Jump to content

Political philosophy: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
Purpose: - elaboration on the distinction between political philosophy and political science as presented in Harvey Mansfield's article
Replacing Leviathan_by_Thomas_Hobbes.jpg with File:Leviathan_frontispiece_cropped_British_Library.jpg (by CommonsDelinker because: File renamed: Criterion 4 (harmonizing names of file se
 
(26 intermediate revisions by 3 users not shown)
Line 3: Line 3:
{{Philosophy sidebar|expanded=Branches}}{{Politics sidebar|expanded=Primary topics}}
{{Philosophy sidebar|expanded=Branches}}{{Politics sidebar|expanded=Primary topics}}


'''Political philosophy,''' or '''political theory,''' is the [[philosophy|philosophical]] study of [[government]], addressing questions about the nature, scope, and legitimacy of public agents and institutions and the relationships between them. Its topics include [[politics]], [[justice]], [[liberty]], [[property]], [[rights]], [[law]], and [[authority]]: what they are, if they are needed, what makes a [[Justification for the state|government legitimate]], what [[fundamental rights|rights and freedoms]] it should protect, what form it should take, what the law is, and what duties citizens owe to a legitimate government, if any, and when it may be legitimately overthrown, if ever.
'''Political philosophy''', or '''political theory''', is the [[philosophy|philosophical]] study of [[government]], addressing questions about the nature, scope, and legitimacy of public agents and institutions and the relationships between them. Its topics include [[politics]], [[justice]], [[liberty]], [[property]], [[rights]], [[law]], and [[authority]]: what they are, if they are needed, what makes a [[Justification for the state|government legitimate]], what [[fundamental rights|rights and freedoms]] it should protect, what form it should take, what the law is, and what duties citizens owe to a legitimate government, if any, and when it may be legitimately overthrown, if ever.


Political theory also engages questions of a broader scope, tackling the political nature of phenomena and categories such as [[Identity (social science)|identity]], [[Cultural studies|culture]], [[Philosophy of sexuality|sexuality]], [[Critical race theory|race]], [[Political economy|wealth]], [[Critical animal studies|human-nonhuman relations]], [[Political ethics|ethics]], [[Political theology|religion]], and more.
Political theory also engages questions of a broader scope, tackling the political nature of phenomena and categories such as [[Identity (social science)|identity]], [[Cultural studies|culture]], [[Philosophy of sexuality|sexuality]], [[Critical race theory|race]], [[Political economy|wealth]], [[Critical animal studies|human-nonhuman relations]], [[Political ethics|ethics]], [[Political theology|religion]], and more.

[[Political science]], the scientific study of [[politics]], is generally used in the singular, but in French and Spanish the plural (''sciences politiques'' and ''ciencias políticas'', respectively) is used, perhaps a reflection of the discipline's eclectic nature.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/political-science|title=Political science|website=Encyclopedia Britannica|language=en|access-date=3 April 2020}}</ref>


Political philosophy is a branch of [[philosophy]],<ref>Strauss, Leo (1959). An introduction to Political Philosophy. Detroit: Wayne State University Press, p. 10.</ref> but it has also played a major part in [[political science]], within which a strong focus has historically been placed on both the history of political thought and contemporary political theory (from [[Normative|normative political theory]] to various [[Critical theory|critical approaches]]).
Political philosophy is a branch of [[philosophy]],<ref>Strauss, Leo (1959). An introduction to Political Philosophy. Detroit: Wayne State University Press, p. 10.</ref> but it has also played a major part in [[political science]], within which a strong focus has historically been placed on both the history of political thought and contemporary political theory (from [[Normative|normative political theory]] to various [[Critical theory|critical approaches]]).
Line 28: Line 26:
[[Indian political philosophy]] in ancient times demarcated a clear distinction between (1) nation and state (2) religion and state. The constitutions of Hindu states evolved over time and were based on political and legal treatises and prevalent social institutions. The institutions of state were broadly divided into governance, diplomacy, administration, defense, law and order. ''Mantranga'', the principal governing body of these states, consisted of the King, Prime Minister, Commander in chief of army, Chief Priest of the King. The Prime Minister headed the committee of ministers along with head of executive (Maha Amatya).
[[Indian political philosophy]] in ancient times demarcated a clear distinction between (1) nation and state (2) religion and state. The constitutions of Hindu states evolved over time and were based on political and legal treatises and prevalent social institutions. The institutions of state were broadly divided into governance, diplomacy, administration, defense, law and order. ''Mantranga'', the principal governing body of these states, consisted of the King, Prime Minister, Commander in chief of army, Chief Priest of the King. The Prime Minister headed the committee of ministers along with head of executive (Maha Amatya).


[[Chanakya]] was a 4th-century BC Indian political philosopher. The ''[[Arthashastra]]'' provides an account of the science of politics for a wise ruler, policies for foreign affairs and wars, the system of a spy state and surveillance and economic stability of the state.<ref>{{cite book|author-link=Roger Boesche|last=Boesche|first=Roger|title=The First Great Political Realist: Kautilya and His Arthashastra|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=K85NA7Rg67wC&pg=PP1|year=2002|publisher=Lexington Books|isbn=978-0-7391-0401-9|page=7}}</ref> Chanakya quotes several authorities including Bruhaspati, Ushanas, Prachetasa Manu, Parasara, and Ambi, and described himself as a descendant of a lineage of political philosophers, with his father Chanaka being his immediate predecessor.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Rangarajan|first1=L N|title=The Arthashastra |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3jbzZkoR36QC&pg=PT22|year=2000|publisher=Penguin UK|isbn=9788184750119|page=95}}</ref> Another influential extant Indian treatise on political philosophy is the Sukra Neeti.<ref>{{cite book|last=Brown|first=D. Mackenzie|title=The White Umbrella: Indian Political Thought from Manu to Gandhi|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JZzXv2JOZUMC&q=sukraniti&pg=PP1|year=1982|publisher=Greenwood Press|isbn=978-0313232107|page=64}}</ref><ref>{{cite book|last1=Sankhdher|first1=Madan Mohan|last2=Kaur|first2=Gurdeep|title=Politics in India: Ancient India, Politics of Change, Modern India|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=veYezcrVAlcC&q=sukra%20neeti&pg=PR4|year=2005|publisher=Deep and Deep Publications|isbn=9788176296557|page=95}}</ref> An example of a [[code of law]] in ancient India is the Manusmṛti or Laws of Manu.<ref>{{cite book|author=Manu ((Lawgiver))|author2=Kullūkabhaṭṭa|title=Institutes of Hindu Law: Or, The Ordinances of Menu, According to the Gloss of Cullúca|url=https://archive.org/details/bub_gb_4caNTgBa6oEC|year=1796|publisher=Calcutta, Printed by order of the government, London reprinted, for J. Sewell and J. Debrett}}</ref>
[[Chanakya]] was a 4th-century BC Indian political philosopher.<ref>{{Cite web|title=Chanakya|url=https://www.worldhistory.org/Kautilya/|access-date=28 November 2020|website=[[World History Encyclopedia]]}}</ref> The ''[[Arthashastra]]'' provides an account of the science of politics for a wise ruler, policies for foreign affairs and wars, the system of a spy state and surveillance and economic stability of the state.<ref>{{cite book|author-link=Roger Boesche|last=Boesche|first=Roger|title=The First Great Political Realist: Kautilya and His Arthashastra|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=K85NA7Rg67wC&pg=PP1|year=2002|publisher=Lexington Books|isbn=978-0-7391-0401-9|page=7}}</ref> Chanakya quotes several authorities including Bruhaspati, Ushanas, Prachetasa Manu, Parasara, and Ambi, and described himself as a descendant of a lineage of political philosophers, with his father Chanaka being his immediate predecessor.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Rangarajan|first1=L N|title=The Arthashastra |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3jbzZkoR36QC&pg=PT22|year=2000|publisher=Penguin UK|isbn=9788184750119|page=95}}</ref> Another influential extant Indian treatise on political philosophy is the Sukra Neeti.<ref>{{cite book|last=Brown|first=D. Mackenzie|title=The White Umbrella: Indian Political Thought from Manu to Gandhi|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JZzXv2JOZUMC&q=sukraniti&pg=PP1|year=1982|publisher=Greenwood Press|isbn=978-0313232107|page=64}}</ref><ref>{{cite book|last1=Sankhdher|first1=Madan Mohan|last2=Kaur|first2=Gurdeep|title=Politics in India: Ancient India, Politics of Change, Modern India|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=veYezcrVAlcC&q=sukra%20neeti&pg=PR4|year=2005|publisher=Deep and Deep Publications|isbn=9788176296557|page=95}}</ref> An example of a [[code of law]] in ancient India is the Manusmṛti or Laws of Manu.<ref>{{cite book|author=Manu ((Lawgiver))|author2=Kullūkabhaṭṭa|title=Institutes of Hindu Law: Or, The Ordinances of Menu, According to the Gloss of Cullúca|url=https://archive.org/details/bub_gb_4caNTgBa6oEC|year=1796|publisher=Calcutta, Printed by order of the government, London reprinted, for J. Sewell and J. Debrett}}</ref>


==== Ancient China ====
==== Ancient China ====
Line 34: Line 32:
[[File:Konfuzius-1770.jpg|thumb|Portrait of [[Confucius]], {{Circa|1770}}]]
[[File:Konfuzius-1770.jpg|thumb|Portrait of [[Confucius]], {{Circa|1770}}]]


Chinese political philosophy dates back to the [[Spring and Autumn period]], specifically with Confucius in the 6th century BC. Chinese political philosophy was developed as a response to the social and political breakdown of the country characteristic of the Spring and Autumn period and the [[Warring States period]]. The major philosophies during the period, [[Confucianism]], [[Legalism (Chinese philosophy)|Legalism]], [[Mohism]], [[School of Agrarianism|Agrarianism]] and [[Taoism]], each had a political aspect to their philosophical schools. Philosophers such as [[Confucius]], [[Mencius]], and [[Mozi]], focused on political unity and political stability as the basis of their political philosophies. Confucianism advocated a hierarchical, [[meritocracy|meritocratic]] government based on empathy, loyalty, and interpersonal relationships. Legalism advocated a highly [[authoritarian]] government. [[Mohism]] advocated a communal, decentralized government centered on [[frugality]] and [[asceticism]]. The Agrarians advocated a peasant [[utopian communalism]] and [[egalitarianism]].<ref>{{cite book|last1=Deutsch|first1=Eliot|first2=Ronald|last2=Bontekoei|year=1999|page=[https://archive.org/details/companiontoworld00deut_616/page/n205 183]|title=A companion to world philosophies|url=https://archive.org/details/companiontoworld00deut_616|url-access=limited|publisher=Wiley Blackwell|isbn=9780631213277}}</ref> Taoism advocated a proto-[[anarchism]]. Legalism was the dominant political philosophy of the [[Qin dynasty]], but was replaced by State Confucianism in the [[Han dynasty]]. Each had [[Religion|religious]] or [[myth]]ic aspects as well that played into how they viewed fairness in governance.
Chinese political philosophy dates back to the [[Spring and Autumn period]], specifically with Confucius in the 6th century BC. Chinese political philosophy was developed as a response to the social and political breakdown of the country characteristic of the Spring and Autumn period and the [[Warring States period]]. Confucius was the first thinker to relate ethics to the political order.<ref>{{Citation |last=Csikszentmihalyi |first=Mark |title=Confucius |date=2020 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/confucius/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |edition=Summer 2020 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=22 April 2022}}</ref> The major philosophies during the period, [[Confucianism]], [[Legalism (Chinese philosophy)|Legalism]], [[Mohism]], [[School of Agrarianism|Agrarianism]] and [[Taoism]], each had a political aspect to their philosophical schools. Philosophers such as [[Confucius]], [[Mencius]],<ref>{{Citation|last=Van Norden|first=Bryan|title=Mencius|date=2019|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/mencius/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Fall 2019|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=15 October 2020}}</ref> and [[Mozi]], focused on political unity and political stability as the basis of their political philosophies. Confucianism advocated a hierarchical, [[meritocracy|meritocratic]] government based on empathy, loyalty, and interpersonal relationships. Legalism advocated a highly [[authoritarian]] government. [[Mohism]] advocated a communal, decentralized government centered on [[frugality]] and [[asceticism]]. The Agrarians advocated a peasant [[utopian communalism]] and [[egalitarianism]].<ref>{{cite book|last1=Deutsch|first1=Eliot|first2=Ronald|last2=Bontekoei|year=1999|page=[https://archive.org/details/companiontoworld00deut_616/page/n205 183]|title=A companion to world philosophies|url=https://archive.org/details/companiontoworld00deut_616|url-access=limited|publisher=Wiley Blackwell|isbn=9780631213277}}</ref> Taoism advocated a proto-[[anarchism]]. Legalism was the dominant political philosophy of the [[Qin dynasty]], but was replaced by State Confucianism in the [[Han dynasty]]. Each had [[Religion|religious]] or [[myth]]ic aspects as well that played into how they viewed fairness in governance.


Prior to China's adoption of [[communism]], State Confucianism remained the dominant political philosophy of China up to the 20th century.<ref>{{cite book|last=Hsü|first=Leonard Shihlien|title=The political philosophy of Confucianism|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FWFtQIyun-8C|year=2005|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-0-415-36154-5|pages=xvii–xx|quote=The importance of a scientific study of Confucian political philosophy could hardly be overstated.}}</ref>
Prior to China's adoption of [[communism]], State Confucianism remained the dominant political philosophy of China up to the 20th century.<ref>{{cite book|last=Hsü|first=Leonard Shihlien|title=The political philosophy of Confucianism|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FWFtQIyun-8C|year=2005|publisher=Routledge|isbn=978-0-415-36154-5|pages=xvii–xx|quote=The importance of a scientific study of Confucian political philosophy could hardly be overstated.}}</ref>
Line 40: Line 38:
==== Ancient Greece ====
==== Ancient Greece ====
[[File:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg|thumb|left|[[Plato]] (left) and [[Aristotle]] (right), from a detail of ''[[The School of Athens]]'', a fresco by [[Raphael]]. Plato's ''[[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]'' and Aristotle's ''[[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]]'' secured the two Greek philosophers as two of the most influential political philosophers.]]
[[File:Sanzio 01 Plato Aristotle.jpg|thumb|left|[[Plato]] (left) and [[Aristotle]] (right), from a detail of ''[[The School of Athens]]'', a fresco by [[Raphael]]. Plato's ''[[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]'' and Aristotle's ''[[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]]'' secured the two Greek philosophers as two of the most influential political philosophers.]]
Western political philosophy originates in the philosophy of [[ancient Greece]], where political philosophy dates back to at least [[Plato]].<ref name="Sahakian 1993 59">{{cite book|last=Sahakian|first=Mabel Lewis|title=Ideas of the great philosophers|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Vi7cQMw8SwYC&pg=PA59|year=1993|publisher=Barnes & Noble Publishing|isbn=978-1-56619-271-2|page=59|quote=... Western philosophical tradition can be traced back as early as Plato (427–347 BC).}}</ref> Ancient Greece was dominated by city-states, which experimented with various forms of political organization. Plato grouped forms of government into five categories of descending stability and morality: [[Republic (Plato)|republic]], [[timocracy]], [[oligarchy]], [[democracy]] and [[tyranny]]. One of the first, extremely important classical works of political philosophy is Plato's ''[[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]'',<ref name="Sahakian 1993 59"/> which was followed by [[Aristotle]]'s ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' and [[Politics (Aristotle)|''Politics'']].<ref>{{cite book|last=Kraut|first=Richard|title=Aristotle: political philosophy|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9BDmX3FBbS4C&pg=PA3|year=2002|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=978-0-19-878200-1|page=3|quote=To understand and assess Aristotle's contributions to political thought ...}}</ref> Roman political philosophy was influenced by the [[Stoics]] and the Roman statesman [[Cicero]].<ref>{{cite book|last=Radford|first=Robert T.|title=Cicero: a study in the origins of republican philosophy|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1cKLGcvuYxQC&pg=PA1|year=2002|publisher=Rodopi|isbn=978-90-420-1467-1|page=1|quote=His most lasting political contribution is in his work on political philosophy.}}</ref>
Western political philosophy originates in the philosophy of [[ancient Greece]], where political philosophy dates back to at least [[Plato]].<ref name="Sahakian 1993 59">{{cite book|last=Sahakian|first=Mabel Lewis|title=Ideas of the great philosophers|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Vi7cQMw8SwYC&pg=PA59|year=1993|publisher=Barnes & Noble Publishing|isbn=978-1-56619-271-2|page=59|quote=... Western philosophical tradition can be traced back as early as Plato (427–347 BC).}}</ref> Ancient Greece was dominated by city-states, which experimented with various forms of political organization. Plato grouped forms of government into five categories of descending stability and morality: [[Republic (Plato)|republic]], [[timocracy]], [[oligarchy]], [[democracy]] and [[tyranny]]. One of the first, extremely important classical works of political philosophy is Plato's ''[[Republic (Plato)|Republic]]'',<ref name="Sahakian 1993 59"/> which was followed by [[Aristotle]]'s ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]'' and [[Politics (Aristotle)|''Politics'']].<ref>{{cite book|last=Kraut|first=Richard|title=Aristotle: political philosophy|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9BDmX3FBbS4C&pg=PA3|year=2002|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=978-0-19-878200-1|page=3|quote=To understand and assess Aristotle's contributions to political thought ...}}</ref> Aristotle is notable for the theories that humans are social animals, and that the [[polis]] (Ancient Greek city state) existed to bring about the good life appropriate to such animals.<ref>{{Citation|last=Shields|first=Christopher|title=Aristotle|date=2020|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/aristotle/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Fall 2020|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=15 October 2020}}</ref> Roman political philosophy was influenced by the [[Stoics]] and the Roman statesman [[Cicero]].<ref>{{cite book|last=Radford|first=Robert T.|title=Cicero: a study in the origins of republican philosophy|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1cKLGcvuYxQC&pg=PA1|year=2002|publisher=Rodopi|isbn=978-90-420-1467-1|page=1|quote=His most lasting political contribution is in his work on political philosophy.}}</ref>


=== Medieval Europe ===
=== Medieval Europe ===
[[Medieval]] political philosophy in Europe was heavily influenced by Christian thinking. It had much in common with the Mutazilite [[Islamic]] thinking in that the [[Roman Catholic]]s thought subordinating [[philosophy]] to [[theology]] did not subject reason to revelation but in the case of contradictions, subordinated reason to faith as the Asharite of Islam. The Scholastics by combining the philosophy of Aristotle with the Christianity of St. Augustine emphasized the potential harmony inherent in reason and revelation.<ref>{{cite book|last=Koetsier|first=L.S.|title=Natural Law and Calvinist Political Theory|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7uLE3DynB0YC&pg=PA19|year=2004|publisher=Trafford Publishing|isbn=978-1-4122-1440-7|page=19|quote=...the Medieval Scholastics revived the concept of natural law. }}</ref> Perhaps the most influential political philosopher of medieval Europe was St. [[Thomas Aquinas]] who helped reintroduce [[Aristotle]]'s works, which had only been transmitted to [[Catholic]] Europe through [[Muslim]] Spain, along with the commentaries of [[Averroes]]. Aquinas's use of them set the agenda, for [[scholasticism|scholastic]] political philosophy dominated European thought for centuries even unto the [[Renaissance]].<ref>{{cite book|last=Copleston|first=Frederick|title=A history of philosophy|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=y_382o-fpOsC&pg=PA346|volume=3|year=1999|publisher=Continuum International Publishing Group|isbn=978-0-86012-296-8|page=346|quote=There was, however, at least one department of thought ...}}</ref>
[[Medieval]] political philosophy in Europe was heavily influenced by Christian thinking. It had much in common with the Mutazilite [[Islamic]] thinking in that the [[Roman Catholic]]s thought subordinating [[philosophy]] to [[theology]] did not subject reason to revelation but in the case of contradictions, subordinated reason to faith as the Asharite of Islam. The Scholastics by combining the philosophy of Aristotle with the Christianity of St. Augustine emphasized the potential harmony inherent in reason and revelation.<ref>{{cite book|last=Koetsier|first=L.S.|title=Natural Law and Calvinist Political Theory|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7uLE3DynB0YC&pg=PA19|year=2004|publisher=Trafford Publishing|isbn=978-1-4122-1440-7|page=19|quote=...the Medieval Scholastics revived the concept of natural law. }}</ref> [[scholasticism|Scholastic]] political philosophy dominated European thought for centuries even unto the [[Renaissance]].<ref>{{cite book|last=Copleston|first=Frederick|title=A history of philosophy|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=y_382o-fpOsC&pg=PA346|volume=3|year=1999|publisher=Continuum International Publishing Group|isbn=978-0-86012-296-8|page=346|quote=There was, however, at least one department of thought ...}}</ref>


Some medieval political philosophers, such as Aquinas in his ''[[Summa Theologica]]'', developed the idea that a king who is a tyrant is no king at all and could be overthrown. Others, like [[Nicole Oresme]] in his ''[[Livre de Politiques]]'', categorically denied this right to overthrow an unjust ruler. [[Magna Carta]], viewed by many as a cornerstone of Anglo-American political liberty, explicitly proposes the right to revolt against the ruler for justice's sake. Other documents similar to Magna Carta are found in other European countries such as Spain and Hungary.<ref>{{cite book|last=Valente|first=Claire|title=The theory and practice of revolt in medieval England|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=B8yRrtm0LicC&pg=PA14|year=2003|publisher=Ashgate Publishing Ltd.|isbn=978-0-7546-0901-8|page=14|quote=The two starting points of most medieval discussions ...}}</ref>
Some medieval political philosophers, such as Aquinas in his ''[[Summa Theologica]]'', developed the idea that a king who is a tyrant is no king at all and could be overthrown. Others, like [[Nicole Oresme]] in his ''[[Livre de Politiques]]'', categorically denied this right to overthrow an unjust ruler. [[Magna Carta]], viewed by many as a cornerstone of Anglo-American political liberty, explicitly proposes the right to revolt against the ruler for justice's sake. Other documents similar to Magna Carta are found in other European countries such as Spain and Hungary.<ref>{{cite book|last=Valente|first=Claire|title=The theory and practice of revolt in medieval England|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=B8yRrtm0LicC&pg=PA14|year=2003|publisher=Ashgate Publishing Ltd.|isbn=978-0-7546-0901-8|page=14|quote=The two starting points of most medieval discussions ...}}</ref>
Line 69: Line 67:
| caption2 = [[Thomas Aquinas]]
| caption2 = [[Thomas Aquinas]]
}}
}}
[[Thomas Aquinas]] meticulously dealt with the varieties of [[philosophy of law]]. According to Aquinas, there are four kinds of law:
Perhaps the most influential political philosopher of medieval Europe was St. [[Thomas Aquinas]] who helped reintroduce [[Aristotle]]'s works, which had only been transmitted to [[Catholic]] Europe through [[Muslim]] Spain, along with the commentaries of [[Averroes]]. Aquinas meticulously dealt with the varieties of [[philosophy of law]]. According to Aquinas, there are four kinds of law:


# Eternal law ("the divine government of everything")
# Eternal law ("the divine government of everything")
Line 77: Line 75:


Aquinas never discusses the nature or categorization of [[canon law (Catholic Church)|canon law]]. There is scholarly debate surrounding the place of canon law within the Thomistic jurisprudential framework. Aquinas was an incredibly influential thinker in the [[Natural law|Natural Law tradition]].
Aquinas never discusses the nature or categorization of [[canon law (Catholic Church)|canon law]]. There is scholarly debate surrounding the place of canon law within the Thomistic jurisprudential framework. Aquinas was an incredibly influential thinker in the [[Natural law|Natural Law tradition]].

In synthesizing Christian theology and Peripatetic (Aristotelian) teaching in his ''[[Treatise on Law]]'', Aquinas contends that God's gift of higher reason—manifest in human law by way of the divine virtues—gives way to the assembly of righteous government.<ref>{{Citation|last1=McInerny|first1=Ralph|title=Saint Thomas Aquinas|date=2018|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/aquinas/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Summer 2018|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=15 October 2020|last2=O'Callaghan|first2=John}}</ref>


=== Islamic Political Evolution ===
=== Islamic Political Evolution ===
Line 130: Line 130:
[[File:Portrait of Niccolò Machiavelli.jpg|thumb|[[Niccolò Machiavelli]]]]
[[File:Portrait of Niccolò Machiavelli.jpg|thumb|[[Niccolò Machiavelli]]]]
One of the most influential works during this burgeoning period was [[Niccolò Machiavelli]]'s ''[[The Prince]]'', written between 1511–12 and published in 1532, after Machiavelli's death. That work, as well as ''[[Discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio|The Discourses]]'', a rigorous analysis of [[classical antiquity]], did much to influence modern political thought in the West. A minority (including [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]]) interpreted The Prince as a satire meant to be given to the Medici after their recapture of Florence and their subsequent expulsion of Machiavelli from Florence.<ref>{{cite web|last=Johnston|first=Ian|title=Lecture on Machiavelli's The Prince|publisher=[[Malaspina University College]]|date=February 2002|url=http://www.mala.bc.ca/~Johnstoi/introser/machiavelli.htm|access-date=20 February 2007|archive-date=18 February 2012|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120218221245/http://www.mala.bc.ca/~Johnstoi/introser/machiavelli.htm|url-status=dead}}</ref> Though the work was written for the di Medici family in order to perhaps influence them to free him from exile, Machiavelli supported the [[Republic of Florence]] rather than the [[oligarchy]] of the [[Medici]] family. At any rate, Machiavelli presents a [[pragmatism|pragmatic]] and somewhat [[consequentialist]] view of politics, whereby good and evil are mere means used to bring about an end—i.e., the acquisition and maintenance of absolute power. [[Thomas Hobbes]], well known for his theory of the [[social contract]], goes on to expand this view at the start of the 17th century during the [[English Renaissance]]. Although neither Machiavelli nor Hobbes believed in the divine right of kings, they both believed in the inherent selfishness of the individual. It was necessarily this belief that led them to adopt a strong central power as the only means of preventing the disintegration of the social order.<ref>{{cite book|last=Copleston|first=Frederick|title=A history of philosophy|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=y_382o-fpOsC&pg=PA310|volume=3|year=1999|publisher=Continuum International Publishing Group|isbn=978-0-86012-296-8|pages=310–12|quote=...we witness the growth of political absolutism ...}}</ref>
One of the most influential works during this burgeoning period was [[Niccolò Machiavelli]]'s ''[[The Prince]]'', written between 1511–12 and published in 1532, after Machiavelli's death. That work, as well as ''[[Discorsi sopra la prima deca di Tito Livio|The Discourses]]'', a rigorous analysis of [[classical antiquity]], did much to influence modern political thought in the West. A minority (including [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]]) interpreted The Prince as a satire meant to be given to the Medici after their recapture of Florence and their subsequent expulsion of Machiavelli from Florence.<ref>{{cite web|last=Johnston|first=Ian|title=Lecture on Machiavelli's The Prince|publisher=[[Malaspina University College]]|date=February 2002|url=http://www.mala.bc.ca/~Johnstoi/introser/machiavelli.htm|access-date=20 February 2007|archive-date=18 February 2012|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120218221245/http://www.mala.bc.ca/~Johnstoi/introser/machiavelli.htm|url-status=dead}}</ref> Though the work was written for the di Medici family in order to perhaps influence them to free him from exile, Machiavelli supported the [[Republic of Florence]] rather than the [[oligarchy]] of the [[Medici]] family. At any rate, Machiavelli presents a [[pragmatism|pragmatic]] and somewhat [[consequentialist]] view of politics, whereby good and evil are mere means used to bring about an end—i.e., the acquisition and maintenance of absolute power. [[Thomas Hobbes]], well known for his theory of the [[social contract]], goes on to expand this view at the start of the 17th century during the [[English Renaissance]]. Although neither Machiavelli nor Hobbes believed in the divine right of kings, they both believed in the inherent selfishness of the individual. It was necessarily this belief that led them to adopt a strong central power as the only means of preventing the disintegration of the social order.<ref>{{cite book|last=Copleston|first=Frederick|title=A history of philosophy|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=y_382o-fpOsC&pg=PA310|volume=3|year=1999|publisher=Continuum International Publishing Group|isbn=978-0-86012-296-8|pages=310–12|quote=...we witness the growth of political absolutism ...}}</ref>

==== Thomas Hobbes ====
[[File:Leviathan frontispiece cropped British Library.jpg|thumb|Frontispiece of ''[[Leviathan]]'']]
The main practical conclusion of Hobbes' political theory is that state or society can not be secure unless at the disposal of an absolute sovereign. From this follows the view that no individual can hold rights of property against the sovereign, and that the sovereign may therefore take the goods of its subjects without their consent.

In [[Leviathan (Hobbes book)|''Leviathan'']], Hobbes set out his doctrine of the foundation of states and legitimate governments and creating an objective science of morality.{{citation needed|date=April 2020}} Much of the book is occupied with demonstrating the necessity of a strong central authority to avoid the evil of discord and civil war.

Beginning from a mechanistic understanding of human beings and their passions, Hobbes postulates what life would be like without government, a condition which he calls the state of nature. In that state, each person would have a right, or license, to everything in the world. This, Hobbes argues, would lead to a "war of all against all".


=== European Enlightenment ===
=== European Enlightenment ===
During the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] period, new theories emerged about what the human was and is and about the definition of reality and the way it was perceived, along with the discovery of other societies in the Americas, and the changing needs of political societies (especially in the wake of the [[English Civil War]], the [[American Revolution]], the [[French Revolution]], and the [[Haitian Revolution]]). These new theories led to new questions and insights by thinkers such as [[Thomas Hobbes]], [[John Locke]], [[Benjamin Constant]] and [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]].
[[File:Salon de Madame Geoffrin.jpg|thumb|Reading of [[Voltaire]]'s tragedy, ''L'Orphelin de n of China'']]
During the [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] period, new theories emerged about what the human was and is and about the definition of reality and the way it was perceived, along with the discovery of other societies in the Americas, and the changing needs of political societies (especially in the wake of the [[English Civil War]], the [[American Revolution]], the [[French Revolution]], and the [[Haitian Revolution]]). These new theories led to new questions and insights by such thinkers as [[Thomas Hobbes]], [[John Locke]], [[Benjamin Constant]] and [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]].


These theorists were driven by two basic questions: one, by what right or need do people form states; and two, what the best form for a state could be. These fundamental questions involved a conceptual distinction between the concepts of "state" and "government." It was decided that "state" would refer to a set of enduring institutions through which power would be distributed and its use justified. The term "government" would refer to a specific group of people who occupied the institutions of the state, and create the laws and ordinances by which the people, themselves included, would be bound. This conceptual distinction continues to operate in [[political science]], although some political scientists, philosophers, historians and [[cultural anthropology|cultural anthropologists]] have argued that most political action in any given society occurs outside of its state, and that there are societies that are not organized into states that nevertheless must be considered in political terms. As long as the concept of [[natural order (philosophy)|natural order]] was not introduced, the [[social sciences]] could not evolve independently of [[theistic]] thinking. Since the cultural revolution of the 17th century in England, which spread to France and the rest of Europe, society has been considered subject to natural laws akin to the physical world.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Barens|first1=Ingo|last2=Caspari|first2=Volker|last3=Schefold|first3=Bertram|editor1-last=Barens|editor1-first=Ingo|others=Volker Caspari ed., Bertram Schefold ed.|title=Political events and economic ideas|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=x6C5AAAAIAAJ&pg=PA206|year=2004|publisher=Edward Elgar Publishing|isbn=978-1-84542-152-6|pages=206–07|quote=Economic theory as political philosophy: the example of the French Enlightenment}}</ref>
These theorists were driven by two basic questions: one, by what right or need do people form states; and two, what the best form for a state could be. These fundamental questions involved a conceptual distinction between the concepts of "state" and "government." It was decided that "state" would refer to a set of enduring institutions through which power would be distributed and its use justified. The term "government" would refer to a specific group of people who occupied the institutions of the state, and create the laws and ordinances by which the people, themselves included, would be bound. This conceptual distinction continues to operate in [[political science]], although some political scientists, philosophers, historians and [[cultural anthropology|cultural anthropologists]] have argued that most political action in any given society occurs outside of its state, and that there are societies that are not organized into states that nevertheless must be considered in political terms. As long as the concept of [[natural order (philosophy)|natural order]] was not introduced, the [[social sciences]] could not evolve independently of [[theistic]] thinking. Since the cultural revolution of the 17th century in England, which spread to France and the rest of Europe, society has been considered subject to natural laws akin to the physical world.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Barens|first1=Ingo|last2=Caspari|first2=Volker|last3=Schefold|first3=Bertram|editor1-last=Barens|editor1-first=Ingo|others=Volker Caspari ed., Bertram Schefold ed.|title=Political events and economic ideas|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=x6C5AAAAIAAJ&pg=PA206|year=2004|publisher=Edward Elgar Publishing|isbn=978-1-84542-152-6|pages=206–07|quote=Economic theory as political philosophy: the example of the French Enlightenment}}</ref>
Line 141: Line 148:
Historians have described Voltaire's description of the history of Christianity as "propagandistic". Voltaire is partially responsible for the misattribution of the expression ''[[Credo quia absurdum]]'' to the Church Fathers. In a letter to Frederick II, King of Prussia, dated 5 January 1767, he wrote about Christianity: La nôtre [religion] est sans contredit la plus ridicule, la plus absurde, et la plus sanguinaire qui ait jamais infecté le monde.
Historians have described Voltaire's description of the history of Christianity as "propagandistic". Voltaire is partially responsible for the misattribution of the expression ''[[Credo quia absurdum]]'' to the Church Fathers. In a letter to Frederick II, King of Prussia, dated 5 January 1767, he wrote about Christianity: La nôtre [religion] est sans contredit la plus ridicule, la plus absurde, et la plus sanguinaire qui ait jamais infecté le monde.
"Ours [i.e., the Christian religion] is assuredly the most ridiculous, the most absurd and the most bloody religion which has ever infected this world. Your Majesty will do the human race an eternal service by extirpating this infamous superstition, I do not say among the rabble, who are not worthy of being enlightened and who are apt for every yoke; I say among honest people, among men who think, among those who wish to think. ... My one regret in dying is that I cannot aid you in this noble enterprise, the finest and most respectable which the human mind can point out." After Voltaire, religion would never be the same again in France.<ref>{{cite book|last=Byrne|first=James M.|title=Religion and the Enlightenment|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FcEy8SF63TgC&pg=PA1|year=1997|publisher=Westminster John Knox Press|isbn=978-0-664-25760-6|pages=1–2|quote=... there emerged groups of freethinkers intent on grounding knowledge on the exercise of critical reason, as opposed to ... established religion ...}}</ref>
"Ours [i.e., the Christian religion] is assuredly the most ridiculous, the most absurd and the most bloody religion which has ever infected this world. Your Majesty will do the human race an eternal service by extirpating this infamous superstition, I do not say among the rabble, who are not worthy of being enlightened and who are apt for every yoke; I say among honest people, among men who think, among those who wish to think. ... My one regret in dying is that I cannot aid you in this noble enterprise, the finest and most respectable which the human mind can point out." After Voltaire, religion would never be the same again in France.<ref>{{cite book|last=Byrne|first=James M.|title=Religion and the Enlightenment|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FcEy8SF63TgC&pg=PA1|year=1997|publisher=Westminster John Knox Press|isbn=978-0-664-25760-6|pages=1–2|quote=... there emerged groups of freethinkers intent on grounding knowledge on the exercise of critical reason, as opposed to ... established religion ...}}</ref>

As well, there was no spread of this doctrine within the [[New World]] and the advanced civilizations of the [[Aztec]], [[Maya civilization|Maya]], [[Inca]], [[Mohican]], Delaware, [[Wyandot people|Huron]] and especially the [[Iroquois]]. The [[Iroquois]] philosophy, in particular, gave much to Christian thought of the time and in many cases actually inspired some of the institutions adopted in the United States: for example, [[Benjamin Franklin]] was a great admirer of some of the methods of the [[Iroquois Confederacy]], and much of early American literature emphasized the political philosophy of the natives. The Iroquois (/ˈɪrəkwɔɪ/ or /ˈɪrəkwɑː/) or Haudenosaunee are a historically powerful northeast Native American confederacy in North America. They were known during the colonial years to the French as the Iroquois League, and later as the Iroquois Confederacy, and to the English as the Five Nations, comprising the Mohawk, Onondaga, Oneida, Cayuga, and Seneca. After 1722, they accepted the Tuscarora people from the Southeast into their confederacy, as they were also Iroquoian-speaking, and became known as the Six Nations.<ref>{{cite book|last=Johansen|first=Bruce Elliott|title=Native American political systems and the evolution of democracy|url=https://archive.org/details/nativeamericanpo0000joha|url-access=registration|year=1996|publisher=Greenwood Publishing Group|isbn=978-0-313-30010-3|page=[https://archive.org/details/nativeamericanpo0000joha/page/69 69]|quote=... the three-tier system of federalism ... is an inheritance of Iroquois inspiration }}</ref>


==== John Locke ====
==== John Locke ====
[[File:John Locke.jpg|thumb|[[John Locke]]]]

[[John Locke]] in particular exemplified this new age of political theory with his work ''[[Two Treatises of Government]]''. In it, Locke proposes a state of nature theory that directly complements his conception of how political development occurs and how it can be founded through contractual obligation. Locke stood to refute Sir [[Robert Filmer]]'s paternally founded political theory in favor of a natural system based on nature in a particular given system. The theory of the [[divine right of kings]] became a passing fancy, exposed to the type of ridicule with which John Locke treated it. Unlike Machiavelli and Hobbes but like Aquinas, Locke would accept Aristotle's dictum that man seeks to be happy in a state of social harmony as a social animal. Unlike Aquinas's preponderant view on the salvation of the soul from [[original sin]], Locke believes man's mind comes into this world as [[tabula rasa]]. For Locke, knowledge is neither innate, revealed nor based on authority but subject to uncertainty tempered by reason, tolerance and moderation. According to Locke, an absolute ruler as proposed by Hobbes is unnecessary, for natural law is based on reason and seeking peace and survival for man.
[[John Locke]] in particular exemplified this new age of political theory with his work ''[[Two Treatises of Government]]''. In it, Locke proposes a state of nature theory that directly complements his conception of how political development occurs and how it can be founded through contractual obligation. Locke stood to refute Sir [[Robert Filmer]]'s paternally founded political theory in favor of a natural system based on nature in a particular given system. The theory of the [[divine right of kings]] became a passing fancy, exposed to the type of ridicule with which John Locke treated it. Unlike Machiavelli and Hobbes but like Aquinas, Locke would accept Aristotle's dictum that man seeks to be happy in a state of social harmony as a social animal. Unlike Aquinas's preponderant view on the salvation of the soul from [[original sin]], Locke believes man's mind comes into this world as [[tabula rasa]]. For Locke, knowledge is neither innate, revealed nor based on authority but subject to uncertainty tempered by reason, tolerance and moderation. According to Locke, an absolute ruler as proposed by Hobbes is unnecessary, for natural law is based on reason and seeking peace and survival for man.

==== David Hume ====
[[David Hume]] criticized the social contract theory of John Locke and others as resting on a myth of some actual agreement. Hume was a realist in recognizing the role of force to forge the existence of states and that [[consent of the governed]] was merely hypothetical. He also introduced the concept of [[utility]], later picked up on and developed by [[Jeremy Bentham]]. Hume also coined the [[is–ought problem]], i.e. that just because something is does not mean that is how it ought to be, which was a very influential idea on normative politics.<ref>MacIntyre, A. (1959). Hume on "Is" and "Ought". The Philosophical Review, 68(4), 451–468. doi:10.2307/2182491</ref>

==== Adam Smith ====
Known as the father of liberalism, [[Adam Smith]] explained emergence of economic benefits from the self-interested behavior (the [[invisible hand]]) of artisans and traders. While praising its efficiency, Smith also expressed concern about the effects of industrial labor (e.g., repetitive activity) on workers. His work on moral sentiments sought to explain social bonds which enhance economic activity.

==== Immanuel Kant ====
[[Immanuel Kant]] argued that participation in civil society is undertaken not for self-preservation, as per [[Hobbes|Thomas Hobbes]], but as a moral duty. He was the first modern thinker who fully analyzed structure and meaning of obligation. He also argued that an international organization was needed to preserve world peace.


==== John Stuart Mill ====
==== John Stuart Mill ====
[[File:Stuart Mill G F Watts.jpg|thumb|[[John Stuart Mill]]]]
[[File:Stuart Mill G F Watts.jpg|thumb|[[John Stuart Mill]]]]
[[John Stuart Mill]]'s work on political philosophy begins in ''[[On Liberty]]''. ''On Liberty'' is the most influential statement of his liberal principles. He begins by distinguishing old and new threats to liberty. The old threat to liberty is found in traditional societies in which there is rule by one (a monarchy) or a few (an aristocracy). Though one could be worried about restrictions on liberty by benevolent monarchs or aristocrats, the traditional worry is that when rulers are politically unaccountable to the governed they will rule in their own interests, rather than the interests of the governed. Mill's explicit theory of rights is introduced in Chapter V of [[Utilitarianism (book)|''Utilitarianism'']] in the context of his sanction theory of duty, which is an indirect form of utilitarianism that identifies wrong actions as actions that it is useful to sanction. Mill then introduces justice as a proper part of the duty. Justice involves duties that are perfect duties—that is, duties that are correlated with rights.
[[John Stuart Mill]]'s work on political philosophy begins in ''[[On Liberty]]'', the most influential statement of his liberal principles. He begins by distinguishing old and new threats to liberty. The old threat to liberty is found in traditional societies in which there is rule by one (a monarchy) or a few (an aristocracy). Though one could be worried about restrictions on liberty by benevolent monarchs or aristocrats, the traditional worry is that when rulers are politically unaccountable to the governed they will rule in their own interests, rather than the interests of the governed. Mill's explicit theory of rights is introduced in Chapter V of [[Utilitarianism (book)|''Utilitarianism'']] in the context of his sanction theory of duty, which is an indirect form of utilitarianism that identifies wrong actions as actions that it is useful to sanction. Mill then introduces justice as a proper part of the duty. Justice involves duties that are perfect duties—that is, duties that are correlated with rights.
Justice implies something which it is not only right to do, and wrong not to do, but which some individual person can claim from us as a matter of right. These perfect duties will thus create liberty and collective freedom within a state.
Justice implies something which it is not only right to do, and wrong not to do, but which some individual person can claim from us as a matter of right. These perfect duties will thus create liberty and collective freedom within a state.
He uses, ''On Liberty'' to discuss gender equality in society. To Mill, Utilitarianism was the perfect tool to justify gender equality in The Subjection of Women, referring to the political, lawful and social subjection of women. When a woman was married, she entered legally binding coverture with her husband; once she married her legal existence as an individual was suspended under "marital unity". While it is easy to presume that a woman would not marry under these circumstances, being unmarried had social consequences. A woman could only advance in social stature and wealth if she had a rich husband to do the groundwork. Mill uses his Utilitarian ethics to assess how gender equality would be the best way to achieve "the greatest good for the greatest number" :
He uses, ''On Liberty'' to discuss gender equality in society. To Mill, Utilitarianism was the perfect tool to justify gender equality in The Subjection of Women, referring to the political, lawful and social subjection of women. When a woman was married, she entered legally binding coverture with her husband; once she married her legal existence as an individual was suspended under "marital unity". While it is easy to presume that a woman would not marry under these circumstances, being unmarried had social consequences. A woman could only advance in social stature and wealth if she had a rich husband to do the groundwork. Mill uses his Utilitarian ethics to assess how gender equality would be the best way to achieve "the greatest good for the greatest number" :
Line 157: Line 171:
The 'chief obstacle' to Mill relates to women's intellectual capability. The Subjection of Women looks at this in the women of society and argues that diminishing their intellectual potential wastes the knowledge and skill of half of the population; such knowledge lost could formulate ideas that could maximize pleasure for society.
The 'chief obstacle' to Mill relates to women's intellectual capability. The Subjection of Women looks at this in the women of society and argues that diminishing their intellectual potential wastes the knowledge and skill of half of the population; such knowledge lost could formulate ideas that could maximize pleasure for society.


==== Benjamin Constant ====
==== James Madison ====
[[James Madison]] was an American politician considered to be "Father of the [[United States Constitution|Constitution]]" and "Father of the [[United States Bill of Rights|Bill of Rights]]" of the United States. As a political theorist, he believed in [[separation of powers]] and proposed a comprehensive set of [[Separation of powers#Checks and balances|checks and balances]] that are necessary to protect the rights of an individual from the [[tyranny of the majority]].


==== Thomas Paine ====
{{Main|The Liberty of Ancients Compared with that of Moderns}}
[[Thomas Paine]] defended [[liberal democracy]], the [[American Revolution]], and the [[French Revolution]] in ''[[Common Sense (pamphlet)|Common Sense]]'' and The ''[[Rights of Man]]''.


==== Benjamin Constant ====
One of the first thinkers to go by the name of "liberal", Constant looked to Britain rather than to ancient Rome for a practical model of freedom in a large, commercial society. He drew a distinction between the "Liberty of the Ancients" and the "Liberty of the Moderns". The Liberty of the Ancients was participatory republican liberty, which gave the citizens the right to directly influence politics through debates and votes in the public assembly. In order to support this degree of participation, citizenship was a burdensome moral obligation requiring a considerable investment of time and energy. Generally, this required a sub-society of slaves to do much of the productive work, leaving the citizens free to deliberate on public affairs. Ancient Liberty was also limited to relatively small and homogenous societies, in which the people could be conveniently gathered together in one place to transact public affairs.
[[File:Roche - Portrait de Benjamin Constant (1767-1830), écrivain et homme politique - P1679 - Musée Carnavalet.jpg|thumb|[[Benjamin Constant]]]]
One of the first thinkers to go by the name of "liberal", [[Benjamin Constant]] looked to Britain rather than to ancient Rome for a practical model of freedom in a large, commercial society. He drew a distinction between the "Liberty of the Ancients" and the "Liberty of the Moderns". The Liberty of the Ancients was participatory republican liberty, which gave the citizens the right to directly influence politics through debates and votes in the public assembly. In order to support this degree of participation, citizenship was a burdensome moral obligation requiring a considerable investment of time and energy. Generally, this required a sub-society of slaves to do much of the productive work, leaving the citizens free to deliberate on public affairs. Ancient Liberty was also limited to relatively small and homogenous societies, in which the people could be conveniently gathered together in one place to transact public affairs.


The Liberty of the Moderns, in contrast, was based on the possession of civil liberties, the rule of law, and freedom from excessive state interference. Direct participation would be limited: a necessary consequence of the size of modern states, and also the inevitable result of having created a commercial society in which there are no slaves but almost everybody must earn a living through work. Instead, the voters would elect representatives, who would deliberate in Parliament on behalf of the people and would save citizens from the necessity of daily political involvement.
The Liberty of the Moderns, in contrast, was based on the possession of civil liberties, the rule of law, and freedom from excessive state interference. Direct participation would be limited: a necessary consequence of the size of modern states, and also the inevitable result of having created a commercial society in which there are no slaves but almost everybody must earn a living through work. Instead, the voters would elect representatives, who would deliberate in Parliament on behalf of the people and would save citizens from the necessity of daily political involvement.
Line 167: Line 185:
Moreover, Constant believed that, in the modern world, commerce was superior to war. He attacked Napoleon's martial appetite, on the grounds that it was illiberal and no longer suited to modern commercial social organization. Ancient Liberty tended to be warlike, whereas a state organized on the principles of Modern Liberty would be at peace with all peaceful nations.
Moreover, Constant believed that, in the modern world, commerce was superior to war. He attacked Napoleon's martial appetite, on the grounds that it was illiberal and no longer suited to modern commercial social organization. Ancient Liberty tended to be warlike, whereas a state organized on the principles of Modern Liberty would be at peace with all peaceful nations.


==== Thomas Hobbes ====
=== Romanticism ===
==== Jean-Jacques Rousseau ====
[[File:Leviathan by Thomas Hobbes.jpg|thumb|Frontispiece of ''[[Leviathan]]'']]
Rousseau analyzed the social contract as an expression of the [[general will]], and controversially argued in favor of absolute [[democracy]] where the people at large would act as [[Sovereignty|sovereign]]. ''[[The Social Contract]]'' (1762) outlines the basis for a legitimate political order within a framework of classical republicanism, becoming one of the most influential works of political philosophy in the Western tradition. It developed some of the ideas mentioned in earlier work, the article ''Discours sur l'oeconomie politique'' (''Discourse on Political Economy''), featured in [[Encyclopédie|Diderot's Encyclopédie]]. The treatise begins with the dramatic opening lines, "Man is born free, and everywhere he is in chains. Those who think themselves the masters of others are indeed greater slaves than they."
The main practical conclusion of Hobbes' political theory is that state or society can not be secure unless at the disposal of an absolute sovereign. From this follows the view that no individual can hold rights of property against the sovereign, and that the sovereign may therefore take the goods of its subjects without their consent.


Rousseau claimed that the state of nature was a primitive condition without law or morality, which human beings left for the benefits and necessity of cooperation. As society developed, the division of labor and private property required the human race to adopt institutions of law. In the degenerate phase of society, man is prone to be in frequent competition with his fellow men while also becoming increasingly dependent on them. This double pressure threatens both his survival and his freedom.
In [[Leviathan (Hobbes book)|''Leviathan'']], Hobbes set out his doctrine of the foundation of states and legitimate governments and creating an objective science of morality.{{citation needed|date=April 2020}} Much of the book is occupied with demonstrating the necessity of a strong central authority to avoid the evil of discord and civil war.


==== G. W. F. Hegel ====
Beginning from a mechanistic understanding of human beings and their passions, Hobbes postulates what life would be like without government, a condition which he calls the state of nature. In that state, each person would have a right, or license, to everything in the world. This, Hobbes argues, would lead to a "war of all against all".
[[G. W. F. Hegel]] emphasized the "cunning" of history, arguing that it followed a rational trajectory, even while embodying seemingly irrational forces. Hegel influenced Marx, [[Kierkegaard]], [[Nietzsche]], and [[Michael Oakeshott|Oakeshott]].


==== Jean-Jacques Rousseau ====
=== Modern era ===
==== Anarchism ====
{{main|Anarchism}}
{{Anarchism sidebar}}
[[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]] is commonly considered the father of modern [[anarchism]], specifically [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualism]]. [[Peter Kropotkin]] is another classic anarchist thinker, who was the most influential theorist of [[anarcho-communism]]. [[Mikhail Bakunin]]'s specific version of anarchism is called [[collectivist anarchism]]. [[Max Stirner]] was the main representative of the anarchist current known as [[individualist anarchism]] and the founder of [[ethical egoism]] which endorses anarchy.<ref>Hospers, John (1973). Rule-Egoism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 54 (4):391.</ref>


[[Henry David Thoreau]] was an influential anarchist thinker writing on topics such as [[pacifism]], [[environmentalism]] and [[civil disobedience]] – notably with his written work [[Civil Disobedience (Thoreau)|''Civil Disobedience'']] – who influenced later important political activists such as [[Leo Tolstoy]], [[Mahatma Gandhi]] and [[Martin Luther King Jr.]] Hard-lining on the individual citizen's right to seek justice over the state's, he was also an outspoken advocate and apologist for [[John Brown (abolitionist)|John Brown]] following his [[John Brown's raid on Harpers Ferry|raid on Harper's Ferry]] for the purpose of abolitionist efforts, writing ''[[A Plea for Captain John Brown]]'' and ''[[The Last Days of John Brown]]''.
''[[The Social Contract]]'' outlines the basis for a legitimate political order within a framework of classical republicanism. Published in 1762, it became one of the most influential works of political philosophy in the Western tradition. It developed some of the ideas mentioned in earlier work, the article ''Discours sur l'oeconomie politique'' (''Discourse on Political Economy''), featured in [[Encyclopédie|Diderot's Encyclopédie]]. The treatise begins with the dramatic opening lines, "Man is born free, and everywhere he is in chains. Those who think themselves the masters of others are indeed greater slaves than they."


[[Noam Chomsky]] is a leading critic of U.S. foreign policy, neoliberalism and contemporary state capitalism, the Israeli–Palestinian conflict, and mainstream news media. His ideas have proven highly influential in the anti-capitalist and anti-imperialist movements, and aligns with anarcho-syndicalism and libertarian socialism.<ref>{{cite web |url=https://chomsky.info/1994____/|title=On Linguistics and Politics, by Noam Chomsky}}</ref><ref>{{cite web |url=https://ourpolitics.net/noam-chomsky-philosophy-anarco-syndicalism-and-truth-to-power/|title=Noam Chomsky: Philosophy, Anarco-Syndicalism, and Truth to Power|date=20 March 2018}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |url=https://www.thenation.com/article/archive/noam-chomsky-neoliberalism-destroying-democracy/|title=Noam Chomsky: Neoliberalism is Destroying Our Democracy|journal=The Nation|date=2 June 2017|last1=Lydon|first1=Christopher}}</ref>
Rousseau claimed that the state of nature was a primitive condition without law or morality, which human beings left for the benefits and necessity of cooperation. As society developed, the division of labor and private property required the human race to adopt institutions of law. In the degenerate phase of society, man is prone to be in frequent competition with his fellow men while also becoming increasingly dependent on them. This double pressure threatens both his survival and his freedom.


=== Modern era ===
==== Austrian School ====
{{main|Austrian School}}
From the end of [[World War II]] until 1971, when [[John Rawls]] published ''[[A Theory of Justice]]'', political philosophy declined in the Anglo-American academic world, as analytic philosophers expressed skepticism about the possibility that normative judgments had cognitive content, and political science turned toward statistical methods and [[behavioralism]]. A number of continental European émigrés to Britain and the United States—including [[Karl Popper]], [[Friedrich Hayek]], [[Leo Strauss]], [[Hannah Arendt]], [[Isaiah Berlin]], [[Eric Voegelin]] and [[Judith Shklar]]—encouraged continued study in political philosophy in the Anglo-American world, but in the 1950s and 1960s, they and their students remained at odds with the analytic establishment.
{{Austrian School sidebar}}
[[Friedrich Hayek]] argued that central planning was inefficient because members of central bodies could not know enough to match the preferences of consumers and workers with existing conditions. Hayek further argued that [[command economy|central economic planning]]—a mainstay of socialism—would lead to a "total" state with dangerous power. He advocated [[free-market]] capitalism in which the main role of the state is to maintain the [[rule of law]] and let [[spontaneous order]] develop.


An economist of the Austrian School, [[Murray Rothbard]] was the central theorist of [[anarcho-capitalism]].
==== Marxism ====
The [[Marxism|Marxist]] critique of capitalism—developed with [[Friedrich Engels]]—was, alongside [[liberalism]] and [[fascism]], one of the defining ideological movements of the twentieth century.{{cn|date=October 2024}} The [[Industrial Revolution]] produced a parallel revolution in political thought. [[Urbanization]] and [[capitalism]] greatly reshaped society. During this same period, the [[History of Socialism|socialist movement]] began to form. In the mid-19th century, [[Marxism]] was developed, and [[socialism]] in general gained increasing popular support, mostly from the urban working class. Without breaking entirely from the past, Marx established principles that would be used by future revolutionaries of the 20th century, namely [[Vladimir Lenin]], [[Mao Zedong]], [[Ho Chi Minh]], and [[Fidel Castro]]. Though [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]]'s philosophy of history is similar to [[Immanuel Kant]]'s, and [[Karl Marx]]'s theory of revolution towards the common good is partly based on Kant's view of history—Marx declared that he was turning Hegel's dialectic, which was "standing on its head", "the right side up again".{{cn|date=October 2024}} Unlike Marx who believed in [[historical materialism]], Hegel believed in the ''[[Phenomenology of Spirit]]''.<ref>{{cite book|last=Kain|first=Philip J.|title=Marx and modern political theory|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kvG8DVBeT9QC&pg=PA1|year=1993|publisher=Rowman & Littlefield|isbn=978-0-8476-7866-2|pages=1–4|quote=Some of his texts, especially the ''Communist Manifesto'' made him seem like a sort of communist Descartes ...}}</ref> The [[Russian Revolution of 1917]]—and similar, albeit less successful, revolutions in many other European countries—brought [[communism]], in particular the political theory of [[Leninism]] but also on a smaller level [[Luxemburgism]], on the world stage.{{cn|date=October 2024}}


==== Christian democracy ====
Contemporaneously with the rise of analytic ethics in Anglo-American thought, several new lines of philosophy directed at the critique of existing societies arose between the 1950s and 1980s. Most of these took elements of Marxist economic analysis but combined them with a more cultural or ideological emphasis. Out of the [[Frankfurt School]], thinkers like [[Herbert Marcuse]], [[Theodor W. Adorno]], [[Max Horkheimer]], and [[Jürgen Habermas]] combined Marxian and Freudian perspectives. Along somewhat different lines, a number of other continental thinkers—still largely influenced by Marxism—put new emphases on [[structuralism]] and on a "return to [[Hegel]]". Within the (post-) structuralist line (though mostly not taking that label) are thinkers such as [[Gilles Deleuze]], [[Michel Foucault]], [[Claude Lefort]], and [[Jean Baudrillard]]. The [[Situationist International|Situationists]] were more influenced by Hegel; [[Guy Debord]], in particular, moved a Marxist analysis of [[commodity fetishism]] to the realm of consumption, and looked at the relation between consumerism and dominant ideology formation.
{{main|Christian democracy}}
{{Christian democracy sidebar}}
Christian democracy is a [[Centre-right politics|centre-right]] ideology inspired by [[Christian ethics#Politics|Christian social teaching]].<ref>{{cite book |last1=Caciagli |first1=Mario |title=The Cambridge History of Twentieth-Century Political Thought |last2=Robeck |first2=Cecil M |last3=Yong |first3=Amos |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2008 |isbn=9781139053600 |pages=165–180 |chapter=Christian democracy|url=}}</ref> It originated as a reaction against the industrialisation and urbanisation associated with ''[[laissez-faire]]'' capitalism.<ref>{{cite book|author-last=Riff|author-first=Michael|title=Dictionary of Modern Political Ideologies|publisher=Manchester University Press|year=1987|isbn=0-7190-3289-X|page=34|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=scxRAQAAIAAJ}}</ref> [[Jacques Maritain]] has been recognized as the leading Christian-democratic philosopher.<ref>{{cite book |last=Invernizzi Accetti |first=Carlo |title=What is Christian Democracy?: Politics, Religion and Ideology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2019 |location=New York|page=23}}</ref> Key ideas in Christian-democratic thought include [[personalism]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Invernizzi Accetti |first=Carlo |title=What is Christian Democracy?: Politics, Religion and Ideology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2019 |location=New York|pages=53–79}}</ref> [[Popolarismo|popularism]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Invernizzi Accetti |first=Carlo |title=What is Christian Democracy?: Politics, Religion and Ideology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2019 |location=New York|pages=80–110}}</ref> [[Subsidiarity (Catholicism)|subsidiarity]],<ref>{{cite book |last=Invernizzi Accetti |first=Carlo |title=What is Christian Democracy?: Politics, Religion and Ideology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2019 |location=New York|pages=111–138}}</ref> and [[Stewardship (theology)|stewardship]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Invernizzi Accetti |first=Carlo |title=What is Christian Democracy?: Politics, Religion and Ideology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2019 |location=New York|pages=243–244}}</ref>

In post-war Europe, Christian-democratic parties dominated politics in several nations—the [[Christian Democratic and Flemish|Christian People's Party]] in Belgium, [[Christian Democratic Union of Germany|CDU]] and [[Christian Social Union in Bavaria|CSU]] in Germany, [[Fine Gael]] and [[Fianna Fáil]] in Ireland, and [[Christian Democracy (Italy)|Christian Democracy]] in Italy.<ref>{{cite book |url=https://archive.org/details/europeanchristia0000unse |title=European Christian Democracy: Historical Legacies and Comparative Perspectives |publisher=University of Notre Dame Press |year=2003 |editor-last=Kselman |editor-first=Thomas |editor-last2=Buttigieg |editor-first2=Thomas |page=122}}</ref> Many post-war Europeans saw Christian democracy as a moderate alternative to the extremes of right-wing nationalism and left-wing communism.<ref>{{cite book |url=https://archive.org/details/conservativepoli0000unse/mode/2up |title=Conservative Politics in Western Europe |publisher=St. Martin's Press |year=1982 |editor-last=Layton-Henry |editor-first=Zig |isbn=9780312164188 |pages=131–133}}</ref> Christian-democratic parties were especially popular among European women, who often voted for these parties to a large extent due to their pro-family policies.<ref>{{cite book |url=https://archive.org/details/christiandemocra0000unse_p1x7/mode/2up |title=Christian Democracy in Europe : A Comparative Perspective |publisher=Pinter Publishers |year=1994 |editor-last=Hanley |editor-first=David |isbn=9781855670860 |pages=56–57}}</ref>

==== Communitarianism ====
{{main|Communitarianism}}
{{Communitarianism sidebar}}
Another debate developed around the (distinct) criticisms of liberal political theory made by [[Michael Walzer]], [[Michael Sandel]] and [[Charles Taylor (philosopher)|Charles Taylor]]. The liberal-communitarian debate is often considered valuable for generating a new set of philosophical problems, rather than a profound and illuminating clash of perspective. These and other communitarians (such as [[Alasdair MacIntyre]] and [[Daniel A. Bell]]) argue that, contra liberalism, communities are prior to individuals and therefore should be the center of political focus. Communitarians tend to support greater local control as well as economic and social policies which encourage the growth of [[social capital]].

==== Conservatism ====
{{main|Conservatism}}
{{Conservatism sidebar}}
An Irish member of the British parliament, [[Edmund Burke]] is credited with the creation of conservative thought. Burke's ''[[Reflections on the Revolution in France]]'' is the most popular of his writings where he denounced the [[French Revolution]], although he supported the [[American Revolution]].<ref>{{Cite web|title=A Guide to Edmund Burke's Political Thought|url=https://great.w3q2u1fy-liquidwebsites.com/burke/|access-date=15 October 2020|website=Edmund Burke|language=en-US}}</ref>

An exponent of [[liberal conservatism]], French sociologist [[Alexis de Tocqueville]] is known for his works ''[[Democracy in America]]'' and ''[[The Old Regime and the Revolution]]''.

A German political theorist of the [[Conservative Revolution]] movement, [[Carl Schmitt]] developed the concepts of the friend/enemy distinction, the [[state of exception]], and [[political theology]]. Though his most influential books were written in the 1920s, he continued to write prolifically until his death (in academic quasi-exile) in 1985. He heavily influenced 20th-century political philosophy.

[[Leo Strauss]] famously rejected modernity, mostly on the grounds of what he perceived to be modern political philosophy's excessive self-sufficiency of reason and flawed philosophical grounds for moral and political normativity. He argued instead that we should return to pre-modern thinkers for answers to contemporary issues. His philosophy was influential on the formation of [[neoconservatism]], and a number of his students later were members of the [[Presidency of George W. Bush|Bush administration]].


==== Intersectionality ====
==== Intersectionality ====
{{main|Intersectionality}}
[[Colonialism]] and [[racism]] were important issues that arose during the 1950s and 1960s. The rise of [[feminism]], [[LGBT social movements]] and the end of colonial rule and of the political exclusion of such minorities as [[African Americans]] and sexual minorities in the developed world has led to feminist, [[postcolonial]], and [[multicultural]] thought becoming significant. This led to a challenge to the [[social contract]] by philosophers [[Charles W. Mills]] in his book ''[[The Racial Contract]]'' and [[Carole Pateman]] in her book ''[[The Sexual Contract]]'' that the social contract excluded persons of colour and women respectively.
[[Colonialism]] and [[racism]] were important issues that arose during the 1950s and 1960s. The rise of [[feminism]], [[LGBT social movements]] and the end of colonial rule and of the political exclusion of such minorities as [[African Americans]] and sexual minorities in the developed world has led to feminist, [[postcolonial]], and [[multicultural]] thought becoming significant. This led to a challenge to the [[social contract]] by philosophers [[Charles W. Mills]] in his book ''[[The Racial Contract]]'' and [[Carole Pateman]] in her book ''[[The Sexual Contract]]'' that the social contract excluded persons of colour and women respectively. [[Michel Foucault]] critiqued the modern conception of power on the basis of the [[prison–industrial complex|prison complex]] and other prohibitive institutions, such as those that designate sexuality, madness and knowledge as the roots of their infrastructure—a critique that demonstrated that subjection is the power formation of subjects in any linguistic forum and that revolution cannot just be thought as the reversal of power between classes.


==== Social liberalism ====
==== Marxism ====
{{main|Marxism}}
In Anglo-American academic political philosophy, the publication of [[John Rawls]]'s ''[[A Theory of Justice]]'' in 1971 is considered a milestone. Rawls used a [[thought experiment]], the [[original position]], in which representative parties choose principles of justice for the basic structure of society from behind a veil of ignorance. Rawls also offered a criticism of utilitarian approaches to questions of political justice. [[Robert Nozick]]'s 1974 book ''[[Anarchy, State, and Utopia]]'', which won a [[National Book Award]], responded to the [[social liberalism]] of Rawls from a [[libertarianism|libertarian]] perspective, gaining much academic respectability.<ref>David Lewis Schaefer, [http://www.nysun.com/sports/reconsiderations-robert-nozick-and-coast-utopia Robert Nozick and the Coast of Utopia], [[The New York Sun]], 30 April 2008.</ref>
{{Marxism}}
[[Karl Marx]]'s critique of capitalism—developed with [[Friedrich Engels]]—was, alongside [[liberalism]] and [[fascism]], one of the defining ideological movements of the twentieth century.{{cn|date=October 2024}} The [[Industrial Revolution]] produced a parallel revolution in political thought. [[Urbanization]] and [[capitalism]] greatly reshaped society. During this same period, the [[History of Socialism|socialist movement]] began to form. In the mid-19th century, [[Marxism]] was developed, and [[socialism]] in general gained increasing popular support, mostly from the urban working class. Without breaking entirely from the past, Marx established principles that would be used by future revolutionaries of the 20th century, namely [[Vladimir Lenin]], [[Mao Zedong]], [[Ho Chi Minh]], and [[Fidel Castro]]. Though [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]]'s philosophy of history is similar to [[Immanuel Kant]]'s, and [[Karl Marx]]'s theory of revolution towards the common good is partly based on Kant's view of history—Marx declared that he was turning Hegel's dialectic, which was "standing on its head", "the right side up again".{{cn|date=October 2024}} Unlike Marx who believed in [[historical materialism]], Hegel believed in the ''[[Phenomenology of Spirit]]''.<ref>{{cite book|last=Kain|first=Philip J.|title=Marx and modern political theory|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kvG8DVBeT9QC&pg=PA1|year=1993|publisher=Rowman & Littlefield|isbn=978-0-8476-7866-2|pages=1–4|quote=Some of his texts, especially the ''Communist Manifesto'' made him seem like a sort of communist Descartes ...}}</ref> The [[Russian Revolution of 1917]]—and similar, albeit less successful, revolutions in many other European countries—brought [[communism]], in particular the political theory of [[Leninism]] but also on a smaller level [[Luxemburgism]], on the world stage.{{cn|date=October 2024}} [[Antonio Gramsci]] instigated the concept of [[hegemony]], arguing that the state and the ruling class use [[culture]] and [[ideology]] to gain the consent of the classes they rule over.


Contemporaneously with the rise of analytic ethics in Anglo-American thought, several new lines of philosophy directed at the critique of existing societies arose between the 1950s and 1980s. Most of these took elements of Marxist economic analysis but combined them with a more cultural or ideological emphasis. One of the founders of [[Western Marxism]], [[György Lukács]] developed the theory of [[class consciousness]] and introduced the concept of [[Reification (Marxism)|reification]] in ''[[History and Class Consciousness]]''. Out of the [[Frankfurt School]], thinkers like [[Herbert Marcuse]], [[Theodor W. Adorno]], [[Max Horkheimer]], and [[Jürgen Habermas]] combined Marxian and Freudian perspectives. Called the father of the [[New Left]], Marcuse introduced the concept of [[repressive desublimation]], in which social control can operate not only by direct control but also by manipulation of desire. Habermas pioneered such concepts as the [[public sphere]], [[communicative action]], and [[deliberative democracy]]. Along somewhat different lines, a number of other continental thinkers—still largely influenced by Marxism—put new emphases on [[structuralism]] and on a "return to [[Hegel]]". Within the (post-) structuralist line (though mostly not taking that label) are thinkers such as [[Gilles Deleuze]], [[Michel Foucault]], [[Claude Lefort]], and [[Jean Baudrillard]]. The [[Situationist International|Situationists]] were more influenced by Hegel; [[Guy Debord]], in particular, moved a Marxist analysis of [[commodity fetishism]] to the realm of consumption, and looked at the relation between consumerism and dominant ideology formation.
==== Communitarianism ====

Another debate developed around the (distinct) criticisms of liberal political theory made by [[Michael Walzer]], [[Michael Sandel]] and [[Charles Taylor (philosopher)|Charles Taylor]]. The [[Liberalism|liberal]]-[[communitarian]] debate is often considered valuable for generating a new set of philosophical problems, rather than a profound and illuminating clash of perspective. These and other communitarians (such as [[Alasdair MacIntyre]] and [[Daniel A. Bell]]) argue that, contra liberalism, communities are prior to individuals and therefore should be the center of political focus. Communitarians tend to support greater local control as well as economic and social policies which encourage the growth of [[social capital]].
==== Objectivism ====
{{main|Objectivism}}
[[Ayn Rand]] was the founder of Objectivism and a prime mover of the libertarian movement in mid-twentieth-century America. Advocating a complete, [[laissez-faire]] capitalism, Rand held that the proper role of government was exclusively the protection of individual rights without economic interference. The government was to be separated from economics the same way and for the same reasons it was separated from religion. Any governmental action not directed at the defense of individual rights would constitute the initiation of force (or threat of force), and therefore a violation not only of rights but also of the legitimate function of government.


==== Republicanism ====
==== Republicanism ====
{{main|Republicanism}}
A pair of overlapping political perspectives arising toward the end of the 20th century are [[republicanism]] (or neo- or civic-republicanism) and the [[capability approach]]. The resurgent republican movement aims to provide an alternative definition of liberty from [[Isaiah Berlin]]'s positive and negative forms of liberty, namely "liberty as non-domination." Unlike the American liberal movement which understands liberty as "non-interference," "non-domination" entails individuals not being subject to the arbitrary will of any other person. To a republican the mere status as a slave, regardless of how that slave is treated, is objectionable. Prominent republicans include historian [[Quentin Skinner]], jurist [[Cass Sunstein]], and political philosopher [[Philip Pettit]]. The capability approach, pioneered by economists [[Mahbub ul Haq]] and [[Amartya Sen]] and further developed by legal scholar [[Martha Nussbaum]], understands freedom under allied lines: the real-world ability to act. Both the capability approach and republicanism treat choice as something which must be resourced. In other words, it is not enough to be legally able to do something, but to have the real option of doing it.
{{Republicanism sidebar}}
A pair of overlapping political perspectives arising toward the end of the 20th century are republicanism (or neo- or civic-republicanism) and the [[capability approach]]. The resurgent republican movement aims to provide an alternative definition of liberty from [[Isaiah Berlin]]'s positive and negative forms of liberty, namely "liberty as non-domination."<ref>{{Citation|last1=Cherniss|first1=Joshua|title=Isaiah Berlin|date=2020|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/berlin/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Fall 2020|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=15 October 2020|last2=Hardy|first2=Henry}}</ref> Unlike the American liberal movement which understands liberty as "non-interference," "non-domination" entails individuals not being subject to the arbitrary will of any other person. To a republican the mere status as a slave, regardless of how that slave is treated, is objectionable. Prominent republicans include historian [[Quentin Skinner]], jurist [[Cass Sunstein]], and political philosopher [[Philip Pettit]]. The capability approach, pioneered by economists [[Mahbub ul Haq]] and [[Amartya Sen]] and further developed by legal scholar [[Martha Nussbaum]], understands freedom under allied lines: the real-world ability to act. Both the capability approach and republicanism treat choice as something which must be resourced. In other words, it is not enough to be legally able to do something, but to have the real option of doing it.


==== Social liberalism ====
== Influential political philosophers{{list entry too long}} ==
{{main|Social liberalism}}
{{famous|date=June 2023}}
In Anglo-American academic political philosophy, the publication of [[John Rawls]]'s ''[[A Theory of Justice]]'' in 1971 is considered a milestone. Rawls used a [[thought experiment]], the [[original position]], in which representative parties choose principles of justice for the basic structure of society from behind a veil of ignorance. Rawls also offered a criticism of utilitarian approaches to questions of political justice. [[Robert Nozick]]'s 1974 book ''[[Anarchy, State, and Utopia]]'', which won a [[National Book Award]], criticized the social liberalism of Rawls from a [[libertarianism|libertarian]] perspective, gaining much academic respectability.<ref>David Lewis Schaefer, [http://www.nysun.com/sports/reconsiderations-robert-nozick-and-coast-utopia Robert Nozick and the Coast of Utopia], [[The New York Sun]], 30 April 2008.</ref>
A larger [[list of political philosophers]] is intended to be closer to exhaustive. Listed below are some of the most [[Archetype|canonical]] or important thinkers, and especially philosophers whose central focus was in political philosophy and/or who are good representatives of a particular school of thought.

* [[Thomas Aquinas]]: In synthesizing Christian theology and Peripatetic (Aristotelian) teaching in his ''[[Treatise on Law]]'', Aquinas contends that God's gift of higher reason—manifest in human law by way of the divine virtues—gives way to the assembly of righteous government.<ref>{{Citation|last1=McInerny|first1=Ralph|title=Saint Thomas Aquinas|date=2018|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/aquinas/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Summer 2018|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=15 October 2020|last2=O'Callaghan|first2=John}}</ref>
==== Traditionalism ====
* [[Aristotle]]: Wrote his ''[[Politics (Aristotle)|Politics]]'' as an extension of his ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]''. Notable for the theories that humans are social animals, and that the [[polis]] (Ancient Greek city state) existed to bring about the good life appropriate to such animals. His political theory is based upon an ethics of [[perfectionism (philosophy)|perfectionism]] (as is [[Marx]]'s, on some readings).<ref>{{Citation|last=Shields|first=Christopher|title=Aristotle|date=2020|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/aristotle/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Fall 2020|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=15 October 2020}}</ref>
{{main|Traditionalism (perennialism)}}
* [[Mikhail Bakunin]]: After [[Pierre Joseph Proudhon]], Bakunin became the most important political philosopher of [[anarchism]]. His specific version of anarchism is called [[collectivist anarchism]].
[[Julius Evola]] called for a return to pre-Renaissance values of [[tradition]] and [[aristocracy]] while discussing possible ways to survive the inevitable collapse of the modern civilization and to bring forth a new order.
* [[Jeremy Bentham]]: The first thinker to analyze social justice in terms of maximization of aggregate individual benefits. Founded the philosophical/ethical school of thought known as [[utilitarianism]].<ref>{{Citation|last=Crimmins|first=James E.|title=Jeremy Bentham|date=2020|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/bentham/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Summer 2020|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=15 October 2020}}</ref>
* [[Isaiah Berlin]]: Developed the distinction between positive and negative liberty.<ref>{{Citation|last1=Cherniss|first1=Joshua|title=Isaiah Berlin|date=2020|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2020/entries/berlin/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Fall 2020|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=15 October 2020|last2=Hardy|first2=Henry}}</ref>
* [[Edmund Burke]]: Irish member of the British parliament, Burke is credited with the creation of [[Conservatism|conservative]] thought. Burke's ''[[Reflections on the Revolution in France]]'' is the most popular of his writings where he denounced the French revolution. Burke was one of the biggest supporters of the American Revolution.<ref>{{Cite web|title=A Guide to Edmund Burke's Political Thought|url=https://great.w3q2u1fy-liquidwebsites.com/burke/|access-date=15 October 2020|website=Edmund Burke|language=en-US}}</ref>
* [[Chanakya]]: Wrote influential text [[Arthashastra]], some of earliest political thinkers in Asian history.<ref>{{Cite web|title=Chanakya|url=https://www.worldhistory.org/Kautilya/|access-date=28 November 2020|website=[[World History Encyclopedia]]}}</ref>
* [[Noam Chomsky]]: He is widely recognized as having helped to spark the cognitive revolution in the human sciences, contributing to the development of a new cognitivistic framework for the study of language and the mind. Chomsky is a leading critic of U.S. foreign policy, neoliberalism and contemporary state capitalism, the Israeli–Palestinian conflict, and mainstream news media. His ideas have proven highly influential in the anti-capitalist and anti-imperialist movements, and aligns with anarcho-syndicalism and libertarian socialism;<ref>{{cite web |url=https://chomsky.info/1994____/|title=On Linguistics and Politics, by Noam Chomsky}}</ref><ref>{{cite web |url=https://ourpolitics.net/noam-chomsky-philosophy-anarco-syndicalism-and-truth-to-power/|title=Noam Chomsky: Philosophy, Anarco-Syndicalism, and Truth to Power|date=20 March 2018}}</ref><ref>{{cite journal |url=https://www.thenation.com/article/archive/noam-chomsky-neoliberalism-destroying-democracy/|title=Noam Chomsky: Neoliberalism is Destroying Our Democracy|journal=The Nation|date=2 June 2017|last1=Lydon|first1=Christopher}}</ref> these labels are contentious however, given Chomsky's support of [[Serbian nationalism]] and participation in [[Bosnian genocide denial|Bosnian Genocide denial]].
* [[Confucius]]: The first thinker to relate ethics to the political order.<ref>{{Citation |last=Csikszentmihalyi |first=Mark |title=Confucius |date=2020 |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2020/entries/confucius/ |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |editor-last=Zalta |editor-first=Edward N. |edition=Summer 2020 |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=22 April 2022}}</ref>
* [[Michel Foucault]]: Critiqued the modern conception of power on the basis of the [[prison–industrial complex|prison complex]] and other prohibitive institutions, such as those that designate sexuality, madness and knowledge as the roots of their infrastructure, a critique that demonstrated that subjection is the power formation of subjects in any linguistic forum and that revolution cannot just be thought as the reversal of power between classes.
* [[Antonio Gramsci]]: Instigated the concept of ''[[hegemony]]''. Argued that the [[Sovereign state|state]] and the ruling class use [[culture]] and [[ideology]] to gain the consent of the classes they rule over.
* [[Jürgen Habermas]]: Philosopher and social critic. He has pioneered such concepts as the [[public sphere]], [[communicative action]], and [[deliberative democracy]]. His early work was heavily influenced by the [[Frankfurt School]].
* [[Friedrich Hayek]]: He argued that central planning was inefficient because members of central bodies could not know enough to match the preferences of consumers and workers with existing conditions. Hayek further argued that [[command economy|central economic planning]]—a mainstay of socialism—would lead to a "total" state with dangerous power. He advocated [[free-market]] capitalism in which the main role of the state is to maintain the [[rule of law]] and let spontaneous order develop.
* [[G. W. F. Hegel]]: Emphasized the "cunning" of history, arguing that it followed a rational trajectory, even while embodying seemingly irrational forces; influenced Marx, [[Kierkegaard]], [[Nietzsche]], and [[Michael Oakeshott|Oakeshott]].
* [[Thomas Hobbes]]: Generally considered to have first articulated how the concept of a [[social contract]] that justifies the actions of rulers (even where contrary to the individual desires of governed citizens), can be reconciled with a conception of sovereignty.
* [[David Hume]]: Hume criticized the social contract theory of John Locke and others as resting on a myth of some actual agreement. Hume was a realist in recognizing the role of force to forge the existence of states and that [[consent of the governed]] was merely hypothetical. He also introduced the concept of [[utility]], later picked up on and developed by [[Jeremy Bentham]]. Hume also coined the 'is/ought' problem i.e. the idea that just because something is does not mean that is how it ought to be. This was very influential on normative politics<ref>MacIntyre, A. (1959). Hume on "Is" and "Ought". The Philosophical Review, 68(4), 451–468. doi:10.2307/2182491</ref>
* [[Thomas Jefferson]]: Politician and political theorist during the [[American Enlightenment]]. Expanded on the philosophy of Thomas Paine by instrumenting [[republicanism]] in the United States. Most famous for the [[United States Declaration of Independence]].
* [[Immanuel Kant]]: Argued that participation in civil society is undertaken not for self-preservation, as per [[Hobbes|Thomas Hobbes]], but as a moral duty. First modern thinker who fully analyzed structure and meaning of obligation. Argued that an international organization was needed to preserve world peace.
* [[Peter Kropotkin]]: One of the classic anarchist thinkers and the most influential theorist of [[anarcho-communism]].
* [[John Locke]]: Like Hobbes, described a social contract theory based on citizens' fundamental rights in the [[state of nature]]. He departed from Hobbes in that, based on the assumption of a society in which moral values are independent of governmental authority and widely shared, he argued for a government with power limited to the protection of personal property. His arguments may have been deeply influential to the formation of the [[United States Constitution]].
* [[György Lukács]]: Hungarian [[Marxist]] theorist, aesthetician, literary historian, and critic. One of the founders of [[Western Marxism]]. In his ''magnum opus'' ''[[History and Class Consciousness]]'', he developed the Marxist theory of [[class consciousness]] and introduced the concept of "[[Reification (Marxism)|reification]]".
* [[Niccolò Machiavelli]]: First systematic analysis of how politics necessitates expedient and evil actions. Gave an account of statecraft in a realistic point of view instead of relying on idealism. Machiavelli also relays recommendations on how to run a well ordered [[Republicanism|republican]] state, as he viewed them to be better forms of government than autocracies.
* [[James Madison]]: American politician and protege of Jefferson considered to be "Father of the [[United States Constitution|Constitution]]" and "Father of the [[United States Bill of Rights|Bill of Rights]]" of the United States. As a political theorist, he believed in [[separation of powers]] and proposed a comprehensive set of [[Separation of powers#Checks and balances|checks and balances]] that are necessary to protect the rights of an individual from the [[tyranny of the majority]].
* [[Herbert Marcuse]]: Called the father of the [[new left]]. One of the principal thinkers within the [[Frankfurt School]], and generally important in efforts to fuse the thought of [[Sigmund Freud]] and [[Karl Marx]]. Introduced the concept of "[[repressive desublimation]]", in which social control can operate not only by direct control, but also by manipulation of desire. His work [[Eros and Civilization]] and notion of a non-repressive society was influential on the 1960s and its counter-cultural social movements.
* [[Julius Evola]]: Called for a return to Pre-Renaissance values of [[Tradition|Traditionalism]] and [[Aristocracy]] while discussing possible ways to survive the inevitable collapse of the modern civilization and to bring forth a new order.
* [[Karl Marx]]: In large part, added the historical dimension to an understanding of society, culture and economics. Created the concept of ''ideology'' in the sense of (true or false) beliefs that shape and control social actions. Analyzed the fundamental nature of class as a mechanism of governance and social interaction. Profoundly influenced world politics with his theory of communism.
* [[Mencius]]: One of the most important thinkers in the Confucian school, he is the first theorist to make a coherent argument for an obligation of rulers to the ruled.<ref>{{Citation|last=Van Norden|first=Bryan|title=Mencius|date=2019|url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2019/entries/mencius/|encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy|editor-last=Zalta|editor-first=Edward N.|edition=Fall 2019|publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University|access-date=15 October 2020}}</ref>
* [[John Stuart Mill]]: A [[utilitarian]], and the person who named the system; he goes further than Bentham by laying the foundation for liberal democratic thought in general and modern, as opposed to classical, liberalism in particular. Articulated the place of individual liberty in an otherwise utilitarian framework.
* [[Charles de Secondat, Baron de Montesquieu|Montesquieu]]: Analyzed protection of the people by a "balance of powers" in the divisions of a state.
* [[Mozi]]: Eponymous founder of the Mohist school, advocated a form of [[Mohist consequentialism|consequentialism]].
* [[Friedrich Nietzsche]]: Philosopher who became a powerful influence on a broad spectrum of 20th-century political currents in [[anarchism]], [[fascism]], [[libertarianism]], and [[conservatism]]. His interpreters have debated the content of his political philosophy.
* [[Robert Nozick]]: Criticized Rawls, and argued for [[libertarianism]], by appeal to a hypothetical history of the [[State (polity)|state]] and of [[property]].
* [[Thomas Paine]]: [[Age of Enlightenment|Enlightenment]] writer who defended [[liberal democracy]], the [[American Revolution]], and the [[French Revolution]] in ''[[Common Sense (pamphlet)|Common Sense]]'' and The ''[[Rights of Man]]''.
* [[Plato]]: Wrote a lengthy dialogue ''[[The Republic (Plato)|The Republic]]'' in which he laid out his political philosophy: citizens should be divided into three categories. One category of people are the rulers: they should be philosophers, according to Plato, this idea is based on his [[Theory of Forms]]. His interpreters have debated the content of his political philosophy.
* [[Pierre-Joseph Proudhon]]: Commonly considered the father of modern [[anarchism]], specifically [[Mutualism (economic theory)|mutualism]].
* [[Ayn Rand]]: Founder of [[Objectivism]] and prime mover of the Objectivist and Libertarian movements in mid-twentieth-century America. Advocated a complete, laissez-faire capitalism. Rand held that the proper role of government was exclusively the protection of individual rights without economic interference. The government was to be separated from economics the same way and for the same reasons it was separated from religion. Any governmental action not directed at the defense of individual rights would constitute the initiation of force (or threat of force), and therefore a violation not only of rights but also of the legitimate function of government.
* [[John Rawls]]: Revitalized the study of normative political philosophy in Anglo-American universities with his 1971 book [[A Theory of Justice]], which uses a version of [[social contract theory]] to answer fundamental questions about [[justice]] and to criticise [[utilitarianism]].
* [[Murray Rothbard]]: The central theorist of [[anarcho-capitalism]] and an [[Austrian School]] economist.
* [[Jean-Jacques Rousseau]]: Analyzed the social contract as an expression of the [[general will]], and controversially argued in favor of absolute [[democracy]] where the people at large would act as [[Sovereignty|sovereign]].
* [[Carl Schmitt]]: German political theorist, tied to the Nazis, who developed the concepts of the Friend/Enemy Distinction and the State of exception. Though his most influential books were written in the 1920s, he continued to write prolifically until his death (in academic quasi-exile) in 1985. He heavily influenced 20th-century political philosophy both within the Frankfurt School and among others, not all of whom are philosophers, such as [[Jacques Derrida]], [[Hannah Arendt]], and [[Giorgio Agamben]].
* [[Adam Smith]]: Often said to have founded modern [[economics]]; explained emergence of economic benefits from the self-interested behavior ("the invisible hand") of artisans and traders. While praising its efficiency, Smith also expressed concern about the effects of industrial labor (e.g., repetitive activity) on workers. His work on moral sentiments sought to explain social bonds which enhance economic activity.
* [[Max Stirner]]: Important thinker within [[anarchism]] and the main representative of the anarchist current known as [[individualist anarchism]]. He was also the founder of ethical egoism which endorses anarchy.<ref>Hospers, John (1973). Rule-Egoism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 54 (4):391.</ref>
* [[Leo Strauss]]: Famously rejected modernity, mostly on the grounds of what he perceived to be modern political philosophy's excessive self-sufficiency of reason and flawed philosophical grounds for moral and political normativity. He argued instead we should return to pre-modern thinkers for answers to contemporary issues. His philosophy was influential on the formation of [[neoconservatism]], and a number of his students later were members of the [[Presidency of George W. Bush|Bush administration]].
* [[Henry David Thoreau]]: Influential American thinker on such diverse later political positions and topics such as [[pacifism]], [[anarchism]], [[environmentalism]] and [[civil disobedience]]- notably with his written work [[Civil Disobedience (Thoreau)|''Civil Disobedience'']]- who influenced later important political activists such as [[Leo Tolstoy]], [[Mahatma Gandhi]] and [[Martin Luther King Jr.]] Hard-lining on the individual citizen's right to seek justice over the state's, he was also an outspoken advocate and apologist for [[John Brown (abolitionist)|John Brown]] following his [[John Brown's raid on Harpers Ferry|raid on Harper's Ferry]] for the purpose of abolitionist efforts, writing two pieces with one pleading for his mercy- ''[[A Plea for Captain John Brown]]''- and the other- ''[[The Last Days of John Brown]]''- describing the life that had been lived fully.
* [[Alexis de Tocqueville]]: A French political scientist and diplomat, known for his works ''[[Democracy in America]]'' and ''[[The Old Regime and the Revolution]]''.
* [[Voltaire]]: French Enlightenment writer, poet, and philosopher famous for his advocacy of civil liberties, including freedom of religion and free trade.


== See also ==
== See also ==
*[[History of political thought]]
{{div col|colwidth=22em}}
* [[Anarchist schools of thought]]
*[[Philosophy of law]]
*[[Political ethics]]
* [[Consensus decision-making]]
*[[Political ideologies]]
* [[Consequentialist justifications of the state]]
* [[Critical theory]]
*[[Political journalism]]
* [[Engaged theory]]
*[[Political theology]]
* [[Justification for the state]]
* [[Majoritarianism]]
* [[Panarchy (political philosophy)|Panarchy]]
* [[Philosophy of law]]
* [[Political ideologies]]
* [[Political journalism]]
* [[Political sophistication]]
* [[Political spectrum]]
* [[Political Theory (journal)|''Political Theory'']]
* [[Post-structuralism]]
* [[Progressivism]]
* [[Rechtsstaat]]
* [[Rule according to higher law]]
* [[Semiotics of culture]]
* [[State-centered theory]]
* [[Theodemocracy]]
{{div col end}}


== References ==
== References ==
Line 280: Line 274:


== Further reading ==
== Further reading ==
* Academic journals dedicated to political philosophy include: ''Political Theory'', ''[[Philosophy and Public Affairs]]'', ''[[Contemporary Political Theory]]'', ''Theory & Event'', ''[[Constellations (journal)|Constellations]]'', and ''Journal of Political Philosophy''
Academic journals dedicated to political philosophy include: ''[[Political Theory (journal)|Political Theory]]'', ''[[Philosophy and Public Affairs]]'', ''[[Contemporary Political Theory]]'', ''[[Constellations (journal)|Constellations]]'', and ''[[The Journal of Political Philosophy]]''

* {{cite book|last=Assiter|first=Alison|author-link=Alison Assiter|title=Kierkegaard, Metaphysics and Political Theory Unfinished selves|publisher=Continuum International Publishing Group|year=2009|isbn=978-0-8264-9831-1}}
* {{cite book|author-last=Wolff|author-first=Jonathan|title=An Introduction to Political Philosophy|publisher=Oxford University Press|year=2006|isbn=9780199296095|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=FVOcAQAAQBAJ}}
* Bielskis, Andrius 2005. ''Towards a Postmodern Understanding of the Political''. Basingstoke, New York: Palgrave-Macmillan.
* {{cite book|first1=James F.|last1=Bohman|first2=William|last2=Rehg|title=Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics|year=1997|publisher=MIT Press|isbn=978-0-262-52241-0}}
* {{cite book|author-last=Miller|author-first=David|title=Political Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction|publisher=Oxford University Press|year=2003|isbn=9780192803955|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=5qziSqDr67MC}}
* {{cite book|first=Gad|last=Barzilai|author-link=Gad Barzilai|title=Communities and Law: Politics and Cultures of Legal Identities|year=2003|publisher=The University of Michigan Press|isbn=978-0-47211315-6}}
* {{cite book|author-last=Strauss|author-first=Leo|title=History of Political Philosophy|publisher=University of Chicago Press|year=2012|isbn=9780226924717|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=E7mScxst9UoC}}
* {{cite book|first=Wendell John|last=Coats, Jr.|title=A Theory of Republican Character and Related Essays|year=1994|publisher=Susquehanna University Press|isbn=0-945636-58-X}}
* {{cite book|author-last=Kymlicka|author-first=Will|title=Contemporary Political Philosophy|publisher=Oxford University Press|year=2002|isbn=9780198782742|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yYCcAQAAQBAJ}}
* {{cite book|first=Wendell John|last=Coats, Jr.|title=The Activity of Politics and Related Essays|year=1989|publisher=Susquehanna University Press|isbn=0-941664-95-3}}
* {{cite book|author-last=Rawls|author-first=John|title=Lectures on the History of Political Philosophy|publisher=Harvard University Press|year=2009|isbn=9780674042568|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yKclZky1oUkC}}
* {{cite book|first1=Roberto|last1=Gatti|first2=Luca|last2=Alici|title=Filosofia politica. Gli autori, i concetti. Edizione ampliata. |year=2018|publisher=[[Morcelliana]]|isbn=978-8-828-40006-6}}
* {{cite book | last=Glinka | first=Lukasz Andrzej | title=Aryan Unconscious : Archetype of Discrimination, History & Politics | publisher=Cambridge International Science Publishing | publication-place=Cambridge | date=2014 | isbn=978-1-907343-59-9 | oclc=896613668}}
* {{cite book|first1=Amy|last1=Gutmann|author1-link=Amy Gutmann|first2=Dennis F.|last2=Thompson|author2-link=Dennis F. Thompson|title=Democracy and Disagreement|year=1996|publisher=Harvard University Press|isbn=978-0-674-19766-4}}
* {{cite book|last1=Gutmann|first1=Amy|last2=Thompson|first2=Dennis|title=Why Deliberative Democracy?|year=2004|publisher=Princeton University Press|isbn=978-0-691-12019-5}}
* {{cite book|first=Eric |last=Nelson|author-link=Eric Nelson (historian)|title=The Hebrew Republic: Jewish Sources and the Transformation of European Political Thought|publisher=Harvard University Press|date=2010}}
* {{cite book|last1=Parkinson|first1=John|last2=Mansbridge|first2=Jane|author-link2=Jane Mansbridge|title=Deliberative Systems: Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale|year=2012|publisher=Cambridge University Press|isbn=978-1-107-02539-4 }}
* [[Alexander F. Tsvirkun]] 2008. ''History of political and legal Teachings of Ukraine''. Kharkiv.
* {{cite book|last=Zippelius|first=Reinhold|author-link=Reinhold Zippelius|title=Geschichte der Staatsideen|year=2003|publisher=C.H. Beck|isbn=978-3-406-49494-9}}


== External links ==
== External links ==

Latest revision as of 16:20, 5 November 2024

Political philosophy, or political theory, is the philosophical study of government, addressing questions about the nature, scope, and legitimacy of public agents and institutions and the relationships between them. Its topics include politics, justice, liberty, property, rights, law, and authority: what they are, if they are needed, what makes a government legitimate, what rights and freedoms it should protect, what form it should take, what the law is, and what duties citizens owe to a legitimate government, if any, and when it may be legitimately overthrown, if ever.

Political theory also engages questions of a broader scope, tackling the political nature of phenomena and categories such as identity, culture, sexuality, race, wealth, human-nonhuman relations, ethics, religion, and more.

Political philosophy is a branch of philosophy,[1] but it has also played a major part in political science, within which a strong focus has historically been placed on both the history of political thought and contemporary political theory (from normative political theory to various critical approaches).

Purpose

[edit]

In the Oxford Handbook of Political Theory (2009), the field is described as: "[...] an interdisciplinary endeavor whose center of gravity lies at the humanities end of the happily still undisciplined discipline of political science ... For a long time, the challenge for the identity of political theory has been how to position itself productively in three sorts of location: in relation to the academic disciplines of political science, history, and philosophy; between the world of politics and the more abstract, ruminative register of theory; between canonical political theory and the newer resources (such as feminist and critical theory, discourse analysis, film and film theory, popular and political culture, mass media studies, neuroscience, environmental studies, behavioral science, and economics) on which political theorists increasingly draw."[2][excessive quote]

In a 1956 American Political Science Review report authored by Harry Eckstein, political philosophy as a discipline had utility in two ways:

the utility of political philosophy might be found either in the intrinsic ability of the best of past political thought to sharpen the wits of contemporary political thinkers, much as any difficult intellectual exercise sharpens the mind and deepens the imagination, or in the ability of political philosophy to serve as a thought-saving device by providing the political scientist with a rich source of concepts, models, insights, theories, and methods.[3]

In his 2001 book A Student's Guide to Political Philosophy, Harvey Mansfield contrasts political philosophy with political science. He argues that political science "apes" the natural sciences and is a rival to political philosophy, replacing normative words like "good", "just", and "noble" with words like "utility" or "preferences". According to Mansfield, political science rebelled from political philosophy in the seventeenth century and declared itself distinct and separate in the positivist movement of the late nineteenth century. He writes:

"Today political science is often said to be 'descriptive' or 'empirical,' concerned with facts; political philosophy is called 'normative' because it expresses values. But these terms merely repeat in more abstract form the difference between political science, which seeks agreement, and political philosophy, which seeks the best."

According to Mansfield, political science and political philosophy are two distinct kinds of political philosophy, one modern and the other ancient. He stresses that the only way to understand modern political science and its ancient alternative fully is to enter the history of political philosophy and to study the tradition handed down over the centuries. Although modern political science feels no obligation to look at its roots, and might even denigrate the subject as if it could not be of any real significance, he says, "our reasoning shows that the history of political philosophy is required for understanding its substance".

History

[edit]

Ancient traditions

[edit]

Ancient India

[edit]

Indian political philosophy in ancient times demarcated a clear distinction between (1) nation and state (2) religion and state. The constitutions of Hindu states evolved over time and were based on political and legal treatises and prevalent social institutions. The institutions of state were broadly divided into governance, diplomacy, administration, defense, law and order. Mantranga, the principal governing body of these states, consisted of the King, Prime Minister, Commander in chief of army, Chief Priest of the King. The Prime Minister headed the committee of ministers along with head of executive (Maha Amatya).

Chanakya was a 4th-century BC Indian political philosopher.[4] The Arthashastra provides an account of the science of politics for a wise ruler, policies for foreign affairs and wars, the system of a spy state and surveillance and economic stability of the state.[5] Chanakya quotes several authorities including Bruhaspati, Ushanas, Prachetasa Manu, Parasara, and Ambi, and described himself as a descendant of a lineage of political philosophers, with his father Chanaka being his immediate predecessor.[6] Another influential extant Indian treatise on political philosophy is the Sukra Neeti.[7][8] An example of a code of law in ancient India is the Manusmṛti or Laws of Manu.[9]

Ancient China

[edit]
Portrait of Confucius, c. 1770

Chinese political philosophy dates back to the Spring and Autumn period, specifically with Confucius in the 6th century BC. Chinese political philosophy was developed as a response to the social and political breakdown of the country characteristic of the Spring and Autumn period and the Warring States period. Confucius was the first thinker to relate ethics to the political order.[10] The major philosophies during the period, Confucianism, Legalism, Mohism, Agrarianism and Taoism, each had a political aspect to their philosophical schools. Philosophers such as Confucius, Mencius,[11] and Mozi, focused on political unity and political stability as the basis of their political philosophies. Confucianism advocated a hierarchical, meritocratic government based on empathy, loyalty, and interpersonal relationships. Legalism advocated a highly authoritarian government. Mohism advocated a communal, decentralized government centered on frugality and asceticism. The Agrarians advocated a peasant utopian communalism and egalitarianism.[12] Taoism advocated a proto-anarchism. Legalism was the dominant political philosophy of the Qin dynasty, but was replaced by State Confucianism in the Han dynasty. Each had religious or mythic aspects as well that played into how they viewed fairness in governance.

Prior to China's adoption of communism, State Confucianism remained the dominant political philosophy of China up to the 20th century.[13]

Ancient Greece

[edit]
Plato (left) and Aristotle (right), from a detail of The School of Athens, a fresco by Raphael. Plato's Republic and Aristotle's Politics secured the two Greek philosophers as two of the most influential political philosophers.

Western political philosophy originates in the philosophy of ancient Greece, where political philosophy dates back to at least Plato.[14] Ancient Greece was dominated by city-states, which experimented with various forms of political organization. Plato grouped forms of government into five categories of descending stability and morality: republic, timocracy, oligarchy, democracy and tyranny. One of the first, extremely important classical works of political philosophy is Plato's Republic,[14] which was followed by Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics and Politics.[15] Aristotle is notable for the theories that humans are social animals, and that the polis (Ancient Greek city state) existed to bring about the good life appropriate to such animals.[16] Roman political philosophy was influenced by the Stoics and the Roman statesman Cicero.[17]

Medieval Europe

[edit]

Medieval political philosophy in Europe was heavily influenced by Christian thinking. It had much in common with the Mutazilite Islamic thinking in that the Roman Catholics thought subordinating philosophy to theology did not subject reason to revelation but in the case of contradictions, subordinated reason to faith as the Asharite of Islam. The Scholastics by combining the philosophy of Aristotle with the Christianity of St. Augustine emphasized the potential harmony inherent in reason and revelation.[18] Scholastic political philosophy dominated European thought for centuries even unto the Renaissance.[19]

Some medieval political philosophers, such as Aquinas in his Summa Theologica, developed the idea that a king who is a tyrant is no king at all and could be overthrown. Others, like Nicole Oresme in his Livre de Politiques, categorically denied this right to overthrow an unjust ruler. Magna Carta, viewed by many as a cornerstone of Anglo-American political liberty, explicitly proposes the right to revolt against the ruler for justice's sake. Other documents similar to Magna Carta are found in other European countries such as Spain and Hungary.[20]

Saint Augustine

[edit]

The early Christian philosophy of Augustine of Hippo was heavily influenced by Plato. A key change brought about by Christian thought was the moderation of the Stoicism and theory of justice of the Roman world, as well emphasis on the role of the state in applying mercy as a moral example. Augustine also preached that one was not a member of his or her city, but was either a citizen of the City of God (Civitas Dei) or the Earthly City (Civitas Terrena). Augustine's City of God is an influential work of this period that attacked the thesis, held by many Christian Romans, that the Christian view could be realized on Earth.[21]

St. Thomas Aquinas

[edit]

Perhaps the most influential political philosopher of medieval Europe was St. Thomas Aquinas who helped reintroduce Aristotle's works, which had only been transmitted to Catholic Europe through Muslim Spain, along with the commentaries of Averroes. Aquinas meticulously dealt with the varieties of philosophy of law. According to Aquinas, there are four kinds of law:

  1. Eternal law ("the divine government of everything")
  2. Divine positive law (having been "posited" by God; external to human nature)
  3. Natural law (the right way of living discoverable by natural reason; what cannot-not be known; internal to human nature)
  4. Human law (what we commonly call "law"—including customary law; the law of the Communitas Perfecta)

Aquinas never discusses the nature or categorization of canon law. There is scholarly debate surrounding the place of canon law within the Thomistic jurisprudential framework. Aquinas was an incredibly influential thinker in the Natural Law tradition.

In synthesizing Christian theology and Peripatetic (Aristotelian) teaching in his Treatise on Law, Aquinas contends that God's gift of higher reason—manifest in human law by way of the divine virtues—gives way to the assembly of righteous government.[22]

Islamic Political Evolution

[edit]

Mutazilite vs. Asharite

[edit]

The rise of Islam, based on both the Qur'an and Muhammad strongly altered the power balances and perceptions of origin of power in the Mediterranean region. Early Islamic philosophy emphasized an inexorable link between science and religion, and the process of ijtihad to find truth—in effect all philosophy was "political" as it had real implications for governance. This view was challenged by the "rationalist" Mutazilite philosophers, who held a more Hellenic view, reason above revelation, and as such are known to modern scholars as the first speculative theologians of Islam; they were supported by a secular aristocracy who sought freedom of action independent of the Caliphate. By the late ancient period, however, the "traditionalist" Asharite view of Islam had in general triumphed. According to the Asharites, reason must be subordinate to the Quran and the Sunna.[23]

Islamic political philosophy, was, indeed, rooted in the very sources of Islam—i.e., the Qur'an and the Sunnah, the words and practices of Muhammad—thus making it essentially theocratic. However, in Western thought, it is generally supposed that it was a specific area peculiar merely to the great philosophers of Islam: al-Kindi (Alkindus), al-Farabi (Abunaser), İbn Sina (Avicenna), Ibn Bajjah (Avempace) and Ibn Rushd (Averroes). The political conceptions of Islam such as kudrah (power), sultan, ummah, cemaa (obligation)-and even the "core" terms of the Qur'an—i.e., ibadah (worship), din (religion), rab (master) and ilah (deity)—is taken as the basis of an analysis. Hence, not only the ideas of the Muslim political philosophers but also many other jurists and ulama posed political ideas and theories. For example, the ideas of the Khawarij in the very early years of Islamic history on Khilafa and Ummah, or that of Shia Islam on the concept of Imamah are considered proofs of political thought. The clashes between the Ehl-i Sunna and Shia in the 7th and 8th centuries had a genuine political character. Political thought was not purely rooted in theism, however. Aristotleanism flourished as the Islamic Golden Age saw rise to a continuation of the peripatetic philosophers who implemented the ideas of Aristotle in the context of the Islamic world. Abunaser, Avicenna and Ibn Rushd where part of this philosophical school who claimed that human reason surpassed mere coincidence and revelation. They believed, for example, that natural phenomena occur because of certain rules (made by god), not because god interfered directly (unlike Al-Ghazali and his followers).[24][25][26]

Other notable political philosophers of the time include Nizam al-Mulk, a Persian scholar and vizier of the Seljuq Empire who composed the Siyasatnama, or the "Book of Government" in English. In it, he details the role of the state in terms of political affairs (i.e. how to deal with political opponents without ruining the government's image), as well as its duty to protect the poor and reward the worthy. In his other work, he explains how the state should deal with other issues such as supplying jobs to immigrants like the Turkmens who were coming from the north (present day southern Russia, Kazakhstan, Turkmenistan and Uzbekistan).[27]

Ibn Khaldun

[edit]

The 14th-century Arab scholar Ibn Khaldun is considered one of the greatest political theorists. The British philosopher-anthropologist Ernest Gellner considered Ibn Khaldun's definition of government, "...an institution which prevents injustice other than such as it commits itself," the best in the history of political theory. For Ibn Khaldun, government should be restrained to a minimum for as a necessary evil, it is the constraint of men by other men.[28]

European Renaissance

[edit]

During the Renaissance secular political philosophy began to emerge after about a century of theological political thought in Europe. While the Middle Ages did see secular politics in practice under the rule of the Holy Roman Empire, the academic field was wholly scholastic and therefore Christian in nature.

Niccolò Machiavelli

[edit]
Niccolò Machiavelli

One of the most influential works during this burgeoning period was Niccolò Machiavelli's The Prince, written between 1511–12 and published in 1532, after Machiavelli's death. That work, as well as The Discourses, a rigorous analysis of classical antiquity, did much to influence modern political thought in the West. A minority (including Jean-Jacques Rousseau) interpreted The Prince as a satire meant to be given to the Medici after their recapture of Florence and their subsequent expulsion of Machiavelli from Florence.[29] Though the work was written for the di Medici family in order to perhaps influence them to free him from exile, Machiavelli supported the Republic of Florence rather than the oligarchy of the Medici family. At any rate, Machiavelli presents a pragmatic and somewhat consequentialist view of politics, whereby good and evil are mere means used to bring about an end—i.e., the acquisition and maintenance of absolute power. Thomas Hobbes, well known for his theory of the social contract, goes on to expand this view at the start of the 17th century during the English Renaissance. Although neither Machiavelli nor Hobbes believed in the divine right of kings, they both believed in the inherent selfishness of the individual. It was necessarily this belief that led them to adopt a strong central power as the only means of preventing the disintegration of the social order.[30]

Thomas Hobbes

[edit]
Frontispiece of Leviathan

The main practical conclusion of Hobbes' political theory is that state or society can not be secure unless at the disposal of an absolute sovereign. From this follows the view that no individual can hold rights of property against the sovereign, and that the sovereign may therefore take the goods of its subjects without their consent.

In Leviathan, Hobbes set out his doctrine of the foundation of states and legitimate governments and creating an objective science of morality.[citation needed] Much of the book is occupied with demonstrating the necessity of a strong central authority to avoid the evil of discord and civil war.

Beginning from a mechanistic understanding of human beings and their passions, Hobbes postulates what life would be like without government, a condition which he calls the state of nature. In that state, each person would have a right, or license, to everything in the world. This, Hobbes argues, would lead to a "war of all against all".

European Enlightenment

[edit]

During the Enlightenment period, new theories emerged about what the human was and is and about the definition of reality and the way it was perceived, along with the discovery of other societies in the Americas, and the changing needs of political societies (especially in the wake of the English Civil War, the American Revolution, the French Revolution, and the Haitian Revolution). These new theories led to new questions and insights by thinkers such as Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Benjamin Constant and Jean-Jacques Rousseau.

These theorists were driven by two basic questions: one, by what right or need do people form states; and two, what the best form for a state could be. These fundamental questions involved a conceptual distinction between the concepts of "state" and "government." It was decided that "state" would refer to a set of enduring institutions through which power would be distributed and its use justified. The term "government" would refer to a specific group of people who occupied the institutions of the state, and create the laws and ordinances by which the people, themselves included, would be bound. This conceptual distinction continues to operate in political science, although some political scientists, philosophers, historians and cultural anthropologists have argued that most political action in any given society occurs outside of its state, and that there are societies that are not organized into states that nevertheless must be considered in political terms. As long as the concept of natural order was not introduced, the social sciences could not evolve independently of theistic thinking. Since the cultural revolution of the 17th century in England, which spread to France and the rest of Europe, society has been considered subject to natural laws akin to the physical world.[31]

Political and economic relations were drastically influenced by these theories as the concept of the guild was subordinated to the theory of free trade, and Roman Catholic dominance of theology was increasingly challenged by Protestant churches subordinate to each nation-state, which also (in a fashion the Roman Catholic Church often decried angrily) preached in the vulgar or native language of each region. Free trade, as opposed to these religious theories, is a trade policy that does not restrict imports or exports. It can also be understood as the free market idea applied to international trade. In government, free trade is predominantly advocated by political parties that hold liberal economic positions while economically left-wing and nationalist political parties generally support protectionism, the opposite of free trade. However, the enlightenment was an outright attack on religion, particularly Christianity. The most outspoken critic of the church in France was François Marie Arouet de Voltaire, a representative figure of the enlightenment.

Historians have described Voltaire's description of the history of Christianity as "propagandistic". Voltaire is partially responsible for the misattribution of the expression Credo quia absurdum to the Church Fathers. In a letter to Frederick II, King of Prussia, dated 5 January 1767, he wrote about Christianity: La nôtre [religion] est sans contredit la plus ridicule, la plus absurde, et la plus sanguinaire qui ait jamais infecté le monde. "Ours [i.e., the Christian religion] is assuredly the most ridiculous, the most absurd and the most bloody religion which has ever infected this world. Your Majesty will do the human race an eternal service by extirpating this infamous superstition, I do not say among the rabble, who are not worthy of being enlightened and who are apt for every yoke; I say among honest people, among men who think, among those who wish to think. ... My one regret in dying is that I cannot aid you in this noble enterprise, the finest and most respectable which the human mind can point out." After Voltaire, religion would never be the same again in France.[32]

John Locke

[edit]
John Locke

John Locke in particular exemplified this new age of political theory with his work Two Treatises of Government. In it, Locke proposes a state of nature theory that directly complements his conception of how political development occurs and how it can be founded through contractual obligation. Locke stood to refute Sir Robert Filmer's paternally founded political theory in favor of a natural system based on nature in a particular given system. The theory of the divine right of kings became a passing fancy, exposed to the type of ridicule with which John Locke treated it. Unlike Machiavelli and Hobbes but like Aquinas, Locke would accept Aristotle's dictum that man seeks to be happy in a state of social harmony as a social animal. Unlike Aquinas's preponderant view on the salvation of the soul from original sin, Locke believes man's mind comes into this world as tabula rasa. For Locke, knowledge is neither innate, revealed nor based on authority but subject to uncertainty tempered by reason, tolerance and moderation. According to Locke, an absolute ruler as proposed by Hobbes is unnecessary, for natural law is based on reason and seeking peace and survival for man.

David Hume

[edit]

David Hume criticized the social contract theory of John Locke and others as resting on a myth of some actual agreement. Hume was a realist in recognizing the role of force to forge the existence of states and that consent of the governed was merely hypothetical. He also introduced the concept of utility, later picked up on and developed by Jeremy Bentham. Hume also coined the is–ought problem, i.e. that just because something is does not mean that is how it ought to be, which was a very influential idea on normative politics.[33]

Adam Smith

[edit]

Known as the father of liberalism, Adam Smith explained emergence of economic benefits from the self-interested behavior (the invisible hand) of artisans and traders. While praising its efficiency, Smith also expressed concern about the effects of industrial labor (e.g., repetitive activity) on workers. His work on moral sentiments sought to explain social bonds which enhance economic activity.

Immanuel Kant

[edit]

Immanuel Kant argued that participation in civil society is undertaken not for self-preservation, as per Thomas Hobbes, but as a moral duty. He was the first modern thinker who fully analyzed structure and meaning of obligation. He also argued that an international organization was needed to preserve world peace.

John Stuart Mill

[edit]
John Stuart Mill

John Stuart Mill's work on political philosophy begins in On Liberty, the most influential statement of his liberal principles. He begins by distinguishing old and new threats to liberty. The old threat to liberty is found in traditional societies in which there is rule by one (a monarchy) or a few (an aristocracy). Though one could be worried about restrictions on liberty by benevolent monarchs or aristocrats, the traditional worry is that when rulers are politically unaccountable to the governed they will rule in their own interests, rather than the interests of the governed. Mill's explicit theory of rights is introduced in Chapter V of Utilitarianism in the context of his sanction theory of duty, which is an indirect form of utilitarianism that identifies wrong actions as actions that it is useful to sanction. Mill then introduces justice as a proper part of the duty. Justice involves duties that are perfect duties—that is, duties that are correlated with rights. Justice implies something which it is not only right to do, and wrong not to do, but which some individual person can claim from us as a matter of right. These perfect duties will thus create liberty and collective freedom within a state. He uses, On Liberty to discuss gender equality in society. To Mill, Utilitarianism was the perfect tool to justify gender equality in The Subjection of Women, referring to the political, lawful and social subjection of women. When a woman was married, she entered legally binding coverture with her husband; once she married her legal existence as an individual was suspended under "marital unity". While it is easy to presume that a woman would not marry under these circumstances, being unmarried had social consequences. A woman could only advance in social stature and wealth if she had a rich husband to do the groundwork. Mill uses his Utilitarian ethics to assess how gender equality would be the best way to achieve "the greatest good for the greatest number" : "The principle that regulates the existing social relations between the two sexes … and is now one of the chief obstacles to human improvement…"

The 'chief obstacle' to Mill relates to women's intellectual capability. The Subjection of Women looks at this in the women of society and argues that diminishing their intellectual potential wastes the knowledge and skill of half of the population; such knowledge lost could formulate ideas that could maximize pleasure for society.

James Madison

[edit]

James Madison was an American politician considered to be "Father of the Constitution" and "Father of the Bill of Rights" of the United States. As a political theorist, he believed in separation of powers and proposed a comprehensive set of checks and balances that are necessary to protect the rights of an individual from the tyranny of the majority.

Thomas Paine

[edit]

Thomas Paine defended liberal democracy, the American Revolution, and the French Revolution in Common Sense and The Rights of Man.

Benjamin Constant

[edit]
Benjamin Constant

One of the first thinkers to go by the name of "liberal", Benjamin Constant looked to Britain rather than to ancient Rome for a practical model of freedom in a large, commercial society. He drew a distinction between the "Liberty of the Ancients" and the "Liberty of the Moderns". The Liberty of the Ancients was participatory republican liberty, which gave the citizens the right to directly influence politics through debates and votes in the public assembly. In order to support this degree of participation, citizenship was a burdensome moral obligation requiring a considerable investment of time and energy. Generally, this required a sub-society of slaves to do much of the productive work, leaving the citizens free to deliberate on public affairs. Ancient Liberty was also limited to relatively small and homogenous societies, in which the people could be conveniently gathered together in one place to transact public affairs.

The Liberty of the Moderns, in contrast, was based on the possession of civil liberties, the rule of law, and freedom from excessive state interference. Direct participation would be limited: a necessary consequence of the size of modern states, and also the inevitable result of having created a commercial society in which there are no slaves but almost everybody must earn a living through work. Instead, the voters would elect representatives, who would deliberate in Parliament on behalf of the people and would save citizens from the necessity of daily political involvement.

Moreover, Constant believed that, in the modern world, commerce was superior to war. He attacked Napoleon's martial appetite, on the grounds that it was illiberal and no longer suited to modern commercial social organization. Ancient Liberty tended to be warlike, whereas a state organized on the principles of Modern Liberty would be at peace with all peaceful nations.

Romanticism

[edit]

Jean-Jacques Rousseau

[edit]

Rousseau analyzed the social contract as an expression of the general will, and controversially argued in favor of absolute democracy where the people at large would act as sovereign. The Social Contract (1762) outlines the basis for a legitimate political order within a framework of classical republicanism, becoming one of the most influential works of political philosophy in the Western tradition. It developed some of the ideas mentioned in earlier work, the article Discours sur l'oeconomie politique (Discourse on Political Economy), featured in Diderot's Encyclopédie. The treatise begins with the dramatic opening lines, "Man is born free, and everywhere he is in chains. Those who think themselves the masters of others are indeed greater slaves than they."

Rousseau claimed that the state of nature was a primitive condition without law or morality, which human beings left for the benefits and necessity of cooperation. As society developed, the division of labor and private property required the human race to adopt institutions of law. In the degenerate phase of society, man is prone to be in frequent competition with his fellow men while also becoming increasingly dependent on them. This double pressure threatens both his survival and his freedom.

G. W. F. Hegel

[edit]

G. W. F. Hegel emphasized the "cunning" of history, arguing that it followed a rational trajectory, even while embodying seemingly irrational forces. Hegel influenced Marx, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and Oakeshott.

Modern era

[edit]

Anarchism

[edit]

Pierre-Joseph Proudhon is commonly considered the father of modern anarchism, specifically mutualism. Peter Kropotkin is another classic anarchist thinker, who was the most influential theorist of anarcho-communism. Mikhail Bakunin's specific version of anarchism is called collectivist anarchism. Max Stirner was the main representative of the anarchist current known as individualist anarchism and the founder of ethical egoism which endorses anarchy.[34]

Henry David Thoreau was an influential anarchist thinker writing on topics such as pacifism, environmentalism and civil disobedience – notably with his written work Civil Disobedience – who influenced later important political activists such as Leo Tolstoy, Mahatma Gandhi and Martin Luther King Jr. Hard-lining on the individual citizen's right to seek justice over the state's, he was also an outspoken advocate and apologist for John Brown following his raid on Harper's Ferry for the purpose of abolitionist efforts, writing A Plea for Captain John Brown and The Last Days of John Brown.

Noam Chomsky is a leading critic of U.S. foreign policy, neoliberalism and contemporary state capitalism, the Israeli–Palestinian conflict, and mainstream news media. His ideas have proven highly influential in the anti-capitalist and anti-imperialist movements, and aligns with anarcho-syndicalism and libertarian socialism.[35][36][37]

Austrian School

[edit]

Friedrich Hayek argued that central planning was inefficient because members of central bodies could not know enough to match the preferences of consumers and workers with existing conditions. Hayek further argued that central economic planning—a mainstay of socialism—would lead to a "total" state with dangerous power. He advocated free-market capitalism in which the main role of the state is to maintain the rule of law and let spontaneous order develop.

An economist of the Austrian School, Murray Rothbard was the central theorist of anarcho-capitalism.

Christian democracy

[edit]

Christian democracy is a centre-right ideology inspired by Christian social teaching.[38] It originated as a reaction against the industrialisation and urbanisation associated with laissez-faire capitalism.[39] Jacques Maritain has been recognized as the leading Christian-democratic philosopher.[40] Key ideas in Christian-democratic thought include personalism,[41] popularism,[42] subsidiarity,[43] and stewardship.[44]

In post-war Europe, Christian-democratic parties dominated politics in several nations—the Christian People's Party in Belgium, CDU and CSU in Germany, Fine Gael and Fianna Fáil in Ireland, and Christian Democracy in Italy.[45] Many post-war Europeans saw Christian democracy as a moderate alternative to the extremes of right-wing nationalism and left-wing communism.[46] Christian-democratic parties were especially popular among European women, who often voted for these parties to a large extent due to their pro-family policies.[47]

Communitarianism

[edit]

Another debate developed around the (distinct) criticisms of liberal political theory made by Michael Walzer, Michael Sandel and Charles Taylor. The liberal-communitarian debate is often considered valuable for generating a new set of philosophical problems, rather than a profound and illuminating clash of perspective. These and other communitarians (such as Alasdair MacIntyre and Daniel A. Bell) argue that, contra liberalism, communities are prior to individuals and therefore should be the center of political focus. Communitarians tend to support greater local control as well as economic and social policies which encourage the growth of social capital.

Conservatism

[edit]

An Irish member of the British parliament, Edmund Burke is credited with the creation of conservative thought. Burke's Reflections on the Revolution in France is the most popular of his writings where he denounced the French Revolution, although he supported the American Revolution.[48]

An exponent of liberal conservatism, French sociologist Alexis de Tocqueville is known for his works Democracy in America and The Old Regime and the Revolution.

A German political theorist of the Conservative Revolution movement, Carl Schmitt developed the concepts of the friend/enemy distinction, the state of exception, and political theology. Though his most influential books were written in the 1920s, he continued to write prolifically until his death (in academic quasi-exile) in 1985. He heavily influenced 20th-century political philosophy.

Leo Strauss famously rejected modernity, mostly on the grounds of what he perceived to be modern political philosophy's excessive self-sufficiency of reason and flawed philosophical grounds for moral and political normativity. He argued instead that we should return to pre-modern thinkers for answers to contemporary issues. His philosophy was influential on the formation of neoconservatism, and a number of his students later were members of the Bush administration.

Intersectionality

[edit]

Colonialism and racism were important issues that arose during the 1950s and 1960s. The rise of feminism, LGBT social movements and the end of colonial rule and of the political exclusion of such minorities as African Americans and sexual minorities in the developed world has led to feminist, postcolonial, and multicultural thought becoming significant. This led to a challenge to the social contract by philosophers Charles W. Mills in his book The Racial Contract and Carole Pateman in her book The Sexual Contract that the social contract excluded persons of colour and women respectively. Michel Foucault critiqued the modern conception of power on the basis of the prison complex and other prohibitive institutions, such as those that designate sexuality, madness and knowledge as the roots of their infrastructure—a critique that demonstrated that subjection is the power formation of subjects in any linguistic forum and that revolution cannot just be thought as the reversal of power between classes.

Marxism

[edit]

Karl Marx's critique of capitalism—developed with Friedrich Engels—was, alongside liberalism and fascism, one of the defining ideological movements of the twentieth century.[citation needed] The Industrial Revolution produced a parallel revolution in political thought. Urbanization and capitalism greatly reshaped society. During this same period, the socialist movement began to form. In the mid-19th century, Marxism was developed, and socialism in general gained increasing popular support, mostly from the urban working class. Without breaking entirely from the past, Marx established principles that would be used by future revolutionaries of the 20th century, namely Vladimir Lenin, Mao Zedong, Ho Chi Minh, and Fidel Castro. Though Hegel's philosophy of history is similar to Immanuel Kant's, and Karl Marx's theory of revolution towards the common good is partly based on Kant's view of history—Marx declared that he was turning Hegel's dialectic, which was "standing on its head", "the right side up again".[citation needed] Unlike Marx who believed in historical materialism, Hegel believed in the Phenomenology of Spirit.[49] The Russian Revolution of 1917—and similar, albeit less successful, revolutions in many other European countries—brought communism, in particular the political theory of Leninism but also on a smaller level Luxemburgism, on the world stage.[citation needed] Antonio Gramsci instigated the concept of hegemony, arguing that the state and the ruling class use culture and ideology to gain the consent of the classes they rule over.

Contemporaneously with the rise of analytic ethics in Anglo-American thought, several new lines of philosophy directed at the critique of existing societies arose between the 1950s and 1980s. Most of these took elements of Marxist economic analysis but combined them with a more cultural or ideological emphasis. One of the founders of Western Marxism, György Lukács developed the theory of class consciousness and introduced the concept of reification in History and Class Consciousness. Out of the Frankfurt School, thinkers like Herbert Marcuse, Theodor W. Adorno, Max Horkheimer, and Jürgen Habermas combined Marxian and Freudian perspectives. Called the father of the New Left, Marcuse introduced the concept of repressive desublimation, in which social control can operate not only by direct control but also by manipulation of desire. Habermas pioneered such concepts as the public sphere, communicative action, and deliberative democracy. Along somewhat different lines, a number of other continental thinkers—still largely influenced by Marxism—put new emphases on structuralism and on a "return to Hegel". Within the (post-) structuralist line (though mostly not taking that label) are thinkers such as Gilles Deleuze, Michel Foucault, Claude Lefort, and Jean Baudrillard. The Situationists were more influenced by Hegel; Guy Debord, in particular, moved a Marxist analysis of commodity fetishism to the realm of consumption, and looked at the relation between consumerism and dominant ideology formation.

Objectivism

[edit]

Ayn Rand was the founder of Objectivism and a prime mover of the libertarian movement in mid-twentieth-century America. Advocating a complete, laissez-faire capitalism, Rand held that the proper role of government was exclusively the protection of individual rights without economic interference. The government was to be separated from economics the same way and for the same reasons it was separated from religion. Any governmental action not directed at the defense of individual rights would constitute the initiation of force (or threat of force), and therefore a violation not only of rights but also of the legitimate function of government.

Republicanism

[edit]

A pair of overlapping political perspectives arising toward the end of the 20th century are republicanism (or neo- or civic-republicanism) and the capability approach. The resurgent republican movement aims to provide an alternative definition of liberty from Isaiah Berlin's positive and negative forms of liberty, namely "liberty as non-domination."[50] Unlike the American liberal movement which understands liberty as "non-interference," "non-domination" entails individuals not being subject to the arbitrary will of any other person. To a republican the mere status as a slave, regardless of how that slave is treated, is objectionable. Prominent republicans include historian Quentin Skinner, jurist Cass Sunstein, and political philosopher Philip Pettit. The capability approach, pioneered by economists Mahbub ul Haq and Amartya Sen and further developed by legal scholar Martha Nussbaum, understands freedom under allied lines: the real-world ability to act. Both the capability approach and republicanism treat choice as something which must be resourced. In other words, it is not enough to be legally able to do something, but to have the real option of doing it.

Social liberalism

[edit]

In Anglo-American academic political philosophy, the publication of John Rawls's A Theory of Justice in 1971 is considered a milestone. Rawls used a thought experiment, the original position, in which representative parties choose principles of justice for the basic structure of society from behind a veil of ignorance. Rawls also offered a criticism of utilitarian approaches to questions of political justice. Robert Nozick's 1974 book Anarchy, State, and Utopia, which won a National Book Award, criticized the social liberalism of Rawls from a libertarian perspective, gaining much academic respectability.[51]

Traditionalism

[edit]

Julius Evola called for a return to pre-Renaissance values of tradition and aristocracy while discussing possible ways to survive the inevitable collapse of the modern civilization and to bring forth a new order.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Strauss, Leo (1959). An introduction to Political Philosophy. Detroit: Wayne State University Press, p. 10.
  2. ^ Dryzek, John S.; Honig, Bonnie; Phillips, Anne, eds. (2 September 2009). "The Oxford Handbook of Political Theory". Oxford Handbooks Online. doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199548439.001.0001. ISBN 9780199548439.
  3. ^ Eckstein, Harry (1956). "Political Theory and the Study of Politics: A Report of a Conference". American Political Science Review. 50 (2): 475–487. doi:10.2307/1951680. ISSN 0003-0554. JSTOR 1951680. S2CID 147351387.
  4. ^ "Chanakya". World History Encyclopedia. Retrieved 28 November 2020.
  5. ^ Boesche, Roger (2002). The First Great Political Realist: Kautilya and His Arthashastra. Lexington Books. p. 7. ISBN 978-0-7391-0401-9.
  6. ^ Rangarajan, L N (2000). The Arthashastra. Penguin UK. p. 95. ISBN 9788184750119.
  7. ^ Brown, D. Mackenzie (1982). The White Umbrella: Indian Political Thought from Manu to Gandhi. Greenwood Press. p. 64. ISBN 978-0313232107.
  8. ^ Sankhdher, Madan Mohan; Kaur, Gurdeep (2005). Politics in India: Ancient India, Politics of Change, Modern India. Deep and Deep Publications. p. 95. ISBN 9788176296557.
  9. ^ Manu ((Lawgiver)); Kullūkabhaṭṭa (1796). Institutes of Hindu Law: Or, The Ordinances of Menu, According to the Gloss of Cullúca. Calcutta, Printed by order of the government, London reprinted, for J. Sewell and J. Debrett.
  10. ^ Csikszentmihalyi, Mark (2020), "Confucius", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 22 April 2022
  11. ^ Van Norden, Bryan (2019), "Mencius", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 15 October 2020
  12. ^ Deutsch, Eliot; Bontekoei, Ronald (1999). A companion to world philosophies. Wiley Blackwell. p. 183. ISBN 9780631213277.
  13. ^ Hsü, Leonard Shihlien (2005). The political philosophy of Confucianism. Routledge. pp. xvii–xx. ISBN 978-0-415-36154-5. The importance of a scientific study of Confucian political philosophy could hardly be overstated.
  14. ^ a b Sahakian, Mabel Lewis (1993). Ideas of the great philosophers. Barnes & Noble Publishing. p. 59. ISBN 978-1-56619-271-2. ... Western philosophical tradition can be traced back as early as Plato (427–347 BC).
  15. ^ Kraut, Richard (2002). Aristotle: political philosophy. Oxford University Press. p. 3. ISBN 978-0-19-878200-1. To understand and assess Aristotle's contributions to political thought ...
  16. ^ Shields, Christopher (2020), "Aristotle", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 15 October 2020
  17. ^ Radford, Robert T. (2002). Cicero: a study in the origins of republican philosophy. Rodopi. p. 1. ISBN 978-90-420-1467-1. His most lasting political contribution is in his work on political philosophy.
  18. ^ Koetsier, L.S. (2004). Natural Law and Calvinist Political Theory. Trafford Publishing. p. 19. ISBN 978-1-4122-1440-7. ...the Medieval Scholastics revived the concept of natural law.
  19. ^ Copleston, Frederick (1999). A history of philosophy. Vol. 3. Continuum International Publishing Group. p. 346. ISBN 978-0-86012-296-8. There was, however, at least one department of thought ...
  20. ^ Valente, Claire (2003). The theory and practice of revolt in medieval England. Ashgate Publishing Ltd. p. 14. ISBN 978-0-7546-0901-8. The two starting points of most medieval discussions ...
  21. ^ Schall, James V. (1998). At the Limits of Political Philosophy. CUA Press. p. 40. ISBN 978-0-8132-0922-7. In political philosophy, St. Augustine was a follower of Plato ...
  22. ^ McInerny, Ralph; O'Callaghan, John (2018), "Saint Thomas Aquinas", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 15 October 2020
  23. ^ Aslan, Reza (2005). No god but God. Random House Inc. p. 153. ISBN 978-1-58836-445-6. By the ninth and tenth centuries...
  24. ^ "Al-Fārābī | Muslim philosopher". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
  25. ^ "Avicenna (Ibn Sina) | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". www.iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
  26. ^ "Al-Ghazālī | Muslim jurist, theologian, and mystic". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
  27. ^ "Niẓām al-Mulk | Seljuq vizier". Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 22 April 2018.
  28. ^ Gellner, Ernest (1992). Plough, Sword, and Book. University of Chicago Press. p. 239. ISBN 978-0-226-28702-7. Ibn Khaldun's definition of government probably remains the best: ...
  29. ^ Johnston, Ian (February 2002). "Lecture on Machiavelli's The Prince". Malaspina University College. Archived from the original on 18 February 2012. Retrieved 20 February 2007.
  30. ^ Copleston, Frederick (1999). A history of philosophy. Vol. 3. Continuum International Publishing Group. pp. 310–12. ISBN 978-0-86012-296-8. ...we witness the growth of political absolutism ...
  31. ^ Barens, Ingo; Caspari, Volker; Schefold, Bertram (2004). Barens, Ingo (ed.). Political events and economic ideas. Volker Caspari ed., Bertram Schefold ed. Edward Elgar Publishing. pp. 206–07. ISBN 978-1-84542-152-6. Economic theory as political philosophy: the example of the French Enlightenment
  32. ^ Byrne, James M. (1997). Religion and the Enlightenment. Westminster John Knox Press. pp. 1–2. ISBN 978-0-664-25760-6. ... there emerged groups of freethinkers intent on grounding knowledge on the exercise of critical reason, as opposed to ... established religion ...
  33. ^ MacIntyre, A. (1959). Hume on "Is" and "Ought". The Philosophical Review, 68(4), 451–468. doi:10.2307/2182491
  34. ^ Hospers, John (1973). Rule-Egoism. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 54 (4):391.
  35. ^ "On Linguistics and Politics, by Noam Chomsky".
  36. ^ "Noam Chomsky: Philosophy, Anarco-Syndicalism, and Truth to Power". 20 March 2018.
  37. ^ Lydon, Christopher (2 June 2017). "Noam Chomsky: Neoliberalism is Destroying Our Democracy". The Nation.
  38. ^ Caciagli, Mario; Robeck, Cecil M; Yong, Amos (2008). "Christian democracy". The Cambridge History of Twentieth-Century Political Thought. Cambridge University Press. pp. 165–180. ISBN 9781139053600.
  39. ^ Riff, Michael (1987). Dictionary of Modern Political Ideologies. Manchester University Press. p. 34. ISBN 0-7190-3289-X.
  40. ^ Invernizzi Accetti, Carlo (2019). What is Christian Democracy?: Politics, Religion and Ideology. New York: Cambridge University Press. p. 23.
  41. ^ Invernizzi Accetti, Carlo (2019). What is Christian Democracy?: Politics, Religion and Ideology. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 53–79.
  42. ^ Invernizzi Accetti, Carlo (2019). What is Christian Democracy?: Politics, Religion and Ideology. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 80–110.
  43. ^ Invernizzi Accetti, Carlo (2019). What is Christian Democracy?: Politics, Religion and Ideology. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 111–138.
  44. ^ Invernizzi Accetti, Carlo (2019). What is Christian Democracy?: Politics, Religion and Ideology. New York: Cambridge University Press. pp. 243–244.
  45. ^ Kselman, Thomas; Buttigieg, Thomas, eds. (2003). European Christian Democracy: Historical Legacies and Comparative Perspectives. University of Notre Dame Press. p. 122.
  46. ^ Layton-Henry, Zig, ed. (1982). Conservative Politics in Western Europe. St. Martin's Press. pp. 131–133. ISBN 9780312164188.
  47. ^ Hanley, David, ed. (1994). Christian Democracy in Europe : A Comparative Perspective. Pinter Publishers. pp. 56–57. ISBN 9781855670860.
  48. ^ "A Guide to Edmund Burke's Political Thought". Edmund Burke. Retrieved 15 October 2020.
  49. ^ Kain, Philip J. (1993). Marx and modern political theory. Rowman & Littlefield. pp. 1–4. ISBN 978-0-8476-7866-2. Some of his texts, especially the Communist Manifesto made him seem like a sort of communist Descartes ...
  50. ^ Cherniss, Joshua; Hardy, Henry (2020), "Isaiah Berlin", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 15 October 2020
  51. ^ David Lewis Schaefer, Robert Nozick and the Coast of Utopia, The New York Sun, 30 April 2008.

Further reading

[edit]

Academic journals dedicated to political philosophy include: Political Theory, Philosophy and Public Affairs, Contemporary Political Theory, Constellations, and The Journal of Political Philosophy

[edit]