32. ^ Schwarz, Henry (1910). Transactions of the American Association of Obstetricians and Gynecologists, Volume 23. pp. 182–183.
  33. ^ McLeod, Samuel (2008), Asch Experiment, Simply Psychology
  34. ^ Webley, Paul, A partial and non-evaluative history of the Asch effect, University of Exeter {{citation}}: Cite has empty unknown parameter: |1= (help)
  35. ^ David, Phillip J.; Hersh, Reuben (1998). New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics (PDF). Princeton University Press. p. 8.

Sources

  • Baronett, Stan (2008). Logic. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Prentice Hall.
  • Walton, Douglas (2008). Informal Logic. London: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-71380-3.