Non-possession (Sanskrit: अपरिग्रह, aparigraha) is a religious tenet followed in Buddhist, Hindu, and Jain traditions in South Asia. In Jainism, aparigraha is the virtue of non-possessiveness, non-grasping, or non-greediness.[1]
Aparigrah is the opposite of parigrah. It means keeping the desire for possessions to what is necessary or important, which depends on one's life stage and context. The precept of aparigraha is a self-restraint (temperance) from the type of greed and avarice where one's own material gain or happiness comes by hurting, killing, or destroying other human beings, life forms, or nature.[2]
Aparigraha is related to and in part a motivator of dāna (proper charity), both from giver's and receiver's perspective.[3]
Non-possession is one of the principles of satyagraha, a philosophical system based on various religious and philosophical traditions originating in India and Asia Minor, and put into practice by Mahatma Gandhi as part of his nonviolent resistance. This particular iteration of aparigraha is distinct because it is a component of Gandhi's active non-violent resistance to social problems permeating India. As such, its conception is tempered with western law. Non-possession is, by definition, concerned with defining the concept of possession. Gandhi intertwined non-possession and voluntary poverty in application, but living according to the guidelines of non-possession is not the same as living in poverty. In practice, the principle of taking what one needs (rather than less than or more than), is essential to the viability of non-possession/aparigraha.
Etymology and meaning
editAparigraha is a compound in Sanskrit, made of "a-" and "parigraha". The prefix "a-" means "non-", so "aparigraha" is the opposite of "parigraha"—speech and actions that oppose and negate parigraha.
Parigraha means 'to amass', 'to crave', 'to seek', 'to seize', and 'to receive or accept' material possessions or gifts from others.[4] The word also includes the idea of doing good with the expectation of benefit or reward, not just for the sake of merely doing good. Parigraha includes the results as well as the intent; in other words, it means the attitudes of craving, possessiveness, and hoarding, but also the things that have been acquired because of those attitudes.[4] That aparigraha is a means to liberate the soul from the cycle of birth and death was first asserted by the first tirthankara in Jainism, Rishabhdeva.[5]
Monier-Williams states that the word parigraha has roots in the Vedic texts as well, referring to fencing an altar, enclosing something, assuming or putting on a dress or receiving something.[6] In the Brahmanas and later texts, the term contextually means accepting or taking a gift; acquiring, possessing, claiming, controlling something such a property; assistance; or constraining force on others.[6] In some texts, the root reflects the state of marriage or having a family.[6]
The virtue of aparigraha means characteristically taking what one truly needs and no more. In the Yoga school of Hinduism, this concept of virtue has also been translated as "abstaining from accepting gifts",[7] "not expecting, asking, or accepting inappropriate gifts from any person", and "not applying for gifts which are not to be accepted".[8] The concept includes in its scope non-covetousness[9] and non-possessiveness.[10] Aparigraha includes the psychological state of "letting go and the releasing of control, transgressions, fears" and living a content life unfettered by anxieties.[11]
Jainism
editAparigraha is one of the virtues in Jainism. It is also one of the five vows that both householders (Śrāvaka) and ascetics must observe. This Jain vow is the principle of limiting one's possessions (parimita-parigraha) and limiting one's desires (iccha-parimana).[4]
In Jainism, worldly wealth accumulation is considered a potential source of greed, jealousy, selfishness, and desires.[12][13] Giving up emotional attachments, sensual pleasures, and material possession is a means of liberation in Jain philosophy.[14] Eating enough to survive is considered more noble than eating for indulgence.[12] Similarly, all consumption is more appropriate if it is essential to one's survival, and inappropriate if it is a form of hoarding, showing off, or for ego. Non-possession and non-attachment are forms of virtue, and are recommended particularly in later stages of one's life.[12] After ahiṃsā, aparigraha is the second most important virtue in Jainism.[14]
Jainism views attachments to material or emotional possessions as what leads to passions, which in turn leads to violence.[15] Jain texts say that "attachment to possessions" (parigraha) is of two kinds: attachment to internal possessions (ābhyantara parigraha), and attachment to external possessions (bāhya parigraha).[16] The fourteen internal possessions are as follows:[17][18]
Wrong belief | |
---|---|
The three sex-passions | Male sex-passion, Female sex-passion, Neuter sex-passion |
Six defects | Laughter, Liking, Disliking, Sorrow, Fear, Disgust |
Four passions (kashaya) | Anger, Pride, Deceitfulness, Greed |
External possessions are divided into two subclasses: the non-living and the living. According to Jain texts, both internal and external possessions are proved to be hiṃsā (injury[clarification needed]).[19]
Hinduism
editIn the Yoga Sūtras (II.30), aparigraha is listed as the fifth of the yamas or code of self-restraint, after ahimsa (nonviolence), satya (non-falsehoods, truthfulness), asteya (not stealing), and brahmacharya (chastity in one's feelings and actions).[8][20]
अहिंसासत्यास्तेय ब्रह्मचर्यापरिग्रहाः यमाः ॥३०॥
Non-violence, Non-falsehood, Non-stealing, Non-cheating (celibacy, chastity), and Non-possessiveness are the five Yamas. (30)
— Patanjali, Yoga Sutra 2.30[21]
Aparigraha is thus one of the five essential restraints (yamas, "the don'ts") in Hinduism, that with five essential practices (niyamas, "the dos") are suggested for right, virtuous, enlightened living. While Yoga Sutras distill the ten yamas and niyamas, these virtues appear, in various discussions, in Vedic texts.[22] It[ambiguous] is part of ethical theory in Hinduism.[23]
James Wood states that aparigraha is the virtue of abstaining from appropriating objects because one understands the disadvantages in "acquiring them, keeping them, losing them, being attached to them, or in harming them".[8] Patanjali suggests that greed and coveting material wealth increases greed and possessiveness, a cycle that distracts from good reasons for activity that should motivate a person:
- When we start to satisfy desires, new levels of greed or attachment can start to develop. Coupled with asteya, parigraha (coveting/hoarding) can lead an individual to lie, steal, cheat, or even murder for the desired item, regardless of the outcome of their actions. Greed is probably the highest act of not practicing aparigraha, since greed generally equates to collecting things well beyond one's immediate or foreseeable future needs.[24]
Restraint from possessiveness and greed, or aparigraha, leads one away from harmful and injurious greed, refraining from harming others, and towards the spiritual state of good activity and understanding one's motives and origins.[8][25] The virtue of non-coveting and non-possessing is a means of sādhanā, a path of spiritual existence.[25] In the outer world, aparigraha manifests as non-possessiveness with simple living; while in psychological terms, it is a state of non-attachment, non-craving, and contentment.[26]
अपरिग्रहस्थैर्ये जन्मकथंतासंबोधः ॥३९॥
With constancy of aparigraha, a spiritual illumination of the how and why of motives and birth emerges.
— Patanjali, Yoga Sutra 2.39[25]
Possession in Satyagraha
editPossession is the de facto claim on another entity based on exclusive access. If access is non-exclusive of some entity, then the object in question is not being possessed.[clarification needed]
The concepts of possession and ownership often overlap, but are not the same. Ownership takes into account the entitlement to priority of access, which is based on agreements and other social protocols.
If more than one entity has access to something simultaneously, and one or more of the entities assert priority of access (exclusivity) over the other(s), or if some external force endows or demands priority of one entity, a group of entity, over some other(s), then there is conflict. Even if those who are excluded concur to such claims, their de facto access will present conflict by necessity.
In the event that more than one entity has access to something simultaneously, exclusion occurs when:
- one or more of the entities assert priority of access over the other(s),
- some external force endows or demands priority of one entity, a group of entities, over some other(s).
Even if those who are excluded concur to the claimed priority, the de facto simultaneous access necessarily present conflict between claim to priority and what actually happens.
Note that the conflict begins with assumed priority not matching empirical reality. Also note that claim can only occur with communicative acts or verbal communication. Concurrence also requires communication, but one cannot concur unless a claim has been posed first (passive action).
The concept of ownership could have been invented, in part, to resolve this dilemma, by instating a system of social protocols.
Ownership as resolution
editOwnership increases the frequency of consensus over disagreement. Using social protocols, ownership establishes one or a group of entities' permanent priority of access to something. Unless the owner relinquishes this right, this established priority stands regardless of empirical phenomena.
A dilemma arises when an entity enters into the sphere of a consensus with no prior knowledge of the agreement. Empirical phenomena would be the basis for both conceptual and empirical reality.
An example of this is Britain entering India. With the simultaneous desire to procure resources already claimed by the aggregate Indian society, and lack of desire to participate in Indian society, Britain's subjects actively challenged established ownership. The act also defined all inhabitants, including not only those actively participating in Hindu society, but also those participating passively (Untouchables,) as part of an aggregate entity. Before asserting its own ownership upon said resources, British interests challenged existing Indian society's ownership by de facto possession (by virtue of being present in India,) India's lack of utilization for said resources (contrasting with Britain's moral and lawful utilization of them, as concurred by its peer nations,) and the inability for India to counter-challenge Britain legally and philosophically.
Non-possession is another concept which can resolve this dilemma. If claims always match empirical reality, then there is no conflict. Eliminating exclusion, claims to priority of access will always be based on empirical reality.
Non-possession as resolution
editIf claims always match empirical reality, then there is no conflict.
Boundaries are a given. Possession as the defining mechanism for boundaries is also a given.
If entities have no cause to endow or assert priority of access over the other(s), cause to exclude is removed. The goal of claiming access will then not be to exclude. The goal of the claims will still remain: (a) one or more of the entities assert priority of access over the other(s), (b) some external force endows or demands priority of one entity, a group of entities, over some other(s). The motivation to establish priority of access will always be based on empirical reality. By extension, pre-established hierarchies of access (ownership) will not increase the frequency of consensus unless the hierarchies support empirical reality. Empirical reality always takes precedence over conceptual reality.
Non-possession is another concept which resolves the dilemma which arises when reasoned reality conflicts with empirical reality.
Non-possession provides for conditions under which none of the entities have cause to assert exclusivity which is not concurred by others.
Contrast with some entity which has ownership of something; if some other entity has possession of that thing, the owner has the right to concede or deny the legitimacy of that other entity's possession. Possession is a necessary component of ownership, but ownership is not a necessary component of possession. This does not mean that something cannot be possessed by some entity other than its owner. It means that the owner of a thing has the exclusive right to concede or deny the legitimacy of anyone who possesses this thing, even if the owner has no intention of accessing the object of possession. Further, the owner has the ability to concede or deny his/her/its own legitimacy of possessing the object of possession. In application, ownership is often asserted when it is challenged by possession (de facto claim to access exclusive of the owner.)
Non-possession denies the exclusive access of an entity by another entity.
To paraphrase: non-possession says that no entity has the right to exclusive access to another entity, either by social agreement, or de facto exclusive access.
Challenge posed toward possession
editBy definition, non-possession is the opposite of possession. There is inherent conflict between the two approaches to organizing priority of access. It is notable that practitioners of non-possession acknowledge the existence of possession. See § Theft.
Those practicing possession do not necessarily acknowledge non-possession for several reasons. Here, they are defined by conditions occurring within different layers of an individual entity's experience:
- not aware of non-possession as an amalgamated concept, (contrast with the awareness of the complex concept of possession);
- non-possession presents logical conflict in the cognitive process when one comes into contact with issues of boundaries and priority of access, therefore, the concept (alternative) is consistently disposed of during the cognitive process;
- non-possession presents interpersonal conflict when one is engaged in social activities.
Non-stealing
editThe practical implications of non-possession can be clarified by defining another principle of Satyagraha: non-stealing.
Non-stealing is the practice of not breaching an entity's entitlement of or sense of entitlement toward something.
Theft has to do with breaching ownership: both possession and sense of entitlement. Non-possession only challenges the idea of possession, not entitlement.
There are concepts associated with ownership which do not conflict with non-possession, such as willingness to cultivate that which is owned, recognition of benefit conferred upon the owner, positive opinion and/ or feelings toward that which is owned, negative opinion and/ or feelings etc.
Under non-possession, these reactions are not (and cannot be) reserved toward possessions. As such, traditional definitions of theft and the reasons for not stealing require clarification.
Sense of entitlement
editSense of entitlement has to do with emotional attachment beyond practical benefit and usefulness to an entity's perceivable physical survival. The belief that one deserves to receive an opportunity or reward. The myriad of ways a sense of entitlement can arise include legal claim, length of time spent with the object, birthright, labour exerted, labour not exerted, comparative social standing, inheritance, perspective, lack of perspective, etc. Practitioners of religious traditions such as Buddhism, Jainism, even the three major western religious traditions consciously aspire to extricate from or modify non-practical emotional attachment in some form. There are branches of philosophy which deal exclusively with such modifications such as Stoicism.
Non-stealing takes the approach of applied Hinduism in that it recognizes that not everyone would either choose to extricate from or would be successful extricating from attachment at any given time. As well, possession exists de facto, and is often cited as support of entitlement to an object of possession.
Theft
editIn the absence of possession (and ownership by extension,) theft would be impossible. But theft is possible under the non-possession worldview. This is possible given that not everyone in the world practices non-possession. It is also difficult to put non-possession into practice under existing socio-economic systems. People have the right to, and likely have to define their boundaries out of necessity. All historically recorded cultures either prescribe laws regarding individuals' personal boundaries, or imply the limits of the individual through practices. Absence of conventions and protocol undermine the ability for humans to understand each other at the conscious level, without which, civilization is not possible. Boundaries between individual entities is an essential component of any grouping, including civilization; they exist in empirical reality and by definition.
Across cultures, the definition of these boundaries can be explicit, implicit, or entirely personal. The United States Constitution has provisions for rights to personal property, but no explicit provisions for boundaries.
Boundaries are one of the essential given conditions for possession to be possible. The reverse is not true. Possession deals with the relationship of something to boundaries, a relationship in which boundaries provide the principle to qualify whether something is being possessed or not being possessed. A boundary can be defined to be independent of the idea of possession: the threshold between two identifiable, separate entities.
Logically, the existence of theft would be invalid If there are no rules as to how one can and cannot define boundaries. Without the ability to define a boundary, there is no way to discern where one entity begins and the other ends, therefore, not possible to define possession. Without possession, there can be no ownership, claim to ownership, or theft.
Hypothetical example: If some entity has the ability to lay claim to any object without contest, theft is still possible. One can steal from this entity if one is not part of this entity. Also, that the entity is empowered to lay claim necessitates that there are objects which the entity can lay claim upon, therefore, objects which this entity does not possess. Boundaries may exist between objects before the entity lays claim to them, (that is, if it intends to lay claim to them.) Breach of these boundaries constitute theft. A hypothetical entity empowered to lay claim upon any object can also approach a grey area between legitimate possession and theft if its possession of an object is not clearly defined, that is, if this entity itself has doubts as to whether it possesses the object in question.
Boundaries exist in empirical reality because people and things obviously do not melt together upon touching. While some systems of thought would contest this even on a limited level, and there are counterexamples, especially when dealing with ideas, in general, it is accepted that boundaries exist at least in some areas of consensus reality. Non-possession does not directly address boundaries, therefore, it neither negates nor confirms the concept. The very existence of boundaries almost necessitates possession, (add graphic) but things can exist on boundaries. Also, boundaries are sometimes defined by possession.
Taking into account both the logical provisions and also that non-possession is a social philosophy specifically applicable to sentient beings (e.g. people), the act of breaching another entity's sense of entitlement constitutes theft.
The specific possessive act of attachment is involuntary, it cannot stop unless the peripheral stimulus which causes it is also removed. The peripheral stimulus can be something which supports the very fabric of consensus reality, like boundaries. As such, non-possession, as a social philosophy, does not and cannot challenge the peripheral stimulus. To paraphrase: attachment begets entitlement in a non-logical, non-physical sense. Given the above, the boundary that is requisite for entitlement to exist on the non-logical, non-physical level is outside of non-possession's scope. This is not the case for aparigraha.
Non-stealing is a necessary component in addition to non-possession because of Satyagraha's applicative nature. Non-possession does not negate boundaries.
Gandhi's view was that possession is more trouble than it is worth:
The possession of anything then became a troublesome thing and a burden. Exploring the cause of that joy, I found that if I kept anything as my own, I had to defend it against the whole world.... And I said to myself: if [other people] want it and would take it, they do so not from any malicious motive but... because theirs was a greater need than mine.[27]
Relation to charity and conservation
editSome[28] suggest that aparigraha implies charity (dāna) and conservation. Taking and wasting more of nature, or from others, is inconsistent with the ethical precept of aparigraha.[29]
Scholars[14] suggest aparigraha allies with ideas that inspire environmental and ecological sustainability. Aparigraha suggests the reduction of waste and adds a spiritual dimension to preventing destructive consumption of ecosystems and nature.
Difference from Asteya
editAsteya is also one of the five vows taken by Jain ascetic monks.[30] It is the virtue of non-stealing and not wanting to appropriate, or take by force or deceit or exploitation, by deeds or words or thoughts, what is owned by and belongs to someone else.[31] Aparigraha, in contrast, is the virtue of non-possessiveness and non-clinging to one's own property, non-accepting any gifts or particularly improper gifts offered by others, and of non-avarice, non-craving in the motivation of one's deeds, words and thoughts.[8][32]
In literature
editThe ancient Tamil moral text Tirukkural speaks about aparigraha in its chapters on renunciation (Chapter 35) and extirpation of desire (Chapter 37), among others.[33]
See also
edit- Civil disobedience – Nonviolent disobedience of the law
- Cooperative – Autonomous association of persons or organizations
- Gift economy – Mode of exchange where valuables are given without rewards
- Moderation – Process of eliminating or lessening extremes
- Non-profit – Organization operated for a collective benefit
- Non-violence – Principle or practice of not causing harm to others
- Nonviolent resistance – Act of protest through nonviolent means
- Postmaterialism – Concept in sociology
- Property – Entity owned by a person or a group of people
- Socialism – Political philosophy emphasising social ownership of production
References
edit- ^ Dhand, Arti (2002). "The dharma of ethics, the ethics of dharma: Quizzing the ideals of Hinduism". Journal of Religious Ethics. 30 (3): 347–372. doi:10.1111/1467-9795.00113.
- ^ Lauricella, Sharon (2013). "Judging by the way animals are treated: Gandhi as a manifestation of Patanjali's Yoga Sutras". Gandhi Marg Quarterly. 35 (4): 655–674.
- ^
- Jain, S.C. (2012). "Spiritual Guidance in Achieving and Sustaining Organizational Excellence". Purushartha: A Journal of Management Ethics and Spirituality. 4 (2): 1–16.
- Kazanas, N. (2013). Balslev, A.N. (ed.). Vedic Tradition and Civilization, in On India: Self-Image and Counter-image. SAGE Publications. pp. 27–41. ISBN 978-8132110927.
- ^ a b c Jain, Kamila. "Relevance of Jaina Economic Philosophy in Modern Times". Indologica Taurinensia. 30 (11): 139–146.
- ^ Gabriel, Theodore P. C.; Geaves, Ron (2007). Understanding Religion. Universe. ISBN 9780789315304.
- ^ a b c Monier-Williams, Sir Monier; Leumann, Ernst; Cappeller, Carl (1899). "Parigraha". A Sanskrit-English Dictionary: Etymologically and Philologically Arranged with Special Reference to Cognate Indo-European Languages. Motilal Banarsidass Publishing House. p. 593. ISBN 978-81-208-3105-6.
- ^ "The Yoga Sutras of Patanjali". Internet Sacred Text Archive. Translated by BonGiovanni. 2.30. Retrieved 11 July 2023.
- ^ a b c d e The Yoga-System of Patañjali. The Harvard Oriental Series. Vol. 17. Translated by Wood, James Haughton. Harvard University Press. 1914. pp. 178–182.
- ^ Mathur, Pragya M.; Mathur, Krishna Mohan; Mathur, Shiv Shubhang (2009). New Horizons in Indian Management. Gyan Publishing House. p. 280. ISBN 978-81-7835-711-9.
- ^ Nancy Gerstein (2005). Guiding Yoga's Light: Yoga Lessons for Yoga Teachers. Pendragon. p. 140. ISBN 978-0-9722809-8-3.
- ^ Taylor, Jennifer (2008). "End-of-Life Yoga Therapy: Exploring Life and Death". International Journal of Yoga Therapy. 18 (18): 97–103. doi:10.17761/ijyt.18.1.f220h7377vtmn852.
- ^ a b c Mehta, M.R. (6 August 2023). Kapur, T.B. Kapur Promila (ed.). Value Education: Based on All the Religions of the World. Vol. 1. Kalpaz Publications. pp. 329–330. ISBN 978-81-7835-566-5.
- ^ "Aparigraha—non-acquisition". BBC Religions. 11 September 2009.
- ^ a b c Vallely, Anne (2012). "Jainism: Aparigraha". In Juergensmeyer, Mark; Roof, Wade Clark (eds.). Encyclopedia of Global Religion. SAGE. p. 609. ISBN 978-0-7619-2729-7.
- ^ Dundas 2002, p. 160.
- ^ Vijay K. Jain 2012, p. 76.
- ^ Vijay K. Jain 2012, p. 77.
- ^ Jaini 1998, pp. 118–119.
- ^ Jain 2012, p. 77.
- ^ Feuerstein, Georg (1997). Feuerstein, Georg; Miller, Jeanine (eds.). The Essence of Yoga. Inner Traditions. ISBN 978-0-89281-738-2.
- ^ Yoga Sutra, Sadhana Pada, sutra 30
- ^ Clarke, Matthew (1 January 2013). Handbook of Research on Development and Religion. Edward Elgar Publishing. p. 83. ISBN 978-0-85793-357-7.
- ^ Hornett, Andrea (2013). "Ancient Ethics and Contemporary Systems: The Yamas, the Niyamas and the forms of Organization". In Prastacos, Gregory P; Wang, Fuming; Soderquist, Klas Eric (eds.). Leadership through the Classics. Springer. pp. 63–69. ISBN 978-3-642-32444-4.
- ^ "About Yoga series: Understanding the Yama's". Archived from the original on 28 February 2019. Retrieved 28 February 2019.
- ^ a b c The Yoga-System of Patañjali. The Harvard Oriental Series. Vol. 17. Translated by Wood, James. Harvard University Press. 1914. pp. 187–188.
- ^ George, K.M. (2014). "Toward a Eucharistic Missiology". International Review of Mission. 103 (2): 309–318. doi:10.1111/irom.12065.
- ^ "The Gospel of Non-possess". The Eleven Vows as a Basis of the Ashram Life.
- ^ Bhagwat, Shonil A. (Fall–Winter 2008). "Yoga and Sustainability". The Journal of Yoga. 7 (1): 1–14.
- ^
- Betal, C. (2008). "Conservation of Ecology and Environment through Yogic Lifestyle". Journal of Environmental Research and Development. 2 (4): 905–911.
- Taneja, D.K. (2014). "Yoga and health". Indian Journal of Community Medicine. 39 (2): 68–73. doi:10.4103/0970-0218.132716. PMC 4067931. PMID 24963220.
- ^ Chapple, Christopher Key (2006). Jainism and Ecology: Nonviolence in the Web of Life. Motilal Banarsidass Publishers. ISBN 9788120820456.
- ^ Farhi, Donna (2011). Yoga Mind, Body & Spirit: A Return to Wholeness. MacMillan. pp. 10–11. ISBN 978-0805059700.
- ^ Frawley, David (6 August 2023). Yoga and the Sacred Fire: Self-Realization and Planetary Transformation. Motilal Banarsidas. ISBN 978-8120827462.
- ^ Pope, George Uglow (1886). The Sacred Kurral of Tiruvalluva Nayanar (PDF) (First ed.). New Delhi: Asian Educational Services. ISBN 8120600223.
Sources
edit- Dundas, Paul (2002) [1992], The Jains (Second ed.), London and New York: Routledge, ISBN 978-0-415-26605-5
- Jain, Vijay K. (2012), Acharya Amritchandra's Purushartha Siddhyupaya: Realization of the Pure Self, With Hindi and English Translation, Vikalp Printers, ISBN 978-81-903639-4-5,
This article incorporates text from this source, which is in the public domain.
- Jaini, Padmanabh S. (1998) [1979], The Jaina Path of Purification, Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, ISBN 978-81-208-1578-0