Sincere favorite criterion: Difference between revisions
No edit summary |
No edit summary |
||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
{{Short description|Criterion that prevents lesser-evil voting}}{{Electoral systems}} |
{{Short description|Criterion that prevents lesser-evil voting}}{{Electoral systems}} |
||
The '''sincere favorite''' or '''no favorite-betrayal criterion''' is a [[voting system criterion|property]] of some voting systems, that says voters should have no incentive to vote for someone else over their favorite.<ref name="small">Alex Small, “Geometric construction of voting methods that protect voters’ first choices,” arXiv:1008.4331 (August 22, 2010), http://arxiv.org/abs/1008.4331.</ref> It protects voters from having to engage in [[lesser |
The '''sincere favorite''' or '''no favorite-betrayal criterion''' is a [[voting system criterion|property]] of some voting systems, that says voters should have no incentive to vote for someone else over their favorite.<ref name="small">Alex Small, “Geometric construction of voting methods that protect voters’ first choices,” arXiv:1008.4331 (August 22, 2010), http://arxiv.org/abs/1008.4331.</ref> It protects voters from having to engage in [[lesser-evil voting]] or a strategy called "decapitation" (removing the "head" off a ballot).<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Merrill |first1=Samuel |last2=Nagel |first2=Jack |date=1987-06-01 |title=The Effect of Approval Balloting on Strategic Voting under Alternative Decision Rules |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/product/identifier/S0003055400194481/type/journal_article |journal=American Political Science Review |language=en |volume=81 |issue=2 |pages=509–524 |doi=10.2307/1961964 |jstor=1961964 |issn=0003-0554}}</ref> |
||
Most [[rated voting]] systems, including [[score voting]], satisfy the criterion.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Baujard |first1=Antoinette |last2=Gavrel |first2=Frédéric |last3=Igersheim |first3=Herrade |last4=Laslier |first4=Jean-François |last5=Lebon |first5=Isabelle |date=September 2017 |title=How voters use grade scales in evaluative voting |url=https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-01618039/file/1729.pdf |journal=European Journal of Political Economy |volume=55 |pages=14–28 |doi=10.1016/j.ejpoleco.2017.09.006 |issn=0176-2680 |quote=A key feature of evaluative voting is a form of independence: the voter can evaluate all the candidates in turn ... another feature of evaluative voting ... is that voters can express some degree of preference.}} |
Most [[rated voting]] systems, including [[score voting]], satisfy the criterion.<ref>{{Cite journal |last1=Baujard |first1=Antoinette |last2=Gavrel |first2=Frédéric |last3=Igersheim |first3=Herrade |last4=Laslier |first4=Jean-François |last5=Lebon |first5=Isabelle |date=September 2017 |title=How voters use grade scales in evaluative voting |url=https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-01618039/file/1729.pdf |journal=European Journal of Political Economy |volume=55 |pages=14–28 |doi=10.1016/j.ejpoleco.2017.09.006 |issn=0176-2680 |quote=A key feature of evaluative voting is a form of independence: the voter can evaluate all the candidates in turn ... another feature of evaluative voting ... is that voters can express some degree of preference.}} |
Revision as of 09:51, 2 September 2024
A joint Politics and Economics series |
Social choice and electoral systems |
---|
Mathematics portal |
The sincere favorite or no favorite-betrayal criterion is a property of some voting systems, that says voters should have no incentive to vote for someone else over their favorite.[1] It protects voters from having to engage in lesser-evil voting or a strategy called "decapitation" (removing the "head" off a ballot).[2]
Most rated voting systems, including score voting, satisfy the criterion.[3][4][5] By contrast, most variants of ranked voting fail this criterion.[4][6][7] Lesser-evil-voting is particularly prevalent in plurality-based voting systems like ranked choice voting (RCV),[8][6][9] traditional runoffs,[4] and first-past-the-post.[4] Such pathologies are typically associated with center-squeeze.
Duverger's law says that systems vulnerable to this strategy will typically (though not always) develop two party-systems, as voters will abandon minor-party candidates to support stronger major-party candidates.[10]
Definition
The no favorite betrayal criterion is defined as follows:
- A voting system satisfies the no favorite betrayal criterion if there cannot exist a situation where a voter is forced to insincerely list another candidate ahead of their sincere favorite in order to obtain a more preferred outcome in the election overall (i.e. the election of a candidate that they prefer to the current winner).
Arguments for
The Center for Election Science argues systems that violate the favorite betrayal criterion strongly incentivize voters to cast dishonest ballots, which can make voters feel unsatisfied or frustrated with the results despite having the opportunity to participate in the election.[11][12][13][14]
Other commentators have argued that failing the favorite-betrayal criterion can increase the effectiveness of misinformation campaigns, by allowing major-party candidates to sow doubt as to whether voting honestly for one's favorite is actually the best strategy.[15]
Compliant methods
Rated voting
Because rated voting methods are not affected by Arrow's theorem, they can be both spoilerproof (satisfy IIA) and ensure positive vote weights at the same time. Taken together, these properties imply that increasing the rating of a favorite candidate can never change the result, except by causing the favorite candidate to win; therefore, giving a favorite candidate the maximum level of support is always the optimal strategy.
Examples of systems that are both spoilerproof and monotonic include score voting, approval voting, and highest medians.
Anti-plurality voting
Interpreted as a ranked voting method where every candidate but the last ranked gets one point, anti-plurality voting passes the sincere favorite criterion. Because there is no incentive to rank one's favorite last, and the method otherwise does not care where the favorite is ranked, the method passes.
Anti-plurality voting thus shows that the sincere favorite criterion is distinct from independence of irrelevant alternatives, and that ranked voting methods do not necessarily fail the criterion.
Non-compliant methods
Instant-runoff voting
This example shows that instant-runoff voting violates the favorite betrayal criterion. Assume there are four candidates: Amy, Bert, Cindy, and Dan. This election has 41 voters with the following preferences:
# of voters | Preferences |
---|---|
10 | Amy > Bert > Cindy > Dan |
6 | Bert > Amy > Cindy > Dan |
5 | Cindy > Bert > Amy > Dan |
20 | Dan > Amy > Cindy > Bert |
Sincere voting
Assuming all voters vote in a sincere way, Cindy is awarded only 5 first place votes and is eliminated first. Her votes are transferred to Bert. In the second round, Amy is eliminated with only 10 votes. Her votes are transferred to Bert as well. Finally, Bert has 21 votes and wins against Dan, who has 20 votes.
Votes in round/ Candidate |
1st | 2nd | 3rd |
---|---|---|---|
Amy | 10 | 10 | – |
Bert | 6 | 11 | 21 |
Cindy | 5 | – | – |
Dan | 20 | 20 | 20 |
Result: Bert wins against Dan, after Cindy and Amy were eliminated.
Favorite betrayal
Now assume two of the voters who favor Amy (marked bold) realize the situation and insincerely vote for Cindy instead of Amy:
# of voters | Ballots |
---|---|
2 | Cindy > Amy > Bert > Dan |
8 | Amy > Bert > Cindy > Dan |
6 | Bert > Amy > Cindy > Dan |
5 | Cindy > Bert > Amy > Dan |
20 | Dan > Amy > Cindy > Bert |
In this scenario, Cindy has 7 first place votes and so Bert is eliminated first with only 6 first place votes. His votes are transferred to Amy. In the second round, Cindy is eliminated with only 10 votes. Her votes are transferred to Amy as well. Finally, Amy has 21 votes and wins against Dan, who has 20 votes.
Votes in round/ Candidate |
1st | 2nd | 3rd |
---|---|---|---|
Amy | 8 | 14 | 21 |
Bert | 6 | – | – |
Cindy | 7 | 7 | – |
Dan | 20 | 20 | 20 |
Result: Amy wins against Dan, after Bert and Cindy has been eliminated.
By listing Cindy ahead of their true favorite, Amy, the two insincere voters obtained a more preferred outcome (causing their favorite candidate to win). There was no way to achieve this without raising another candidate ahead of their sincere favorite. Thus, instant-runoff voting fails the favorite betrayal criterion.
Condorcet methods
This section is empty. You can help by adding to it. (May 2024) |
See also
- Comparison of electoral systems
- Electoral systems
- Vote splitting
- Independence of irrelevant alternatives
- Strategic voting
External links
- Collective Decisions and Voting: The Potential for Public Choice
- Chaotic Elections!: A Mathematician Looks at Voting
- Decisions and Elections: Explaining the Unexpected
- Election Methods
- Survey of methods satisfying FBC
- FBC in relation to duopoly
- FBC used in mathematical proofs
- Commentary on FBC in relation to other voting methods
References
- ^ Alex Small, “Geometric construction of voting methods that protect voters’ first choices,” arXiv:1008.4331 (August 22, 2010), http://arxiv.org/abs/1008.4331.
- ^ Merrill, Samuel; Nagel, Jack (1987-06-01). "The Effect of Approval Balloting on Strategic Voting under Alternative Decision Rules". American Political Science Review. 81 (2): 509–524. doi:10.2307/1961964. ISSN 0003-0554. JSTOR 1961964.
- ^ Baujard, Antoinette; Gavrel, Frédéric; Igersheim, Herrade; Laslier, Jean-François; Lebon, Isabelle (September 2017). "How voters use grade scales in evaluative voting" (PDF). European Journal of Political Economy. 55: 14–28. doi:10.1016/j.ejpoleco.2017.09.006. ISSN 0176-2680.
A key feature of evaluative voting is a form of independence: the voter can evaluate all the candidates in turn ... another feature of evaluative voting ... is that voters can express some degree of preference.
- ^ a b c d Wolk, Sara; Quinn, Jameson; Ogren, Marcus (2023-03-20). "STAR Voting, equality of voice, and voter satisfaction: considerations for voting method reform". Constitutional Political Economy (Journal Article). 34 (3): 310–334. doi:10.1007/s10602-022-09389-3. Retrieved 2023-07-16.
- ^ Eberhard, Kristin (2017-05-09). "Glossary of Methods for Electing Executive Officers". Sightline Institute. Retrieved 2023-12-31.
- ^ a b Woodall, Douglas (1997-06-27). "Monotonicity of single-seat preferential election rules". Discrete Applied Mathematics. 77 (1): 81–98. doi:10.1016/S0166-218X(96)00100-X. Retrieved 2024-05-02.
- ^ Fishburn, Peter; Brams, Steven (1983-09-01). "Paradoxes of Preferential Voting". Mathematics Magazine. 56 (4): 207–214. doi:10.1080/0025570X.1983.11977044. JSTOR 2689808. Retrieved 2024-05-02.
- ^ Dellis, Arnaud; Kröger, Sabine (2023). "How Do People Vote Under Instant Runoff Voting? An Experiment on Complexity and Voting Behavior". SSRN Electronic Journal. doi:10.2139/ssrn.4602773. ISSN 1556-5068.
- ^ Sullivan, Brendan (2022). An Introduction to the Math of Voting Methods. 619 Wreath. ISBN 9781958469033.
- ^ Volić, Ismar (2024-04-02). "Duverger's law". Making Democracy Count. Princeton University Press. Ch. 2. doi:10.2307/jj.7492228. ISBN 978-0-691-24882-0.
- ^ Hamlin, Aaron (2015-05-30). "Top 5 Ways Plurality Voting Fails". Election Science. The Center for Election Science. Retrieved 2023-07-17.
- ^ Hamlin, Aaron (2019-02-07). "The Limits of Ranked-Choice Voting". Election Science. The Center for Election Science. Retrieved 2023-07-17.
- ^ "Voting Method Gameability". Equal Vote. The Equal Vote Coalition. Retrieved 2023-07-17.
- ^ Hamlin, Aaron; Hua, Whitney (2022-12-19). "The case for approval voting". Constitutional Political Economy. 34 (3): 335–345. doi:10.1007/s10602-022-09381-x.
- ^ Ossipoff, Michael (2013-05-20). "Schulze: Questioning a Popular Ranked Voting System". Democracy Chronicles. Retrieved 2024-01-01.